Anda di halaman 1dari 14

The Paradigm Wars: Reports from the Front The Paradigm Dialog by E.

Guba; The Nature of Social and Educational Inquiry: Empiricism versus Interpretation by J. K. Smith Review by: Martyn Hammersley British Journal of Sociology of Education, Vol. 13, No. 1 (1992), pp. 131-143 Published by: Taylor & Francis, Ltd. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1392863 . Accessed: 08/02/2013 05:49
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Taylor & Francis, Ltd. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to British Journal of Sociology of Education.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded on Fri, 8 Feb 2013 05:49:59 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

BritishJournal of Sociologyof Education, Vol. 13, No. 1, 1992

131

REVIEW ESSAY

The Paradigm Wars: reportsfrom the front

MARTYN HAMMERSLEY

The Paradigm Dialog E. GUBA(Ed.), 1990 Newbury Park, Sage The Nature of Social and Educational Inquiry: empiricism versus interpretation J. K. SMITH, 1989 Norwood, NJ, Ablex Having rightly concluded that philosophy was of some importance to the sociological enterprise, sociologists (and I am one) have used that discipline much as the military might use a guided missile. Safely fired in the conviction that it will seek and destroy, the solider need know little of the missile's true workings and consequences. Likewise for the sociologist. Recognising the incipient power of labels borrowed from philosophy, sociologists have strewn them about with little regard to their detailed signifiance. Indeed, if armies were so irresponsible (and they may yet be) I should not be writing, nor you reading, this essay. We would have long since vanished in drifting clouds of nuclear fallout. (Tudor, 1982, pp. 1-2) In a recent futuristic sketch of research on teaching in the two decades from 1989, Gage refers to this period as "the paradigm wars and their aftermath" (Gage, 1989). There is no doubt that the 1980s and early 1990s have seen growing debates among educationa,l researchers about methodology, sometimes taking the form of conflicts between incommensurable paradigms in which philosophical terms have been used as weapons. The two books under review provide us with an insight into the current state of these debates, as waged on the other side of the Atlantic. At face value, these two books are quite different from one another. One is a collection of conference papers, the other an introductory text. However, they

This content downloaded on Fri, 8 Feb 2013 05:49:59 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

132

Review Essay

share more in common than these descriptions imply. Both the editor of the collection and the author of the introductory text (who also contributes a paper to the collection) are leading representatives of what they term constructivism, a view about educational research that seems currently to be gaining ground in the USA. This view dominates both these books. One of my purposes in this review, therefore, will be to explore and assess this perspective. The Paradigm Dialog is presented by the editor as an authentic, rather than a sanitised, representation of a conference held in San Francisco in March 1989. Thus, the structure of the book broadly follows the rather complicated organisation of the conference, but the focal point is the division among three paradigms, held to represent the current state of educational research methodology: postpositivism, critical theory, and constructivism. The book opens with a chapter by Guba giving an overview of these paradigms, and this is followed by presentations from representatives of each of them (Phillips, Popkewitz, and Lincoln). The first section concludes with a discussion of the implications of the paradigms for practice (by Eisner). The rest of the book is organised into sections dealing with specific topics relevant to the relationships among the three paradigms: the possibility of accommodation between them, ethics, goodness criteria, implementaion, knowledge accumulation, methodology, training, and values. Within each of these sections there is a main paper, a response to it, and a summary of the main points arising in discussion at the conference. The papers and responses present a variety of views, though the majority seem closest to constructivism. The final section of the book consists of an informal ethnography of the conference by Peshkin, a report from auditors at the conference who were given the responsibility of identifying possible future developments, and some closing reflections by the editor. Having declared his commitment as a constructivist in the opening chapter, at the end Guba expresses the hope that the divisions among the three paradigms can be transcended into a "better informed" and "more sophisticated" meta-paradigm (Guba, 1990, pp. 370-371). This volume suffers from some of the failings of 'authentic' collections of conference papers. One is the considerable uneveness in the quality of the chapters, along with an occasional failure to connect, even in the case of what are supposed to be responses to other papers. There is also a substantial amount of repetition. Each of the presenters in the sections on specific topics seeks to structure her or his discussion in terms of the three paradigms, and as a result they go over some of the same ground, albeit from slightly different angles. This problem is worsened by the fact that many of the topics are very closely related, so that discussion of one inevitably spills over into the others. While this is a much more coherent book than most conference collections, like them its value hangs on the quality of particular papers. For this reason, and for reasons of space, my discussion of it will be very selective [1]. The Nature of Social and Educational Inquiry is an introductory account of the philosophical assumptions implicated in the methodology of social research. It treats these assumptions in terms of a contrast between two approaches or 'logics of justification', variously referred to as empiricism/externalism/objectivism on the one hand, and interpretation/internalism/relativism on the other. The opening chapters introduce these two approaches and sketch some of their history. Subsequent chapters address areas where these approaches are most sharply at odds: the relationship of the investigator to what is investigated; the realtion

This content downloaded on Fri, 8 Feb 2013 05:49:59 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Review Essay

133

between facts and values; the goals of inquiry; and the role of procedures in the inquiry process. The book concludes with the author declaring that it is unlikely that advocates of these two approaches will agree and that "eventually we must somehow 'transcend' this issue and develop new ways to think about the nature of inquiry", but that at present it is impossible to see how this might happen (Smith, 1989, p. 173). Smith's book covers many of the key issues relevant to his theme, and shows a knowledge of, and sensitivity towards, the philosophical literature that is absent from most of the chapters in Guba's collection. It is pitched at a relatively elementary level. However, because it deals with complex issues, readers new to the field may nonetheless find some of it difficult. There is no doubt that, given the degree to which social and educational researchers have become embroiled in philosophical debates about methodology, some such introductory text is required. As will become clear later, I think this book suffers from a fundamental flaw in perspective; but this does not nullify its value. While Guba employs a three-fold division of paradigms and Smith a two-fold one, their two schemes can be easily related to one another. Smith effectively deals with positivism and post-positivism together, and largely ignores critical theory, while his interpretive paradigm is substantially equivalent to Guba's constructivism. Indeed, in his article in Guba's collection Smith uses Guba's typology without apparent distortion of his views. (For convenience, in the remainder of this review I will often refer to positivism/post-positivism as Paradigm 1, construtivism as Paradigm 2, and critical theory as Paradigm 3.) Divisions into methodological paradigms like these are of course by no means new, and these two schemes have close analogues elsewhere. The distinction between Paradigms 1 and 2 is a variation on that between quantitative and qualitative approaches. Indeed, in an earlier formulation of his views Smith employed this terminology (Smith & Heshusius, 1986). His shift to other terms reflects a desire to emphasise that the differences between the paradigms lie not at the level of methods or techniques but rather at that of philosophical assumptions, both about the nature of the social world and about knowledge and the process of inquriy. Both Smith and Guba regard the ambiguity between technical and philosophical levels of the earlier terminology as a problem, and even in The Paradigm Dialog Guba complains that some of the contributors failed to maintain this distinction between levels. Guba's three-fold division also corresponds broadly to that used by Habermas, distinguishing between empirical-analytic sciences, hermeneutical sciences and critical science (Habermas, 1987), a typology that has been widely employed by others [e.g. by Fay (1975) and Bernstein (1976)]. However, the order of presentation, the relative value given to the different paradigms, and some details of their definition, differ in Guba's account. It is worth considering briefly the dangers of such typologies of methodological approach. An obvious one is that they reduce a complex field of variation in perspective and practice to a small number of possibilities. Thus, Smith's typology largely excludes consideration of the critical theory tradition. And even Guba's typology by no means exhausts the range of variation. This can be shown by comparing it with the three-fold division used in a recent book by Alasdair MacIntyre (1990). While MacIntyre is not concerned with social research methodology but with ethics, there is sufficient common ground to make the point.

This content downloaded on Fri, 8 Feb 2013 05:49:59 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

134

Review Essay

MacIntyre's threesome are: the enlightenment or encyclopaedic paradigm; the genealogical paradigm; and the Thomist or natural law paradigm. The first of these corresponds to Guba's and Smith's Paradigm 1. The second is close to Paradigm 2 in some respects, but not in others, as indicated by the fact that Nietzsche and Foucault are taken as exemplars. This highlights the almost complete absence from the two books under review of attention to post-structuralism-it makes a significant appearance in Lather's contribution to Guba's collection and in Grumet's interesting critical response to it, but nowhere else. The third tradition MacIntyre discusses, and which he himself advocates, is entirely missing from Guba and Smith's typologies. This neglect of the natural law tradition is less surprising than that of post-structuralism. But, while it is hardly represented at all within the field of educational research at the moment, at the very least this perspective provides a useful context in which to consider the other paradigms. After all, Paradigm 1 was in large part a reaction against medieval and later natural law theory; and there are interesting similarities and differences between it and Guba's three paradigms, as I will show later [2]. There are other traditions that are neglected in the two books under review. An obvious one, since it has been very influential in the development of social science methodology, is neo-Kantianism. This omission creates distortion in Smith's discussion of Max Weber's views, since he is forced by the framework he adopts to present Weber as straddling Paradigms 1 and 2. While by no means unique to Smith (e.g. Runciman, 1972), this is an interpretation that misconstrues Weber's position in important respects (Burger, 1978; Oakes, 1988). Of course, even an expansion to six paradigms would still not satisfactorily cover the potential, or even the actual, range of methodological views to be found amongst educational and social researchers. Furthermore, Guba's division into three paradigms is built on a rather misleading view of the history of methodological thinking about social research, a point that LeCompte makes in her contribution to the collection. This thinking is portrayed as having been dominated by positivism until recently, with post-positivism, constructivism, and critical theory emerging in the wake of its collapse. However, most of the ideas involved in these three paradigms have been available in one form or another at least since the late nineteenth century. And while it is true that a set of ideas we can call positivism has strongly influenced thinking about social and educational research for much of the twentieth century, these ideas never totally dominated and were subject to a multitude of interpretations. Indeed, there have been important changes not just in the fortunes but also in the content of positivism over the course of the past century. It is treated by these authors as realist and as committed to the hypothetico-deductive method. Yet early in the twentieth century there was a strong element of phenomenalism among positivists, exemplified in the operationist movement. Furthermore, nineteenth century positivists, and some twentieth century ones, were inductivists rather than being advocates of the hypothetico-deductive method. While frameworks of types of approach can certainly be useful, giving us some purchase on a complex field, it is important that their instrumental function be remembered, and that the dangers of omission and oversimplification that they can produce be avoided. In my view both these books suffer from a failure in this respect. For example, Guba states "the reader should never forget that the only alternative to relativism is absolutism" (Guba, 1990, p. 18). While he does not tell

This content downloaded on Fri, 8 Feb 2013 05:49:59 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Review Essay

135

us what 'absolutism' means, we are left in no doubt that it is a bad thing. What it seems to involve is rejection of other views out of hand and the belief that we can gain absolutely certain knowledge about the world. But, of course, relativism is by no means the only alternative to this rather extreme view, unless one defines that term in a way that is so broad as to make it a nonsense, and this broad usage is not the one that Guba uses elsewhere in the book. This sort of slippage in the meaning of terms is characteristic of the Guba collection. Smith's book also illustrates the way that typologies can mislead. At one point he asks: Is social and educational inquiry a matter of the discovery and description of how things really are, or is it a process of constructing realities that depend for their acceptance on considerations of historical time and cultural place? (1989, pp. 2-3) Here again we are apparently faced with just two options, but these hardly represent the range of epistemological views to be found among philosophers. In accepting that the goal of research is to discover the nature of reality, we do not have to deny that any account of that nature is a construction; nor that it will be accepted in particular times and places on the basis of considerations that are taken to be cogent then and there but that are not judged so universally. To paraphrase Shakespeare, quoted by Firestone (Guba, 1990, p. 105), there are more things in philosophy than dreamt of by constructivists. The adequacy of the presentations of the three paradigms in Guba's collection is uneven. Constructivism is introduced by Guba in his opening chapter and elaborated by Lincoln through an autobiographical account. These discussions display a lack of philosophical sophistication, but the accounts provided later in the book by Smith and Schwandt are better. Critical theory is the least well served of the three paradigms, in that neither Guba's opening treatment nor Popkewitz's plenary paper gives much clarification about what it entails. It comes across as constructivism with a harder political edge, but retaining an element of metaphysical realism that constructivists reject. No one else in the volume provides much compensation for this poor treatment. In one respect Paradigm 1 is the best served of all three paradigms in Guba's book. Phillips provides an excellent account of recent developments in the analytical philosophy of science, pointing out that these do not imply the relativism embraced by constructivists. This chapter complements the accounts he has provided elsewhere (Phillips, 1987, 1990). However, the other discussions of positivism and post-positivism in the collection, and (in places) that in Smith's book, border on caricature. Post-positivism is often conflated with positivism, hence my inclusion of both under the head of Paradigm 1. They are portrayed as treating the goal of research as producing representations of a reality that is independent of them and of the researcher, whose validity is absolutely certain, and which are value-free in the sense of being untainted by values. From this point of view, the knowledge produced by research is intrinsically superior to the views of others, the implication being that the latter must simply accept research findings as valid on trust. Yet, it would be difficult to find anyone who holds or held this view. More importantly, contrary to what Guba, Smith, and many of the other contributors imply, it is not the case that one must either accept this position or embrace constructivism (or critical theory).

This content downloaded on Fri, 8 Feb 2013 05:49:59 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

136

Review Essay

Each of the components of Paradigm 1 identified above can be, and often have been, interpreted in much more defensible forms. For instance, to treat research as representing a reality that is independent of the researcher is to set up a mindreality dualism that has all sorts of unacceptable implications, as Smith documents. But this is not necessary to preserve the idea that the goal of research is representation, or to render this goal feasible. All that is necessary is that the phenomena being investigated (not reality as a whole) are causally independent of the researcher, and this is to a large extent generally the case. Similarly, we can, and must, recognise that research never reproduces the phenomena investigated, producing some one true account of them. Rather, it is selective, according to the particular focus and set of purposes motivating the research. But, once again, we can accept this without undercutting the prospect of accurate representation (Hammesley, 1992a, Chapters 1 and 4). And, as regards belief in the possibility of knowledge whose validity is certain, while there are those who have adopted this assumption, notably Descartes, it has been rejected by most analytic philosophers of science, most obviously in the fallibilism of Peirce and Popper. It is not essential to Paradigm 1, at least not in its post-positivistic form. The issue of value neutrality is the one where there is the most confusion. What needs to be made clear here, and it is a scandal that it is so widely misunderstood, is that this concept does not imply that research could or should be free from the influence of values, contrary to what some contributors to the Guba volume assume, including Lincoln and House. As used by its originator, Max Weber, the term refers to the principle that value judgements should not be presented as if they have been or could be scientifically validated, that researchers should seek to minimise the influence of their views about how things ought to be on their factual judgements about how they are, and that the main business of research should be the production of factual rather than value conclusions. Weber did not deny the influence of values on research findings, nor did he believe that their influence was always deleterious. Indeed, it was recognition of that influence and its complexity that led him to propose that social research should strive to be both value relevant and value neutral, and to claim that an important function of it is value clarification. To his credit, in his book Smith provides an account of Weber's views on this issue that is more accurate than many. But because he sees Weber as trying to reconcile Paradigms 1 and 2, he comes to the erroneous conclusion that value relevance is in conflict with value neutrality (Smith, 1989, p. 56), whereas they are complementary. He also fails to realise the commonality between his constructivism and Weber's position: the latter is founded on the principle of value relativism. Finally, Smith cannot seem to decide whether his argument is that values determine facts (which presupposes a distinction between the two) or that no reasonable distinction can be made. It is largely because of this that he finds Weber's views contradictory. For Weber, facts and values are distinct but there can be no idiographic knowledge without values. Indeed, there could be no knowledge at all without commitment to the value of truth. Not all proponents of Paradigm 1 have upheld the principle of value neutrality as developed by Weber, and adherence to the principle has not prevented value bias. But neither of these facts undermines the validity of the principle. Let me turn now to Paradigm 2, the alternative proposed by Smith, Guba, and some of the other contributors to Guba's collection. It is a distinctive feature of

This content downloaded on Fri, 8 Feb 2013 05:49:59 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Review Essay

137

this position that the various approaches to educational research identified are not treated as representing merely different tendencies, but rather as incommensurable paradigms. In other words, these approaches are logically coherent positions founded on incompatible assumptions about the nature of the social world and of social inquiry. These assumptions are presumed to prescribe the whole character of research within the relevant paradigm. Thus, Lincoln claims that: The adoption of a paradigm literally permeates every act even tangentially associated with inquiry, such that any consideration even remotely attached to inquiry processes demands rethinking to bring decisions into line with the worldview embodied in the paradigm itself. (Guba, 1990, p.

81)
And Smith takes much the same view (1989, p. 5). A direct implication of this position is relativism, and both Guba and Smith explictly adopt that epistemological position. However, they vary in their apparent awareness of its implications, and in my view neither of them, nor any of their fellow constructivists, recognises the true nature of the labyrinth that they have entered. One obvious way of addressing the issues raised in these books is to ask: which of the three paradigms is the correct one? Yet, while both Guba and Smith adhere to constructivism, neither is able to, nor claims to, establish its superiority. This is reasonably clear from the language that they use. Thus, Smith declares that he finds Paradigm 2 "more satisfying" (1989, p. 3), while Guba states that he "has his own preference, for constructivism" (1990, p. 17). This is not a matter of false modesty or of practically contingent failure on the part of these authors, leaving the possibility of the superiority of Paradigm 2 being established on some future occasion. It arises because establishing the superiority of that paradigm is impossible in principle. This results from the well-known fact, noted by Smith, that relativism is self-refuting (1989, p. 168). Relativism is a position which in denying that there is any meta-paradigmatic level at which the truth of paradigms can be determined, even in principle, thereby itself surreptitiously makes a meta-paradigmatic claim. One result of this is ambivalence on the part of constructivists towards the concept of reality. On the one hand, they regard reality as constructed by people on the basis of their paradigmatic assumptions. On the other, they recognise that such realities are multiple and thereby presuppose a larger reality within which these various constructed realities have a place, the task of the researcher being to document this larger reality. Thus, we find constructivists vacillating between two incompatible positions: A. The first states that there is only one reality, that which is constructed by one's own paradigm. There can be no overarching reality containing other paradigms because there is no meta-paradigmatic level. The world simply is how it appears to be, or how it can be construed to be on the basis of one's paradigmatic assumptions. Even if someone could step out of one paradigm into another, that would not allow her or him to engage in any relating of the one to the other. Using the analogy of the well-known optical illusion, either the faces are there or the vase is there, not both. B. The second position proposes that constructivism alone provides an accurate

This content downloaded on Fri, 8 Feb 2013 05:49:59 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

138

Review Essay

account of reality. But in doing so it operates at a meta-paradigmatic level: what it claims is that the world is made up of groups of people with very different perspectives. Furthermore, these are constructions not reflections
of some independent reality; and insofar as they do not contradict constructivism

they are all true in their own terms. Guba moves between these two positions without any apparent awareness that they are in conflict. Thus, operating on the basis of Position B, he declares that: ... there are many paradigms that we use in guiding our actions: the adversarial paradigm that guides the legal system, the judgmental paradigm that guides the selection of Olympic winners, the religious paradigms that guide spiritual and moral life, and many others. (1990, p. 18) And, as we have seen, he also identifies three paradigms relating to educational research. Here he seems to be standing above all the paradigms and surveying them from outside. Furthermore, he states that the purpose of the conference on which his book is based was "to legitimate the two contenders not now enjoying
hegemony, by demonstrating that their positions are at least as reasonable and useful as those of either positivism or post-positivism (1990, p. 9, emphasis added). Clearly, this

claim is intended to be a general truth, not just a statement of what constructivists believe; otherwise the argument would be circular. At other times, Guba adopts Position A. Thus, before presenting his survey of the three paradigms of educational research he comments: I recognise that what I am about to say is my own construction,not necessarily an objective(whatever that may be) analysis. Indeed, as we shall see, constructivists not only abjure objectivity but celebrate subjectivity. (1990, p. 17) This passage is representative of much of the writing in the Guba volume in its lack of clarity. In one sentence Guba denies knowing what objectivity is, only to treat the meaning of the term as obvious in the next. And notice that he does not say that his construction is not objective, only that it is not necessarilyobjective; yet who would claim that their accounts are necessarily objective? Even so, it would seem that Guba recognises here that constructivism, in the form of Position A, does not allow him to claim that his account of the other paradigms, even of their existence, .is anything more than his own paradigm-relative perspective. Perhaps this recognition is also the reason why Lincoln argues that researchers should be trained in a single paradigm not multiple paradigms (Guba, 1990, p. 87); whereas Reinharz, perhaps influenced by Position B, goes in the other direction, advocating that students be encouraged to invent their own paradigms (Guba, 1990, p. 300). The same tension between incompatible positions is found in Smith's book. Early on, he states that: ... even though this author finds the interpretive perspective more satisfying, the intent is much less to advocate one perspective over another than it is to present as straightforward a discussion as possible of the underlying issues involved in this discussion (1989, p. 3) Given that the paradigms are incommensurable (that is assuming Position A), how can Smith present a straightforward discussion that does not advocate one side or the other? Any discussion would be premissedon the validity of one or other of the

This content downloaded on Fri, 8 Feb 2013 05:49:59 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Review Essay

139

paradigms. Of course, if Smith were to accept Paradigm 1 the paradigms would not be incommensurable and he could do this. But if he is a constructivist he cannot! And he does not. While his book has an even-handed appearance, it implicitly advocates the interpretive perspective. The pattern almost throughout is a presentation of the objectivist view, followed by an account of the criticisms directed at this view by interpretivists and their own positive proposals. It is only in the last chapter that we are given any hint of the criticisms that objectivists make of the interpretivist position, and then only briefly [3]. Another illustration of this commitment to conflicting positions is the assumption of both Guba and Smith that paradigms can be criticised in terms of their internal consistency [see Guba (1990, p. 373) and Smith's criticism of Weber for being contradictory (Smith, 1989, p. 95)]. This would be possible from Position B, if consistency were a defining criterion built into the concept of paradigm. However, it is not a legitimate criterion from the point of view of Position A. For the consistent relativist it is no more possible to justify consistency as a paradigmtranscendent criterion than any other! It may be that the three paradigms under consideration share a commitment to consistency, but it is quite possible that others do not, and constructivists cannot rule these out. But in any case, from a Position A point of view, it is not likely, or perhaps even possible, that 'consistency' will have an equivalent meaning within different paradigms. Much the same applies to the hopes of the two authors that the paradigm disputes can be transcended. Relativism rules this out since transcendence implies paradigmneutral criteria of judgement. This vacillation between the two positions is understandable, since each of them has troublesome implications. If the first is true it is only true from a constructivist point of view and is false from the point of view of Paradigm 1, and we have no way of adjudicating between these two perspectives. Even from the point of view of constructivism, those committed to Paradigm 1 may quite legitimately continue to regard their research as directed towards understanding the nature of social reality from an objective perspective, and even claim to have achieved this. The very idea of representatives of the paradigms engaging in debate with one another, on which the Guba collection is founded, is ruled out by Position A. There is no possibility of it, and no need for it. The second position avoids these problems, but only at the cost of constructivists having to try to show that their account and judgements of the positions currently adopted by educational researchers is superior to that of the other paradigms. Yet constructivism provides no resources for such epistemological justification. Indeed, it denies that very possibility. It may seem that my criticisms of the accuracy of Smith's and Guba's accounts of Paradigms 1 and 2 are open to question on the general grounds that their validity is relative to my own paradigmatic assumptions. But even from a constructivist point of view this would only be true for constructivists. Since I am not a constructivist, it is not true for me, even from a constructivist point of view! Put another way, if constructivist relativism is true it is true only within the framework of constructivism. Hence, beyond that framework truth is not relative, so that the validity of my arguments is not relative to my paradigm. Constructivists may be in a hall of mirrors, but the rest of us do not have to join them. Over and above its epistemological self-destructiveness, there are other, practical, reasons for rejecting constructivism. The most important is that it logically

This content downloaded on Fri, 8 Feb 2013 05:49:59 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

140

Review Essay

excludes its adherents from engaging in the normal process of social research. Lather seems to take this view the furthest, quoting Said to the effect that social science should forget itself and become something else (Guba, 1990, p. 315). But it seems implicit in some of the other contributions too. The conventional view is that social and educational research is concerned with documenting not just people's perspectives but also their actions, for example reporting the ways in which powerful groups structure the situations in which the less powerful live. Taken to its logical conclusion, constructivism rules out any such investigation. The point of origin of constructivism is the denial that research accounts can be in any sense more valid than those of participants. And the constructivist adaptation to this is to redefine the goal of research as the documentation of participant perspectives, and to redefine truth in terms of respondent validation. In LeCompte's words (Guba, 1990, p. 252), the educational researcher is turned into a folklorist or collector of stories. In practice, of course, constructivists may be selective in how they apply their ideas, seeking to document the perspectives of underdogs, but describing the activities of overdogs in ways that the latter would not accept. But there is no principle built into constructivism that would allow or justify that selectivity. Worse than this, though, this version of constructivism does not avoid the problem of representation, it simply transposes it to another level: that between the researcher's account and the accounts of participants. And once we recognise that the researcher's account of participants' accounts is itself only a construction, the full implications become clear. The obvious questions that arise are: Why should policy-makers and practitioners take any notice of research? Why should anyone fund it? Indeed, why should students be educated in one or other or any paradigm? Up to now I have been concerned with the epistemological aspects of constructivism and their implications. While important, these are probably not the driving force behind it. It is not simply a scientific paradigm. At its heart is a rejection of truth, however defined, as the goal of inquiry. What is to be put in its place is some conception of the political good life. Smith declares that the regulative ideal of constructivism is solidarity (Guba, 1990, p. 179), appealing to the work of Rorty (1985); though neither he nor Rorty is clear about exactly what this entails, with whom researchers should (and should not?) seek solidarity, why this value should be taken as pre-eminent, or why it should be the particular concern of educational researchers. What seems to be involved, for constructivists like Lincoln at least, is an extension of commitment to equality, so that within educational research all voices must be treated as equal, and such research must be directed towards achieving equal representation for all voices in society. This certainly implies a dramatic reorientation of educational and social research, yet there is little supporting argument provided to convince those of us who believe that this is an over-extension of the concept of equality, and who regard equality as only one of several important values by which public and private life should be governed. And, as we have seen, ironically, the relativist character of constructivism rules out the possibility of such dialogue. This value commitment of constructivism brings it quite close to that of some forms of critical theory, but in other respects Paradigms 2 and 3 are quite different. I mentioned earlier the poor treatment of critical theory in the Guba volume. Neither Popkewitz nor any of the other contributors relate it to its Marxist and Hegelian background (indeed one participant at the conference

This content downloaded on Fri, 8 Feb 2013 05:49:59 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Review Essay

141

apparently complained that Marxism had been absent, see Guba, 1990, p. 362). Without that background it is impossible to recognise that Paradigm 3 does represent a quite coherent and distinctive position, instead of an eclectic and incoherent synthesis of elements from the other two paradigms. Of course, spelling out that background immediately reveals some assumptions, for instance of history, that are difficult to defend, about the teleological development and post-structuralist relativism (Hammerin a climate of constructivist especially It for this reason that advocates of this position is Ch. 6). perhaps sley, 1992a, down that background, apparently seeking the social science equivalent today play of the alchemist's formula: a position that is both relativistic and 'critical' [4]. And there are signs in the constructivist camp of such ambitions too, notably in the chapter by Lincoln where she lists empowerment as one of the criteria by which case studies should be judged (Guba, 1990, p. 74). However, it should be obvious that the labyrinthine character of relativism rules out any possibility of a critique that anybody who does not accept the assumptions of the critics needs to take seriously. Ultimately, all the relativist can say is that, for example, the beliefs of racists and sexists may be true in their own terms but are not true from her or his perspective. This hardly seems a strong basis for concerted political action [5]. It also implies that there is little scope for reasoned argument in politics; resolution of conflict by coercion seems the only likely solution. At this point, we might usefully try to sum up what seem to be the main options that social researchers face. Earlier I mentioned the natural law tradition. That tradition holds that rational and universally valid knowledge is possible about value issues. From this point of view science is not restricted to the factual domain. At the same time, rational inquiry is held to be founded on faith. Guba's three paradigms each accept some parts of this but reject others: Paradigm 1 rejects reliance on faith in favour of the possibility of sound, universally valid knowledge on the basis of rational inquiry alone, but only in the factual domain. Neo-Kantianism also falls into this category [6]. Paradigm 2 rejects the possibility of universally valid knowledge in either domain (indeed, the distinction between the two may be abandoned). All knowledge is the product of inquiry that takes some set of founding assumptions on faith. Paradigm 3 historicises natural law theory, retaining the possibility of rational universally valid knowledge of both factual and value matters, but regards this as only becoming available through a process of historical development into which the potential for realising it, and a society based on it, is built. In my judgement, this typology gives a more accurate view of the general philosophical positions that are available to educational researchers than does that around which the Guba volume is organised; though of course it carries the dangers associated with any typology, which I outlined earlier. All four positions suffer from serious problems that need to be addressed. In my judgement Paradigm 1 remains the most promising, but this is by no means to deny that much can be learned from the others. I suspect that for many readers of this review the question will have arisen as to whether these philosophical debates have any practical implications for educational research. Can they not be left to the philosophers? As we have seen, Guba and Smith think not. They do so on the grounds of what has been referred to as

This content downloaded on Fri, 8 Feb 2013 05:49:59 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

142

Review Essay

methodological holism-the idea that researchers' philosophical and practical assumptions form, or should form, a coherent whole with the first determining the second. As Firestone points out in his contribution to the Guba volume, this view is not accurate empirically nor does it represent a desirable ideal. Philosophical assumptions do not have strongly determinate implications for how we should carry out research, nor are they a privileged starting point. The experience of doing research is just as likely legitimately to throw doubt on our philosophical assumptions as reflection on those assumptions is likely to change our research practices. For these reasons I do not believe that philosophical issues are as significant for the practice of educational research as Guba and Smith do. At the same time, it would be foolish to ignore the fact that there is at least one area of dispute that does have major implications for practice. The question here is: What is the goal of educational research? How one answers that question has dramatic implications for how one goes about research; indeed for whetherone engages in research at all. These books raise that question, but the constructivist answer towards which they suggest many educational researchers in the USA are moving is not one that bodes well for the future. While both Guba and Smith express hopes for peaceful transcendence of paradigms, constructivism seems to imply that the wars can only go on. Martyn Hammersley, School of Education, The Open University, Correpondence: Milton Keynes MK7 6AA, UK. NOTES
[1] It is worth comparing this volume with another recently published conference collection in the same area, edited by two of the contributors to this one and involving some of the others (Eisner & Peshkin, 1990). This collection covers some of the same topics (subjectivity and objectivity, validity, ethics, the uses of qualitative research), as well as one that is not dealt with in the Guba volume, generalisability. Here also there is some unevenness, though in myjudgement the quality overall is somewhat higher than in the Guba collection (Hammersley, 1992b). Taken together these two volumes give an impression of very considerable diversity in methodological perspective among US educational researchers. [2] In fact, rather misleadingly, Schwandt treats MacIntyre's position as constructivist in his contribution to the Guba volume (p. 268). Smith draws on Leo Strauss's criticisms of Weber (Smith, 1989, p. 95), but without any indication of the direction from which those criticisms come. [3] Smith's treatment of the three paradigms in his article in the Guba collection is more evenhanded. Here he does give equal mention to others' criticisms of constructivism. In that chapter the balance seems to be tipped towards Position B, but still without the dilemma being resolved. [4] This eclectic mixture is also to be found in Apple and Roman's contribution to the Eisner and Peshkin volume. [5] This is a point that has been recognised by some feminists in their responses to post-structuralism, as Lather notes (Guba, 1990, pp. 319-320); though she does not seem to recognise the intractability of the problem. [6] There are a few advocates of this paradigm who believe that values can be based on science. For a discussion, see Keat (1981).

REFERENCES
BERNSTEIN, R. (1976) Pennsylvania Press). The Restructuring of Social and Political Theory (Philadelphia, University of

This content downloaded on Fri, 8 Feb 2013 05:49:59 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Review Essay

143

BURGER, T. (1978) Max Weber'sTheoryof ConceptFormation(Durham, North Carolina, Duke University Press). A. (Eds) (1990) Qualitative Inquiry:the continuing debate (New York, Teachers E. & PESHKIN, EISNER, College Press). FAY,B. (1975) Social Theoryand Political Practice(London, Allen and Unwin). N. (1989) The paradigm wars and their aftermath: a "historical" sketch of research on teaching GAGE, since 1989, EducationalResearcher,18, pp. 4-10. HABERMAS, J. (1987) Knowledgeand Human Interests(Cambridge, Polity Press). M. (1992a) What's Wrongwith Ethnography? HAMMERSLEY, (London, Routledge). M. (1992b) Review of Eisner and Peshkin, InternationalJournal of Qualitative Studies in HAMMERSLEY, Education (forthcoming). R. (1981) The Politics of Social Theory(Oxford, Blackwell). KEAT, A. (1990) ThreeRival Versionsof Moral Enquiry (London, Duckworth). MACINTYRE, OAKES,G. (1988) Weber and Rickert: conceptformation in the cultural sciences (Cambridge, Mass., Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press). D. (1987) Philosophy,Scienceand Social Inquiry (Oxford, Pergamon). PHILLIPS,
PHILLIPS, D. (1990) Subjectivity and objectivity: an objective inquiry, in E. EISNER & A. PESHKIN(Eds)

Qualitative Inquiry:the continuing debate(New York, Teachers College Press). R. (1985) Solidarity or objectivity?, in: J. RAJCHMAN & C. WEST(Eds) Post-AnalyticPhilosophy RORTY, (New York, Columbia University Press). W.G. (1972) A Critique of Max Weber'sPhilosophy of Science (Cambridge, Cambridge RUNCIMAN, University Press). L. (1986) Closing Down the Conversation: the end of the quantitativeSMITH, J.K. & HESHUSIUS, qualitative debate among educational inquirers, EducationalResearcher,15, 1, pp. 4-12. A. (1982) BeyondEmpiricism(London, Routledge and Kegan Paul). TUDOR,

This content downloaded on Fri, 8 Feb 2013 05:49:59 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Anda mungkin juga menyukai