Anda di halaman 1dari 25

The Sublime and the Grotesque in Romantic Drama Language Forum, Vol. 27, No. 1-2, Jan.-Dec.

2001, New Delhi, India Abstract

The verse dramas of the early romantic period have recently been reconsidered for their significance in reorienting our approaches to drama and performance. This article highlights the closet dramas of the early British romantics as a subversive and ideological genre which has inspired radical experimentalists in the field of dramatic theory and practice. In spite of the old argument that these plays have no performance potentialities of their own, new readings of them suggest that the early romantics were in search of new forms to challenge the established norms of mimesis in drama. It is maintained that their exploitation of the sublime and the grotesque as devices for such a challenge was rooted in their faith in science, on the one hand, and in their strategy of subverting the prevailing norms of perception, on the other. It has also been argued that these devices were the necessary consequences of dramas which meant to portray disoriented people who were the first victims of a society that was heading towards economic liberalism, a society that glorified energy and, at the same time, was shocked by the terrors it inflicted on the bodies involved.

The Sublime and the Grotesque in Romantic Drama

Arn. Do you - dare you To taunt me with born deformity? Str. Were I to taunt a buffalo with this Cloven foot of thine, or the swift dromedary With thy sublime of humps, the animals Would revel in the compliment. ... ...Thy form is natural: `t was only Natures mistaken largess to bestow The gifts which are of others upon man.1 (The Deformed Transformed, I, i, 100-112)

Milton, it will be remembered, has given a clouded moon to paradise itself. Wordsworth2 ...confusion...can likewise serve as a representation of the supersensuous and supply the mind with upward impetus... . Schiller 3

We have known the early romantics mainly as poets and not as dramatists. Contemporary theatrics has only recently acknowledged its debt to the early romantics contributions in this field. Research in the last three decades has suggested that their dramas, invigorated by a language that had to be artificial, subversive, and socially informed, attempted to interpret the universe as a phenomenon basically founded in chaos and incomprehensibility rather than in a divinely ordained teleology4 It has also been laid down that they retreated from representation to higher performative levels such as parody, romance, farce and grotesque. This paper tries to establish the scene to view the early romantics verse (closet) dramas -- a drama that happens primarily in language and/or in the mind -- as prototypes of contemporary theatres. The early romantics were bent on undermining the hegemonic discourse(s) of power which was beginning to solidify itself in more concrete institutions. They felt the need for subversive dramatic strategies to unravel the power-body mechanisms of their age; contemporary dramatists such as Artaud, Grotowsky or Beckett, among others, never overlooked their legacy. It might sound strange that while this papers concern is body/politics, closet dramas which were primarily written to be read should be foregrounded. The truth of

the matter is that the romantics were highly conscious of dramatic form as a sociopolitical medium. We should also bear in mind that the term closet does not mean their dramas were unperformable; it may also suggest a kind of rear-guard attack in a society which was beginning to be afflicted with commercial theatres. In other words, closet drama might as well suggest a kind of drama written for another age which was ready to break the ground and move away from theatre to performance.

The romantic verse drama occurs within language. Language is thus a scene which must ingest gestures and language resonances to put the body in a relational situation between internal and external spaces. This type of drama, to borrow Sartres remark, makes the whole world a part of language...the horizons, the obscure forces which work within us and outside us.5 At the same time, we know that romantic irony considers language a structured, rational system that by its very nature cannot capture or articulate the unstructured and chaotic.6 Thus, language can only be considered as an index registering interactions between the triangle of space(s), energy, and the body. Such relationships demand a mode of perception which, as language becomes the instrument through which the internal voice/ energy bends the dimensions of space and body, can manifest itself in a more material way. A close study of Shelley's The Cenci (1819) or Byron's The Two Foscari (1821) and The Deformed Transformed (1822) or Wordsworth's only play, The Borderers (17967), suggests that in all of these plays body is the locus on which energy hinges as we watch power either (re)inscribe body or itself challenged by the body. The dramas of the romantics is an arena in which the rules of mimesis are allegorically questioned by having the individual and the institutions de-scribe and (re)inscribe power on the body, respectively. Speculating on the body and expressing sympathy with the outcast and the victim of brutal judgment were rooted in the French Revolution and its campaign for slave emancipation.7 It also became a part of the dramaturgy of the romantics. It is in the nature of power to theatricalise and/or legitimize itself. This also was the lesson disseminated to society by those who created the reign of terror in France. Therefore, as

institutions of power tried to parcel the body of the dispossessed and their spaces out into non-existence, the dramas of romantic poets revived social and symbolic topographies by having their characters participate in a program of rethinking of [their] bodies and [their] visions.8 Coleridges Alvar in Remorse and Shelleys Beatrice in The Cenci are two instances of such characters who try to relocate their bodies. Optimistic as Coleridge was, and unlike Wordsworth, Shelley, or Byron, whose revolutionary reflections take tragic turns in their plays,9 he has Alvar re-claim his body, while in Shelley's The Cenci and in Byron's The Two Foscari, the bodies of the protagonists get eliminated. This process of the body cast out and/or reclaimed is a common experience among the early romantic playwrights. Francis Barker identifies this as a powermechanism which used to exclude the dispossessed and/or make use of them. It matures in L`age classique and is consummated in the nineteenth century with the global triumph of the bourgeois class.
10

The romantics verse dramas are strong socio-political

comments on the plights of a society disturbed and disoriented by some such socioeconomic catastrophes consequent on the rise of economic liberalism.11 And it was the theatrical representation of such ordeals that forced the romantics to look for new devices to enable them to foreground the complex manifestations of power/energy on body and space. A representation of this kind which highlighted body-power relations chose to contravene the tenets of the established theatre of the time by propounding sublime and grotesque elements in the realm of perception. This call for change also came from another quarter: interest in science in general and in optics in particular.

In the sphere of science which manifested itself in the workings of energy and body, Frankenstein, among others, puts forth the polemics of an age concerned with change and transformation by focusing on body. This novel has several undercurrents12 but, generally speaking, it can be viewed as a preoccupation with energy empowering man to capture the so far uncaptured realms of mind and body. One of the first preoccupations of Victor, the Swiss prodigy in Frankenstein, is power. The morning after a thunder strikes an oak, he visits the tree and beholds that it was not splintered by the shock, but entirely reduced to thin ribands of wood. He then so casually mentions: I never beheld anything so utterly destroyed. To further our knowledge of his peculiar nature -- which runs parallel to the workings of nature -- victor explains how a man of great research who is, like Victor, excited by this catastrophe tries to acquaint him with the more obvious laws of electricity, and enters on the explanation of a theory which he had formed on the subject of electricity and galvanism, which was at once new and astonishing to me.13 Victor, the embodiment of the scientist-demon-hero of the Renaissance modernity, is not an accidental fictitious character molded by a distempered brain, but a natural, and evidently ultimate, consequence of a new mode of perception that conceived the universe as a flux of energy and as the overriding agent in any operations in nature, a tendency which can be described as a strong longing for a new form of humanity.14 Before Mary Shelley, it was Wordsworth who acknowledged his faith in a new Being who could serve as a dear and genuine inmate of the household of man15 if man could familiarize himself with science.

This thirst for relating energy to the workings of the mind and the body had great enticement for Coleridge. In a letter to Henry Crabb Robinson (7 Dec., 1812), he requests him to procure for him the perusal of Goethes work on Light & Color.16 What interests him in this work is Goethes idea that light is the source of energy and motion. Later, in his Notebooks (Aug. 1818), he identifies five powers to have plus/minus features: ...,there are five distinct Powers, Gravitation, Light, Magnetism, Electricity, and Galvanism... . Each of the 5 have two Poles, or antithetic forces, + and -, or posi- and nega- tive. Grav.= centrifugal & centripetal = - and + light, colorific and calorific = - and. + Magnetism, attractive and repulsive = - and + Electr.- contractive and dilative = - and + Galvanism, separative & constructive = - and + These are the Pythagoreans.17 cosmical Decad of the

Thus Coleridges acquaintance with light as energy with the intensifying heat at one end of the spectrum and the intensifying darkness at the other end18 had great consequences in his theory of perception. His use of light and darkness can best be illustrated in his play Remorse where he stages extreme darkness with extreme light, a cinematic technique which is of a high theatrical value. This new mythology gained force as the matter-based physics of the eighteenth century began to give way to the energy-based physics of the nineteenth century.19 If science expanded its realm to cover the mind, then the polarities of electricity, magnetism, galvanism had to inform the construction of mind and matter.20 Goethe argued that all of us have some electrical and magnetic forces within us; and we put

forth, like the magnet itself, an attractive or repulsive power, as we come in contact with something similar or dissimilar.21 His praise for Napoleon best illustrates this new faith: to Goethe, he was a man endowed at every hour with energy.22 Byron, Shelley, and Keats had their own preoccupations with energy and matter/body. Harmony, framework, and structure are but known codes in the discourse of order. On the other hand, energy-based perception affects the classical notion of framed and fixed or bounded ideas or substances. In Romanticism, observes Gilbertson, boundaries cease to be the immovable partitions between discrete substances, the walls by which man determines his order and security among the categories of existence.23 Byron, however, by trespassing these boundaries, subscribes to a disorderly order not to affirm chaos but to accentuate change that has a different set of codes. Byron, as Garber observes, does not choose to stand against chaos but to stand with it, to give it a fertilizing role in an encompassing scheme.24 His play, Sardanapalus (1821), in which a king decides not to rule exploits the codes of a universe informed by the tenets of a chaos rather than order. Landscape or space, for instance, in his works -- especially in Childe Harold and Don Juan -- points to the polarities of energy: one extreme showing agonized, corrupted, and spoiled nature -- nature elevated to the level of human history as chaos, the other showing a Dionysian, innocent, and fertile nature -- nature considered as sublime. Shelleys interest in energy can be traced in his concern with music. Not only is the transforming world a music that dissolves strain, but also, as he elaborates on the role of language in A Defence, energy manifests itself best in language and the energy latent in it. The huge machination of violence and atrocity, for instance, evoked in his

play, The Cenci(1819), is done through a vibrating language the resonances of which create bold outlines of the bodies which are either subjected to violence or subject others to it Keats, on the other hand, has always been known for his non-kinetic imagery describing moments prolonged by the play of imagination. In a letter to George and Georgiana Keats, he celebrates the latent energy in life as an Electric fire in human nature tending to purify - so that among these human creatures there is continually some birth of new heroism.25 His craze for the concrete world is proverbial and this mesmerized attitude towards objects poses him in sharp contrast with Byron and Shelley mainly because Keats solidifies the transient moments into static pictures, or rather immortalizes objects, whereas Shelley, for instance, lets his eyes run with the flow of the world. Yet Keats' method is another mode of creating tension by concentrating so much energy in objects that their familiarity disappears. Thus poetic objects threaten our secure world as he prolongs the length of perception whereby habit is replaced by desire. Keats idea of an oscillatory and oscillating mind is central to the discussion at hand. The germinal cause of the gothic (not in its modern popular sense which, in Coxs words, supports institutionalized power),26 of the romantic sublime, and of the grotesque, is an oscillatory mind which, like a champion of a non-despotic empire, always breaks through systems associated with power, determinism, fanaticism. Such a mind prefers self-imposed subjection to half-truths to prepare the ground for change. Energy-based science was destined to have a direct impact on perception. The early romantics propounded seeing as an agency-acquiring power. To them, beholding, not passive on-looking, is a means in their long-term strategy of overcoming mimesis and

the psychology pertinent to it. It is evident in Keats and Charles Browns play Otho the Great where Ludolph says:27 When I close These lids, I see far fiercer brilliances,Skies full of splendid moons, and shooting stars, And panting fountains quivering with deep glows. ( V, v, 43-47 )

Here conventional seeing is contravened; the eye -- a different eye -- becomes the executive agent of the oscillating mind. It is this new organ that establishes a dome in Xanadu or, when bestowed to an Ancient Mariner, disorients the fact-oriented young man and creates polarity in the monotonous rhythms of a routine life. It is this fascination with the eye which is directly related to the early romantics preoccupation with the grotesque and the sublime which, in turn, affected romantic theatrics. Their achievement in this field gave rise to bi-focal perception which, as a theatrical means, has had a great impact on drama in general and on performance in particular. Among the British romantics European counterparts, Goethes contribution to bi-focality is remarkable. In response to empirical psychology that assumes our senses as passive recipients of external impressions, Goethe, establishes the idea of opposition between the external world and our senses. Goethe asserts that colours produced in our perception may be seeing colours produced by the eye itself. ...28 To enlighten Eckermann, he says that our eye works according to the law of required change perhaps to harmonize itself with our higher spiritual nature.29Fascinated by Goethes Theory of Colors, Eckermann comes across yet another of Goethes laws which is relevant to the law of required change:

On a clear winters day, and in the sunlight, the shadows cast upon the snow frequently appear blue. This is classed by Goethe,..., under the subjective phenomena: for he assumes as a principle that the sunlight comes down to us not perfectly white; but, penetrating through an atmosphere more or less misty, yellowish: so that the snow, when the sun shines upon it, is not perfectly white, but tinged with yellow, which charms the eye to opposition production of blue. The blue shadow is, according to this view, a demanded colour. ...30 This was in accord with Coleridges theory of perception. Goethes effort to explain sensory perception as the link between subjective quality and objective quantity31 paved the way, in Burwicks words, to a literary fascination with the dream-vision and the trance.32 This looked more like the conspiracy of the senses to establish their own visionary republic in which the material world is re-fused according to a high degree of autonomy. This he further emphasizes by referring us to Kants notion of time and space. In a letter to Pryce (April, 1818), he praises Kants merit as a man who proved that Space and Time were 1, neither general terms, 2. nor abstractions from Things, 3. nor Things themselves; but, 4. the pure a priori forms of the intuitive faculty... . They are the acts of the perceptive powers of which all particular acts of perception are modifications & c.33 If time and space are subjective entities within the subject, then perception which must always be of things in space -- real or imaginary, static or dynamic -- is subject to the momentum or synchronic potentialities of the subject. Perhaps when Byron in his poem, The Dream(1816), says, ...- The mind can make / Substance, and people planets of its own / With beings brighter than have been, and give/A breath to forms which can outlive all flesh.(I, 19-22), he, too, celebrates this autonomy of the mind that creates its

10

own tyranny of pleasure and pain, (I, 14) because the mind expands its territory in dreams and this distorts the present. As perception expands its scope, our being divides, and thus, as the compound eye divides transversely, the focal point is -- if not lost -- blurred, displaced, or softened. This is irresistible to Goethe who was bent towards classicism. Goethe shows Eckermann a lithograph done by Delacroix, a scene from Faust showing Mephistopheles and Faust on their way to free Margareta from prison. Eckermanns account of the picture is absorbing enough to be quoted here at length: They ride so fast that Faust can scarcely keep his seat; the wind has blown off his cap, which fastened by straps about his neck, flies far behind him. He has turned his fearful inquiring face to Mephistopheles, to whom he listens. Mephistopheles, on the contrary, sits undisturbed, like a being of a higher order: he rides no living horse, for he loves not what is living; indeed, he does not need it, for his will moves him with the swiftness he requires. He has a horse... that is a mere bag of bones... . It is of a bright colour, and seems to be phosphorescent in the darkness of night. It is neither bridled nor saddled. The supernatural rider sits easily and negligently, with his face turned towards Faust in conversation. The opposing element of air does not exist for him; neither he nor his horse feels anything of it. Not a hair of either is stirred.34 Eckermann is puzzled over Delacroixs art because he has made no figure like another, but in each expressed some different part of the action.35 Goethe, it seems, is having Ekermann understand bi-focality, a tendency central to romantic imagination. A more brilliant passage on this same idea of de-centralization in works of art can be found in another of Goethes essays. In discussing Leonardos The Last Supper

11

he maintains that the artist, by dividing Christs devotees in groups of three, has given more energy to the sides, leaving the centre almost empty. He then concludes if centre is emptied or not accented, attention is concentered on the sides36 which can stimulate our imagination. No wonder, then, that Keats citizens on the Grecian Urn are emptying the town, Byrons Don Juan and Childe Harold set out for a new life, leaving behind their centres of family and tribe, Sardanapalus sheds the corrupt monarchy of his predecessors by setting his castle ablaze to lesson the ages, Shelleys Prometheus sides with an unbound growth to be materialized beyond the boundaries of a determined order/centre, and, finally, a group of men oscillate between the borders of Scotland and England in Wordsworths The Borderers. It is this legacy which has strengthened the epic element in modern drama. The early romantics were among the forerunners of those dramatists who, by accentuating fragmentation of plot, exploiting scenic methods of presentation and inclining towards polyphony, are more intimate with contemporary dramatists. This tipping over, this centrifugal or eddying movement has its unique consequences. In the realm of the self one tends to be a negotiator with, if not an annihilator of, its rigidity, a thing so crucial in the theatre of contradictions. Socially or politically, one is apt to believe in a positive antagonism. And aesthetically, when one shies away from the centre, one tends to deviate from the norms of beauty which are usually centralized. Trespassing the boundaries of the received forms and norms, we are at the threshold of the terrible, the awful, the boundless, and the ugly - all but names for what has come to be called the sublime; which, in turn, widens the chasm between the eddying self and the normal society.

12

The role that Schiller assigns to the sublime in mans life is one of overcoming violence in nature. It manifests itself realistically or idealistically. To avoid natures violence realistically or to impose our will upon it, we use science, but the way Schiller suggests to deal with nature idealistically might sound odd: To destroy the very concept of a force means simply to submit to it voluntarily.37 Schiller identifies two genii to accompany us through life. The first conduces us to beauty and, its realm is the world of sense only and beyond this its earthly wings cannot bear us.38 But when the second approaches, it is tacit and solemn, and upon its powerful pinion we are borne across the vertiginous depths.39 The sublime is further associated with rupture because it Not gradually..., but suddenly and with a shock40 ushers us into an acquaintance aided by the terrifying and magnificent spectacle of change which destroys everything and creates it anew, and destroys again -.... To mankind the sublime is valuable with reference to the pure daemon in him.41 Locke destroys will, and Schiller revives it in the form of the sublime. If the sublime is a yearning for what is not, Schillers sense of the sublime must be one step ahead of Lockes psychology, on the one hand, and Freuds precursor in the realm of the unconscious, on the other. As Weiskel says, Locke actually substituted anxiety for the will. He concludes that since Locke says will arises from the perception of absence,42 the consequence of such a perception is anxiety the antidote of which is the sublime, or, in Freuds terminology, the defense mechanism known as sublimation. Thus the romantic poets, with their emphasis on the expressive self, foreground consciousness contact with, and wish for, what is not.

13

The romantic sublime, however, should not be confused with irrationality, for, more than anything else, it was rather anti-rationalist or a critique of reason as defined by the Enlightenment. To destroy or challenge the constructs of the age of Enlightenment, Romanticists had to develop their own discourse. They, for instance, were critical of the boundary strategy of the eighteenth century mentality. Gilbertson sees this metaphoric meaning of boundary functional from feudalism to the eighteenth century Enlightenment. In feudalism, Gilbertson informs us, boundary designated the social and economic distinctions attendant to landed property. And the Enlightenment conventions that established cultural boundaries to define the conventions of thought and action, and therefore of personal identity,43 seemed to romanticists not that much remote from the fetters used in the Feudal age. Thus, the sublime must be redefined as transgressing the borders, a campaign against the status-quo with metaphors of aggression and transgression. Schiller sees the same power struggle in world history, where prosperity and order without freedom reduce man to an obedient cog in a machine. Only when freedom contradicts this procession of the physical order, Schiller believes, world history appears to me a sublime object.44 It, therefore, must be noted here that the appeal of history -- as a moment of confusion or catastrophe -- for the romantic dramatists has its roots in such a notion of history . The classical notion of beauty emphasized verification, a tenet which supported order and decorum to establish a conservative order. To the classicist Goethe ancient literature borders on the serious and dignified, while romanticism is an unnatural and original thing but artificial, recherch, heightened, exaggerated, bizarre, to the point of

14

travesty and caricature.

45

On the other side, there is Lessing, who recognizes the

sublime in nature where everything is interwoven, everything changes with everything, everything merges from one into another. But he, like Goethe, maintains that for us -fine spirits that we are -- to witness this state of enjoyment in nature, we should be able to set up arbitrary limits... to eliminate and to guide46 our enjoyment at will. In dealing with the sublime, the romantics needed an autonomy which they ultimately found in Kants aesthetics. After analyzing different kinds of the sublime and the effect of each on the subject, Kant observes that the sublime in nature is improperly so called, and the sublimity should in strictness, be attributed merely to the attitude of thought... .47 Thus Kant provides the license for Coleridge to make his pleasure dome in Xanadu or for Wordsworth to go dreaming disguised as Peter Bell. If reason cloaked the discourse of confinement with decorum, symmetry and harmony, romanticists counterbalanced this strategy by declaring theirs the subversive discourse of the oppressed, which gives priority to a-symmetries deemed inappropriate for the stage by the canons. This is why their mirrors are almost never plane but convex or concave ones and, thus, the image rarely the classical life-size portraits, but broken, dull, vague, and agonized fantasies of the self, and very rarely the determined self itself. The irony in romantic process of making is that it is at the same time an unmaking process and these, making and unmaking... are the essential gestures in that wary cooperation with chaos which defines the romantic ironist.48 But if the sublime crosses the borders of decorum, of what can its essence be comprised? Of the great, the unlimited, the colossal, the astronomical only? Does it comprise only positive aspects or should we speak of a negative sublime? In other words,

15

does romanticism neglect impure elements in the sublime? In spite of the fact that Kant sees the sublime as the attitude of thought, he shows his reserve of mind by setting a limit to the limitless products of the mind. He allows the artist to show Furies, disease, devastations of war,... as evils in a very beautiful manner. But with regard to one kind of ugliness he cautions us and it is that which excites disgust. Because, to him, this feeling destroys all aesthetic delight, and consequently artistic beauty... .49 Both Shelley and Schiller, however, transgressed such limits, the former in The Cenci and the latter in The Robbers. Likewise, F. Schlegel owns that impurity is a part of mans soul. Just as pure oxygen is not good for breathing and is mixed with nitrogen, shunning from the impure is the essence of foolishness. And when discussing the novel and psychology, he considers it illogical...to shrink from even the most painstaking and thorough analysis of unnatural pleasure, horrible tortures, revolting infamy, and disgusting physical or mental impotence. 50 The road to this mode, ironic though it may sound, had previously been paved by Lessing. In Laocoon ( 1766) he shows his surprise when he comes across terror, extreme pain and the disgusting in art. Gerald Gillespie observes that in this set of statues Lessing recognized two mixed sensations, the ridiculous and the horrible, springing from incongruity or deformation. Lessing, says Gillespie, realized that sentiments of disgust for the corporeal state of character, but respect for his spirit, could combine to produce a different new sensation, not the desire to laugh, but rather a feeling of sympathy and fascination.51

16

Elsewhere, Schiller is quite alert to the value of intensity. To Schiller theft in a tragedy could, morally speaking, be considered as something vile but, aesthetically, the artist will discard it. But a vile action can be reinstated in our aesthetic estimation, if the artist can raise it to the level of a crime, say a murder. He confronts us with a contradiction here: our moral judgment does not like the terrible, while our aesthetic judgment seeks to be masked by a strong impression.52 Schiller resolves this contradiction by saying that terror finally serves on the side of moral judgment in that our mind switches from the quality of crime to thinking about its consequences. The sublime is also a component of romantic irony. To Schiller, it can also consist of confusion. He does not limit the sublime to what is unattainable for imagination, the sublime of quantity, but what is incomprehensible for the understanding, confusion, which can elevate the mind provided it advances to greatness and announces itself as a work of nature... .53 Burke also considers obscurity as a sublime element. Clarity for him is an enemy to all enthusiasms whatsoever and dark, confused, uncertain images have a great power on the fancy... .54 From the above discussion it is clear that in the aesthetics of the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries the sublime began to include the caricature and the grotesque. Beside ontological and psychological reasons for this development, one should not neglect its socio-political dimensions. Erich Auerbach suggests that this mixing of the genres, this elevation of the low to the sublime is a result of the collapse of the classical creed that each subject had its own scale or level of representation: All that contributed to the stability and greatness of the state... was portrayed in the high style, while the rest was considered as reality or domestic aspect.55 The contempt of the higher class for

17

this reality, according to Harpham, is because reality had a darker side, connected with the vulgar and possibly orgiastic growth processes in the depths... . Because of this, decorum is shaken and, in Harphams words, as the mighty shiver on their thrones... diction becomes overburdened and harsh... .56 To believe that the romantic imagination breaks the boundaries and camps forever outside the limits of the self and society is a mere misconception. To them, the self renews itself permanently, but this renewed thing comprises of those broken pieces put together again: the difference is the fractures and the missing pieces now supplied with other materials. Besides, the structure of the romantic works can also suggest a return in which the glittering eye -- exposed to the terrors of vastness -- relocates the self and society; a relocation which is also a displacing of the received forms of the past. Byrons play Cain: A Mystery (1821) exemplifies this. It has three-acts, of which the middle one occurs in The Abyss of Space and the first and the last occur on The land without paradise. In the last act, after his abysmal journey in the second act, Cain sees things not as they were but as new things that have a displaced or corrupted aspect. This is because, in his wifes words, ...that proud spirit, who withdrew thee hence,/ Hath saddened thine [eyes] still deeper... (III, 44-46). Related also to the sublime and the grotesque is the romantic poets preoccupation with images and after-images. Here again we are confronted with Platos The Parable of The Cave, but this time shadows or the phantasmagorical figures of this world do not move us away from essence. Now, they themselves are but essences that enhance the dance of the silhouettes. The mind is the cave or grotto out of which grotto-esque shapes emerge. In other words, perception is now willing to probe into the nocturnal side

18

of life. This was one of the long term programs of the romantics for subverting the empirical view of perception. If Schelling discusses the effects of Galvanic, electric, and magnetic forces on our perception, Schubert, observes Burwick, makes us think of perception and the night-side of our planet: ...Schubert declares that it is not merely the darkness that makes us see things differently at night. The energy from the sun now radiates through the earth and reflects from the moon and planets rather than shining upon us directly; on the night-side of the planet, too, we are exposed to starlight unseen by day.57 Thus, we are subjected to an altered perception by which we become aware of influences obscured by the daylight demands on our attention. In interpreting Schuberts concepts, Burwick concludes that the old faith in the supernatural now is reinterpreted as the inner...world which must stand in harmony with the outer world, something roughly synonymous with Abramss sense of natural supernaturalism. In Non-Aristotelian Drama, Madland seems to be arguing that eighteenth-century German poets like Lenz, did not turn their backs to the cave but were fascinated by the struggle of light with darkness: The camera obscura or darkened chamber has a fissure or crack, the image of which is reflected is no longer clear, but becomes diffused and distorted. Madlands understanding of Lenzs argument that the artist has the freedom to portray a figure as he sees it - as an individual or as a caricature 58 is essential to our discussion here because the dominant metaphor for the mind among the romantics is the metaphor of the cave, typically representable in Keats letter to H. Reynolds (3 May 1818) in which he compares mans life to a large Mansion of many apartments the first being Thoughtless Chamber and the last the Chamber of Maiden Thought whereby vision becomes darker and the poise between good and evil gets distorted.59

19

Darkness is an element that Burke considers to be sublime. It is because imagination is baffled or terrified. Yet romantic imagination, which identifies the mind as a cave, by letting some light break through from the fractures in this cave, or what Locke called Camera Obscura, substituted the material determinism of the natural world with split characters, demon-heroes, marginal ghosts who, in Gillespies words, all of which can be a variation of the discovery of a mysterious linkage between modern liberated creativity and the shadow side of existence.60 This shadow side of existence is sublime, yet because the characters or images appear displaced, corrupted or absurd, we can say that sublime has another side, the grotesque. Coleridge has both a taste for, and a simple definition of, the grotesque. The Odd or the grotesque, to him is when words or images are placed in unusual juxta-position rather than connection,...the occasional use of which in the minor ornaments of architecture is an interesting problem for a student in [the] psychology of the Fine Arts.61 Wordsworths inner eye (Prelude, V, 453), also suggests his concern with fantasies rather than copies. Keats sense of grotesque is best seen in his letter to George and Georgiana Keats (1818-19), in which he admires cartoons for being grotesque to a curious pitch...as there was left so much room for imagination.62 Keats proves that he is well aware of caricature and the grotesque as highly charged images which cause an electric shock in the reader. Madland believes that the grotesque is not an idealized reality. In contrast to classicism which shows nature in a perfect condition which calms the reader or spectator, the grotesque has a tendency to disturb him or her.63 The equivalent for Madlands idea that the grotesque tends to disturb is Keats idea that it leaves so much room for imagination, which undercuts the well-formed works and

20

questions their validity. Even Kant votes against stiff regularity because it is inherently repugnant to taste. But further on, what he says anticipates Keats taste for the cartoon and the grotesque: On the other hand, anything that gives the imagination scope for unstudied and final play is always fresh to us.64 In fact when we consider the definitions of the sublime and the grotesque, we can see that they overlap in many points. Weiskel knows the sublime to be cognate with the experiential structure of alienation. ... Alienation also presupposes the bathetic collapse of the signifying relations which make a social order. The sublime also does not satisfy understanding completely because it comes down to the claim that the failure to understand something has the very highest meaning.65 Whats more, there has been a tendency to set the grotesque in opposition to the beautiful. However, both Burke and Kant provoke us to reconsider the definition of deformity. The former does not consider deformity as the antonym of beauty because, in his view, deformity is opposed not to beauty, but to complete common form. Burke further argues that it is a prejudice in favor of proportion which sets a well-shaped object in contrast with a deformed one and takes the former as a beautiful object.66 As stated earlier, the early romantics, with their organic approach towards the soul and imagination, could not exclude or discard the abysmal world as the impure or demonic layer of mans consciousness because they considered the ugly an aspect of humanity. Among the romantic plays Byrons Manfred, Cain, and The Deformed

Transformed, Shelleys The Cenci, Wordsworths The Borderers, and Coleridges Remorse do have elements of the sublime and the grotesque, yet none stands as unique as The Cenci, a play not so popular in its own time for its impurity.

21

In this play Shelley does not demarcate the sublime and the grotesque; on the contrary, he pauses on each so long that one flows into the other. In fact had he demarcated them, he would have contradicted himself because in A Defence of Poetry he knows drama to be a prismatic and many-sided mirror( 121). If to him this is the essence of poetry in drama, the manner of representation must very precisely take care of it. Elsewhere in A Defence he admires Milton as a genius for treating both God and his Devil equally. Milton, he says, mingled... the elements of human nature as colours upon a single Pallet, and arranged them in the composition of his great picture according to the laws of epic truth... ( 130). Shelley achieves this objective in The Cenci by creating a bi-focal view in portraying his characters. As, for instance, we look at the conflicts between a cruel father and a resisting daughter, Shelley makes us consider power as inside-out energy which deforms and disorients both the oppressor and the oppressed. Shelley knows drama to be the best vehicle to usher us into the shocking moment when energy/power inscribes itself on the body. His fascination with terror is reminiscent of Schillers where he says, sorrow, terror, anguish, despair itself, are often the chosen expressions of an approximation to the highest good ... tragedy delights by affording a shadow of that pleasure which exists in pain. ...67 The early British romanticists failed to communicate with their own audience. They were looking for a heightened language which could let the body move more freely according to emotions, negative or positive. This eventually led to some stylized actions that would reduce actions to gestures including both realms of the sublime and the grotesque. The fact that Stanislavsky chose Byrons Sardanapalus and Grotowsky went for his Cain, and Artaud re-wrote The Cenci to stand as his manifesto for the Theatre of

22

Cruelty corroborates the claim that the early romantics had a lot in stock to offer to the posterity to enable them to experiment with forms as some radical gesture in modern theatre. NOTES
1 2

Frederick Page, ed., Byron: Poetical Works (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1970). W. J. B. Owen and Jane Worthington Smyser, eds., The Prose Works of William Wordsworth (Oxford: At The Clarendon Press, 1974), II, 192 3 Friedrich von Schiller, Naive and Sentimental Poetry and On the Sublime, trans. Julius A Elias ( New York: Frederick Ungar Publishing Co., 1966 ), 204 4 Anne K. Mellor, English Romantic Irony (Cambridge, Mass. : Harvard University Press, 1980), vii. 5 Jean-Paul Sartre, Myth and Reality in the Theatre, Gambit, Vol. 3, No. 9, 64. 6 Mellor, English Romantic Irony, 10. 7 Alethea Hayter, Opium and the Romantic Imagination (London: Faber and Faber, 1968), 237 8 Johannes Birringer, Theatre, Theory, Postmodernism (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1991), 28. 9 Julie Carlson, Command Performances: Burke, Coleridge, and Schillers Dramatic Reflections on the Revolution in France, Wordsworth Circle, Vol. 23, No. 2, 127. 10 Francis Barker, The Tremulous Private Body: Essays on Subjection (London: Methuen, 1984), 13. 11 See, Marjean D. Purinton, Romantic Ideology Unmasked (London: Associated University Press, 1994.) The reader is also invited to look at some plays written by radical British dramatists of the last three decades of the twentieth century in which these dramatists identify themselves and their own age crazed with privatization and market economy with the social life and institutions of the early romantics. Howard Brentons (1942- ) Bloody Poetry (1984) and Edward Bonds(1934 - ) The Fool (1976) are but two outstanding examples. 12 Bette Londons reading of this novel in her essay Mary Shelley, Frankenstein, and the Spectacle of Masculinity PMLA, Vol. 108, No., 2, 253-267 gives the major role to the male body as spectacle. A body that is seen, nonetheless, grotesque and on the threshold of decomposition. 13 Mary Shelley, Frankenstein (Hertfordshire: Wordsworth Classics, 1993), 32. 14 Eric Bentley, The Modern Theatre (London: Robert Hale Limited, 1950), 25. 15 The Prose Works of W. Wordsworth, I, 141. 16 E. L. Grigs, ed., Collected Letters of S.T. Coleridge, 6 Vols. (Oxford: At The Clarendon Press, !956 ), III, 442. 17 K. Coburn, ed., Notebooks, 3 vols.,(London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1973), III, 1808-1819. Ent. 4420, Aug., 1818. 18 F. Burwick, The Damnation of Newton: Goethes Color Theory And Romantic Perception ( Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1986), 226. 19 F.Burwick, The Haunted Eye: Perception and The Grotesque in English and German Romanticism, ( Heidelberg: Carl Winter, 1987), 76. 20 Ibid. 21 Eckermann, Conversations of Goethe with Eckermann, trans. John Oxenford, ed. J. K. Moorhead( London: J. M. Dent & Sons Ltd., 1930 ), 234. 22 Ibid., 245. 23 Philip Gilbertson, Boundaries and the Self in Romanticism, in English and German Romanticism: Cross-Currents and Controversies, ed. James Pipkin (Heidelberg: Carl Winter, 1985), 150-51.

23

Frederick Garber, Byron, Schelegel, and the Ironists Lucid Contours, in English and German Romanticism: Cross-Currents and Controversies. ed., James Pipkin (Heidelberg: Carl Winter, 1985), 175. 25 H. Buxton Forman, ed., The Complete Works of John Keats, 5 vols. (Glasgow: Gowars and Gray, 1901), V, (Letters 1819-1820), 37. 26 Jeffrey N. Cox, ed., Intro., Seven Gothic Plays ( Athens: Ohio University Press, 1992 ), 18. 27 Also quoted by Alethea Hayter, Opium and the Romantic Imagination (London: Faber and Faber, 1968), 319. 28 Eckermann, 168. 29 Ibid., 169. 30 Ibid., 298. 31 The Damnation of Newton, 9. 32 Ibid., 210. 33 Collected Letters of S.T. Coleridge, IV, 852. 34 Eckermann,135. 35 Ibid.,135. 36 Goethe, The Relief from Phigalia, in Goethe on Art, ed., John Gage (London: Scholar Press, 1980), 98. 37 Naive and Sentimental Poetry & On the Sublime, 195. 38 Ibid., 197. 39 Ibid., 198. 40 Ibid., 210. 41 Ibid. 42 The Romantic Sublime, 18. 43 Boundaries and The Self in Romanticism, 145, 146, 148. 44 Naive and Sentimental Poetry & On The Sublime, 206. 45 Eckermann, 70-71. 46 G. E. Lessing, Hamburg Dramaturgy, trans. Helen Zimmern. Intro. by Victor Lange ( New York: Dover Publications, Inc., 1962 ), 171. 47 Immanuel Kant, The Critique of Judgment, trans. James Creed Meredith (Oxford: At the Clarendon Press, 1973), 134. 48 Frederick Garber, Byron, Schelegel, and the Ironists Lucid Contours, 179. 49 Ibid., 173-74. 50 F. von Schlegel, The Aesthetic and Miscellaneous works, trans. E. J. Millington, (London: Henry G. Bohn, 1849) , 419, 11, 34. 51 Gerald Gillespie, Romantic Irony and Anti-Theatre, in English and German Romanticism, ed., James Pipkin (Heidelberg: Carl Winter, 1985), 200-201 52 F. Schiller Reflections on The Use of The Vulgar and Low Elements in Works of Art (1793) in Dramatic Theory and Criticism: Greeks to Grotowsky , ed. B. F. Dukore (New York: University of Hawaii, 1974 ), 470-71. 53 Naive and Sentimental Poetry and On the Sublime, 205. 54 Edmund Burke, The Works and Correspondence, VIII vols. (London: Francis and John Rivington, 1852), II, 600, 602. 55 See, G. Harpham, On the Grotesque: Strategies of contradiction in Art and Literature (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1982 ), 73. 56 Ibid. 57 Burwick, The Haunted Eye, 58. 58 Madland, Non-Aristotelian Drama ( Main: Peter Lang, 1982),134. 59 The Complete Works of J. Keats, (Letters: 1814-1819), 109. 60 Romantic Irony and Anti-Theatre, 205. 61 Notebooks, III, 4503. 62 Letters, IV, 202. 63 Non-Aristotelian Drama, 183. 64 The Critique of Judgment, P.88.
24

24

65

Thomas Weiskel, The Romantic Sublime: Studies in the Structure and Psychology of Transcendence (London: The Johns Hopkins University, 1976), 35, 36. 66 Burke, 629. 67 P. B. Shelley, A Defence of Poetry, in The Complete Works of P. B. Shelley, 10 vols., eds. Roger Ingpen and Walter E. Peck ( New York: Gordian Press, 1965 ), VII, 248.

25

Anda mungkin juga menyukai