Anda di halaman 1dari 42

MATERNITY NURSING

ETHICS IN MIDWIFERY PRACTICE


INTRODUCTION Ethics is an essential dimension of obstetric and gynecologic practice Preventive ethics helps to build and sustain a strong physician patient relationship in the practice of obstetrics and gynecology. The key components of the ethical framework are definitions of ethics and medical ethics and an explication of the fundamental ethical principles of medical ethics, beneficence and respect for autonomy. The next concern is how these two ethical principles should interact in gynecologic clinical judgment and practice. Again how these two ethical principles should interact in obstetric judgment and practice, with emphasis on the concept of the fetus as a patient, which is unique to the practice of obstetrics. There are different concepts of the ethical principles of justice. It is important that ethical issues are responsible in resource management, emphasizing the virtues of the physician as a professional. Finally, provide a guide for critically appraising the literature of ethics in obstetrics and gynecology TWO DEFINITIONS AND TWO ETHICAL PRINCIPLES Ethics is the disciplined study of morality. Morality concerns our actual behaviors and our beliefs about what standards our behavior should meet. Medical ethics is the disciplined study of morality in medicine and concerns the obligations of physicians and health-care organizations to patients as well as the obligations of patients. It is important not to confuse medical ethics with the many sources of morality in a pluralistic society. These include the law, our political heritage, the worlds religions, ethnic and cultural traditions, families, the traditions and practices of medicine, and personal experience. Medical ethics, since the eighteenth century European and American Enlightenments, has been secular.
1

It makes no reference to God or revealed tradition, but to what rational discourse requires and produces. At the same time, secular medical ethics aims not to be intrinsically hostile to religious beliefs. This can be a real challenge in the ethics of obstetrics and reproductive medicine. In medical ethics, ethical principles and virtues should be understood to apply to all physicians, regardless of their personal religious and spiritual beliefs. The Ethical Principle of Beneficence The ethical principle of beneficence in its general meaning and application requires one to act in a way that is expected to reliably produce the greater balance of benefits over harms in the lives of others. To put this principle into clinical practice requires a reliable account of the benefits and harms relevant to the care of the patient, and of how those benefits and harms should be reasonably balanced against each other when not all of them can be achieved in a particular clinical situation, such as a request for an elective cesarean delivery. In medicine, the ethical principle of beneficence requires the physician to act in a way that is reliably expected to produce the greater balance of clinical benefits over harms for the patient. Beneficence-based clinical judgment has an ancient pedigree in the history of medical ethics. The first expression of the ethical principle of beneficence in the history of Western medical ethics occurs in the Hippocratic Oath and accompanying texts. These texts make an important claim: to interpret reliably the health-related and other interests of the patient from a medical perspective. This perspective is provided by accumulated medical research, clinical experience, and reasoned responses to uncertainty. On the basis of this rigorous clinical perspective, focused on the best available evidence, beneficence-based clinical judgment identifies the clinical benefits that can be achieved for the patient in medical practice based on the competencies of medicine. The clinical benefits that medicine is competent to seek for patients are the prevention and management of disease, injury, disability, and unnecessary pain, distress, and suffering, and the prevention of premature or unnecessary death. Pain, distress, and suffering become unnecessary when they do not result in achieving the other benefits of medical care, e.g. allowing a woman to labor without effective analgesia.
2

The Ethical Principle of Nonmaleficence Nonmaleficence means that the physician should prevent causing only or net clinical harm to patients and is best understood as expressing the limits of beneficence. Nonmaleficence is also known as Primum non nocere or first do no harm. This commonly invoked rule emphasized beneficence while avoiding harm when approaching the limits of medicine. Nonmaleficenceshould be incorporated into beneficence-based clinical judgment: when the physician approaches the limits of beneficence-based clinical judgment, i.e. when the evidence for expected net clinical benefit diminishes and the risks of clinical harm increase, then the physician should proceed with great caution. The physician should be especially concerned to prevent serious, far-reaching, and irreversible clinical harm to the patient. The preventive ethics response to paternalism is for the physician to explain the diagnostic, therapeutic, and prognostic reasoning that leads to his or her clinical judgment about what is in the interest of the patient so that the patient can assess that judgment for herself. This general rule can be put into clinical practice in the following way: The physician should disclose and explain to the patient the clinically salient or important factors of this reasoning process, including matters of uncertainty. One advantage for the physician in carrying out this approach to communicating with the patient would be, we believe, to increase the likelihood of compliance. This is an especially pertinent consideration in gynecologic practice, where the patient often must monitor herself for clinical changes (e.g., a woman at risk for ectopic pregnancy), and take an active role in preventive medicine (e.g., breast self-examination), as well as in obstetric practice (e.g., self-observation for unusual weight gain or bleeding). Another advantage would be to provide the patient with a better-informed opportunity to make a decision about whether to seek a second opinion. The Ethical Principle of Respect for Autonomy In contrast to the principle of beneficence, there has been increasing emphasis in the literature of medical ethics on the principle of respect for autonomy.In general, this ethical principle requires one always to acknowledge and carry out the value-based preferences of the adult, competent patient, unless there is compelling ethical justification for not doing so, e.g. prescribing antibiotics for
3

viral respiratory infections. The female or pregnant patient increasingly brings to her medical care her own perspective on what is in her interest. The principle of respect for autonomy translates this fact into autonomy-based clinical judgment. Because each patients perspective on her interests is a function of her values and beliefs, it is impossible to specify the benefits and harms of autonomy-based clinical judgment in advance. Indeed, it would be inappropriate for the physician to do so, because the definition of her benefits and harms and their balancing are the prerogative of the patient. To understand the moral demands of the ethical principle of respect for autonomy, we need an operationalized concept of autonomy to make it relevant to clinical practice. To do this, we identify three sequential autonomy-based behaviors on the part of the patient: (1) Absorbing and retaining information about her condition and alternative diagnostic and therapeutic responses to it; (2) Understanding that information (i.e., evaluating and rank-ordering those responses and appreciating that she could experience the risks of treatment); and (3) Expressing a value-based preference. The physician has a role to play in each of these. They are, respectively, (1) To recognize the capacity of each patient to deal with medical information, provide information and recognize the validity of the values and beliefs of the patient. (2) Not to interfere with but, when necessary, to assist the patient in her evaluation and ranking of diagnostic and therapeutic alternatives for managing her condition; and (3) To elicit and implement the patients value-based preference. The legal obligations of the physician regarding informed consent were established in a series of cases during the early twentieth century. In 1914, Schloendorff v. The Society of the New York Hospital established the concept of simple consent, i.e. whether the patient says yes or no to medical intervention. To this day in the medical and bioethics literature, this decision is quoted: Every human being of adult years and sound mind has the right to
4

determine what shall be done with his body, and a surgeon who performs an operation without his patients consent commits an assault for which he is liable in damages. Simple consent is based on the legal concept of battery, or unconsented-to touching.

The Ethical Principle of Distributive Justice Considered as one type of justice, distributive justice is a central concept and is closely linked to the concepts of human dignity, the common good, and human rights. Considered as an ethical principle, distributive justice refers to what society or a larger group owes its individual members in proportion to : 1) the individuals needs, contribution and responsibility; 2) the resources available to the society or organization (market considerations would be included under this, as well as other financial considerations); and 3) the societys or organizations responsibility to the common good. In the context of health care, distributive justice requires that everyone receive equitable access to the basic health care necessary for living a fully human life insofar as there is a basic human right to health care. THREE CONCEPTS OF JUSTICE Ethical concerns about justice arise when resources are scarce. Justice requires that in the distribution of resources, each should receive what is due to him or her. Different concepts of justice define due in different ways. Each strives to result in a fair distribution of benefits, i.e. access to resources, and burdens, the risks that could follow from lack of such access. Utilitarianism is a theory of justice that makes central the obligation to produce the greatest good for the greatest number in the management of scarce resources. To be successful in guiding practical, day-to-day decisions about the allocation of resources, utilitarianism requires an account of the greatest good. For society overall, it has been difficult, if not impossible, to define what the greatest good is. The value of utilitarianism is the balance it seeks to achieve among benefits and burdens of scarce resources, so that inequalities do not become inequities, i.e. unfair. Critics of utilitarians have pointed out that sometimes utilitarianism results in inequities, i.e. shared distributions of benefits and burdens.
5

Two other concepts of justice have been developed to address this problem. The first of these is a libertarian concept of justice. This concept of justice was developed to correct for tyrannical burdens that pure utilitarianism could create. In particular, libertarianism was developed to give priority to individual freedom and property rights, as correctives to the potential excesses of utilitarianism and, in the political realm, of state power. Libertarians argue that in a market that places different values on different services and products, and in which there is an equal opportunity to develop ones talents, those who provide more highly valued services rightly earn more than those who provide less valued (though not necessarily less intrinsically valuable) services. Everyone should get to keep what he or she earns through these marketplace exchanges, reflecting the strong emphasis of the libertarian concept of justice on property rights. Libertarian theories emphasize fairness of process, rather than equality of outcomes. The other concept of justice that has been developed is an egalitarian concept of justice. This concept was developed to protect vulnerable and disadvantaged members of society, who may lose out in a utilitarian distribution of scarce resources. This concept of justice corrects for unfair outcomes in the form of undue burdens on those least able to protect themselves. BENEFICENCE-BASED AND AUTONOMY-BASED GYNECOLOGIC JUDGMENT AND PRACTICE Beneficence-based and autonomy-based clinical judgments in gynecologic practice are usually in harmony.Sometimes, beneficence-based and autonomybased clinical judgments are in conflict in gynecologic practice. In situations of conflict, neither beneficence nor respect for autonomy automatically should be taken to be overriding. Instead, both ethical principles should initially be understood as theoretically equally weighted. Thus, their differences must be negotiated in clinical judgment and practice. The competing demands of both principles must be balanced and negotiated in the specific clinical case to determine which management strategies protect and promote the patients interests. In the technical language of ethics, we are treating these principles as prima facie or potentially overridable, on the basis of careful reflection and argument in the clinical setting. The ethical and legal obligation of the physician in the matter of informed refusal is very clear and not difficult to fulfill. In all cases, without exception,
6

the patient should be clearly informed about the medical risks that she is taking in her refusal. The risks to be disclosed are those that are salient in clinical judgment: if they are important to the physician, that is, motivating the offering or recommending of the diagnostic test or therapy, they are salient. This discussion, especially the risks of refusal, should be thoroughly documented in the patients chart. The patient does not have to sign this chart entry. It is the physicians strict legal obligation to make sure that the disclosure of risk and documentation of that disclosure are comprehensive and detailed. This is all that the law requires. Preventive ethics requires that this disclosure be followed by a recommendation that the patient reconsider her refusal. This preventive-ethics approach avoids the need to abandon the patient, keeps lines of communication open, and sends a powerful signal of concern by the physician to the patient about the medical folly of her refusal. The process of negotiating conflict between the two principles is a function of several factors involved in gynecologic clinical judgment: subject matter; probability of net medical benefit; availability of reasonable alternatives; and the ability of the patient to participate in the informed consent process. When the subject matter is primarily technical in nature, such as the selection of an effective antibiotic regimen or intraoperative surgical technique, clinical judgment is justifiably beneficence-based. This is because technical matters largely concern the evidence-based benefits for aggregates of patients with a particular diagnosis and treatment plan. Such decisions are justifiably within the gynecologists purview. The individual values and beliefs of a particular patient cannot readily be taken into account in this process. By contrast, when the patients basic values and beliefs are at stake, e.g. the work-up or treatment of infertility or elective abortion, clinical judgment is justifiably autonomy-based. This is because particular diagnostic or treatment interventions can directly and adversely affect the basic values and beliefs of a particular patient, a matter that only each individual patient can decide. Such decisions are justifiably within the patients purview. BENEFICENCE-BASED AND JUDGMENT AND PRACTICE AUTONOMY-BASED OBSTETRIC

The ethical principles of beneficence and respect for autonomy play a more complex role in obstetric judgment and practice than they do in gynecologic judgment and practice. There are obviously beneficence-based and autonomy7

based obligations to the pregnant patient: the physicians perspective on the pregnant womans health-related interests provides the basis for the physicians beneficence-based obligations to her, whereas her own perspective on those interests provides the basis for the physicians autonomy-based obligations to her. Because of an insufficiently developed central nervous system, the fetus cannot meaningfully be said to possess values and beliefs. Thus, there is no basis for saying that a fetus has a perspective on its interests. There can therefore be no autonomy-based obligations to any fetus. Hence, the language of fetal rights has no meaning and therefore no application to the fetus in obstetric clinical judgment and practice despite its popularity in public and political discourse in the United States and other countries. Obviously, the physician has a perspective on the fetuss health-related interests, and the physician can have beneficence-based obligations to the fetus, but only when the fetus is a patient. Because of its importance for obstetric clinical judgment and practice, the ethical concept of the fetus as a patient requires detailed consideration The Ethical Concept of the Fetus as a Patient The ethical concept of the fetus as a patient is essential to obstetric clinical judgment and practice. Developments in fetal diagnosis and management strategies to optimize fetal outcome have become widely accepted, encouraging the development of this concept. This concept has considerable clinical significance because, when the fetus is a patient, directive counseling, that is, recommending a form of management, for fetal benefit is appropriate, and when the fetus is not a patient, nondirective counseling, that is, offering but not recommending a form of management for fetal benefit, is appropriate. However, there can be uncertainty about when the fetus is a patient. One approach to resolving this uncertainty would be to argue that the fetus is or is not a patient in virtue of personhood, or some other form of independent moral status. We now show that this approach fails to resolve the uncertainty, and we therefore defend an alternative approach that does resolve the uncertainty. RESPONSIBLE RESOURCE PROFESSIONAL VIRTUES MANAGEMENT AND THE

The practice of obstetrics and gynecology is coming under increasingly powerful economic constraints, e.g. managed-care and resource-management strategies imposed by hospital managers, used by both private and public payers and by health-care organizations to control the cost of medical care. Two main
8

business tools are used to achieve this goal: creating conflicts of interests in how physicians are paid, diplomatically called sharing economic risk, and increasingly strict control of clinical judgment and practice through such means as practice guidelines, critical pathways, physician report cards, and retrospective chart review. These business tools generate ethical challenges to obstetrician-gynecologists that seriously threaten the virtues that define the fiduciary character of medicine as a profession The first virtue is self-effacement. This requires the physician not to act on the basis of potential differences between the patient and the physician such as race, religion, national origin, gender, sexual orientation, manners, socioeconomic status, or proficiency in speaking English. Self-effacement prevents biases and prejudices arising from these differences that could adversely impact on the plan of care for the patient. The second virtue is self-sacrifice. This requires physicians to accept reasonable risks to themselves. As one example, physicians manifest this virtue in their willingness to care for patients with infectious diseases such as hepatitis, HIV infection, and tuberculosis, all of which are a potential threat to the physicians health. In both fee-for-service and managed care, this virtue of self-sacrifice obligates the physician to turn away from economic self-interest and focus on the patients need for relief when the two are in conflict. The third virtue, compassion, motivates the physician to recognize and seek to alleviate the stress, discomfort, pain, and suffering associated with the patients disease and illness. Self-effacement, self-sacrifice, and compassion provide the basis for a powerful ethical response to the business tool of conflicts of interest by the physician. This response is strengthened by the fourth virtue, integrity. This virtue imposes an intellectual discipline on the physicians clinical judgments about the patients problems and how to address them. Integrity prescribes rigor in the formation of clinical judgment. Clinical judgment is rigorous when it is based on the best available medical information or, when such information is lacking, consensus clinical judgment and on careful thought processes of an individual physician that can withstand peer review. Integrity is thus an antidote to the pitfalls of bias, subjective clinical impressions, and unexamined clinical common sense that can undermine evidence-based practice. Integrity provides
9

the basis for the physicians ethical response to the business tool of control of clinical judgment and practice. The professional virtue of integrity should never be compromised, while the other three professional virtues have justified limits, based on careful reflection and argument. The task of medical ethics is to identify both the application and the limits of these four virtues. The concept of legitimate self-interest provides the basis for these limits. Legitimate self-interest includes protecting the conditions for practicing medicine well, fulfilling obligations to persons in the physicians life other than the patient, and protecting activities outside the practice of medicine that the physician finds deeply fulfilling.

THE ICN CODE OF ETHICS FOR NURSES

An international code of ethics for nurses was first adopted by theInternational Council of Nurses (ICN) in 1953. It has been revisedand reaffirmed at various times since, most recently with thisreview and revision completed in 2005. The code of ethics provides a basic manual for the nurses in the practice situations. The ICN code was made generally for all the nurses in all the practice situations and for all the speciality conditions.
ELEMENTS OF THE CODE The ICN Code of Ethics for Nurses has four principal elements that outline the standards of ethical conduct.

1. NURSES AND PEOPLE The nurses primary professional responsibility is to people requiring nursing care .In providing care, the nurse promotes an environment in which the human rights, values, customs and spiritual beliefs of the individual ,family and community are respected.The nurse ensures that the individual receives sufficient informationon which to base consent for care and related treatment.The nurse holds in confidence personal information and uses judgement in sharing this information.The nurse shares with society the
10

responsibility for initiating and supporting action to meet the health and social needs of the public, inparticular those of vulnerable populations.The nurse also shares responsibility to sustain and protect the naturalenvironment from depletion, pollution, degradation and destruction. 2. NURSES AND PRACTICE The nurse carries personal responsibility and accountability fornursing practice, and for maintaining competence by continuallearning. The nurse maintains a standard of personal health such that theability to provide care is not compromised.The nurse uses judgement regarding individual competence when accepting and delegating responsibility.The nurse at all times maintains standards of personal conductwhich reflect well on the profession and enhance public confidence.The nurse, in providing care, ensures that use of technology andscientific advances are compatible with the safety, dignity andrights of people. 3. NURSES AND THE PROFESSION The nurse assumes the major role in determining and implementingacceptable standards of clinical nursing practice, management,research and education.The nurse is active in developing a core of research-based professionalknowledge.The nurse, acting through the professional organisation, participatesin creating and maintaining safe, equitable social and economicworking conditions in nursing. 4. NURSES AND CO-WORKERS The nurse sustains a co-operative relationship with co-workers innursing and other fields.The nurse takes appropriate action to safeguard individuals, families and communities when their health is endangered by a co workeror any other person. 4 SUGGESTIONS FOR USE OF THE ICN CODE OF ETHICS FOR NURSES The ICN Code of Ethics for Nurses is a guide for action based onsocial values and needs. It will have meaning only as a living documentif applied to the
11

realities of nursing and health care in a changing society .To achieve its purpose the Code must be understood, internalisedand used by nurses in all aspects of their work. It must be availableto students and nurses throughout their study and work lives.

INTERNATIONAL

CONFEDERATION

OF

MIDWIVES

(ICM) CODE OF ETHICS FOR MIDWIVES

A code of ethics is not a dry dusty piece of paper; it is a living breathing embodiment of the spirit of midwifery and we are the ones that make it not only live, but sing and dance with the joy of life itself BronwinPelvin New Zealand Midwife Journal of NZCOM, 1992 The ICM code was specially designed for the midwifery practice. The maternity and child health nursing is now emerging as a very peculiar and strong division in the nursing practice areas. The ICM code provides a basic practice standard for the nurse midwives all over the world to perform in a better way and to follow agneralised standard all over the world. PREAMBLE The aim of the International Confederation of Midwives (ICM) is to improve the standard of care provided to women, babies and families throughout the world through the development, education, and appropriate utilization of the professional midwife. In keeping with its aim of womens health and focus on the midwife, the ICM sets forth the following code to guide the education, practice and research of the midwife. This code acknowledges women as persons with human rights, seeks justice for all people and equity in access to health care, and is based on mutual relationships of respect, trust, and the dignity of all members of society.

12

Introduction In an effort to increase understanding and, hence, use of the International Code of Ethics for Midwives (1999), the ICM Board of Management commissioned the publication of this document. The document contains: the Code of Ethics, the glossary of terms used in the Code, the ethical analysis of the Code, a brief history of the development of the Code and suggestions on how the midwife can use this Code in practice, education or research.

THE CODE I. Midwifery Relationships a. Midwives respect a womans informed right of choice and promote the womans acceptance of responsibility for the outcomes of her choices. b. Midwives work with women, supporting their right to participate actively in decisions about their care, and empowering women to speak for themselves on issues affecting the health of women and their families in their culture/society. c. Midwives, together with women, work with policy and funding agencies to define womens needs for health services and to ensure that resources are fairly allocated considering priorities and availability. d. Midwives support and sustain each other in their professional roles, and actively nurture their own and others sense of self-worth. e. Midwives work with other health professionals, consulting and referring as necessary when the womans need for care exceeds the competencies of the midwife. f. Midwives recognise the human interdependence within their field of practice and actively seek to resolve inherent conflicts. g. The midwife has responsibilities to her or himself as a person of moral worth, including duties of moral self-respect and the preservation of integrity. II. Practice of Midwifery

13

a. Midwives provide care for women and childbearing families with respect for cultural diversity while also working to eliminate harmful practices within those same cultures. b. Midwives encourage realistic expectations of childbirth by women within their own society, with the minimum expectation that no women should be harmed by conception or childbearing. c. Midwives use their professional knowledge to ensure safe birthing practices in all environments and cultures. d. Midwives respond to the psychological, physical, emotional and spiritual needs of women seeking health care, whatever their circumstances. e. Midwives act as effective role models in health promotion for women throughout their life cycle, for families and for other health professionals. f. Midwives actively seek personal, intellectual and professional growth throughout their midwifery career, integrating this growth into their practice. III. The Professional Responsibilities of Midwives a. Midwives hold in confidence client information in order to protect the right to privacy, and use judgment in sharing this information. b. Midwives are responsible for their decisions and actions, and are accountable for the related outcomes in their care of women. c. Midwives may refuse to participate in activities for which they hold deep moral opposition; however, the emphasis on individual conscience should not deprive women of essential health services. d. Midwives understand the adverse consequences that ethical and human rights violations have on the health of women and infants, and will work to eliminate these violations. e. Midwives participate in the development and implementation of health policies that promote the health of all women and childbearing families. IV. Advancement of Midwifery Knowledge and Practice a. Midwives ensure that the advancement of midwifery knowledge is based on activities that protect the rights of women as persons. b. Midwives develop and share midwifery knowledge through a variety of processes, such as peer review and research. c. Midwives participate in the formal education of midwifery students and midwives.
14

Ethical Analysis of the Code of Ethics Introduction Ethics codes are often a mix of universal ethical principles and strongly held values specific to the professional group. Below is a brief analysis of the major ethical principles and concepts that form the basis for each of the statements of the ICM International Code of Ethics for Midwives (1999). I. Midwifery Relationships a. b. c. d. e. f. g. II. Autonomy and accountability of women; right to make choices Autonomy and human equalities of women; empowered to speak for herself Justice/fairness in the allocation of resources Respect for human dignity; viewing herself as a worthy individual Competence, interdependence of health professionals, safety Respect for one another Moral self-respect, dignity

Practice of Midwifery a. b. c. d. e. f. Respect for others, do good, do not harm Client accountability for decisions, do not harm, safety Safety; cultural relevance Respect for human dignity, treat women as whole persons Health promotion: attain/maintain autonomy, good/no harm, allocation of resources Competence in practice

III.

Professional Responsibilities of Midwives a. b. c. d. e. Confidentiality; privacy Midwife accountability Midwife conscience clause: autonomy and respect of human qualities of the midwife Prevent human rights violations Health policy development: justice, do good

IV.

Advancement of Midwifery Knowledge and Practice


15

a. b. c.

Protect rights of women as persons Midwife accountability, safety, competence Professional responsibility: enhance competence professionals to do good, do not harm

of

all

ETHICAL AND LEGAL ISSUES IN REPRODUCTION


Reproductive issues often involve conflicts in which a woman behaves in a way that may cause harm to her fetus. Conflicts occurs between a mother and a fetus when the mothers needs, behaviors, or wishes may injure the fetus.Ethicl and Legal issues in reproduction generates a major area as far as the nursing practice is concerned. Now a days the area is facing a lot of issues which should be managed very carefully.

REPRODUCTIVE TECHNOLOGY
When conceiving a child naturally is not physically not possible, technology is now capable of assisting the couple the assisted reproductive technology has its own benefits and harms and a lot of ethical and value based issues are concentrating around this.

Artificial insemination
It is one of the oldest terms of reproductive technology. Artificial insemination, or AI, is the process by which sperm is placed into the reproductive tract of a female for the purpose of impregnating the female by using means other than sexual intercourse or natural insemination. In humans, it is used as assisted reproductive technology, using either sperm from the woman's male partner or sperm from a sperm donor (donor sperm) in cases where the male partner produces no sperm or the woman has no male partner (i.e., single women, lesbians). In cases where donor sperm is used the woman is the gestational and genetic mother of the child produced, and the sperm donor is the genetic or biological father of the child. Requests by single women for artificial insemination by donor (AID) raise important ethical issues concerning the obligations of physicians and the wellbeing of the children who would be conceived. Specific objections to AID for single women can be raised, including that the absence of a father may adversely affect the child or that a lesbian mother may influence the child to become homosexual. A review of the relevant social science research indicates,
16

however, that these and other objections are not supported by the available data. In support of AID for single women it can be argued that the life of the child who would be produced could be expected to have value, considered in itself. Consideration of the various aspects of the issue suggests that AID for single women is permissible in selected cases and that the physician has a right to refuse to carry out such requests.

In vitrofertilisation
In vitrofertilisation (IVF) is a process by which egg cells are fertilised by sperm outside the body: in vitro. IVF is a major treatment in infertility when other methods of assisted reproductive technology have failed. The process involves hormonally controlling the ovulatory process, removing ova (eggs) from the woman's ovaries and letting spermfertilise them in a fluid medium. The fertilised egg (zygote) is then transferred to the patient's uterus with the intent to establish a successful pregnancy. The first successful birth of a "test tube baby", Louise Brown, occurred in 1978

Ethical Issues
In a few cases, laboratory mix-ups (misidentified gametes, transfer of wrong embryos) have occurred, leading to legal action against the IVF provider and complex paternity suits. The Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (HFEA )for example, requires clinics to use a double witnessing system, where the identity of specimens is checked by two people at each point at which specimens are transferred. Alternatively, technological solutions are gaining favour, to reduce the manpower cost of manual double witnessing, and to further reduce the risk of human error. Another concern is that people will screen in or out for particular traits, using preimplantation genetic diagnosis. Some medical ethicists have been very critical of this approach. Jacob Appel wrote that "intentionally culling out blind or deaf embryos might prevent considerable future suffering, while a policy that allowed deaf or blind parents to select for such traits intentionally would be far more troublesome."

17

Pregnancy past menopause Although menopause is a natural barrier to further conception, IVF has allowed women to be pregnant in their fifties and sixties. Women whose uterus has been appropriately prepared receive embryos that originated from an egg of an egg donor. Therefore, although these women do not have a genetic link with the child, they have an emotional link through pregnancy and childbirth. In many cases the genetic father of the child is the woman's partner. Even after menopause the uterus is fully capable of carrying out a pregnancy. Same-sex couples, single and unmarried parents Ethical concerns include reproductive rights, the welfare of offspring, nondiscrimination against unmarried individuals, homosexual, and professional autonomy. Catholic objections The Catholic Church opposes all kinds of in vitrofertilisation because, as with contraception, it separates the procreative purpose of the marriage act from its unitive purpose: Legal status Government agencies in China passed bans on the use of IVF in 2003 by unmarried women or by couples with certain infectious diseases. Sunni Muslim nations generally allow IVF between married couples when conducted with their own respective sperm and eggs, but not with donor eggs from other couples. But Iran, which is Shi'a Muslim, has a more complex scheme. Iran bars sperm donation but allows donation of both fertilised and unfertilised eggs. Fertilised eggs are donated from married couples to other married couples, while unfertilised eggs are donated in the context of mut'ah or temporary marriage to the father WHAT ARE CLONING? THE ETHICAL ISSUES REGARDING HUMAN

The possibility of human cloning has long fired the popular imagination, including in the world of popular entertainment. For many others, cloning
18

implied overtones of human immortality or of assembly-line eugenics. The high failure rates (more than 90 per cent) and high morbidity of animal cloning strongly suggests its inapplicability to humans. Furthermore, cloned animals seem to suffer high deformity and disability rates. Dolly herself was finally put down in 2003, at the age of just six and a half years, even though many sheep live more than 10 years. She had developed a progressive lung disease, which is usually found in older sheep, as well as premature arthritis

Ethical Issues regarding Human Reproductive Cloning


Technical and medical safety Undermining the concept of reproduction and family Ambiguous relations of a cloned child with the progenitor Confusing personal identity and harming the psychological development of a clone Concerns about eugenics Contrary to Human Dignity Promoting trends towards designer babies and humanenhancement Human cloning elaborated by UNESCO. In Section C of the Declaration, Research on the Human Genome, it is stated Practices which are contrary to human dignity, such as reproductive cloning of human beings, shall not be permitted. After careful consideration, several countries have formulated opinions and regulations on human IS RESEARCH CLONING DIFFERENT FROM REPRODUCTIVE CLONING? Meanwhile, biomedical researchers have focused their attention since Dollys birth on experimental, so-called therapeutic cloning, centering on the use of the cloning technique to obtain embryonic stem cells for research and potential therapeutic purposes. Since the notion therapeutic suggests possible beneficial applications of cloning, which at the present time seem completely unjustified, it is more appropriate to change this positive connotation and use a more neutral wording, viz. research cloning. In the case of reproductive cloning, the aim of somatic cell nuclear transfer is to create an embryo carrying the same genetic
19

information as the progenitor and to implant this embryo into a womb to generate a pregnancy, and from there to produce a baby. The goal of research cloning, however, is to create an embryo in the same manner as for reproductive cloning, not to produce a child but in order to derive embryonic stem cells which contain the same genetic characteristics as the progenitor. ETHICAL ISSUES What are the pros and cons of using unused embryos for medical research? Is there anything wrong with disposal of unused embryos leaving them on the counter to unthaw and degenerate? What if the surrogate decides to maintain her privacy? What if the surrogate and the spouse violate the abstention clause? What if the surrogate decides to keep the baby? What if the surrogate with genetic ties demands to visit her child? Is there anything wrong with a surrogate giving her unused embryos to someone else? Who should make a decision to unthaw frozen embryos? Is handing over a child after delivery for a fee baby-selling? Do women participate in surrogacy to save their marriage? Is it wrong for a surrogate to abort? Donor anonymity In 2004, the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (Disclosure of Donor Information) Regulations 2004/1511, enabled donor-conceived children to access the identity of their sperm, egg or embryo donor upon reaching the age of 18. The Regulations were implemented on 1 April 2005 and any donor who donated sperm, eggs or embryos from that date onwards is, by law, identifiable. Since that date, any person born as a result of donation is entitled to request and receive the donors name and last known address, once they reach the age of 18

SURROGATE MOTHER
Surrogate mothers are women who agree to carry and give birth to a child or children to be raised by another couple or person. Arrangements with surrogate
20

mothers are often made by couples with fertility problems, and laws dictating the legality of this practice vary from one country to the next. But beyond the legal and medical considerations, which can be very complex, there are complex ethical issues that should be considered prior to entering a surrogate mother agreement. Gestational Mother Attachment In a surrogate mother arrangement, the gestational mother is the woman who carries the baby to term. One common objection raised by critics of surrogate motherhood, according to "Surrogate Motherhood: International Perspectives" by Rachel Cook, Shelley Day Sclater and Felicity Kaganas, is a belief that the gestational mother inevitably develops a relationship with the child she carries, and relinquishing the child after this can be difficult and emotionally taxing. However, the authors paint this as a misconception, stressing that most surrogate mothers take deliberate steps throughout the process to mentally and emotionally prepare themselves, as well as emotionally detach themselves from the infants they carry. Gestational Mother Involvement The gestational mother in a surrogacy arrangement is unquestionably an important part of the child's background and, depending on the manner of surrogacy chosen, may be genetically linked to the child. However, since the gestational mother will not be the child's primary caretaker, and since typical surrogate mother arrangements involve full parental rights being transferred to another party, there will naturally be questions about the extent to which the gestational mother should be involved in the child's life. Such arrangements are often decided in advance and specified in legal contracts between the surrogate mother and the intended parents or parent. In some arrangements, the identities of the two parties are never revealed to one another. In others, the gestational mother may be granted legal visitation rights. There are plenty of other types of arrangements, with no rules dictating right or wrong. But it is important for this arrangement to be thought out, agreed upon and perhaps established in legal terms prior to beginning the surrogacy. Child Identity

21

An issue closely related to gestational mother involvement, as well as to special considerations of adoption, is how the identity of the child will be affected by the surrogacy. Some parents may choose to never tell their child about the surrogate arrangement. Others may tell the child as soon as they're old enough to understand. Others still may wait until the child turns 18. In any circumstance, knowledge or lack thereof regarding the surrogate arrangement may have an effect on the child's self-identity. Right and wrong in this case are also not well-defined, though the decision is worthy of careful thought and gentle handling. Compensation In some surrogacy arrangements, often when the aspiring parents do not know the gestational mother personally, the gestational mother is financially compensated for her services. It is not uncommon for the aspiring parents to pay for related medical expenses and even things such as meals, housing and maternity wear throughout the pregnancy, but some couples with the means to do so may pay what amounts to a fee to the gestational mother. Ethical criticisms of this practice, according to Cook, Sclater and Kaganas, include the view that this is a luxury available only to the wealthy and that it amounts to pregnancy-for-hire. Some critics also say that this presents an opportunity for wealthy, fertile couples to choose surrogacy rather than endure the strain involved in pregnancy.

Ethics of Surrogacy: Infertile People Should Adopt


Opposing viewpoints of surrogate parenthood argue, with all the unfortunate babies being born today in this world, isn't it the duty of the infertile couples out there to adopt them, instead of bringing more children, science babies at that, into this already overcrowded and difficult world? There are several reasons why an infertile couple may choose surrogacy over adoption. Often, there simply isn't a choice.

AdoptionLimitations In order to adopt a child in the United States, intended parents must jump through enormous hoops. There are interviews with social workers, home studies, and a long list of requirements. One of those requirements, in most situations, is age. This means that older intended parents are less likely to be
22

given

the

approval

to

adopt.

Infertility is commonly diagnosed in the late 30's to early 40's. So an intended mother, who is say, 38 when she tries to begin a family, and spends the next five years seeking treatment might be 43 by the time she has come to the point where adoption is a serious option. At that point, she is interviewed by an adoption agency and told that there is a 5 year waiting list. This puts her too old to be able to adopt, according to the rules and regulations in her area. AdoptionRisks Unlike in surrogacy, adoptive mothers have legal rights. In most cases, they have the ability to change their minds after they give birth and decide to keep the baby. This does not happen in surrogacy. A set of intended parents can become attached to an adoptive mother and baby, spending months of their time with her, going to doctor's appointments in some cases, paying for her cost of living, decorating a nursery for the upcoming birth, having a baby shower, watching the birth of their supposed child only to have the mother decide at the last minute that she doesn't want to put the baby up for adoption. AdoptionCosts Adoptive parents often pay for the medical and living expenses of the biological mother who "may" be giving up her baby to them. They also pay the legal fees. These collective fees are paid even if the biological mother ends up keeping the baby.Often, these fees equal an inexpensive surrogacy. Add in a failed adoption or two and the costs are completely in line with a typical surrogacy. So those arguments against surrogacy but for adoption who say that surrogacy is more expensive are not correct. Just uninformed.

Abortion
Abortion is the most difficult and controversial moral topic in todays society. Many people view abortion as a murder of unborn children. On the other hand, some people view it as freedom for women. We need to listen to both sides, even if that is difficult to do. Both sides have negative and positive moral
23

insights, even if ultimately these insights are outweighed by the insights of the otherside. There are two principal morals we need to consider; first, the moral status of the fetus. Is the fetus a person? At what age in its development does it becomes a person? Conception? First trimester? Birth? Secondly, the right of the pregnant woman, does the pregnant woman have the right to decide if she is going to carry the baby to term or not? As we consider these difficult issues, it is imperative to distinguish two other questions. Is abortion morally wrong or should abortion be illegal? These are distinct issues because not everything that is immoral is necessarily illegal. Another argument that is usually advanced against abortion is the fact that the fetus is an innocent person. It is morally wrong to end the life of an innocent person; therefore, it is morally wrong to end the life of a fetus. Much of the debate in regard to abortion has been centered on whether the fetus is a person or not. If the fetus is a person then it has the right that belongs to persons, including the right to life Is the Fetus a Person with Rights?: Much debate about the legality of abortion involves debating the legal status of the fetus. If the fetus is a person, anti-choice activists argue, then abortion is murder and should be illegal. Even if the fetus is a person, though, abortion may justified as necessary to womens bodily autonomy but that wouldnt mean that abortion is automatically ethical. Perhaps the state cant force women to carry pregnancies to term, but it could argue that it is the most ethical choice. Does the Woman have Ethical Obligations to the Fetus?: If a woman consented to sex and/or didnt properly use contraception, then she knew that pregnancy might result. Being pregnant means having a new life growing inside. Whether the fetus is a person or not, and whether the state takes a position on abortion or not, its arguable that a woman has some sort of ethical obligation to the fetus. Perhaps this obligation isnt strong enough to eliminate abortion as an option, but it may be enough to limit when abortion can be ethically chosen.

24

Does Abortion Treat the Fetus in an Unethical, Callous Way?: Most debates on the ethics of abortion focus on whether the fetus is a person. Even if it is not a person, however, this doesnt mean that it cant have any moral standing. Many people object to abortions later in pregnancy because they intuitively feel that there is something too human about a fetus which looks so much like a baby. Anti-choice activists rely heavily upon this and they have a point. Perhaps the ability to kill something which looks like a baby is one which we should avoid. Ethics of Personal, Bodily Autonomy: Its arguable that a right to abortion is a right to control ones body and the death of the fetus is a unavoidable consequence of choosing not to continue a pregnancy. That people have some ethical claim to personal, bodily autonomy must be regarded as fundamental to the conception of any ethical, democratic, and free society. Given that autonomy exists as an ethical necessity, the question becomes how far that autonomy extends. Can the state really force a woman to carry a pregnancy to term? Is it Ethical to Force a Woman to Carry a Pregnancy to Term?: If legalized abortion is eliminated, then the law will be used to force women to carry pregnancies to term using their bodies to provide a place where a fetus can develop into a baby. This is the ideal of anti-choice activists, but would it be ethical? Not permitting women a choice over being pregnant and reproducing is not compatible with justice in a free, democratic state. Even if the fetus is a person and abortion unethical, it shouldnt be prevented through unethical means. Ethics and the Consequences of Sexual Activity: Pregnancy almost invariably occurs as a consequence of sexual activity; thus, questions about the ethics of abortion must include questions about the ethics of sex itself. Some argue, or at least seem to assume, that sexual activity must carry consequences, one of which may be pregnancy. It is therefore unethical to try to prevent those consequences whether through abortion or contraception. Modern sexual liberty, however, is often focused on freeing sex from traditional consequences.
25

Does the Woman have Ethical Obligations to the Father?: Pregnancy can only occur with the participation of a man who is equally as responsible for the existence of the fetus as the woman. Should women give fathers any say in deciding whether the pregnancy is carried to term? If men have an ethical obligation to support a child after birth, dont they have an ethical claim on whether a child is born? Ideally, fathers would be consulted, but not every relationship is ideal and men dont run the same physical risks as a pregnant woman. Is it Ethical to Give Birth to an Unwanted Child?: While anti-choice activists like to hype supposed examples of women having abortions to keep their careers alive, its far more common that women have abortions because they feel unable to properly care for the child. Even if it were ethical to force women to carry pregnancies to term, it would not be ethical to force the birth of children who are unwanted and cannot be cared for. Women who choose to abort when they cannot be good mothers are making the most ethical choice open to them. Political vs. Religious Debates over the Ethics of Abortion: There are both political and religious dimensions to ethical debates over abortion. Perhaps the most significant error which people make is to confuse the two, acting as though a decision on the religious front should necessitate a particular decision on the political front (or vice-versa). So long as we accept the existence of a secular sphere where religious leaders have no authority and religious doctrines cannot be the basis for law, we must also accept that civil law may be at odds with religious beliefs

26

STANDARDS OF NURSING PRACTICE


The international organizations in the field of nursing has adopted certain standards in the professional practice situations. The international professional organizations of midwives such as The ANA , AWHONN have their own written manuals for the standards which the nurses are expected to implement in their practice situations. In India since the nursing as an emerging profession now a days we are adopting these standards into our practice situations in a modified form which is suited for the Indian situations. In midwifery practice mainly the ANA standards and the AWHONN standards are adapted. STANDARDS OF MATERNAL AND CHILD HEALTH NURSING PRACTICE BY ANA Standard 1 The nurse helps the children and parents to attain and maintain optimum health Standard 2 The nurse assists the families to achieve and maintain a balance between the personal growth needs of the individual family members and the optimum family functioning. Standard 3 The nurse intervenes with vulnerable clients and families at risk to prevent potential developmental and health problems. Standard 4 The nurse promote an environment free of hazards to reproduction , growth and development, wellness and recovery from the illness.

27

Standard 5 The nurse detects changes in health status and deviations from the optimum development

Standard 6 The nurse carries out appropriate interventions and treatment to facilitate the survival and recovery from the illness. Standard 7 The nurse assists the client and families to understand and cope with developmental and traumatic situations during illness , childbearing , childrearing and childhood. Standard 8 The nurse actively persues strategies to enhance acces to and use of adequate health care services. Standard 9 The nurse improves the maternal and child health practices through the evaluation of practice ,education and research. ASSOCIATION OF WOMENS HEALTH, OBSTETRIC AND NEONATALNURSES(AWHONN) NURSING PRACTICE STANDARDS Standard 1 Comprehensive nursing care of women and newborn focus on individuals, families and communities achieve their optimum health potential. This is best achieved within the framework of the nursing process.

Standard 2

28

Health education for the individual, family and community is an integral part of the comprehensive nursing practice and care. Such education encourages the participation in and shared responsibility for health promotion , maintenance and restoration

Standard 3 Written policies , procedures and protocols clarify the scope of nursing practice and delineate the qualifications of the personnel authorized to provide the care to women and newborns within the healthcare settings. Standard 4 Comprehensive nursing care for women and newborns is provided by nurse who are clinically comprehentand accountable for professional actions and legal responsibilities inherent to the nursing role. Standard 5 Nursing care for women and newborn is conducted in practice settings that have qualified nursing staff in sufficient numbers to meet the patient care needs Standard 6 Ethical principles guide the process of decision making for nurses caring for women and newborns at all times and especiallt when personal and professional values conflict with those of patients, families, colleagues or practice settings. Standard 7 Nurses caring for women and newborns utilize research findings, conduct nursing research, and evaluate nursing practice to improve outcomes of care. Standard 8 Quality and appropriateness of patient care and evaluated through a planned assessment program using specific, identified clinical indicators.
29

STANDING ORDERS
Standing orders are those orders which a nurse could be carried out in emergency situations in the absence of a physician. The nurse midwife should expand the range of knowledge to be a perfect health care professional and to implement the standing orders by identifying the situations correctly. The nurse practitioner must pocess a detailed knowledge regarding the disease process and the drug peculiarities before administering the drug. Core Section of Patient Group Directions Introduction Patient group direction supersedes Midwives Standing Orders. This patient group direction states which medicines may be supplied and administered by midwives within the Borders General Hospital NHS Trust. Midwives may, under the Medicines Act 1968, supply all medical products on the General Sale List and Pharmacy List and administer a small range of Prescription Only Medicines. The formulary contains monographs for all products within the patient group directions and should be used in conjunction with the information in the core section of the patient group direction. Clinical Decision Making Patientswhomayreceivemidwivesformularymedicines This patient group direction should be used for the supply and/or administration of the agreed medicines to ante-partum, intra-partum or postpartum mothers within the Borders General Hospital NHS Trust. The medicines may only be used within individual product monograph recommendations and contra-indications.

30

Consent If the patient does not wish to receive treatment with a formulary item, and no alternative is listed, medical help should be sought to find a suitable therapy. Patient Information Leaflets may be supplied if available. Contra-indications No product in this formulary should be used without consideration of the possible consequences to the patient. Formulary products should not be used if the patient has previously had or suspected an adverse reaction to the product, or if a contra-indication for that patient occurs in the monograph. In these cases the patient should be referred to a doctor. Precautions The products listed in this formulary should be used only for the specific condition specified in the monograph. Formulary items should not be used for the treatment of patients who have known, or suspected hypersensitivity to any product or any of its ingredients. In the event that an adverse reaction occurs, use of the product should be stopped and medical help sought immediately. Facilities for treating anaphylaxis should always be available.

Designated staff authorised to administer midwives formulary products


Authorised Staff The following staff who are employed by the Borders General Hospital NHS Trust are authorised to administer Midwives Formulary products without individual medical prescription for conditions specified in the product monograph. Registered Midwife In addition the following requirements are necessary: To be professionally accountable To have received adequate training and be competent To be familiar with contra-indications to the product
31

To have access to the current group protocols for the administration of Medicines in the Midwives Formulary To be trained to identify anaphylaxis To have immediate access to appropriate equipment and drugs to treat anaphylaxis and have access to the current protocol and guidelines for its management To maintain their own professional level of competence and knowledge.

Head of Midwifery/Midwife Managers will be responsible for: Ensuring that there are patient group directions for the administration of medicines in the midwifery formulary Ensuring that midwives administering products have received adequate training and follow the patient group directions for the administration of products in the midwifery formulary.

The midwife will be given a copy of the patient group directions which she/he will sign along with the line manager and Pharmacist. Treatment Available Product, Dose, Route and Frequency See individual product monograph and summary table Adverse Reactions See individual product monographs Follow-up Treatment Patients should be observed for any sign of adverse drug reaction Documentation Out-patient settings The supply of medicines must be documented in the womans case notes, eg an immediate discharge letter should be completed and filed (B77). In-patients

32

All medicines must be prescribed on the Obstetric Medicine Chart for Self Medication/Borders General Hospital NHS Medicine Chart and documented in the case notes, according to policies and procedures relating to the department. The name of the prescribing midwife must be printed legibly and signed. FurtherPoints Manufacturer and patient information leaflets for any product in the formulary should be read and advice taken from them. The recommendations for storage and handling of any product in the formulary must be followed.

Concurrent Medication See individual product monograph for the details of each medications.

ANTEPARTUM
ANALGESIA ANTACID Paracetamol 1gram as a single dose once only Maalox suspension 10ml as a single dose, once only or Peptac liquid 10-20ml as a single dose, once only APERIENT Ispaghula Husk 3.5g one sachet in water, once only

PROPHYLAXIS FOR Ranitidine tablet 150mg at 22.00 on night MENDELSONS SYNDROME before theatre, repeated two hours before IN ELECTIVE LSCS theatre. Sodium Citrate 0.3M 30ml orally once only immediately prior to transfer to Theatre

33

I.V. THERAPY

Compound Sodium Lactate 1 litrei.v. over 8-12 hours, to a maximum of two litres Heparin 10iu/ml 5ml instilled into i.v. cannula when required every 4-8 hours

LOCAL ANAESTHETIC

Lignocaine 1% 0.1ml intradermally prior to cannulation once only Amethocaine gel 4% 1g under occlusive dressing 45 minutes prior to venouscannulation once only

NIGHT SEDATION

Temazepam10mg as a single dose up to 2.00am in the morning.

DINOPROSTONE VAGINAL GEL As per induction of labourguidelines.

FOLIC ACID DEMULCENT COUGH PREPARATION

Folic acid 400microgram tablet once daily, until 12-14 weeks gestation. Simple linctus 5ml once only

ANTISPASMODIC

Peppermint water 10ml in plenty of water, once only.

ANTI D IMMUNOGLOBULIN Anti-D immunoglobulin may be given to all non-sensitised Rh D negative women within 72 hours of a sensitising event in the following circumstances
34

Prior to 20 weeks gestation Anti-D 250iu by i.m. injection Threatened miscarriage after 12 weeks gestation Spontaneous miscarriage after 12 weeks gestation Ectopic pregnancy Therapeutic termination of pregnancy medical and surgical Following sensitising events such as amniocentesis Incomplete miscarriage requiring E.R.P.O.C.

After 20 weeks gestatation Anti- D 500i.u. by i.m. injection Antepartum haemorrhage External cephalic version Intrauterine death Invasive prenatal diagnostic and intrauterine procedures Blunt abdominal trauma Routine Ante-natal Anti-D prophylaxis Anti-D 500i.u. by i.m. injection at 28 and 34 weeks gestation

INTRAPARTUM
ANALGESIA Entonox inhalation as required Diamorphinei.m. 5-10mg every 3-4 hours (women <50kg before pregnancy 5mg only) providing delivery is not imminent, up to a maximum of 2 doses without reference to a Registrar. Monitor respirations for 30 minutes after administration Cyclizine50mg i.m. every 8 hours as required to a maximum of 150mg/24 hours Metoclopramide 10mg i.m. every 8 hours as required to a maximum of 30mg in 24 hours or 500 micrograms per Kg in 24 hours for women<60kg

ANTI-EMETICS

35

PROPHYLAXSIS FOR Ranitidine tablet 150mg every 6 MENDELSONS SYNDROME Sodium Citrate 0.3M 30ml prior to Theatre ACTIVE MANAGEMENT OFLABOUR Oxytocin 10i.u.as per unit policy Syntometrine 1ml i.m. with anterior shoulder at delivery Compound Sodium Lactate 1 litrei.v. every 8-12 hours as required to a maximum of 2 litres Heparin 10u/ml 5ml instilled into i.v. cannula every 4-8 hours when required Lignocaine 1% 0.1ml intradermally prior to cannulation, once only Amethocaine gel 4% 1g under occlusive dressing 45 minutes prior to venous cannulation once only Glycerine Suppository 1 or 2 per rectum or Docusate sodium 90mg microenema as required EPISIOTOMY PAEDIATRICS The following may be administered to babies after delivery without reference to Paediatric staff: Oxygen by facemask Phytomenadione 1mg by i.m. injection Lignocaine 1% 10ml by perineal infiltration

I.V. THERAPY

LOCAL ANAESTHETIC

LAXATIVES

POSTPARTUM

36

EPISIOTOMY REPAIR

Lignocaine 1% by perineal infiltration to a maximum of 20ml

ANALGESIA NSAID ANALGESIC Only one NSAID should be prescribed at any one time

Cesarean Section for first 24 hours: Anaesthetist will be responsible for analgesia. Unless contra-indicated diclofenac suppository 100mg will be given rectally in Theatre. One dose of an NSAID can be given 14-16 hours after the suppository. If Diclofenac is given, the total dose must not exceed 150mg by all routes in any 24 hours period.

Vaginal delivery or Cesarean Section after first 24 hours: Ibuprofen tablet or syrup 400mg or 600mg three times a day. Diclofenac tablet or suppository 50mg three times a day (to a maximum of 150mg in 24 hours by any route).

PARACETAMOL BASEDANALGESIC Only one paracetamol based analgesicshould be prescribed at any one time. Paracetamol 1gram every 4-6 hours to a maximum of 4grams in any 24 hours as plain or effervescent tablets or rectally as suppository. Co-dydramol 2 tablets every 4-6 hours to a maximum of 8 tablets in any 24 hours. ANTIEMETIC Cyclizine50mg i.m. every 8 hours as required to a maximum of 150mg/24 hours. Metoclopramide 10mg i.m. every 8 hours as required to a maximum of 30mg in 24 hours or 500 micrograms per Kg in 24 hours for women<60kg

37

LAXATIVES

Ispaghula Husk 3.5g, 1 sachet in water twice Daily

Lactulose 10ml orally twice daily Glycerine suppository 1 or 2 per rectum as required I.V. THERAPY Compound Sodium Lactate 1 litre i.v. every 8-12 hours as required to a maximum of 2 litres Heparin 10u/ml 5ml instilled into i.v. cannula every 4-8 hours when required

LOCAL ANAESTHETIC

Lignocaine 1% 0.1ml intradermally prior to cannulation, once only Amethocaine gel 4% 1g under occlusive dressing 45 minutes prior to venous cannulation once only

ANTI D

Anti-D Immunoglobulin 500i.u or more. by i.m. injection to Rh D negative women with a Rh D positive baby within 72 hours of delivery as per obstetric unit guidelines.

VACCINES

Rubella vaccine (live) 0.5ml by deep subcutaneous or intramuscular injection if mother not immune.

IRON SUPPLEMENT

Ferrous sulphate tablet 200mg three times a day if haemoglobin below 10g/dl. If symptomatic refer to SHO.
38

DEMULCENT COUGH PREPARATION

Simple linctus 5ml 3-4 times a day.

ANTISPASMODIC

Peppermint water 10ml in plenty of water, once only.

EMERGENCY PRESCRIPTIONS
The following can be administered FOLLOWING AND ONLY WITH reference to medical staff, provided that all are entered correctly in the casenotes/drug or i.v. prescription sheet, signed by the initiating midwife and countersigned by the duty SHO as soon as practicable

OXYGEN TREATMENT OF SEVERE HYPOGLYCAEMIA

Oxygen6 litres/minute by face mask Glucagon 1mg i.m. or i.v. Hypostop gel orally as required

ANTEPARTUM Compound Sodium Lactate 500HAEMORRHAGE1000ml stat IV POSTPARTUM HAEMORRHAGE Syntometrine 1ml I.M Oxytocin 10i.u by i.m. or i.v. injection Oxytocin 40i.u. in 1 litre Compound Sodium Lactate at a rate of up to 250ml/hour

CONCLUSION

39

Maternity nursing is now a days emerging as the most considerable regions in the field of nursing. In our country also it is developing into an independent practice area while considering the other areas of nursing are not yet approached to the level of an independent professional practice area. So the nurse midwives should have a thorough understanding and independent and interdependent wide range of thought in the field of ethical considerations, professional standards and standing orders for a nurse midwife should be taken into account before planning the actions and implementing them because the nurse midwife is answerable legally towards any unwanted outcome of the intervention. So it is the responsibility of the nurse to gain adequate knowledge and skill in the professional practice areas.

BIBLIOGRAPHY
Lowdermilk& Perry MATERNITY AND WOMWENS TH HEALTHCARE8 edn Mosby publications . Pp 11-12 Adele Pilletteri MATERNAL AND CHILD HEALTH NURSING CARE OF CHILD BEARING AND CHILD REAEING FAMILY 2NDedn. J. B Lippincott company Pp 20-22 Murrey&Mc Kinney FOUNDATIONDS OF MATERNAL, TH NEWBORN AND WOMENS HEALTH NURSING 5 edn Saunders publication Pp 37-51 GiaGanguly Mukherjee MEDICOLEGAL ASPECTS IN OBSTETRICS AND GYNECOLOGY 2NDednJaypee brothers publications New DelhiPp1-20 Illyasa R Foster & Jon Lasser PROFESSIONAL ETHICS IN MIDWIFERY PRACTICE 1STedn Jones and Bartilett publishers Pp9-37 NET REFERANCES http://books.google.co.in/books/about/Ethics_in_Midwifery.html http://www.facebook.com/pages/Professional-Ethics-in-Midwifery-Practice http://midwiferytoday.com/articles/interncode.asp www.facebook.com/pages/Professional-Ethics-in-Midwifery-Practice http://www.midwives.org.au/scripts/ http://www.nmc-uk.org/Nurses-and-midwives/The-code
40

http://www.dundee.ac.uk http://www.scidev.net/en/health/clinical-ethics http://infomidwife.blogspot.com/2008/03 http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/ http://www.handbook.uts.edu.au/subjects http://fhs.mcmaster.ca/ethics/documents/Ethics_in_Midwifery_

41

42

Anda mungkin juga menyukai