Anda di halaman 1dari 20

Soochow Journal of Philosophical Studies, No. 16August 2007, pp.

283-302
2007 Soochow University
283
The Analytic/Continental Divide:
Entities and Being

Nevia Dolcini

I. Introduction
Though it remains controversial and is often the subject of strident
criticism, the tradition of sharply dividing Analytic from Continental
philosophy persists and is widely accepted. Anglo-American philosophers of
the middle twentieth-century are well-known for neglecting Continental ideas
by simply appealing to the orthodoxy of an allegedly unbridgeable
analytic/continental divide. The same tactic is now prevalent among
SKLORVRSKHUV ZKR GLVWLQJXLVK WKHPVHOYHV DV LQ WKH &RQWLQHQWDO WUDGLWLRQ
Many authors have dedicated themselves to the topic of the Divide in the
attempt to single out its historical and philosophical origins. Among others,
this includes: Richard Rorty
1
and Michael Friedman
2
(two non-partisan
analytic philosophers); Andrew Cutrofello
3
)UDQFD '$JRVWLQL
4
and Franco

Proofreaders: Donald James Sturgeon, Ya-Ting Yang, Kuan-Jung Kao

Assistant Professor, Department of Philosophy, University of Macerata, Italy.


1
Richard Rorty (1979).
2
Michael Friedman (2000).
3
Andrew Cutrofello (2005).
4
)UDQFD '$JRVWLQL (1997).
Soochow Journal of Philosophical Studies, No. 16
284
Restaino
5
(who describe the Divide from an historical point of view); Pascal
Engel
6
, etc. In this paper, I begin by presenting a short overview and
criticism of the traditional ways in which the Divide has been analyzed. I then
show that the two schools are fundamentally different because of their
orientation to the problem of accommodating time in a theory of Being.
According to my approach, the Divide finds its deepest roots in two different
RQWRORJLFDO SHUVSHFWLYHV ,Q SDUWLFXODU , ZLOO DUJXH WKDW WKH QHZ DQG
UHDFWLRQDU\ RQWRORJLFDO SHUVSHFWLYH SURSRVHG E\ +HLGHJJHU LQ Being and
Time (B&T) is the proper way to understand what is distinct about the so-called
&RQWLQHQWDO WUDGLWLRQ +HLGHJJHU FKDUDFWHUL]HV WKLV SHUVSHFWLYH DV EHLQJ LQ
RSSRVLWLRQ WR WKH WUDGLWLRQDO RQWRORJ\ ZKLFK KH FDOOV D VXEVWDQFH WKHRU\ RU
RQWRORJ\ RI SUHVHQFH The substance theory, at least as Heidegger presents it,
is naturally bounded to science and to a kind of philosophical methodology
that is well represented by analytical philosophy.
+HLGHJJHU GUDZV D GLVWLQFWLRQ EHWZHHQ DQ RQWLFDO DQG DQ RQWRORJLFDO
OHYHO RI LQTXLU\ +LV GLVWLQFWLRQ FRXOG EH LQWHUSUHted more generally as an
unbridgeable gulf between a substance-theory-EDVHG RU VWDWLF RQWRORJ\ WR
which analytical philosophers and scientists are normally wedded), and a
G\QDPLF RQWRORJ\ 7KH ODWWHU FOHDUO\ ILQGV RQH RI LWV PRVW VWULNLQJ
representations in Heidegger
7
and seems to be compatible with, if not to
underlie, most of the streams of continental philosophy (hermeneutics,
5
Franco Restaino (1999).
6
Pascal Engel (1997).
7
There is no real GLIIHUHQFH ZLWK UHJDUG WR WKLV SRLQW DIWHU +HLGHJJHUV SKLORVRSKLFDO WXUQ WKH
VHFRQG +HLGHJJHU RIWHQ FKDUDFWHUL]HV WKH %HLQJ LQ WHUPV RI Ereignis HYHQW IXOO\
SUHVHUYLQJ WKH G\QDPLF FRQFHSWLRQ RI WKH %HLQJ 6HH IRU H[DPSOH +HLGHJJHU (1947).
The Analytic/Continental Divide: Entities and Being
285
existentialism, and so on.).
The traditional trust that analytical philosophy gives to scientific
disciplines can perhaps be best understood by observing the affinity between
the static ontology of substance theory and the scientific approach represented,
in particular, in neo-positivism. On the other side, the Heideggerian
ontological perspective that influenced many of the continental philosophers is
incompatible with the substance theory (and its philosophy of science). Thus,
the difficulties of communication (and sometimes dismissive attitudes)
between continental and analytic traditions is best explained by appeal to their
two very different orientations to the place of time in ontology.
II. Characterizing the Divide by its Origins and Sources
A number of writers have attempted to characterize the differences
between Analytical and Continental Philosophy in the hope of pinpointing the
origins and nature of the divisions between them. Currently, many
philosophers working within the Western tradition consider themselves, or are
considered by the others, as belonging to one of the two philosophical
IDPLOLHV $ VKRUW OLVW RI PHPEHUV RI WKH $QDO\WLFDO IDPLO\ ZRXOG LQFOXGH
Bolzano, Husserl, Frege (who are among its founding fathers), Brentano,
Meinong, Moore, Russell, Wittgenstein, Carnap, Tarski, Schlick, Neurath, Ayer,
Popper, Quine, Davidson, Putnam, Dummett, Strawson, and Kripke. Within the
&RQWLQHQWDO IDPLO\ ZH ILQG SKLORVRSKHUV VXFK DV +HLGHJJHU $GRUQR
Gadamer, Sartre, Merleau-Ponty, Derrida, Habermas, etc.
8
8
See, Kevin Mulligan (1998).
Soochow Journal of Philosophical Studies, No. 16
286
7DNLQJ D FXH IURP WKH ZRUG FRQWLQHQWDO RQH PLJKW DWWHPSW WR FODVVLI\
each family on the basis of geography. Thus, Analytical Philosophy (AP) will
be that kind of philosophy practiced in countries where the English language is
dominant (Great Britain, North European countries, U.S.A., Canada, and
Australia), while Continental Philosophy (CP) will be the kind practiced
mostly on the European continent (in countries such as Germany, France, Italy,
and Spain). But a geographical characterization is problematic for at least two
reasons: first, AP itself has its roots on the continent as much as CP does
(Frege, Wittgenstein, Carnap, among others, are unquestionably among
analytic philosophers and nonetheless are geographically continental); second,
there are currently many analytic philosophers on the Continent and even more
Continental philosophers in English language dominated countries. It is often
the case that philosophers belonging to the two different traditions share
philosophy departments, both in English-speaking countries and on the
Continent. The communication and interaction between them, though, is not
easy and sometimes even absent, as suggested by the metaphor in which
0LFKDHO 'XPPHWW FRPSDUHV $3 DQG &3 WR WKH 5KLQH DQG WKH 'DQXEH >@
rivers that rise quite close to one another and for a time pursue roughly
parallel courses, only to diverge in utterly different directions and flow into
different seas. >@ LWV QR XVH QRZ VKRXWLQJ DFURVV WKH JXOI
9
Why is such communication so difficult? Is there a real
LQFRPPHQVXUDELOLW\ EHWZHHQ DQDO\VWV DQG FRQWLQHQWDOV" 6RPH DXWKRUV LQ
order to clarify the gap between the two traditions, try to identify its sources.
9
Michael Dummett (1993).
The Analytic/Continental Divide: Entities and Being
287
According to Dummett, for example, AP finds its point of departure in Frege,
while CP starts with the phenomenology of Husserl. Franco Restaino considers
:LWWJHQVWHLQV Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (1921-22) as the origin of the
$3 WUDGLWLRQ DQG +HLGHJJHUV Being and Time (1927) as the origin of the CP
tradition.
10
Often the Divide has been characterized as a struggle over the Kantian
legacy
11
. Rorty and Friedman, for example, have each tried to represent the
division has having its roots in a distinction that Kant draws between two
VXSSRVHGO\ VHSDUDEOH HOHPHQWV RI KXPDQ FRJQLWLRQ LQWXLWLRQV DQG
FRQFHSWV
12
. In A Parting of the Ways: Carnap, Cassirer, and Heidegger
13
,
Friedman locates the divisiRQ EHWZHHQ SKLORVRSK\V WZR FXOWXUHV LQ WKH DWWHPSW
made by rival schools of late-nineteenth and early-twentieth-century
neo-Kantians to rid themselves of the intuition/concept dichotomy. One school
presented an account of human experience that gave primacy to the natural
sciences (the view adopted by the Marburg School of neo-Kantianism); the
other privileged the Geisteswissenschaften or cultural sciences (the position of
the Southwest School).
Another aspect that has been thought to characterize the divide is the
10
Restaino (1999: 5-16). According to Restaino, Wittgenstein would be the father of three
streams of AP, namely, logical atomism (in England), logical positivism (in Vienna), and, later
on, ordinary language philosophy. Heidegger would play a central role as the main source of
phenomenology, existentialism and hermeneutics.
11
Ricouer (1998: 50).
12
According to Kant (1997), intuitions are immediate representations of individual objects that
are somehow given to us through a faculty of receptivity, while concepts are spontaneously
generated forms of thought in terms of which we recognize such objects.
13
Friedman (2000: 155-156).
Soochow Journal of Philosophical Studies, No. 16
288
relationship between science and art. In Nineteenth-Century Idealism and
Twentieth-Century Textualism
14
Rorty observes that a certain way of thinking
about the relationship gave rise to a nineteenth-century polemic between
SRVLWLYLVWV DQG 5RPDQWLFV DQG KH VXJJHVWV WKDW WKH WZHQWLHWK-century split
between analytic and continental philosophers is just an extension of this
debate. Freidman implicitly agrees that the analytic/continental division
concerns the relative importance of science and art, but, as noted, he considers
this to be a consequence of the split between different forms of
neo-Kantianism.
Sometimes the Divide has been interpreted as a metaphilosophical
conflict which is intrinsic to the philosophical enterprise itself. This account is
IRXQG LQ &XWURIHOORV SUHVHQWDWLRQ
15
of the Divide as a controversy about the
nature of philosophical controversies themselves.
In Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature
16
, Rorty characterizes the
differences between analytical and continental philosophical practices in terms
RI DQ HVVHQWLDOO\ GLIIHUHQW UHODWLRQ WR 7UXWK ,QIOXHQFHG E\ *DGDPHUV Truth
and Method
17
5RUW\ VHHV $3 DV D V\VWHPDWLF SKLORVRSK\ DQG &3 DV DQ
HGLI\LQJ SKLORVRSK\ +H ZULWHV I want now to generalize this contrast
between philosophers whose work is essentially constructive and those whose
14
The essay, published in 1981, is collected in Rorty (1982).
15
Cutrofello (2005).
16
Rorty (1979).
17
Gadamer (1975). In particular Rorty takes from Gadamer the idea of the contrast between the
desire for edification (Bildung) and the desire for truth. According to Gadamer (and many
continentals such as Heidegger and Sartre), however, such a contrast does not need to be
resolved: the search for the truth (via objective knowledge) is just one human project (or type
RI HGLILFDWLRQ DPRQJ RWKHUV
The Analytic/Continental Divide: Entities and Being
289
work is essentially reactive. I shall thereby develop a contrast between
philosophy which centers in epistemology and the sort of philosophy which
takes its point of departure from suspicion about the pretensions of
HSLVWHPRORJ\ 7KLV LV WKH FRQWUDVW EHWZHHQ V\VWHPDWLF DQG HGLI\LQJ
philosophies
18
This characterization is drawn at the epistemological level.
Focusing again on the role of language in the two traditions in Contingency,
Irony and Solidarity,
19
Rorty characterizes the continental philosophers (such
as Nietzsche, Heidegger, Foucault and Derrida) as ironists who aim not at the
truth, as do analysts, but at self-transformation. In fact, Rorty goes so far as to
GHILQH DQ LURQLVW DV RQH ZKR UHIXVHV WR DFFHSW DQ\ ILQDO YRFDEXODU\ DV
absolute.
All these interpretations of the divide focus on the origins and sources of
WKH WZR WUDGLWLRQV 7KH\ HDFK DGG LPSRUWDQW HOHPHQWV WR RQHV understanding of
the current situation in philosophy. But their explanations of the actual
differences are limited.
III. Explaining the Differences: Some Criteria
Recently there have been new attempts to explain the divide by
establishing criteria apparently crucial for grasping its nature. The list of the
main criteria used in the critical comparison of the two traditions includes: the
style; specialization into philosophical sub-disciplines or the lack thereof; the
relationship between the kind of philosophy and other disciplines such as
18
Rorty (1979: 366).
19
Rorty (1989).
Soochow Journal of Philosophical Studies, No. 16
290
science and history; language, etc
20
.
The style of philosophical expression has been considered one of the most
important of the criteria for distinguishing analysts from continentals. In
JHQHUDO FRQWLQHQWDOV DGRSW D PRUH OLWHUDU\ VW\OH WKDQ DQDO\VWV VRPHWLPHV
continentals give their concern for style override their concern for ideas,
allowing the coloring of their sentences to take precedence over their
discursive clarity. Although continentals often adopt distinctive personal styles,
it is normally very easy to distinguish them from analysts. In contrast, the
concern for clarity is always a top priority among analysts and as a result they
seem to adopt a more unified and recognizable style employing definitions and
a careful use of arguments. The role of argument is different in the two
traditions.
21
AP has concern for rigor and correct reasoning; its practices are
based on the elucidation of propositions, and definitions, descriptions and
DQDO\VHV SHUYDGH WKHLU FRQVWUXFWLRQ RI WKHRULHV &3V SKLORVRSKLFDO ZRUNLQJV
are based on creating concepts, unmasking, decoding, intuiting by the usage of
metaphors and even (often undefined) neologisms.
Another criterion is specialization (or the lack of specialization) of the
type of philosophy into sub-disciplines. Generally, in CP there is a relative
lack of specialization into sub-disciplines. While engaged in cultural critique,
continental philosophers search for a systematic and global view, working at
20
See, Neil Levy (2003) )UDQFD '$JRVWLni (1997: 57-62).
21
Dagfinn Fllesdal (1997), for example, characterizes the differences between the two traditions
as essentially a difference in the place given to arguments, rather than rhetoric. Rorty (1979:
369), in distinguishing between systematic and edifying philosophers, states that the former
are constructive and offer arguments ZKLOH WKH ODWWHU are reactive and offer satires,
parodies, aphorisms
The Analytic/Continental Divide: Entities and Being
291
the same time on several issues under a general theme. AP often rejects
systematic philosophy, dividing issues into myriad sub-disciplines (philosophy
of mind, of language, metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, and so on)
specialized in a very well-defined thematic field.
The two traditions differ in their relationship with other disciplines such
as history, politics, sociology, and psychology. In contrast with much of
analytic philosophy, continental philosophers do not take empirical science as
paradigm of rationality.
22
While analysts share with scientists a fundamental
DWWLWXGH RI WUXVW LQ WKH SRVVLELOLW\ RI objective knowledge and progress,
continental thinkers frequently reject this attitude, emphasizing the role of the
VXEMHFW DQG VXEMHFWLYLW\ DQG RIWHQ VHHP DQWL-VFLHQWLVWLF 7KH\ REMHFW WR WKH
hegemony empirical science has had in shaping modern culture, insisting that
the concepts of empirical science offer neither the only kind of knowledge nor
even the most basic kind. They tend to favor the view that modern scientific
concepts present a secondary or derivative way of knowing (Husserl,
Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, Levinas, Lyotard, Foucault, etc.). AP is generally
not just friendlier with science, it also often endeavors to work together with it.
,Q WKLV YLHZ WKH SKLORVRSKHUV WDVN LV WR SURYLGH WKH IRXQGDWLRQV RI ERWK WKH
empirical and mathematical sciences. There is also an evident attempt within
the analytic tradition to think of philosophical and scientific inquiries as
related, mutually supportive and sharing the same PHWD-ODQJXDJH ,Q
Analytic and Conversational Philosophy
23
, Rorty characterizes the dominant
analytic conception of philosophy as a kind of conceptual handmaiden to
22
Cooper (1994) takes this criterion to be the most crucial one.
23
Richard Rorty (2003).
Soochow Journal of Philosophical Studies, No. 16
292
VFLHQFH JHWWLQJ WKLQJV ULJKW DQG VHDUFKLQJ IRU WLPHOHVV SURSRVLWLRQDO WUXWKV
while the dominant continental conception of philosophy is characterized as
cultural critique.
The two traditions relate differently to history
24
. In CP philosophical
problems are treated in their historical context, while in AP there is a tendency
to treat them in an atemporal or ahistorical way. In another sense, history is the
element in which continental philosophers find their work meaningful. As
5RUW\ SXWV LW they know their work loses its point when the period they were
reacting against is over
25
$QDO\WLF SKLORVRSKHUV DV VFLHQWLVWV WHQG WR EXLOG
IRU HWHUQLW\ DQG FRQVLGHU WKHLU SUDFWLFHV DV DWHPSRUDO LQ WKH VHQVH WKDW DQ\
philosophical theory has (or does not have) validity independently from its
historical context.
The Divide has often been characterized as deriving from differences in
concern with language. One of the best-known attempts to characterize it in
these terms is due to Michael Dummett. He claims that AP distinguishes itself
IURP WKH RWKHU WUDGLWLRQ E\ WKH EHOLHI ILUVW that a philosophical account of
thought can be attained through a philosophical account of language, and,
secondly, that a comprehensive account can only be so attained
26
. This
account of language is closely related to what is presented by Rorty as the
LPDJH RI V\VWHPDWLF SKLORVRSK\ DV LQYROYHG ZLWK WKH LPDJH RI WKH PLQG RU
24
Simon Critchley (1997) takes this criterion as the main one in explaining the Divide; thus,
Critchley interprets the two traditions as essentially based on their different attitudes toward
history.
25
Rorty (1979: 369).
26
Dummett (1993: 4).
The Analytic/Continental Divide: Entities and Being
293
ODQJXDJH DV PLUURULQJ WKH QDWXUH
27
.
It would be possible to go on analyzing the differences between AP and
CP taking into account other criteria, such as the different audiences to which
the two traditions address themselves
28
, the different subjects they deal with,
and so on. I suggest, though, that such descriptive accounts characterize only
WKH SKHQRPHQRQ RI WKH 'LYLGH ZLWKRXW FDSWXULQJ LWV QDWXUH 0\ SURSRVDO LV
that the Divide is best understood by individuating it by means of a
fundamental disagreement in the role time is to play in ontology. This
difference, which is sometimes not explicitly manifest, is the basis of their
divergent orientations. It is this disagreement that generates their differences in
method, style, interests, languages, the role of the subject and subjectivity in
inquiry, and so forth.
IV. Entities and Being: An Ontological-Ground for the Divide
Early signs of a fundamental difference between two ways of conceiving
philosophy began to appear around the end of the Nineteenth Century
29
, but the
'LYLGH EHFDPH GUDPDWLF LQ WKH 7KLUWLHV ZLWK WKH DSSHDUDQFH RI &DUQDSV HVVD\
27
Rorty (1979: 393).
28
Continental philosophers commonly address themselves to the educated public at large, while
analytic philosophers are generally comprehensible only to other specialists.
29
Franz Brentano (considered by many as one of the fathers of analytical philosophy), in
UHYLHZLQJ DQ HVVD\ E\ :LOKHOP 'LOWKH\ FULWLFL]HG WKH REVFXULW\ RI 'LOWKH\V DUJXPHQWDWLRQ
WKH ODFN RI ORJLF DQG WKH QXPHURXV PLVWDNHV LQ WKH WH[W .HYLQ 0XOOLJDQ KDV SRLQWHG RXW WKDW
%UHQWDQRV UHYLHZ ZLWKRXW VLJQDWXUH DQG FULWLFLVP RI 'LOWKH\V ZRUN FDQ EH FRQVLGHUHG WKH
first document in the struggle between analytic and continental philosophers.
Soochow Journal of Philosophical Studies, No. 16
294
The elimination of Metaphysics through Logical Analysis of Language
30
.
&DUQDSV SDSHU KHUDOGHG WKH JHQHUDO UHMHFWLRQ RI PHWDSK\VLFV DV PHDQLQJOHVV
and contained D VFDWKLQJ FULWLFLVP RI +HLGHJJHUV ZRUN LQ SDUWLFXODU ,Q
D IHZ \HDUV EHIRUH &DUQDSV HVVD\ +HLGHJJHUV Being and Time (B&T) was
published. Its influence has been extensive and contributed in particular to
phenomenology (Merleau-Ponty, Levinas), existentialism (Sartre, Ortega y
Gasset), hermeneutics (Gadamer, Ricouer), political theory (Hanna Arendt, the
early Marcuse), post-modernism (Lyotard, Derrida), and even to theories of
psychotherapy (Medard Boss, Ludwig Binswanger, Rollo May). It is a book
DERXW RQWRORJ\ +HLGHJJHUV RQO\ GHFODUHG SKLORVRSKLFDO FRQFHUQ +HLGHJJHU
boldly presents his attempt as revolutionary because it offers a new conception
of how to state and to answer the fundamental philosophical question (the
question of Being) and contrasts it with that of the Western philosophical
tradition. In B&T he interprets Western traditions of explanation as dominated,
since Plato and Aristotle, by the concept of an entity and its properties and
UHODWLRQV ,Q +HLGHJJHUV YLHZ WKLV IRUPV DQ RQWLFDO LQTXLU\ +H GRHV QRW
reject the concept of an entity and he considers ontical inquiry to be useful, but
he maintains that a new kind of inquiry is needed in philosophy: an
RQWRORJLFDO LQTXLU\
What is the distinction between an ontical and the ontological inquiry?
30
Carnap (1932) 7KH PDLQ WDUJHW ZDV +HLGHJJHUV :DV LVW 0HWDSK\VLN" DQG LQ
SDUWLFXODU &DUQDS FULWLFL]HG +HLGHJJHUV UHIOHFWLRQV RQ WKH VHQWHQFH 1RWKLQJQHVV LWVHOI
nothings [Das Nichts selbst nichtet@ +H PDLQWDLQV WKDW VLQFH LW YLRODWHV WKH ODZV RI ORJLF WKLV
sentence was utterly meaningless. According to Carnap, Heidegger and philosophers of that
VRUW DUH MXVW OLNH PXVLFLDQV ZLWKRXW PXVLFDO DELOLW\ 7KLV FULWLFLVP IURP D &DUQDSLDQ SRLQW RI
view, can be easily applied to the most contemporary continental philosophers.
The Analytic/Continental Divide: Entities and Being
295
Ontological inquiry is concerned primarily with Being; ontical inquiry is
concerned with entities and the facts about them. As one might suspect,
+HLGHJJHU GRHV QRW SURYLGH XV ZLWK D GHILQLWLRQ RI RQWRORJLFDO LQTXLU\ 7KLV
should not be VXUSULVLQJ VLQFH RQ KLV YLHZ %HLQJ LWVHOI LV LQ SULQFLSOH
resistant to definition because it must be understood in terms of temporality.
Being cannot properly be captured as itself an entity among others standing in
fixed relations; it cannot be defined atemporally. Moreover, an ontological
inquiry is more primordial than any ontical inquiry (as for example is found in
empirical science), because Being is more primordial than entities. Heidegger
writes: The question of being aims therefore at ascertaining the a priori
conditions not only for the possibilities of the sciences which examine entities
as entities of such and such a type, and, in so doing, already operate with an
understanding of Being, but also for the possibility of those ontologies
themselves which are prior to the ontical sciences and which provide their
foundations
31
.
The decision about which of the two kinds of inquiry should be preferred
WR WKH RWKHU GHSHQGV RQ RQHV DVVXPSWLRQV DERXW WKH QDWXUH RI RQWRORJ\
Philosophers dealing with an ontical inquiry seem to assume, even if just for
FULWLFL]LQJ LW D VRUW RI VXEVWDQFH RQWRORJ\ LQ +HLGHJJHUV WHUPV DFFRUGLQJ
to which reality has the following nature: what is ultimately real is that which
XQGHUOLHV SURSHUWLHV RU DWWULEXWHV VXE-staQWLD VXEVWDQFH VWDQGV XQGHU
WKLQJV DUH HQWLWLHV RU VXEVWDQFHV ZLWK SURSHUWLHV WKLQJV LQWHUDFW FDXVDOO\
with one another; substance remains continuously present throughout all
31
Ibid.
Soochow Journal of Philosophical Studies, No. 16
296
change.
The traditional ontology based on substance has its emphasis on
HQGXULQJ SUHVHQFH DQG LW LV DOVR FDOOHG PHWDSK\VLFV RI SUHVHQFH ([DPSOHV
of products stemming from the metaphysics of presence LQFOXGH 3ODWRV QRWLRQ
RI WKH )RUPV $ULVWRWOHV SULPDU\ VXEVWDQFHV WKH &UHDWRU RI &KULVWLDQ EHOLHI
'HVFDUWHV res extensa and res cogitans .DQWV noumena +XVVHUOV LQWHQWLRQDO
content
32
; the physical stuff presupposed by scientific naturalism, etc. In
contrast with this tradition, the assumptions underlying an ontological inquiry
challenge the idea that reality must be thought of in terms of the idea of
substance
33
: Being is rather understood in terms of temporality; it is a process
DQG LW KDSSHQV
Since the two inquires investigate objects of a different nature, different
tools are needed. The ontical inquiry privileges analysis that offers static,
WLPHOHVV GHILQLWLRQV DQG FRQFHLYHV RI HQWLWLHV VWDQGLQJ DWHPSRUDOO\ LQ
relations. According to the ontological level of investigation these tools for
explanation are deceptive. If the object of the inquiry is a process, then it
cannot be properly understood by using analytic definitions as if it were a
32
+HLGHJJHU FRQVLGHUV +XVVHUOV SKHQRPHQRORJ\ DV DQ H[DPSOH RI WKH WUDGLWLRQDO RQWRORJ\ 7KH
fact that the intentional objects are self-given in the stream of consciousness (and are studied in
D GHWDFKHG YLHZLQJ RU LQWXLWLRQ VKRZV WKDW +XVVHUOV RQWRORJ\ LV VWLOO RQWRORJ\ RI
SUHVHQFH $JDLQ LQ +XVVHUOV SKHQRPHQRORJLFDO DQDO\VLV WKH REMHFWV LQ consciousness retain
WKH VWDWXV RI PHUH RFFXUUHQFH EXW %HLQJ LV QRW VLPSO\ D PHUH RFFXUUHQFH SUHVHQFH-at-KDQG
The mode of Being that we assign to different entities is never fixed once for all. The context
GHWHUPLQHV WKH EHLQJ RI HQWLWLHV RQH DQG WKH VDPH WKLQJ FDQ EH WUHDWHG DV D SLHFH RI DUW DV
the object of scientific investigation, etc.).
33
Heidegger claims that philosophy misunderstood the nature of reality. The misunderstanding is
inevitable once one adopts the detached standpoint of theoretical reflection (for when we step
EDFN DQG WU\ WR JHW LPSDUWLDO REMHFWLYH YLHZV RI WKLQJV WKH ZRUOG JRHV GHDG IRU XV
The Analytic/Continental Divide: Entities and Being
297
VWDWLF HQWLW\ 7LPH DQG WKH LQTXLUHU Dasein) are the key aspects of the
RQWRORJLFDO LQTXLU\ +HLGHJJHU ZULWHV Time must be brought to light and
genuinely conceived as the horizon for all understanding of Being and for
any way of interpreting it. In order for us to discern this, time needs to be
explicated primordially as the horizon for the understanding of Being, and in
terms of temporality as the Being of Dasein, which understands Being
34
As we have seen, the ontical/ontological distinction is very useful. It is
particularly illuminating when it comes to understanding the source of the
serious difficulties of communication that exist between analysts and
continentals. It might be objected, however, that not all who have been
traditionally regarded as analytic philosophers explicitly (or even implicitly)
reject the importance of accommodating temporal processes in a dynamic way.
:KLWHKHDGV ODWHU SKLORVRSK\ Rf process might be cited as an example, though
PDQ\ DQDO\WLF SKLORVRSKHUV FDPH WR UHJDUG :KLWHKHDGV ODWHU ZRUN DV DQ
abandonment of analytic methods.) But my thesis is not that AP rejects
+HLGHJJHUV RQWLFDORQWRORJLFDO GLVWLQFWLRQ ZKHUHDV &3 DFFHSWV LW The relevant
issue is the sort of ontological assumptions that generally underlie the two
traditions, even when such assumptions are of a meta-theoretical (or
motivational) sort. Given the wide influence of Heidegger, it is very likely that
his characterization of Being is implicit in the many streams of continental
34
Heidegger (2006: 39). Such an understanding of time differs from the ordinary way of
conceiving it, which has persisted from Aristotle to Bergson. Nonetheless one might object that
even within the traditional philosophical perspective, time has been seriously investigated. But
even time, Heidegger would argue, must be taken outside of any ontology of presence. For a
dialectical discussion on how Heidegger relates himself to the tradition, see Dorothea Frede
(2006).
Soochow Journal of Philosophical Studies, No. 16
298
philosophy. Continental philosophers do not generally deal with ontological
LVVXHV H[SOLFLWO\ DQG GR QRW H[SUHVV WKHLU SHUVSHFWLYHV XVLQJ +HLGHJJHUV
ODQJXDJH RI WKH RQWRORJLFDO versus WKH RQWLFDO 1RQHWKHOHVV PRVW RI WKHLU
philosophical work is readily understood as implicitly an ontological
SHUVSHFWLYH LQ +HLGHJJHUV VHQVH HYHQ ZKHQ WKH SHUVSHFWLYH LV XQGHFODUHG
&RQWLQHQWDOV DUH EHVW XQGHUVWRRG DV V\PSDWKHWLF WR D G\QDPLF WHPSRUDO
characterization of philosophical inquiry.
We have seen that the many different manifestations of the Divide have
led historians and philosophers to offer several different criteria for
distinguishing AP from CP (and vice versa). Though useful, the criteria fail
to reveal the deep nature of the Divide. On the present thesis, the different
manifestations all derive from a common source: different assumptions
(ontical versus ontological) about the nature of and inquiry about Being. Of
course, a detailed derivation of the differences is not possible within the short
space of the present work. A few examples and brief sketch of the power of the
present interpretation will have to suffice. Consider the literary and personal
style of continental philosophers. It is readily interpreted as flowing from the
fact that the subject herself is part of and participating in the process of Being
DQG LQ WKH DFWLYLW\ RI FRQVWLWXWLQJ KHU REMHFWV RI NQRZOHGJH 6LPLODUO\ DQ
emphasis on historical context is thrust upon the continental philosopher
because the systematic entwining of events proceeding through time as the past
gives way to the future constitute a relevant aspect of an philosophical inquiry.
&3V DQWL-VFLHQWLVP LV FOHDU LI ZH UHPLQG RXUVHOYHV RI +HLGHJJHUV FULWLFLsm of
all ontical inquiries. He says that any inquiry about entities (from the
perspective of different hard scientific disciplines as biology, chemistry,
The Analytic/Continental Divide: Entities and Being
299
physics, etc.) is limited and should be preceded by a wider ontological inquiry
about Being. The ontical/ontological distinction also gives rise to the many
ways in which AP manifests its division from CP. It explains its dialogue with
the hard sciences ZLWK ZKLFK LW VKDUHV WKH RQWLFDO SHUVSHFWLYH $QDO\VLV E\
LWV YHU\ QDWXUH LV ZHGGHG WR VWDWLF DWemporal) and ontical characterizations
RI %HLQJ 7KLV H[SODLQV $3V XVDJH RI FDWHJRULHV DQG GHILQLWLRQV
35
and its
DWWHPSW LV WR SURYLGH VWDWLF UHSUHVHQWDWLRQV WKDW DV 5RUW\ SXWV LW PLUURU
QDWXUH
On the present account of the Divide, difficulties of communication
between analysts and continentals quite naturally arise because of the different
assumptions about the role of time in a philosophical inquiry. The different
assumptions manifest themselves in the ways language is used to express the
nature of Being. The different uses of language to represent, and the different
QRWLRQV RI D OLQJXLVWLF UHSUHVHQWDWLRQ LWVHOI WHQG WR SUHYHQW SKLORVRSKHUV
within the schools from understanding one another. The present perspective on
the Divide, however, opens up a new opportunity for understanding. Realizing
that the nature of the Divide derives from the ontical/ontological distinction,
one may explore the limits that constrain the ways in which the two languages
of time might be translatable into one another.
35
For example, Carnap criticized the non-referential language used by Heidegger. Heidegger
would answer that his language is referential, but the referent (an element within his accepted
ontological realm) has a different nature; or, in other words, the referent will not be found in
&DUQDSV RQWRORJLFDO UHDOP EXW LW LV SODFHG LQ WKH +HGHJJHULDQ ZLGHU RQWRORJLFDO UHDOP
Soochow Journal of Philosophical Studies, No. 16
300
References
Carnap, R. (1959). The Elimination of Metaphysics through Logical Analysis
of Language. In Ayer A.J. (Ed.), Pap, A. (Trans.) (Tit. or., berwindung
der Metaphysik durch Logische Analyse der Sprache. Erkenntnis, vol. II),
Logical Positivism (pp. 60-81). Glencoe: The Free Press. (Original work
published 1932)
Cooper, D. (1994). Analytical and Continental Philosophy. Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, 94: 1-18.
Critchley, S. (1997). What is Continental Philosophy? International Journal of
Philosophical Studies, 5, 3: 347-64.
Cutrofello, A. (2005). Continental Philosophy: a contemporary introduction.
New York: Routledge.
'agostini, F. (1997). Analitici e Continentali. Guida alla filosofia degli ultimi
WUHQWDQQL. Milano: Raffaello Cortina Editore.
Dummett, M. (1993). Origins of Analytical Philosophy. London: Duckworth.
Engel, P. (1997). La Dispute. Une introduction a la philosophie analytique.
Paris: Minuti.
FLLESDAL, D. (1997). Analytic Philosophy: What Is It and Why Should
One Engage in It? Monist, 82, 2: 218-34.
Frede, D. (2006). 7KH 4XHVWLRQ RI %HLQJ +HLGHJJHUV 3URMHFW. In Guignon, C.
B. (Ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger (pp. 42-69).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Friedman, M. (2000). A parting of the Ways: Carnap, Cassirer, and Heidegger.
The Analytic/Continental Divide: Entities and Being
301
Chicago: Open Court.
Gadamer, H.G. (1975). Truth and Method (Sheed & Ward, Trans.) (Tit. or.
Wahrheit und Methode. J.C.B. Mohr. Seibeck. Tbingen.). The Seabury
Press. (Original work published 1960)
Heidegger, M. (2006). Being and Time (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.)
(Tit. or. Sein und Zeit.). Oxford: Blackwell. (Original work published
1926-7)
Heidegger, M. (1993). Letter on Humanism. In Krell, D. F. (Ed.) (Tit. or. Brief
ber den Humanismus), Basic Writings (pp. 217-265). New York:
Routledge. (Original work published 1947)
Kant, E. (1997). Critique of Pure Reason (Guyer, P. & Wood, A., Trans.). New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Levy, N. (2003). Analytic and Continental Philosophy: explaining the
differences. Metaphylosophy, 34, 3: 284-304.
Mulligan, K. (1998). The great divide (Title page, The battle of the two
schools). The Times Literary Supplement, June 26, pp. 6-8.
Restaino, F. (1999). La filosofia contemporanea. Filosofie analitiche e
continentali. Dal 1918 ad oggi. In Restaino F., Storia della filosofia, Vol.
IV, 2, Torino, U.T.E.T.
Riceour, P. (1998). Critique and Conviction: Conversations with Franois
Azouvi and Marc de Launay (Blamey, K., Trans.). New York: Columbia
University Press.
Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Rorty, R. (1982). Consequences of Pragmatism (Essays: 1972-1980).
Soochow Journal of Philosophical Studies, No. 16
302
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Rorty, R. (1989). Contingency, Irony and Solidarity. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Rorty, R. (2003). Analytic and Conversational Philosophy. In C.G. PRADO
(Ed.), A House Divided: Comparing Analytic and Continental Philosophy
(pp. 17-31). Humanity Books.

Anda mungkin juga menyukai