Anda di halaman 1dari 22

http://ant.sagepub.

com/
Anthropological Theory
http://ant.sagepub.com/content/1/1/9
The online version of this article can be found at:

DOI: 10.1177/14634990122228601
2001 1: 9 Anthropological Theory
Stephen P. Reyna
confrontational stance
Theory counts: (Discounting) discourse to the contrary by adopting a

Published by:
http://www.sagepublications.com
can be found at: Anthropological Theory Additional services and information for

http://ant.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Email Alerts:

http://ant.sagepub.com/subscriptions Subscriptions:
http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav Reprints:

http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav Permissions:

http://ant.sagepub.com/content/1/1/9.refs.html Citations:

What is This?

- Mar 1, 2001 Version of Record >>


at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
Anthropological Theory
Copyright SAGE Publications
London, Thousand Oaks, CA
and New Delhi
Vol 1(1): 929
[1463-4996(200103)1:1;929;015920]
9
Theory counts
(Discounting) discourse to the contrary by
adopting a confrontational stance
Stephen P. Reyna
University of New Hampshire
Abstract
This article argues the virtues of a particular research methodology, the
confrontational stance, for making theory count by helping it to formulate
approximate truths of some rigor. Argument proceeds by rst showing how a
particular anthropological tradition, social anthropology, achieved success by
haphazardly adopting such a stance; and then by suggesting certain requirements
needed to systematically adopt such a stance.
Key Words
approximate truth research methodology social anthropology validation
Tiresias. . . a blind prophet, usually said to have been blinded because he saw Athena
bathing, and then to have been awarded the gift of prophecy . . . (Random House
Dictionary, 1967)
This article begins with an assessment of the state of current anthropology in order to
do something about it. Lvi-Strauss observed that anthropology began as a Rousseauean
project because J.-J. Rousseau had once remarked, . . . the whole world is covered with
nations of which we know only the names (in Lvi-Strauss, 1976: 30). So, to acquire
further knowledge, he recommended that dauntless folk be sent . . . traveling in order
to inform their compatriots by observing . . . Let us suppose that these new Herculeses
. . . then wrote the natural, moral, and political history of what they had seen; we our-
selves would see a new world come from their pens . . . (Lvi-Strauss, 1976: 30). Now
the observers who became the new Herculeses were the anthropologists, and as a result
of their odysseys, they created a new world of theory about humanity.
In the 19th century the likes of E.B. Tylor and Lewis Henry Morgan constructed uni-
linear evolutionary theories that sought to account for the universals of human culture.
Radcliffe-Brown offered his view of social anthropology in the 1930s which became a
British social anthropological canon in the rst half of the 20th century; a canon whose
rst premise was that social anthropology was . . . the theoretical natural science of
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 9
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
human society . . . (Radcliffe-Brown, 1965/1940: 188, 189). This was a deft piece of
intellectual imperialism. Sociology, political science, and economics as they studied
particular types of societies, or different aspects of particular societies, smaller realities
in the larger whole were reduced to sub-disciplines within anthropology, as they well
should be. At roughly the same time, largely at Columbia University, Franz Boas and
his associates were devising an even vaster anthropology which would be the science of
man in all aspects, biological as well as cultural (Kroeber, 1963/1923: 1). Thus, anthro-
pology was the most comprehensive discipline investigating humanity in either its 19th
century form or its two variants in the rst half of the 20th century. It was a vast project
sending new Herculeses everywhere to erect a human science and in science: theory
counts! That was then; what can be said of the anthropological present?
Sherry Ortner, writing on the subject of anthropological theory since the 1960s,
determined that it had become a thing of shreds and patches (Ortner, 1984: 126).
Judgements in the 1990s continued Ortners concern. Keith Hart, in 1990, castigated
anthropology as alienated . . . and lacking any vision (in Firth, 1992: 208). Joel Kahn
(1990: 230) described it in a state of methodological and epistemological crisis. Debate
in the US pertains to whether the discipline is self destructing (Knauft, 1996: 1).
Sahlins (1995: 14) believes that Culture . . . is in the twilight of its career, and anthro-
pology with it. Geertz agrees, prophesying that the discipline will probably disappear
in about 50 years (in Handler, 1991: 612). Such opinions, according to Knauft (1996:
296), are widely shared. The point of the preceding is that signicant thinkers ques-
tion the vision, to use Harts term, of anthropology. It is as if the discipline has gone
from a confederacy of new Herculeses to one of blind Tiresiases, sightless seers.
Why does anthropology appear to be in such a situation?There are a number of
answers to this question. Certainly, the investment preferences of current neo-liberalism
hurt anthropology. Such preferences privilege nancing of penal institutions at the
expense of those in education. Prisons are growing everywhere in the US, while public
universities are declining or stagnating. This explains in some measure why perhaps half
of those who have received PhDs in anthropology in the US since the early 1970s have
not been able to secure permanent positions in colleges or universities (Roseberry, 1996).
So great a loss of intellectual resources over three decades unquestionably clouds anthro-
pologys vision. But there is another problem.
Thisproblemis, that for anumber of reasons, astronganti-sciencefaction hasarisen
inanthropology.Thisfaction, inthewordsof StevenTyler (1987), ndssciencedegraded
and archaic. It insistsupon thick description, or ethnography (Geertz, 1973), in place
of science. Someinthetraditionconsider themselvesexperimentalists whowant totrade
in thescholarly treatise. . . for interviews, conversations, and biographical portraitsin a
manner moreevocativeof journalists (Marcus, 1993: 1). Let usbecrystal clear about what
is being proposed here. The blind Tiresiases will trade in scientic scholarship for inter-
views. Theory nolonger countsin such an anthropological discourse.
1
How does one confront such discourse?One strategy is to bracket it in the sense of
the Greek sceptics when they put something in epoche. When you place a discoursein
epoche, you suspend judgement on it; that is, you bracket it and get on with other busi-
ness. If I bracket (war) I set speech of war aside, and get on with talking about peace. If
the Tiresiases discount theory, we shall discount without rancor, with dispatch their
(discounting) to confront the chore of helping to make theory count.
ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 1(1)
10
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 10
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
How can one do this?Albert Einstein once remarked that a decisive event in science
was that of the confrontation of theory and facts (Einstein, 1970: 29). Further, for a
long time many scientists have been fully aware that there are difculties inherent in
grasping the nature of this confrontation (Lakatos, 1970: 113). This article contends
that a way of making theory count can be had if anthropologists examine what is
involved in confrontation, and then take a confrontational stance.
Bertrand Russell, writing in Unpopular Essays, pointed a way to understanding con-
frontation when he said, But if philosophy is to serve a positive purpose, it must not
teach skepticism, for while the dogmatist is harmful, the skeptic is useless (Russell, 1951:
27). Dogmatism was harmful, according to Russell, because it was an absolutist posture
that insisted there was Absolute Truth, when it was uncertain whether such truths exist.
Skepticism was useless because it, too, was an absolutist position, one whose prac-
titioners produced a lack of knowledge, an Absolute Ignorance. The unilinear evolu-
tionists, like Morgan, with his insistence upon the absolute truth of one line of evolution
from savagery to civilization, are an example of Russells dogmatism. Postmodernists,
like Lyotard (1984), with his skepticism towards all metanarratives, exemplies Russells
skepticism. What Russell was suggesting was that philosophy, here understood as an
epistemological stance, could have a positive purpose if it steered a course between the
Scylla of dogmatism and the Charybdis of skepticism.
I argue in this article that a confrontational stance is just such a philosophy and will
utilize the social anthropologists encounter with unilinear evolutionary theory to illus-
trate why. Argument is developed over four sections. The rst section introduces certain
basics of confrontation. The second section presents the social anthropologists version
of it. The third section documents the social anthropologists confrontation with uni-
linear evolutionary theory. The fourth section explains how the formulation of validation
histories is vital when taking a confrontational stance, and provides insight as to how to
make such histories. Finally, the conclusion, surveying the analysis of the preceding sec-
tions, argues that when confrontational stances establish validation histories bearing
upon theoretical propositions, they create more rigorous approximate truths of social
reality, a rigor necessary for making theory count.
THE CONFRONTATIONAL STANCE
Different formsof scientic practicemay tend toward oneof two limitswhere, asone
approachesthem, they (thepractices) becomelessand lessscientic. Onelimit isthat
of puretheory. Here, practitionersutterly ignoreobservation whilepropounding non-
validated generalizations. The other limit is that of pure observation. Here, prac-
titioners only perform observation, while formulating no generalizations. The former
limit might be called Panglossian, because Dr Panglosss discourse in Candidewas a
babbleof theoretical absurditiesunconstrained by reality. Thelatter limit might besaid
to beBaconian becausemany commentatorsthought that Sir Francis, likeDetective
Webb in Dragnet, fancied just thefacts. A scienceaway from theseextremesoperates
under the principle that every generalization should have its set of validating obser-
vationsand every set of observationsshould havetheir generalizations. Such ascience
isconfrontational, confronting generalization with observation, and observation with
generalization.
REYNA Theory counts
11
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 11
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
It is important to recognize what is confronting what. The confrontation in the con-
frontational stance is not directly between one group of thinkers jawing with another
group concerning whose views are truer, although this can occur. It is a confrontation
between a particular theoretical proposition, or sets of such propositions, and reality.
Theoretical propositions are generalizations in which there are at least two concepts and
at least one relationship between these concepts. Such propositions may be one of three
types. Empirical generalizations are propositions that are relatively low in generality and
abstraction, and are arrived at through observation. Theories are propositions with enor-
mous generality and high abstraction arrived at through a formal or informal logical pro-
cedure. Hypotheses are propositions deduced from theories which are lower in generality
and abstraction than the theory from which they derive.
3
Scientists formulate theory
whenever they construct any of these three types of propositions.
Empirical statements are needed to allow theoretical propositions to confront reality.
Theoretical propositions assert uniformities of relationship in reality. Empirical state-
ments describe how to sense the posited reality because they contain information con-
cerning what sensations of reality correspond to which concepts in the theoretical
propositions. For example, Emile Durkheim invented in Suicide(1897) the theoretical
proposition that deviance varied inversely with social integration. Empirical statements
applicable to this theory are: Suicide is a form of deviance, Catholicism and Protes-
tantism are forms of social integration, and inverse relationships are observed when
something goes up when something else goes down.
Confrontation is based upon having showdowns.
4
The image that this word may
evoke is of the moment of truth at the end of a cowboy movie when the good guy and
the bad guy test each other to discover who shoots best. I use the term in a slightly differ-
ent sense. A showdown is certainly a moment of truth involving a test; but what is being
tested is whether what is observed of reality is what has been imagined of it. Scientists
make observations that produce sensory information concerning whether what is asserted
in theory to be is sensedin reality to be. Thus, the showdown in the confrontational
stance is between imagination and perception of reality, and concerns whether the
sensory information of reality, the facts, is the sensory information that particular
empirical statements of particular theoretical propositions imagined would be the
sensory information of that reality.
Personsadopting aconfrontational stancewill beinvolved in two related practices
thoseof observation and validation. Observation concernsthe sensing of being. It is
focusing upon apatch of reality with aparticular sense, i.e. vision, and takingasnap-
shot of it, i.e. of allowingthat sensetomakeaneurological recordof thereality.Theneuro-
logical record is the observation. Validation concerns the production of a particular
knowledgeabout observation. Either what theoriesassert will beobservedisobserved, in
whichcasethepropositionsarevalidated(for thoseobservations); or what theyassert will
beobserved isnot observed, in which casethey arefalsied. Repeated confrontation of
contendingtheoriesconcerningsomerealitywiththat realityresultsinvalidationhistories
which contain information concerninghowwell contendingpropositionsdowhen con-
frontingreality. Validationhistoriesprovidethebasisfor assertionsof approximatetruth
(Miller, 1987). Thisisnot TheTruth, but truer truthamonggalaxiesof contendingtruths
given aparticular validation history. Confrontational showdownsaremomentsof truth
becauseat theend of themyou knowwhohasthetruer truth.
ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 1(1)
12
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 12
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
The actual techniques that sciences use when they make their confrontations are their
observational and validational toolkits. Some might deride the notion of a toolkit as an
unimportant concept of interest only to more technical plebs. My judgement is precisely
the reverse. More approximately, true knowledge depends upon more complete and
accurate observation and validation, which is what toolkits are all about. Let us investi-
gate something of the confrontational toolkits with which the unilinear anthropologists
and social anthropologists practiced their anthropologies.
FULL-FLAVOURED OBSERVATION
William James tells us that when he asked Sir James Frazer about natives he had
known, Frazer exclaimed, But heaven forbid! (in Jarvie, 1969: 2).
The anthropologist must relinquish his comfortable position in the long chair . . .
He must go out into the villages, and see the natives at work in gardens, on the beach,
in the jungle, must sail with them . . . and observe them in shing, trading, and cer-
monial . . . Information must come to him full avoured from his own observations
of native life . . . (Malinowski, 1954/1926: 14647).
Theunilinear evolutionists confrontational toolkit wasbased on circuitousand indirect
observation.
5
Certainly, nobody had theslightest intention of directly observing those
being investigated, astheabovequotation concerning Frazer makesclear. Rather, they
would practisethecomparativemethod. Thebasicproceduresof thiswereto rst read
accountsof thesavages bymissionaries, soldiers, andcolonial administratorstodiscover
survivals, elementsof low culturethat survived in higher culture. Oncethesehad been
identied, theinformation they supposedly borewould betreated aspremisesin syllo-
gisms from which other aspects of primitive culture would be inferred. Of course,
soldiers, and thelike, weregullibleand biased sothat theaccuracy of thepremiseswhich
formed the basis of their deductions was unknown. This being the case, Malinowski
(1944: 26) declaredthat theshortcomings of unilinear evolutionarytheoryresultedfrom
insufcient attention to. . . reality. All in all, theunilinear evolutionary theorists com-
parativemethodmadetheobservational part of their confrontational toolkit conjectural.
The social anthropologists antidote for neglecting reality, as the above quotation
from Malinowski underscores, was to get out of the long chair to make full avoured
observations.
6
This included a number of observational procedures championed by
Malinowski in the rst chapter of Argonautsof theWestern Pacic(1922) that became
the social anthropologists standard ethnographic toolkit and was the observational basis
of their confrontational stance.
7
A.C. Haddon and W.H.R. Rivers had actually developed the essentials of the social
anthropological observational toolkit following the Torres Straits expedition at the turn
of the century. Haddon introduced the notion that the preferred type of research should
be based upon eldwork (Young, 1988: 4). Rivers (1900) developed the genealogical
method during the Torres Straits Expedition. The unilinear evolutionists had made it
clear that savages and barbarians lived with their relatives. This indicated who needed
to be directly observed. But the evolutionists, with their aversion to actually meeting
with the object of their study, could only suggest utilization of the comparative method
to make these observations.
REYNA Theory counts
13
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 13
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
The genealogical method was the rst technique explicitly developed for directly
observing relatives. It was to be utilized in conjunction with census and settlement plans
of localities, and required the collection of the vital statistics, kinship ties, and statuses
concerning rights and responsibilities, especially as these referred to the inheritance of
property and succession to ofce for individuals in the census of a particular locality.
Thus, it forced anthropologists to see and hear actualities of primitive actors, and
thereby gave its users an observational advantage over unilinear evolutionists.
Notesand Querieson Anthropology, used since the 1870s as a handbook of anthropo-
logical method, was revised in 1912. Rivers contributed an article to the new, fourth
edition, General Account of Method. This was, perhaps, the rst presentation of par-
ticipant observation. A guiding principle offered in this article was that, the abstract
should always be approached through the concrete (Rivers, 1912: 115). The concrete
was actual observation of discourse and practice. The methodological point argued here
is that more abstract generalizations need to be validated by concrete observation. Of
course, the term concrete has its ambiguities, so it is appropriate to probe further to
explore in greater detail what it meant.
Rivers was interested in problems of the observation of discourse. He was especially
concerned not to conate the cultural categories of native discourse with those of the
observer. This meant that, as with practice, discourse was to be actually experienced so
that native terms must be used to designate the meaning of this discourse, wherever
there is the slightest chance of a difference of category. Furthermore, the greatest
caution must be used in obtaining information by means of direct questions, since it is
probable that such questions will inevitably suggest some civilized category (Rivers,
1912: 110111). If ethnographers were to know what native terms corresponded to
what sensed discourse, then they had to move in with the natives to acquire as com-
pletely as possible their languages (Rivers, 1912: 109), and through interaction in their
lives, to hear how these categories were actually used in ordinary discourse. This, of
course, meant participant observation.
How did Malinowski t into the current of Riverss observational innovations?He
went with the ow. His brief treatise on eldwork in the rst chapter of Argonautsadded
additional techniques for directly observing people in communities that complemented
Riverss genealogical method, but these were amplications of Riverss intention of having
anthropologists experience what those they observed experienced; for, as Malinowski
said, the . . . goal is . . . to grasp the natives point of view, . . . to realize hisvision of his
world (Rivers, 1912: 25, emphasis in the original).
The Rivers/Malinowski approach to observation came to dominate social anthro-
pology after 1922. Consequently, no more comparative method, no relying upon some
amateurs observations and fractured logics based upon those observations. As Mali-
nowski declared at the beginning of this section, long chairs were out and tents were
in, as everybody rushed to betherewith the natives. So, Frazers refusal to meet the natives
was replaced by Malinowskis full-avoured observation; or as he put it, I saw them
through their eyes . . . (Malinowski, 1989: 163).
Full-avoured observation sharpened the anthropologists observational toolkit,
strengthening their ability to be confrontational. The signicance of this needs to be
recognized. Microscopes were revolutionary to the biologists toolkits because they reveal
new, microscopicrealities. Full-avoured observationdidthesameinsocial andcultural
ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 1(1)
14
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 14
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
realms. Theory could be confronted with greater and more detailed observation. Greater
and more detailed observation could inform theory. Jarvie (1969: 2) has judged that the
switch to full-avoured observation was a revolution that social anthropology intro-
duced to social and cultural thought. I agree. It is time to investigate how this enhanced
power of confrontation was used against unilinear evolutionary theory.
CONFRONTING UNILINEAR EVOLUTION
. . . one feels also a moral separation from the anthropologists of last century or at
least I do. Their reconstructions were not only conjectural but evaluatory. . . . they
believed above all in progress, the kind of material, political, social, and philosophi-
cal changes which were taking place in Victorian England. . . . consequently the
explanations of social institutions they put forward amount . . . to little more than
hypothetical scales of progress, at one end of which were placed forms of institutions
or beliefs as they were in 19th-century Europe and America, while at the other end
were placed their antitheses . . . (Evans-Pritchard, 1962: 41).
The social anthropologists, as the preceding quotation from Evans-Pritchard makes clear,
had reservations concerning the unilinear evolutionists theories, reservations that
extended into moral domains. Consequently, they sought to challenge these theories
whenever possible. They did not do so by explicitly applying validation procedures,
though I hope to show in the next few pages that this is implicitly exactly what they did.
The heart of unilinear evolutionary theory, as expressed by Tylor, was the insistence that
cultureoccurredindifferent higher andlower grades withit understoodthat primi-
tives had failed to make the grade (Tylor, 1958/1871: vol. 1: 1). They did not do so
because they were devoid of reason, the key determinant of sociocultural evolution.
Comte (1896: 667) expressed this view as follows, It is only through more and more
marked inuence of reason over the general conduct of man and of society that the
general march of our race has attained . . . regularity . . .. Reason organized the general
march and, as Spencer put it, the inferior races (Spencer, 1883: vol. 1: 62) missed their
marching orders because they were subject to the uncontrolled following of immediate
desires (Spencer, 1883: vol. 1: 71), as they lacked adequate mental powers (Spencer,
1883: vol. 1: 119). Social anthropologists, using their full-avoured toolkit, confronted
the truth of such propositions. Below, different examples of such confrontations are
explored. Let us begin with kinship, as this was perhaps where the social anthropologists
enjoyed their nest hour.
Kinship
The social anthropologists seemed to devote exclusive attention to kinship and the
subjects directly related to it (Murdock, 1951: 466). There was a rationale guiding this
infatuation with kinship. The unilinear evolutionists, most importantly Morgan (1870;
1877), discovered that savages and barbarians organized themselves for the most part
into systems of consanguinity and afnity. He, and other unilineal evolutionary theor-
ists, then, offered theoretical propositions concerning these systems, propositions to
which thesocial anthropologiststook exception. Fortesbelievedthat enough evidencehad
beencollectedbythe1950storelegate. . . tothelimboof historical curiosities suchuni-
linear evolutionary chestnuts as . . . the Matriarchal Controversy; the pseudo-historical
REYNA Theory counts
15
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 15
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
and pseudo-psychological theories of classicatory kinship, incest, totemic descent and
so forth . . . (Fortes, 1957: 158).
The thrust of the arguments in these works was that efforts to confront particular uni-
linear explanations about kinship with evidence led to their falsication. Morgan, for
example, posited an evolutionary sequence for the family that started with promiscu-
ous intercourse (Morgan, 1877: 505). Try as they might, the old social anthropologists
never observed a single instance of this. Perhaps the classic confrontation was between
Henri Junod and Radcliffe-Brown over how to explain a nephews relationship to his
maternal uncle in certain populations.
Junod, a missionary turned ethnographer of the Thonga in southern Africa, discov-
ered what he believed was a most curious aspect of Thonga society (Junod, 1962/1913:
253). Generally, throughout Africa, juniors treat their elders with respect. The curiosity
was that, among the Thonga, younger sisters sons treated their elder maternal uncles
with a hearty disrespect. For example, a nephew who arrived when food had just been
prepared was allowed to gobble it down, leaving nothing for his maternal uncle. Junod
explained this in terms of unilinear evolutionary theory, asserting that it was a survival
of a matriarchal stage.
Radcliffe-Brown, in TheMothersBrother in South Africa (1924) ashewasabout
to offer hisown solution to thiscuriosity, and speaking of theory-building in general,
said it was easy enough to invent hypotheses but difcult when we set out to verify
them (Radcliffe-Brown, 1965: 21) was being confrontational and using the term
verify aswehavebeen usingvalidate. Hewassayingthat hewould confront whether
what Junodstheory stateswill occur with observationsto seewhether it actually does
occur. Radcliffe-Brown then proceeded to show that crucial aspects of the mothers
brothers (MBs) behaviour towards the sisters son (ZS) were unaccounted for in the
matriarchal survival theory (Radcliffe-Brown, 1965: 24, 25). He pointed out that in
more matriarchal societies the MB has considerable authority within the lineage
organization and isusually accorded respect. Thismeans, if theMB/ZSrelationship is
a survival of an earlier matriarchal stage, that the ZSshould show respect to his MB.
But asalready observed, hedoesnot. What thetheory imaginesshould occur, respect
of ZSfor MB, does not occur. So, Junods theory appears falsied when confronted
with thisevidence.
Radcliffe-Brown, then, offers an alternative explanation based on a principle of the
equivalence of brothers (Radcliffe-Brown, 1965: 2930). This principle was a gener-
alization about how particular relatives are treated. His explanation can be summarized
as follows:
1 People in kin-based societies group their kin into cultural categories towards whom,
and from whom, particular types of behaviour are assigned.
2 This categorization is based upon analogies between kin within the nuclear family
and more distant relatives.
This leads us to the principle of the equivalence of siblings, which is that:
3 Siblings of parents are placed in the same category as parents.
4 Therefore, a MB is treated like a mother.
ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 1(1)
16
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 16
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
5 A mother is treated in a free and easy, indulgent manner.
6 Therefore, a MB should be treated in the same manner.
The two theories may now be compared. What is supposed to occur in Junods theory
does not, while what is supposed to occur in Radcliffe-Browns theory does. Radcliffe-
Browns theory, when confronted with the evidence, passed the confrontation. Junods
unked it. Consequently, given this validation history, Radcliffe-Browns theory is
approximately truer than Junods. Let us now turn to economics.
Economics
Unilinear evolutionary theorists insisted that savage economies were wretched. Morgan,
speaking of native Americans, tied the weakness in their economies to the absence of a
mental trait that allowed a race to become civilized, for he said, The great passion
[for economic gain] of civilized man . . . never roused the Indian mind. It was doubt-
less the great reason for his continuance in the hunter state, for the desire for gain is one
of the earliest manifestations of the progressive mind. It . . . has civilized our race
(Morgan, 1851: 139). Essentially what was being said here was that the great reason
savages had pathetic economies, was that they were not racially driven to gain. Spencer
tied this lack of passion to their impulsiveness. If the inferior races were impulsive,
as Spencer insisted they were, then they were lazy, because as Spencer put it referring
to a group in India they will half starve rather than work . . . (Spencer, 1883: vol. 1:
66). The outrage of laziness was reported by colonial bureaucrats concerned to get the
colonized to work for their colonizers. For example, the colonial administration in
Northern Rhodesia (today Zambia) lamented that the natives were incorrigibly lazy . . .
(in Richards, 1939: 398).
Such judgements were premature because, as Malinowski said, concerning economics,
There is no other aspect of primitive life where our knowledge is more scanty and our
understanding more supercial (Malinowski, 1922: 84). Social anthropological research
rapidly altered this situation. Malinowskis own work on the Trobriand economy in both
Argonauts(1922) and Coral Gardens(1935); Firths on Tikopia in PrimitivePolynesian
Economy(1939); and Richards on the Bemba, whom the administrators termed lazy, in
Land, Labour and Diet(1939), provided detailed accounts of non-industrial production,
distribution and consumption. These accounts provided a rst observational base from
which to confront unilinear evolutionary claims of laziness.
For example, Malinowski documented in Argonautsthat one aspect of Trobriand
culture was the belief that certain objects called vaygua principally bracelets (mwali)
and necklaces (soulava) were of immense value and, hence, desirable to possess. He
further established that a particular practice called the kula, where Trobrianders made
long ocean voyages exchanging these bangles, was the way by which Trobrianders could
satisfy their goal of acquiring value. In fact, most of Argonauts text can be read as a docu-
mentation of how hard the natives worked (building canoes, sailing canoes, etc.) to get
their vaygua. After reading Argonauts, some commentators might impugn Trobrianders
for putting their faith in bangles, but they could not fault them on their work ethic to
get those bangles. A tacit criticism here was that natives would labour for themselves,
not their colonizers. Attention now focuses upon politics.
REYNA Theory counts
17
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 17
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
Politics
Herewemust deal with politicsboth in societiesthat lacked government, thesavages
in unilinear evolutionary schemes, and in those with some form of more centralized
government, thebarbarians. Bear in mind: political evolutionary theory could legiti-
mateimperialismif it madesavage and barbarian governmentsincompetent, because
imperialistswerethen justied in stepping in and taking over. Herbert Spencer, com-
menting upon a group of Shoshone, an uncentralized Native American foraging
people, revealed something of unilinear evolutionary sentiment towards savage politics
when he announced, that the Digger Indians, very few degrees removed from the
ourang-outang, who scattered among the mountains of the Sierra Nevada, sheltering
in holes and living on roots and vermin, drag out a miserable existence in a state of
nature, amid the most loathsome and disgusting squalor, and differ from the other
divisions of the Shoshones by their entire lack of social organization (Spencer, 1883:
vol. 2: 248).
Next contemplate the account by a Danish traveler, J.V. Helms, of a barbarous Indo-
nesian kingdom he happened upon in the 1880s. Helms conded,
While I was at Bali one of these shocking sacrices took place. The Rajah of the neigh-
boring State died . . . his body was burned with great pomp, three of his concubines
sacricing themselves in the ames.
It was a sight never to be forgotten by those who witnessed it, and brought to ones
heart a strange feeling of thankfulness that one belonged to a civilization . . . To the
British rule it is due that this foul plague of suttee is extirpated in India . . . Works
like these are the credentials by which the Western civilization makes good its right
to conquer and humanize barbarous races. . . (in Geertz, 1983: 3739).
The foregoing indicates just how disparaging unilinear evolutionary theory was of
savage or barbarian politics. Governmentless savages were like apes living in dis-
gusting anarchy. Barbarous races, for their part, did shocking things to their women
which made good the right of Western civilization to conquer them.
Most social anthropologists studied stateless peoples, and most, to some degree or
other, addressed the issue of anarchy. Evans-Pritchards Nuer studies became the key to
discussions of this question. This research was performed at the request of the colonial
government of the Sudan (Evans-Pritchard, 1940: vii) when the Nuer were at war with
the authorities requesting Evans-Pritchards assistance. It has been condemned as an
instance of anthropological collaboration with colonial projects (Johnson, 1981). Cer-
tainly, stripped of veiling hypocrisies, the authorities, bent on conquering the southern
Sudan, hoped that the anthropologist would give them pointers about how to rule the
unruly Nilotics. Evans-Pritchard gave them something else.
Hetook Durkheimsnotion of segmentary organization, elaborated in TheDivision
of Labor (1964/1893) on thebasisof few empirical specics, and developed aseriesof
generalizations derived from his direct observation of how the Nuer controlled their
lives. These generalizations, such as that concerning the segmentary principle (Evans-
Pritchard, 1940: 263), sought to explain how segmentary lineages actually governed
variousaspectsof social lifewithout all thebother and expenseof government. When
ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 1(1)
18
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 18
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
confronted with evidence, the unilinear evolutionary claim of savage anarchy was
unsubstantiated. Thus, in effect, what Evans-Pritchard did in TheNuer was, instead of
showingthecolonialistshowto rule, showed themthat thosethey werekillingin order
to rule, ruled themselves quite well. Of course, he did not openly criticize the colo-
nialists. He merely pointed a nger and thanked the authorities for their hospitality
(Evans-Pritchard, 1940: vii).
Other social anthropologists replicated Evans-Pritchards ndings by observing other
institutions by which savages controlled themselves. There were institutions that did
this by organizing people on the basis of age (Wilson, 1951; Gulliver, 1963). Equally
important were studies of the feud (Evans-Pritchard, 1940), witchcraft (Bohannon,
1958), and divination and ancestor worship (Middleton, 1960), which showed how
these operated, often together, to motivate people to comply with the values of their
society. Such ndings, summarized in Gluckman (1963), Mair (1962) and Schapera
(1956), falsied the unilinear evolutionary assertion that savages lived in anarchy. In
fact, they governed themselves so well that a new approximate truth seemed to have
emerged. Fortes expressed this when, on the basis of his Tallensi eldwork, he offered
what amounted to an empirical generalization that economic life among the Tallensi
made possible a social equilibrium (Fortes, 1945: x). Out with the old, anarchy; in
with the new, equilibrium.
Let us turn to barbarous states. In African Political Systems (Fortes and Evans-
Pritchard, 1940), these were given the designation Type A societies and their study
began later than did that of uncentralized polities. However, by the 1950s, social anthro-
pologists had provided the most extensive analysis of non-Western centralized polities
that had been offered up to that time. These included, in southern Africa, Kriges (1936)
account of the Zulu and her (1943) description of the Luvedu; H. Kupers (1947) analy-
sis of the Swazi; and Schaperas (1940) investigations among the Tswana. There were, in
eastern Africa, Barness (1954) inquiry into the Ngoni; Fallerss (1956) work among the
Soga; and Southwalds (1961) study of the Ganda. Finally, in west Africa, S.F. Nadel
(1942) wrote on the Nupe; Bradbury (1957) researched Benin; Lloyd (1954) analysed
the Yoruba; and M.G. Smith (1960) investigated Zaria.
This was a diverse group of studies. However, they generally corroborated the con-
clusions of the authors who wrote about centralized societies in African Political Systems.
Fortes and Evans-Pritchard summarized these ndings. If African states were not liberal
Western democracies, nevertheless,
. . . the government of an African state consists in a balance of power and authority
on the one side and obligation and responsibility on the other. Everyone who holds
political ofce has responsibilities for the public weal corresponding to his rights and
privileges. The distribution of political authority provides a machinery by which the
various agents of government can be held to their responsibilities. A chief or a king
has the right to exact tax, tribute, and labour service from his subjects; he has the cor-
responding obligation to dispense justice to them, to ensure their protection from
enemies and to safeguard their general welfare by ritual acts and observances. The
structure of an African state implies that kings and chiefs rule by consent. (Fortes and
Evans-Pritchard, 1940: 12)
REYNA Theory counts
19
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 19
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
The crucial judgement here is that Type A politics were found to exhibit a balance of
power and to have mechanisms that allowed rulers to govern with the consent of the
governed.
Again, confrontation suggested a new approximate truth. The states in societies colon-
ized by imperialists did not really do such shocking things. Rather, it appeared to be
the case that they managed with at least some of the attributes of soi disant civilized
liberal democracies. Implicit in this approximate truth was a criticism of imperialism.
Helms had expressed the imperialist position when he said the civilized had a right to
conquer, because they could humanize the barbarous. However, the social anthro-
pologists reported that it was mistaken to represent non-Western states as barbarous,
which eliminated any imperialist justication of their right to conquer. It is time to
turn to religion.
Religion
The study of religion had been an important feather in the cap of unilinear evolution-
ary theory. The most celebrated scholar dealing with this topic was E.B. Tylor who, as
a result of the application of the comparative method over an enormous range of materi-
als, believed that he had discovered the rst form of religion. This was animism, . . . the
general belief in spiritual beings (Tylor, 1871, vol. 2: 10). Tylor saw animism arising
from a childlike philosophy (Tylor, 1871, vol. 2: 100). Similarly, he commented upon
the proliferation of magical beliefs among the natives. These he believed were illusional,
and that magic itself was . . . one of the most pernicious delusions that ever vexed
mankind (Tylor, 1871, vol. 1: 112). Morgan (1877: 5) caught this spirit when he said,
. . . primitive religions are grotesque. Religion, then, among the lower races was full
of magical terrors that took the form of grotesque, childlike delusions, and thus
appeared to conrm the claim that inferior races could not make the grade because they
lacked reason.
There was a considerable old social anthropological research in religion. Perhaps the
most inuential research was that of Evans-Pritchard among the Azande (1937) and
Nuer (1956). Additionally important, however, were Nadels (1954), Middletons
(1960), Leinhardts (1961), and Douglass (1966) contributions. Much is divergent in
these studies, but common to all was a reluctance to issue sweeping proclamations, such
as Tylors that he had found the rst form of religion. Rather, as Nadel put it, in the
spirit of cautious confrontational science, Today we have grown more modest, but also
more conscious of the need for precision and solid empirical evidence (Nadel, 1957:
198). However, all agreed with Evans-Pritchard, speaking of the Nuer, that the evidence
pointed to one truth, that the . . . religious thought of those they analysed was, remark-
ably sensitive, rened and intelligent. It is also highly complex (Evans-Pritchard, 1956:
311).
The essential text reporting evidence in support of this proposition was Evans-
Pritchards Witchcraft, Oraclesand Magic AmongtheAzande(1937). Commenting upon
it almost two decades after its original publication, Evans-Pritchard said that it was an
attempt to take what at rst glance seems to be the absurd superstition (1962: 102)
of Azande beliefs and practices involving witches and . . .to make [these] intelligible, all
of which are foreign to the mentality of a modern Englishman, by showing how they
form a comprehensible system of thought. . .and how this system of thought is related
ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 1(1)
20
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 20
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
to social activities, social structure, and the life of the individual (Evans-Pritchard, 1962:
98). Further, he allowed that the complex system of beliefs surrounding Azande witch-
craft . . . make sense only when they are seen as interdependent parts of a whole which
has a logical structure (Evans-Pritchard, 1962: 99).
The point of the preceding is twofold. The Azande may not have had Cartesian reason
that Comte could recognize, but they had a logical structure, a reason. So, savage
thought was not childlike. Rather, evidence supported a new approximate truth. There
were forms of reason that existed of which the savages were informed, and Comte and
his colleagues were oblivious. Secondly, implicit in Evans-Pritchards evidence was an
irony. Those who called others childlike turned out to be childlike themselves, because,
like impetuous children, they were unable to resist the impulse to make assertions based
upon the rst glance.
What conclusion might readers draw from the two previous sections?The social
anthropologists were not confrontational in the sense of having an explicit research strat-
egy that they consciously applied. Rather, imagining themselves as scientists, they
muddled their way to making observational advances, chiey by replacing the com-
parative method with full-avoured observation. Furthermore, if they did not know
they were interested in invalidating theory, they did know they intended to confront
unilinear theory with the facts; which they did, and in so doing, they literally assumed
a confrontational stance. It may be observed that Franz Boas, and his students, were sub-
jecting unilinear theoretical propositions to confrontation at exactly the same time and
it became clear: the imagined world of the unilinear evolutionists, so congenial to the
Imperial imaginary, was unreal. Confrontation had done the job. Basic theoretical
propositions of the unilinear evolutionists were falsied. Now, if informal application of
the confrontational stance can have such impressive results, perhaps it is sensible to for-
mally specify some of the practices involved in this stance, especially as they pertain to
validation histories, so as to know how to replicate these results.
VALIDATION HISTORIES
A rst and fundamental requirement of being confrontational is to recognize that to
some degree, all people are blind Tiresiases rich in imagination, short on vision. The
confrontational stance is a way of combining the frailer visions of many individuals to
achieve a more exact vision for the social whole. It does this by being a comparativeenter-
prise, but in a way that is unfamiliar to anthropology. Generally, anthropologists under-
stand comparison to be observation of two different societies or cultures Barma in
Chad versus Nuer in the Sudan in order to discover similarities and differences. This
is a comparison of two different realities to understand the degree to which they are a
single type of reality. The comparison which underlies the confrontational stance is
between two or more theoretical propositions and their associated empirical statements
which concern a single type of reality. It is comparison of Comtes empirical statement
that primitives lack reason with Evans-Pritchards assurance that they have it in abun-
dance. If theoretical propositions and empirical statements are imaginations of the real,
then the comparison in the confrontational stance is between whose imaginaries are
more real; and many visionaries are called upon to make the observations that judge the
reality of the imaginary. These visionaries, to avoid being Tiresiases, need to cooperate
in constructing validation histories. The formulation of such histories requires concern
REYNA Theory counts
21
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 21
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
for confrontational feasibility, validation episodes, validation sets, validation universes,
positive and negative confrontation, confrontation records, and rigour, which are dis-
cussed here.
A validation episode isa record of a confrontation of a theoretical proposition, or
propositions, with the reality to which they pertain. However, before a validation
episode can occur, there must be judgements about whether the concepts and the
relationshipsin theoretical propositionsaresuch that aconfrontation isfeasible. Con-
frontation, it will beremembered, isobservation of whether what somebody imagines
to beissensed to be. Certain concepts, however, defy observation, either becausethey
lack empirical referentsor they aresimply too ambiguous. Empirical referentsareinfor-
mation in aconcept concerning what it refersto in reality. Freudian concepts, such as
the id, have been criticized as lacking in empirical referents. Ambiguous concepts are
those which are so unclear that there is no clarity about what observations could be
madethat pertain to theconcept. Somewould admit to therebeingambiguitiesin the
concept of equality.
The problem with concepts in theoretical propositions that lack empirical referents
and/or are ambiguous is that they do not have the information necessary to instruct an
investigator as to how to sense the reality to which they are imagined to pertain. Where,
for example, do you look to see the id?This makes it impossible to derive empirical state-
ments from them. Confrontational infeasibility occurs when there is no, or unclear,
knowledge of how to sense the reality referred to in a concept. For example, Fortess
empirical generalization that economic conditions caused equilibrium among the
Tallensi might be considered confrontationally questionable because it is not clear what
sensory information bears upon the concept of equilibrium. Fortes assumed in his text
that his readers knew what equilibrium was, so he gave them no instructions as to what
they would see or hear that indicated a particular social reality is in equilibrium. If an
investigator claims to have made a confrontation, even though it is abundantly clear that
a proposition is confrontationally unfeasible, then that validation episode should be said
to have been inconclusive.
If theoretical propositions are composed of confrontationally feasible concepts, if
empirical statements have been derived from these, then there must be a moment of
confrontation when observations are made. This moment is the validation episode.
In the confrontation between Junod and Radcliffe-Brown over the MB/ZS relation-
ship, thiswould betheexact timeand placeamong certain peoplewhen Junod made
theobservationswhich hebelieved allowed him to assert that therehad been amatri-
archal stageamong theThonga. Similarly, it would betheexact timeand placeamong
certain people from which Radcliffe-Brown made his observations. In fact, both gen-
tleman were unclear about exactly what observations they were referring to, so that
their specication of thevalidation episodeswhich form thebasisof their judgements
isobscure.
The results of a confrontation in a validation episode may be said to be positive or
negative. Positive confrontation is validation. Sensation of reality consistent with what
an empirical statement says will be sensed. Negative confrontation is falsication. Sen-
sation of reality inconsistent with what an empirical statement says will be sensed. The
unilinear evolutionists offered the theoretical proposition that the savages were lazy
because they lacked reason. An empirical statement based upon this was that particular
ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 1(1)
22
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 22
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
examples of savages would be found to not work hard. However, Malinowski sensed
that the Trobrianders worked darn hard. Thus, the unilinear evolutionary theoretical
proposition received negative conrmation. However, the exact same observations which
falsied the unilinear evolutionists theory provided positive conrmation of the alterna-
tive theoretical proposition that people labor industriously to acquire culturally dened
value.
A validation set is the set of all validation episodes reporting confrontation between
particular theoretical propositions and their realities. Validation sets have their con-
frontation records, which are the number of positive and negative confrontations in the
different validation episodes composing the entire set. If the confrontation record in a
validation set is entirely positive, then the proposition undergoing validation may be said
to be approximately true.
The construction of validation sets is not part of current anthropological practice, so
it is not possible to specify with any certainty the confrontation records of particular
theoretical propositions. However, it might be said informally that a fair number of
anthropologists have examined the question of the savages laziness, and have reported
ndings similar to those of Malinowski among the Trobrianders. Thus, it seems likely
that if one were to formulate a validation set for the theoretical proposition people labor
to acquire culturally dened value, than it would be judged approximately true on the
basis of its confrontation record. However, approximate truths promulgated in the
absence of a validation universe should be recognized to be tentative.
Less tentative approximate truths are possible when validation histories have been
constructed in which there are opposing validation sets. Validation universes are two
or more validation sets for two or more theoretical propositions dealing with the same
reality. This means that there is a showdown between the confrontation records of com-
peting validation sets in validation universes. Consider, for example, the dueling
Comtean and Malinowskian propositions that the savages are lazy because they lack
reason versus people labor industriously to acquire culturally dened value. These deal
with the same type of reality, that of people working. Anecdotal evidence of different
validation episodes pertaining to the two validation sets suggests falsication for the
Comtean theoretical proposition and validation for its Malinowskian competitor. If a
formal validation universe for these two theoretical prepositions was constructed, and if
this universe sustained the previous sentences judgement, then Malinowskis theoretical
proposition would be approximately truer than that of Comte.
Finally, let me introduce the notion of rigour as it pertains to the confrontational
stance. Rigour refers to how theory has been produced. The rigour of a theoretical
proposition is the number of times and places it has been validated, with it understood
that the greater the number of times and places of validation, the greater the rigour. The
notion of place in a validation episode needs to be made explicit. Places are regions in
reality where validation episodes occur, and the greater the number of places in which
a theoretical proposition has been validated, the greater its generality. If a theoretical
proposition has received no validation, it lacks rigour. If it has been validated in a
number of places in a number of validation episodes in a validation set, then it has still
some rigour. However, its rigour is still not sufcient to say that it has some truth.
A theoretical proposition may be known with such rigour that it is said to be true when
a showdown has occurred in a validation universe. If the showdown reveals that one
REYNA Theory counts
23
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 23
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
theoretical proposition has been validated and another falsied, then the validated
proposition may be said to be approximately truer for the validation universe in which
the confrontations have occurred. Thus, it is literally appropriate to assert that theory
counts, because researchers must compute the numbers, places and outcomes of con-
frontations in order to establish the truth with any rigour.
The case of the social anthropologists reveals the potential of taking a confron-
tational stance. Malinowski and company disclosed the falsity of unilinear evolution-
ary theory because of their better observational techniques and their will however
slap-dash to validate. However, though they took their observation very seriously,
they were casual about validation. They were poor at specifying their validation
episodes. They did not takedifferent ethnographers validation episodesbearing upon
the same theoretical propositions and explicitly build validation sets. They never for-
mally sought to build validation universes, though on occasion they casually con-
structed them when Radcliffe-Brown and Malinowski confronted Junod and Comte.
Thus, the social anthropologists revelation of the falsity of unilinear evolutionary
theory lacked any great rigour.
Further, when the social anthropologists rejected the evolutionists comparative
method, they did something that continues to bedevil the disciplines ability to take a
confrontational stance. Rejection of the comparative method marginalized comparative
research. Such marginalization still characterizes both social and cultural anthropology.
I study my people. You study your people. This means, even though we look at differ-
ent places, as the term has just been dened, we do not compare them. There is no
explicit conducting of validation episodes concerning a particular theoretical proposi-
tion among the different places anthropologists study. This, in turn, means that the gen-
erality of such propositions is not established, so that they lack rigour. Thus, the absence
of comparative research is a fundamental constraint upon the assumption of a confron-
tational stance in anthropology. Let us draw the argument of this article to a conclusion
by returning to the blind Tiresiases and the philosopher.
CONCLUSION
A great deal has been at issue in this essay, for the concern has been to nudge anthro-
pology away from being a confederation of blind Tiresiases, and towards one of new
Herculeses, with the ability to make it the central discipline investigating humanity. The
blindness of the Tiresiases is not that their visions are always incorrect. Tiresias, in fact,
often got it right. Their blindness lies in the fact that they have no idea howthey got it
right. The confrontational stance is a way of knowing how to get it right.
A discipline that deliberately develops improved observational and validational tool-
kits is taking a confrontational stance. Such a methodological strategy tells anthropolo-
gists when they should be skeptical when there are frail observational techniques and
no validation histories bearing upon theory; and how to avoid dogmatism by improv-
ing observational capacities as well as formulating validation histories. Such histories
provide anthropologists with chronicles of confrontation in validation universes indi-
cating that this proposition, on the basis of its confrontation record, is approximately
truer than that one. A virtue, then, of the confrontational stance is that, in Bertrand
Russells sense, it serves a positive purpose by telling one with rigour when it is right to
be skeptical of a truth, in the absence of validation histories, and how to rightly avoid
ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 1(1)
24
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 24
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
dogmatism concerning truth, by making more rigorous validation universes. When last
heard from, the anthropological Tiresiases were bracketed. Let the unbracketing occur,
and the games of confrontation begin.
Notes
1 Tyler and Marcus consider themselves to be postmodern, so it may seem that I judge
postmodernism to be anti-theoretical. This is correct. My sense is that post-
modernists do not formulate theory as it is understood in science. Lyotard (1984),
for example, was interested in the utility of metanarratives. He decided all of these
should be treated skeptically. Now, a certain metanarrative, that of science, is used to
make theory. This meant, if all metanarratives should be treated with incredulity, and
theory was part of the metanarrative of science, then theory was to be treated with
skepticism.
2 Readers should note that the discussion in this paragraph concerns scientic and not
mathematical practices. Mathematical propositions are validated by different logics
and not observation. The argument in this text is not concerned with validation of
mathematical generalizations.
3 Readers may construe discussion of empirical generalization, hypothesis, and theory
in the text as indicating support for covering law explanations. This is not the case.
The article is about the virtues of confrontation and not those of different forms of
explanation. Hence, it does not advocate any particular explanatory mode. However,
I am partial to causal explanations.
4 There are competing doctrines of confrontation in the philosophy of science. The
traditional view had been that of justicationalism, which believed that confrontation
could result in proven theory. This view is said to have suffered a breakdown
(Lakatos, 1970: 93) and to have been replaced by different forms of neojustica-
tionalism, notably that of Carnaps probabalism, also said to have failed (Lakatos,
1968), and to have been replaced by different forms of falsicationism, associated with
Popper (1959) and his followers. The approach proposed in this text is indebted to
Lakatoss (1970) version of falsicationism.
5 The major unilinear evolutionists, in addition to Tylor and Morgan, were A. Comte,
H. Spencer, J.J. Bachofen, L.H. Maine, J. Lubbock and J.F. McLennon. Their most
intense period of publication was the quarter of a century between 1860 and 1885.
6 The chief social anthropologists, beside Malinowski, were A.R. Radcliffe-Brown,
E.E. Evans-Pritchard, M. Fortes, R. Firth, S.F. Nadel, M. Gluckman, I. Schapera,
G. Wilson and M. Wilson. They ourished from 1922, and the publication of Arg-
onauts, until 1957 when Leach announced that it was time to start rethinking the
whole project.
7 Readers should not misconstrue this section, and the one following, to be a hagiog-
raphy in praise of social anthropology. They should consult the critical, and not so
critical, commentaries to get a fuller appreciation of the tradition (see especially
Kuper, 1973; and Kuklick, 1991; Goody, 1995; Stocking, 1995). Elsewhere I have
argued that social anthropologists created a regime of hypocrisy congenial to imperial-
ist times (Reyna, n.d.). However, their researches can be used to illustrate the taking
of a confrontational stance.
REYNA Theory counts
25
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 25
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
References
Barnes, J.A. (1954) Politicsin a ChangingSociety. London: Oxford University Press.
Bohannon, Paul (1958) Extra-Processual Events in Tiv Political Institutions, American
Anthropologist 60: 112.
Bradbury, R.E. (1957) TheBenin Kingdom and theEdo-SpeakingPeoplesof
Southwestern Nigeria. London: International African Institute.
Comte, A. (1896) ThePositivePhilosophy of AugusteComte, 3 vols. London: G. Bell
and Sons.
Douglas, Mary (1966) Purity and Danger. London: Routledge.
Durkheim, E. (1951/1897) Suicide. New York: Free Press.
Durkheim, E. (1964/1893) TheDivision of Labor in Society. New York: Free Press.
Einstein, A. (1970) Autobiographical Notes, in P.A. Schilpp (ed.) Albert Einstein:
Philosopher-Scientist, vol. 1, pp. 295. LaSalle, IL: Open Court.
Evans-Pritchard, E.E. (1937) Witchcraft, Oraclesand Magic AmongtheAzande.
London: Oxford University Press.
Evans-Pritchard, E.E. (1940) TheNuer: A Description of theModesof Livelihood and
Political Institutionsof a Nilotic People. London: Oxford University Press.
Evans-Pritchard, E.E. (1956) Nuer Religion. London: Oxford University Press.
Evans-Pritchard, E.E. (1962) Social Anthropology and Other Essays. New York: Free Press.
Fallers, L. (1956) Bantu Bureaucracy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Firth, Raymond (1965/1939) PrimitivePolynesian Economy. New York: Norton.
Firth, Raymond (1992) A Future for Social Anthropology, in Sandra Wallman (ed.)
Contemporary Futures: Perspectivesfrom Social Anthropology, pp. 20824. London:
Routledge.
Fortes, M. (1945) Dynamicsof Clanship AmongtheTallensi. London: Oxford
University Press.
Fortes, M. (1957) Malinowski and the Study of Kinship, in W.R. Firth (ed.) Man and
Culture: An Evaluation of theWork of Bronislaw Malinowski, pp. 15788. London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Fortes, M. and Evans-Pritchard, E.E. (eds) (1940) African Political Systems. London:
Oxford University Press.
Geertz, C. (1973) TheInterpretation of Cultures. New York: Basic Books.
Geertz, C. (1983) Local Knowledge: Further Essaysin InterpretiveAnthropology. New
York: Basic Books.
Gluckman, Max (1963) Custom and Conict in Africa. New York: Barnes and Noble.
Goody, Jack (1995) TheExpansiveMoment: Anthropology in Britain and Africa
19181970. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Gulliver, P. (1963) Social Control in an African Society: A Study of Arusha, Agricultural
Masai of Northern Tanganyika. London: Routledge.
Handler, R. (1991) An Interview with Clifford Geertz, Current Anthropology32:
60313.
Jarvie, Ian (1969) TheRevolution in Anthropology. Chicago, IL: Henry Regnery Co.
Johnson, D.H. (1981) The Fighting Nuer: Primary Sources and the Origins of a
Stereotype, Africa. 51: 50827.
Junod, H.A. (1962/1913) TheLifeof a South African Tribe, 2 vols. New Hyde Park,
NY: University Books.
ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 1(1)
26
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 26
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
Kahn, Joel (1990) TowardsaHistoryof theCritiqueof Economism: TheNineteenth-
CenturyGerman Originsof theEthnographersDilemma, Man25: 23049.
Knauft, B.M. (1996) Genealogiesfor thePresent in Cultural Anthropology. New York:
Routledge.
Krige, E. (1936) TheSocial System of theZulus. London: Longmans, Green and Co.
Krige, E. and Krige, J.D. (1943) TheRealm of theRain Queen. London: Oxford
University Press.
Kroeber, A.L. (1963/1923) Anthropology: Cultural Patternsand Processes. New York:
Harcourt.
Kuklick, Henrika (1991) TheSavageWithin: TheSocial History of British Anthropology,
18851945. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Kuper, Adam (1973) Anthropologistsand Anthropology: TheBritish School, 19221972.
New York: Pica Press.
Kuper, H. (1947) An African Aristocracy: Rank AmongtheSwazi. London: Oxford
University Press.
Lakatos, Imre (1968) Changes in the Problem of Inductive Logic, in I. Lakatos (ed.)
TheProblem of InductiveLogic, pp. 315417. Amsterdam: North Holland Pub.
Co.
Lakatos, Imre (1970) Falsication and the Methodology of Scientic Research
Programmes, in I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (eds) Criticism and theGrowth of
Knowledge, pp. 91196. London: Cambridge University Press.
Leinhardt, G. (1961) Divinity and Experience: TheReligion of theDinka. London:
Oxford University Press.
Lvi-Strauss, Claude (1976) Structural Anthropology, vol.2. New York: Basic Books.
Lloyd, Peter 1954. The Traditional Political System of the Yoruba, Southwestern
Journal of Anthropology10: 36684.
Lyotard, J.-M. (1984) ThePostmodernCondition. Minneapolis: University of
MinnesotaPress.
Mair, Lucy (1962) PrimitiveGovernment. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Malinowski, B. (1922) Argonautsof theWestern Pacic. New York: Dutton.
Malinowski, B. (1935) Coral GardensandtheirMagic, 2vols. London: AllenandUnwin.
Malinowski, B. (1944) A Scientic Theory of Cultureand Other Essays. Chapel Hill:
University of North Carolina Press.
Malinowski, B. (1954/1926) Myth and Primitive Psychology, in B. Malinowski
Magic, Scienceand Religion and Other Essays. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.
Malinowski, B. (1989) A Diary in theStrict Senseof theTerm. Stanford, CA: Stanford
University Press.
Marcus, George (1993) Introduction to the Series and to Volume 1, in G. Marcus
(ed.) PerilousStates, pp. 117. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Middleton, John (1960) Lugbara Religion: Ritual and Authority Amongan East African
People. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Miller, R.W. (1987) Fact and Method. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Morgan, L.H. (1851) Leagueof theHo-d-no-sau-nee, or Iroquois. Rochester, NY: Sage
and Brother.
Morgan, L.H. (1870) Systemsof Consanguinity and Afnity of theHuman Family, vol.
17. Washington, DC: Smithsonian Institution.
REYNA Theory counts
27
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 27
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
Morgan, L.H. (1963/1877) Ancient Society. New York: Meridian Books.
Murdock, G.P. (1951) British Social Anthropology, American Anthropologist 53:
46573.
Nadel, S.F. (1942) A Black Byzantium: TheKingdom of Nupein Nigeria. London:
Oxford University Press.
Nadel, S.F. (1954) NupeReligion. London: Routledge.
Nadel, S.F. (1957) TheTheory of Social Structure. London: Cohen and West.
Ortner, Sherry (1984) Theory in Anthropology Since the Sixties, ComparativeStudies
in Society and History26: 12666.
Popper, Karl (1959) TheLogic of Scientic Discovery. London: Hutchinson.
Radcliffe-Brown, A.R. (1965/1924) The Mothers Brother in South Africa, Structure
and Function in PrimitiveSociety, pp. 1532. New York: Free Press.
Radcliffe-Brown, A.R. (1965/1940) On Social Structure, Structureand Function in
PrimitiveSociety, pp. 188205. New York: Free Press.
Random HouseDictionary of theEnglish Language(1967) New York: Random House.
Reyna, S.P. (n.d.) Art and Mummery: Towards a Social Anthropology of Hypocrisy.
Durham, NH: Anthropology Department, University of New Hampshire.
Richards, Audrey (1939) Land, Labour and Diet in Northern Rhodesia: An Economic
Study of theBemba Tribe. London: Oxford University Press.
Rivers, W.H.R. (1900) A Genealogical Method of Collecting Social and Vital
Statistics, Journal of theAnthropological Institute30: 7482.
Rivers, W.H.R. (1912) Notesand Querieson Anthropology, 4th edn. London: British
Association for the Advancement of Science.
Roseberry, W. (1996) The Unbearable Lightness of Anthropology, Radical History
Review65: 525.
Russell, B. (1951) Unpopular Essays. New York: Simon and Schuster.
Sahlins, M. (1995) How Natives Think About Captain Cook, For Example. Chicago,
IL: University of Chicago Press.
Schapera, Isaac (1940) The Political Organization of the Ngwato of Bechuanaland
Protectorate, in M. Fortes and E.E. Evans-Pritchards (eds) African Political Systems.
London: Oxford University Press.
Schapera, Isaac (1956) Government and Politicsin Tribal Societies. London: Watts.
Smith, M.G. (1960) GovernmentinZazzau18001950. Oxford: OxfordUniversity
Press.
Southwald, M. (1961) Bureacracy and Chiefship in Buganda. Kampala: East African
Institute of Social Research.
Spencer, Herbert (1883) ThePrinciplesof Sociology, 2vols. NewYork: Appleton andCo.
Stocking, George (1995) After Tylor: British Social Anthropology 18881951. Madison:
University of Wisconsin Press.
Tyler, Steven (1987) TheUnspeakable: Discourse, Dialogueand Rhetoric in the
Postmodern World. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
Tylor, E.B. (1958/1871) PrimitiveCulture, 2 vols. New York: Harper.
Wilson, Monica (1963/1951) Good Company: A Study of Nyakyusa AgeVillages.
Boston: Beacon.
Young, Michael (ed.) (1988) Malinowski AmongtheMagi: TheNativesof Mailu.
London: Routledge.
ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 1(1)
28
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 28
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from
S.P. REYNA is at the Max Planck Institute in Halle until December 2001 after which time he will return to
University of New Hampshire. He is interested in anthropological theory, the history of anthropological
theory, and power within a global context. Address: Max Planck Institute for Social Anthropology, Leipzer
Strasse 91 (Ritterhaus), Postfach 11 03 51, 06017 Halle, Germany.
Anthropology Dept., University of New Hampshire, 311 Huddlestone Hall, Durham, NH 03824, USA.
[email: reyna@eth.mpg.de]
REYNA Theory counts
29
02 Reyna (JB/D) 15/2/01 3:42 pm Page 29
at COLEF BIBLIOTECA on September 2, 2014 ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from

Anda mungkin juga menyukai