Anda di halaman 1dari 46

ISSN 1801-0938

New Perspectives on Political Economy


Volume 3, Number 2, 2007, pp. 139 184

The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society in


the Medieval West
Boudewijn R.A. Bouckaert
JEL Classication: N43, N93, O10
Abstract: This article deals with the genesis of civil society in medieval society in
the hope that this might elucidate the general conditions in which a civil society can
ourish. We are, moreover, well aware that some of the viewpoints espoused have
strong contenders with opposed views. We mention them in order to indicate to the
reader the major dilemmas, which arise on the concerned historical subject. In order
to avoid misunderstandings on the main tendency of our historical analysis, we deal
briey with the notion of civil society as it appears in political philosophical literature
because this notion is used with strongly diverging meanings. Then we build a picture
of European society at the dawn of the emergence of civil society, during the period
843-1073 . We deal subsequently with crucial factors in the emergence of civil society
in the Middle Ages such as peace and labour, associative life, the medieval nomos,
including medieval humanism, the ius commune of Europe and the rule of law in
the Middle Ages. We conclude with some considerations about the late medieval era,
in order to bridge the gap with the modern conception of civil society.

Boudewijn Bouckaert professor and Head of Department of Legal Theory and Legal History, Ghent
University, Boudewijn.Bouckaert@UGent.be

140

New Perspectives on Political Economy

Introduction
Alexander Kojeve, philosopher and pre-eminent interpreter of Hegel came, whilst still
in the middle of his career as a philosopher, to the conclusion that his philosophical
master was correct about the end of history and decided because of this to stop his
career and become a full-time bureaucrat in the European Commission (Fukuyama
1996, p. XIII). About a thousand years earlier, the Holy Roman emperor Otto III and
pope Sylvester II spent New Years eve praying in the church of St. John of Laterans
as they were fearful of the coming apocalypse at the end of the millennium. As expost-spectators we know that Kojeve, Otto III, and Sylvester II were wrong.
History did not and will not end because history is not an energy, a process, or a
fatality, separated from the action of innumerable human agents. History is driven
by the perceptions and preferences of its actors, who aect the decisional context of
other actors, present and future, by the intended and unintended consequences of
their actions. Pretending to know the end of history, as Hegelian historians do, is,
therefore, an act of supreme hubris. It presupposes that we know what preferences
and inspirations are the most common and most profound to humanity, and by what
mechanisms they will nally triumph over their historical obstacles.
Releasing such strong Hegelian assumptions about the cognitive position of the
historian does not necessarily entail extreme scepticism, according to which history
is only a confused heap of facts, as was considered by Lord Chestereld (Mencken
1991).
Theoretical insights about the human psyche and about relationships between
human action and its unintended consequences, do allow us to understand some concatenation of events and compatibilities of dierent political institutions and social
structures. In this way, knowledge, useful for our moral engagement in the present,
can be won from the study of the past. Advocates of a free society may learn from
history that some strategies, the purpose of which may not have been liberty-driven,
resulted, through their unintended consequences, into more freedom. The movement for the libertas of the 11th century church, for instance, was not liberty-driven
in the modern, classical liberal sense. It may even have had some theocratic traits.
Nevertheless, it produced, as an unintended consequence, a less monopolised and

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

141

thus freer political context. From this, a classical liberal can learn what kind of political, religious and social evolution, even when non-liberal in its main aim, deserves
his support.
From history we can learn the type of institution we should cherish in order to
safeguard liberty. The leaders of the medieval communes, for instance, though
driven by aims which were fairly close to modern classical liberal ones, often surrendered their liberties quite easily in an alliance with the king, in order to reap some
short-term benets (Spruyt 1996, p. 86). They clearly lacked insights into the long
term value of communal independence.
This article deals with the genesis of civil society in medieval society, in the hope
that this might elucidate the general conditions in which a civil society can ourish.
We do not pretend to have found the key to ultimate wisdom on this matter. Many
subjects remain open to further research. We are, moreover, well aware that some
of the viewpoints espoused, have strong contenders with opposed views. We will
mention them in order to indicate to the reader the major dilemmas, which arise on
the concerned historical subject.
In order to avoid misunderstandings on the main tendency of our historical analysis, we will deal briey in the rst two sections with the notion of civil society as it
appears in political philosophical literature because this notion is used with strongly
diverging meanings. In the third section we will build a picture of European society at the dawn of the emergence of civil society, during the period 843-1073. In the
fourth, fth, sixth, seventh, eighth, and ninth section we deal subsequently with crucial factors in the emergence of civil society in the Middle Ages such as peace and
labour (section 4), associative life (section 5), the medieval nomos, including medieval humanism (section 7), the ius commune of Europe (section 8) and the rule
of law in the Middle Ages (section 9). We will conclude with some considerations
about the late medieval era, in order to bridge the gap with the modern conception
of civil society.

142

New Perspectives on Political Economy

The Concept of Civil Society in Its Liberal Meaning

Not satised with the usual dichotomy market-state, several liberal scholars developed a sociological concept of society or civil society opposed to the state, but
wider than the naked market. David Green puts it as follows: Contrary to the view
attributed to Mrs. Thatcher, that there is no such thing as society, there is indeed
such a thing. But it is not synonymous with the state. It is the realm of activity in
common, which is at once voluntary and guided by a sense of duty to other people and to the social system on which liberty rests (Green 1993, p. 3). In his last
book Trust, Francis Fukuyama speaks about The Twenty Percent Solution, arguing
that neo-classical economics is correct, up to eighty percent, in explaining society,
but needs to be supplemented by a theory on social capital, in order to explain the
other twenty percent (Fukuyama 1996, p. 13).
Older liberal scholars, such as Hayek (Hayek 1973) and Oakeshot (Oakeshot 1975,
p. 313) developed similar notions: Hayek distinguished the cosmos of a great society,
resting upon a nomocracy, from the taxis of a constructed order such as the state,
directed by teleocratic strategy; Oakeshot distinguished the civil association, based
on general rules of conduct, from the enterprise association, set up in pursuit of a
common objective.
It seems that all these liberal notions about society have two elements in common: 1) their notion of society is about a horizontalistic network of interpersonal
co-ordinations of individual action; 2) these co-ordinations are voluntary and based
on respect for property rights.
The notion is horizontalistic because it covers relationships from person to person, persons to groups (community), or groups to groups, but never a relationship
from the single to the whole. The society is just a construction of the mind to conceptualise the broad cosmos of interaction in which individuals, groups and organisations are involved and through which actions and strategies of some reect in an
intended and unintended way on the position of others. As a consequence of which,
it would be absurd to conceive a relationship between an individual and society. It is

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

143

even more absurd to speak about duties of the individuals towards society. In a civil
society, within the liberal meaning, individuals have duties towards other individuals
or groups, according to values, which may be shared by most actors in society. This
fact, however, does not allow us to substitute dyadic relationships among actors in
society for a dyadic relationship of actors with society.
To put it dierently: the liberal notion of society is non-holistic and by this, also
non-organic. This latter point is not unimportant with regard to the discussion about
the conception of society (universitas, societas) during the Middle Ages (see below
section 5). Society, in its liberal version, is not constructed as a whole but develops
either by the deliberate social constructions of groups and organisations, or by spontaneous (unintended) adaptation.
The horizontalistic character of society in its liberal version also implies that it
has no formal borders such as membership (groups, corporations, political parties)
or territorial borders (nation-states). If we try to visualise it, it would not look like
an organisational structure, but rather like a nebula, with thicker and thinner areas,
according to the intensity (close knittedness, Ellickson 1991) of interaction. The informal and gradual borders of a society in its liberal version are inuenced by several
factors, be they natural (e.g. innavigable oceans), religious and cultural (e.g. xenophobic tradition), or political. The latter ones do not only concern radical measures
such as erecting Iron Curtains, but also policies such as linguistic and monetary policies intended to obstruct interaction between subjects of dierent states.
Besides the structural feature of horizontalism, society in the liberal sense also
requires two normative elements: voluntarism and respect for property rights. The
notion of voluntarism should here be understood in its widest sense; it covers deliberate as well as spontaneous co-ordination. Deliberate co-ordination occurs through
the discipline of conventions (e.g. Victorian manners and morals) (Himmelfarb
1995, p. 21), contracts and rms. Spontaneous co-ordination occurs through processes in which actors adapt their behaviour to changing social environments, while
the actions which caused these changes were not aimed at these adaptations of behaviour. The latter form the unintended consequences of the former. Patterns of
spontaneous co-ordination are the subject of study by economists par excellence,

144

New Perspectives on Political Economy

while sociologists and historians tend to focus more on the various forms of deliberate
co-ordination. Both traditions can contribute to the understanding of the working of
civil society. Moreover, processes of spontaneous co-ordination and acts of deliberate
co-ordination do not occur in isolation from each other. The fact that a specic deliberate co-ordination, or a class of such co-ordinations appear at a certain moment
in society, can be often understood as an unintended consequence of other patterns
of human action. Thus, the notion of civil society within its liberal meaning, oers
not only room for the dierent disciplines of social sciencebut also a context for cooperation and mutual enrichment.
Finally, it has to be remarked that both normative elements of civil society, voluntarism and respect for property rights, constitute only the most basic characteristics
of it. This does not endorse the claim that both characteristics suce to uphold a
civil society in the longer run. Several authors, qualied by Green as civic capitalists (Green 1993, p. 12), emphasised the need for a constant moral eort in order to
protect civil society against its demoralisation and thus, degradation.
According to Macedo, Tocqueville was the pre-eminent civic capitalist because he
emphasised the stable moorings of religious belief, a caring sphere of family life and
a variety of ties to intermediate groups as the prerequisite for the development of
individual condence and pride (Macedo 1989, p. 133).
These viewpoints of civic capitalists are, however, positions about the workability and stability of a civil society. It is also conceivable to deny these positions of civic
capitalism by claiming that a legal order of individual rights and the elimination of
all obstacles to individual freedom, suce for the constitution of a stable civil society
and that consequently all the values talk of civic capitalists is historically contingent
and morally paternalistic. Hence, by including the moral values of civic capitalism
within the denition of civil society we would already give a positive answer to the
question, raised by civic capitalism. It remains an open question whether moral values, such as family-mindedness, self-condence, pride, honesty, reciprocity, decency,
etc., are prerequisites for civil society or just consequences, which will probably be
produced in a society, based on voluntarism and respect for property rights.

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

145

2 Civil Society: Other Meanings


This outline of a liberal concept of civil society allows us to contradistinguish it from
other current and often radically dierent meanings. To cover the most important
ones, we will deal briey with the concept of civil society in social contractarianism
in the Hegelian line of thought and in neo-corporatism.
In social contractarianism civil society is opposed to the state of nature, a (mostly)
hypothetical state without institutions and without social bonds stretching beyond
the natural family. Civil society on the contrary is a state with developed political institutions and established political, legal, and religious authorities. Because the picture of the state of nature varies widely across the many social contract-theories, civil
society, the outcome of the contracting process out of the state of nature, also takes a
dierent shape depending on the concerned authors. So, the monarchist civil society
of Hobbes diers substantially from the liberal-constitutional civil society of Locke,
while the latter diers again from Rousseaus civil society of popular democracy.
It should be emphasised that the concept of civil society in the social contractarian
context is not necessarily politically hostile to the development of civil society in the
previously outlined liberal sense. Lockean civil society for instance, with its stress
upon limited government and individual rights, is particularly conducive for such a
development, as the history of eighteenth century England and nineteenth century
America shows.
Both notions of civil society dier, however, in their expository status. The liberal notion conceptualises the possibility and the value of a broad, non-planned but
ordered cosmos of human interaction in opposition to social theories, denying or
neglecting spontaneous co-ordination and advocating a deliberately created and imposed order in society. In this way, the liberal notion is a substantive part of a deep
analytical and normative debate. The social contractarian notion on the contrary, has
only a formal status. It is a step in the form of argumentation about the foundation of
political authority and political institutions. This dierence between substantive and
formal expository status explains why the meaning of both notions can be politically
reconcilable.

146

New Perspectives on Political Economy

Within the tradition of social contractarianism no distinction is made between


civil society and the state (here in the sense of a political institution). Civil society
as a stage in the hypothetical genesis of institutions encompasses the institutions of
the nomocratic cosmos (civil society in the liberal sense) as well as the institutions of
the state (the holder of the monopoly of organised violence within a given territory).
Moreover, the borders between the dierent civil societies in the social contractarian
sense correspond with the borders of the state territory. Civil society in its social contractarian sense is as much national as civil. Through the equation civil = national,
social contractarianism, especially in its Rouseauan version, contributed a lot to the
violent nationalism of the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries.
Closer to the liberal notion of civil society is the Hegelian one (brgerliche Gesellschaft). According to Hegel, the life of the individual should evolve on three levels:
1) the family, in which natural solidarity prevails, 2) the civil society, in which individualism and selshness (das Prinzip der Persnlichkeit) dominates, 3) the state,
in which the individual acts as a citizen, i.e. oriented towards the common interest
of the whole political community (Hegel 1820, par. 181). Being familiar with the works
of contemporary authors such as Smith, Say, and Ricardo, Hegel realised that most individual action on the level of civil society benets the well-being of others through
the mutual benets of exchange and the division of labour (Hegel 1820, par. 243).
Moreover, Hegel did not consider civil society as a jungle, as Marx did. Hegel realised
very well that a well functioning civil society required an institutionally protected
discipline of respect for individual rights and property rights, and respect for mutual
promises (pacta sunt servanda). Hegel evaluated the genesis of the civil society as
an immense progress in human history and rejected strongly a return to the Staat des
Altertums, in which individuality was suppressed for the sake of common interest.
He did not consider, however, the emancipation of the individual on the level of civil
society as the ultimate realisation of freedom. In civil society, the person remains narrowly constrained by the horizon of his self-interest. Limiting our lives to the levels of
family and civil society would make of us crippled personalities. In order to be really
free, the human being needs a third level, the state, on which he can join his own
possibilities with the ones of his fellow citizens (citoyens, not bourgeois) in order
to realise the common good of all members of the state (Hegel 1820, par. 257-259).

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

147

When we compare the Hegelian notion of civil society with the liberal one, as outlined above, we remark at least two important dierences. Firstly, the liberal notion
encompasses the family, the Hegelian does not. This dierence is not merely conventional. By isolating the family from civil society, Hegel demoralises the latter
level, for few will deny that the family is a solid source of natural solidarity and as
such is a hotbed for wider forms of voluntary solidarity. Secondly, the Hegelian tripartite distinction overlooks systematically the possibility of voluntary associations,
aimed at non-selsh goods (charity, philanthropy, mutual aid, solidarity, etc.). Hegel
restricts the associative capacity of human beings to the level of the state. It is true
that between state and civil society Hegel situated the so-called Korporation (Hegel
1820, par. 201-208). But these associations (Stand des Gewerbs, Handwerksstand,
Fabrikantenstand, Handelstand, allgemeiner Stand, i.e. civil servants) are halfpolitical institutions, established to cater to the link between state and civil society.
By locating our moral capacities of altruism within the family and within the
state, only a demoralised shell is left for civil society. As for Hegel himself, an excuse can be found in the fact that he did not experience the amazing ourishing of
voluntary associations in the second half of the nineteenth century (for instance, the
Friendly Societies in England) (Green 1993, p. 89). Such an excuse does not exist,
however, for the numerous authors who continued to rely on the demoralised notion of civil society of Hegel, and to use it as an argument for the nationalisation of
solidarity.
In order to minimise the risk of confusion about our notion of civil society, we
should also mention the usage of the notion in its present, neo-corporatist sense.
Traditions of thought, such as corporatism and neo-corporatism, are much more
popular in continental Europe than in the Anglo-Saxon West. This is due to several
factors, such as the survival until deep into the nineteenth century of pre-modern,
corporatist economic (guilds) and political (die Standen) institutions and the preeminence of the Catholic Church, which advocated often corporatism as a third way
between capitalism and socialism (see the Encyclical Quadragesimo Anno, 1934). In
general, corporatist thought favours the organisation of the population into several
bodies, which are not directly initiated by or dependent on state authorities, but do,

148

New Perspectives on Political Economy

however, perform tasks, which are of public interest and may, by this, have compulsory characteristics. The corporations are not a part of the state, but act loco the
state.
Although a complete failure in its main aim to constitute a third way, corporatist thinking left its traces within the organisation of the welfare state in continental Europe. Often the collection of contributions to welfare and social securityinstitutions and the payment of social allowances are handled, not by state agencies,
but by associations with a voluntary pedigree (mutual aid-organisations, professional
associations, labour unions). Furthermore, the regulations of certain professions
(doctors, pharmacists, architects, lawyers) are left to corporate bodies, independent
from the state but enjoying a monopolistic protection from it.
The wide and often very heterogeneous collection of such intermediate bodies between state and individuals are also called, in present political literature in Europe,
civil society (societ civile, middenveld). The champion of global governance,
Riccardo Petrella and The Group of Lisbon, pretends to rely on the global civil society in order to accomplish his dream of governance of the world through dierent
social contracts (Petrella 1993, p. 173). The advocates of the welfare state shrewdly presented the neo-liberal attack on the welfare state as an attack on civil society and as
a relapse into brutal atomism, in which the isolated individual was put naked before
the state and private enterprise. By this, the debate about present welfare statism was
perceived by the majority of public opinion, not as a choice between compulsory and
voluntary solidarity and mutual aid, but as a choice between co-operation and isolation, the group and the atomised individual, the warm group-solidarity and the cold
market mechanism. The way how the debate about welfare-statism developed during
the last decade, especially in continental Europe, illustrates well how important it is
to dene civil society in its wide and rich liberal sense.

3 At the Dawn of Civil Society: Europe between 843-1073


During this period the European West touched the absolute bottom of its social, economic and cultural evolution. During the same period, however, the seeds were sown

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

149

for the spectacular revival of the 12th century. Economically and demographically the
European West must have looked during the 9th and 10th century like one vast wilderness with only small spots of habitation and cultivation. Total population around 1000
is estimated at about 12 million, the population of the present greater Paris area. In
1200 the population had risen to about 50 million, an increase of more than 300%
(Cameron 1993, p. 54). Rome, once a city of two million inhabitants, was now inhabited by only 20,000 people, living amidst antique monuments, which were gradually
falling into ruins.
Militarily, the European West was constantly plagued by internal civil wars and
by outside threats of barbarian invasions. Especially France, the former heart land
of Merovingian and Carolingian Empires, was the theatre of dynastic wars between
the Carolingians and Capetians, and countless battles between the lesser castle nobility (Duby 1978, p. 178). Very probably, the deep incursions from invaders into the
Western heartlands were made by small and unorganised bands. Nevertheless, public power was too weak to ward o these dangers. In 854 the ower of chivalry in
France had to be mobilised to repel an attack of Normans on Paris.
Only in 912, by the treaty of Claire-sur-Epte, Norman invasions came to an end by
ceding them the territory west of Paris, the later duchy of Normandy. Between 889972, Saracens occupied the fortress Fraxinetum in the neighbourhood of Marseille,
from which they organised raids up to the lake of Constanz. In 972 count William of
Provence was nally able to chase them out of the south of France. The south of Italy
and the western part of the Mediterranean Sea was dominated by Saracen pirates.
Emperor Otto II was killed in a campaign against them in southern Italy.
Only during the 11th century with the conquests of Sardinia (1022), Sicily (10581090), and Corsica (1091) was the Mediterranean Sea cleared and did it become open
for trade with the East. The German Empire was attacked from the east, rst by the
Avars and then by Magyars. The defeat of the latter at Lechfeld in 955 nally ended
this threat. Large parts of England were occupied and terrorised by Vikings and Danes
until they were nally expelled in the second half of the eleventh century.
As this overview of wars and raids shows, it would not be exaggerated to say that
Western European civilisation was threatened, during the ninth and tenth centuries

150

New Perspectives on Political Economy

with virtual disappearance. The social structure during this period reects all but
that of a civil society in its classical liberal sense. The picture of society during this
period is far from the broad network of interactive co-ordination based on exchange,
the division of labour, and free association. Due to the constant threat of war, trade
had virtually disappeared and economic agricultural life retreated to the small unit of
the manor. Within the already mentioned dichotomy, made by Oakeshot and Hayek,
these manors should be qualied as enterprise associations or taxis rather than as
civil associations or cosmos of a great society.
The enterprise association character of the manor was particularly reected by
the status of the unfree tenant, who was tied to the land and restricted in his personal
rights, such as the right to move and to marry. The unfree tenant belonged to the
enterprise of the manor. The rule of the lord over the unfree tenant coincided totally
with the management of his estate. It was a rule of men on men in the most literal
sense (Duby 1978, pp. 173-195).
This stringent inequality of rights within the early medieval manorial economy
found itself expressed in the image of the three orders. The bishops Gerard of Cambrai and Adalbero of Laon represented the ideal society as an organic body with three
functional parts: the praying and thinking part, i.e. the clergy (oratores); the ghting part, i.e. the military (bellatores); the working part, i.e. the vast majority of
agricultural labourers (plebs, populus). Clergy here referred more precisely to secular clergy, i.e. the hierarchy of archbishops, bishops, members of chapters, parish
priests. The status of the top-layer, especially of the bishops, was in many respects
similar to that of the ghting nobility. Bishops too had the status of manorial lords.
They were linked within feudal relationships of lord and vassal and were recruited
from the sons of landed aristocracy. They were regarded as real church princes. It is
important to note this, because, as we will see later, the other clergy, i.e. the regular
one of the monks, played a crucial role in the disturbance of this three order image
of society.
Within the prevailing political theory of these centuries, church and secular political institutions were hardly considered as separate entities. The church (ecclesia)
was not conceived of as a well outlined and organised body, with its own legal entity,
but as the vast collection of Christian people (populus christianus). At the head

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

151

of this populus christianus stood, not the bishop of Rome, but the king, considered the Vicar of Christ. Because his body was permeated with the Holy Unction, his
mind was permeated with wisdom, sapientia (Duby 1978, p. 26). As a king he did
not only protect Christianity by arms, he was also considered as the moral head of it.
This theory of sacred kingship is well developed in the famous Norman Anonymus,
a book written in 1100 in reaction to the new developments triggered by the papal
revolutions. The theory of sacred kingship had its impact on political practice. The
German emperors, considering themselves as the supreme head of Christianity, required the pope on his election to swear an oath of loyalty to the emperor. Of the
twenty-ve popes who held oce during the century prior to 1059, twenty-one were
directly appointed by emperors and ve were dismissed by them (Berman 1983, p. 91).
By this thorough merger of secular and spiritual power in the person of the king or
emperor, religion remained a tool in the hands of the powerful in order to legitimise
their privileges and to control the intellectual life of the rest of the people. Being
faithful meant for a large part recognising without any sign of resistance the power
of kings, lords, and bishops and resigning to their humble position, determined by
birth.
However dark these centuries were from a civil society viewpoint, two prevailing
factors should be mentioned, which would contribute to the dramatic change in the
twelfth century, i.e. feudalism and Christian universalism. Both factors as such did
not trigger social change. They would, however, do just this when combined with
other factors such as the papal revolution, the booming of associative life, and the
development of the rule of law.
The notion of feudalism is taken here in a narrow sense, i.e. as a system of recognised relationships between members of the ruling military or cleric order. The duties stipulated in the feudal contracts between lords and vassals could encompass
elements of a private and public character as well. With reference to private character we should mention: the granting of a benece (benecium), that is land or other
property such as cattle (the German term feod originally meant cattle, as the German word Vieh indicates, Berman 1983, p. 298). With reference to public character
we should mention the pledge of delity by the vassal (hommage), the obligation
of the vassal to render military service to the lord and the granting of the exercise

152

New Perspectives on Political Economy

of oces (manorial justice, taxation, service monopolies) by the lord to the vassal
(Berman 1983, pp. 295-313; Heirbaut 1997; Ganshof 1982). We can distinguish feudalism from the manorial system, which relates to the relationship between the lord
of a manor and the peasants, working on the manor under dierent statutes, such
as free tenants, serfs and slaves. Of course, the feudal and the manorial system were
related. The manor was often a benet (benecium) within the feudal relationship
and obtaining a feudal benet was attractive due to the dominant position the lord
held within the manorial system (Berman 1983, p. 316).
The narrow sense of feudalism is to be preferred for analytical reasons, for it is
possible that a manorial system persists without a feudal system. After the emergence of the monarchic states during the 15th and 16th century in Europe, feudalism
was gradually hollowed out, especially of its public content, while the manorial relationship persisted in many parts of Europe, especially the more eastern ones. Within
Marxist thinking the notion of feudalism has even acquired the status of a universal
stage in the history of mankind, i.e. the stage between slavery or the Asiatic way of
production and capitalism. This obliges the Marxist historian to distinguish feudal
stages in the historic development of non-western cultures. As a result, the notion of
feudalism receives such a wide meaning that it loses all analytical capacity. Marxist
historians are, as Berman pointed out (Berman 1993, pp. 296, 541), by no means able
to explain why the political superstructure of western feudalism diered so radically
from that of the east. The Marxist historian Perry Anderson has well perceived this
problem and attempted to save the Marxist notion of feudalism by arguing that the
distinction of superstructure and infrastructure is not applicable to feudalism. The
mode of production and the mode of exercising political and legal power are, according to Anderson, completely intertwined in feudalism (Anderson 1979, p. 400). This
position, however, threatens the whole distinction between super- and infrastructure,
which is vital for Marxist economic materialism. By the same token, we can question the distinction between superstructure and infrastructure within capitalism. As
the Marxist legal theorist Pasukanis argued, institutions such as property and contract also belong, in fact, to the capitalist infrastructure because a capitalist mode of
production is not thinkable without circulation of commodities and this circulation
presupposes legal institutions, such as property and contract (Pasukanis 1970).

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

153

Feudalism, as we understand it in its narrow sense, was indeed a pillar of the old
order, the one prevailing in the tenth and eleventh centuries. Through feudalism
the military class organised its dominance on the rest of the population. Through
feudalism some order prevailed after the total collapse of the Carolingian state. The
eect of feudalism was, however, not only conservative.
First of all, feudalism allowed for a more or less ordered decentralisation of political power. Western Europe of the eleventh century was, especially in the heart-land,
France, a patchwork of innumerable small political entities. According to the theory
of federalism (Tiebaut 1956, Inman and Rubinfeld 1998 ) decentralisation allows for
benecial eects such as voting with the feet, the submission of political power to
some competitive pressure, and institutional competition, allowing political entities
to learn from each others experiences.
Voting with the feet under feudalism occurred in many ways. The most important
movement concerns the constant escape of serfs from the manor to the emerging
cities (Bouckaert 1997). Often lords, but especially monasteries, attracted serfs from
other manors by oering them a better legal status. The coastal area of Flanders, for
instance, only had free peasants, because the abbeys, which undertook the winning
of land on the sea, oered them this status.
Learning by competition also occurred in feudalism. The reaction of feudal lords
to cities was, at the beginning, very hostile. Ivo of Chartres for instance, advised the
bishops, who were forced to concede liberties to revolting communes, to retract them
because they were made under threat (Pirenne 1925, p. 128). Some feudal authorities,
such as the Flemish counts of the house of Alsace during the twelfth century, pursued
a supply side policy towards the cities by granting them many freedoms in the hope
of getting tax returns. This attitude spread quickly. According to Spruyt, the alliance
between king and cities laid even the base for the emergence of the French nationstate (Spruyt 1996, p. 153).
Secondly, feudalism was crucial in the later development of the rule of law. This
remark, probably surprising for many, deserves some qualication. In its major characteristic feudalism is indeed a at negation of the rule of law, for it favours the
emergence of numerous concrete legal arrangements between lords, vassals and their

154

New Perspectives on Political Economy

subjects, characterised by inequality and diversity. The emergence of a more abstract


rule of law, adequate for a broad abstract order, would occur entirely at the expense
of the dierent concrete feudal legal orders (Macfarlane 1987). Yet, feudalism contained one feature, crucial for the expansion of the rule of law, namely its character
of reciprocity. Lord and vassal had reciprocal duties. When the lord did not full his
duties, the vassal could consider himself to be freed from his. He even had a right
of resistance towards acts of his lord, which were contrary to the feudal agreement.
Consequently, the power of the lord was not absolute. Moreover, the vassal had the
right to defend himself against misdeeds of his lord. Such a reciprocity is completely
absent in the later, emerging theory of state sovereignty. The reciprocity of feudalism
is clearly at the base of the famous founding document of the English constitution,
the Magna Carta. The freedom of the barons against the kings articulated in it were
later on gradually extended to all citizens of the kingdom. In Flanders, at the beginning of the twelfth century, the cities revolted against Count William of Normandy,
the political favorite of the French king. Their spokesman, Iwein of Aalst, claimed
that William had broken his contract with the cities so that they were freed from
their political obligations towards the count. William of Normandy was killed in battle during the following civil war in Flanders and Dirk of Alsace, a pro-city-count
became the new count. Both events, crucial for the respective countries, show that
the reciprocal element within feudal law was invoked as a legitimate base to claim
initially and to extend gradually the rights status of the vassal to broader layers of the
population (Heirbaut 1997, p. 225).
The second element, which contributed to the dramatic change in the twelfth century, needs much less explanation, for it is less contested. Whatever the complicity
of the church authorities with the secular political authorities, the church has to be
credited with upholding the idea of Christian universalism and, more or less linked
with it, the cultural legacy of Roman antiquity. Thanks to the existence of the church
and the however limited intellectual activity within it, the total spiritual decomposition of the West into tribal or local mini-cultures was prevented. The church not
only saved the books during this period, but was also able to maintain the idea of
the Latin West (lOccident), a culture with a common destiny and common overarching values. The revolutionary potential of this idea remained only latently present

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

155

during this period, due to mentioned factors. As soon as these obstacles would waver,
the power of this idea would be soon unleashed.

Peace and Work

Few will question that war is detrimental to the development of civil society. War not
only causes the destruction of economic and cultural wealth, but it often aects profoundly the relationships between rulers and ruled, between state and civil society.
War tends to turn a civil association, to use Oakeshots terminology again, into one
gigantic enterprise association. War disrupts familial and voluntary relationships and
drags large parts of the young male population into the machine of military massication. Examples of the profoundly decivilising eect of war are not hard to nd. The
rather peaceful and libertarian political relationships within early Anglo-Saxon tribes
were pushed into an authoritarian direction by the constant wars with the Vikings
and the Danes (Benson 1989, pp. 1-81). As mentioned already, the retreat of the
early medieval economy into the manor was due to the threat of constant warfare, by
which peasants sought refuge under the umbrella of armed protection of the knights.
The endless wars of the monarchist states between 1450 and 1750 triggered the rise
of taxation and the formation of a state bureaucracy (Webber and Wildawsky 1986,
pp. 228-298; Tilly 1975). The First World War disrupted entirely the emerging civil
society in Russia and provided Lenin with the revolutionary masses he needed for the
realisation of his totalitarian plans. In more liberal and democratic societies, such as
the US and Western Europe, the world wars led to upswings in state regulation and
central planning, which could only be partially reduced after the war (the ratchet
eect, Higgs 1987).
How did war evolve after the disastrous era (843-1077) outlined above? By about
1050 all external threats to the Latin West had been warded o. However, internal
warfare by the armed knights continued, causing enormous terror and damage to the
labouring peasant population. Indeed, ghting remained, even without external military threat, a part of the life style of the large class of knights inhabiting their fortied
castles across the West, especially in the heartland, France. Among Germanic peoples

156

New Perspectives on Political Economy

honour (die Ehre) ranked high in the value scale, especially among the elites. As a
consequence, the slightest feeling of insult or humiliation could trigger a feud (faida,
Fehde, vete) between knights (Heyn 1982, p. 24). It is unnecessary to add that these
wars of honour created very unpleasant spill-over eects to the peasant population:
harvests were burnt, serfs killed, women raped, churches and monasteries pillaged.
In the German Reich, which was ruled during the tenth and eleventh centuries by
powerful emperors, knightly warfare was quite successfully reduced by a policy of
Landesfrieden. The emperor convened on regular time intervals with the Great of
the Reich in order to take oaths of peace. The Great in turn tried to do the same
in their stemduchies (the Landfriede of 1084, Ronkalisher Landfriede of 1158, Rheinfrnkischer Friede of 1179, Reichslandfriede of 1234, Bayerischer Landfrieden of 13th
century; see Heyn 1982, pp. 26-32).
In France (West-Francia still at that time), no royal power was able to impose
such a peace. The early Capetian kings (987-1180) ruled eectively only in the area
between Paris and Orleans. Especially the south of France, escaping totally from
royal control, was plagued by vehement knightly wars. In these regions the movement of the Peace of God (Pax Dei) arose. Contrary to the imperial Landesfrieden,
the French peace movement rose from the lower layers of society. Special attention
should be paid, however, to the role of the monks. Since the tenth century, the monks
manifested themselves more and more as a power, independent from secular clergy
and the knightly class. They did so mostly by putting themselves under the direct supervision of the pope. They must have thought it better to have a remote ineective
overlord than a petty but close, and hence, eective one. The leading monastery in
this respect was no doubt Cluny, founded in 910 and exempted from local supervision
in 998. This exemption was later extended by pope Benedictus VIII to all dependent
monasteries. As a result a whole network of intellectually and economically ourishing enterprises spread in Europe, escaping totally from local control. Unarmed but
quite wealthy, the monasteries were easy prey for the warring knights. As a result,
the monasteries took the lead in the peace movement in France during the tenth
and eleventh century. They organised large, regional meetings, on which the local
population gathered, and during which series of war restrictions were voted (e.g.,
meetings of 989-990 in Charroux-Poitou, 990 in Narbonne, 994 in Limoges, Le Puy

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

157

and Anse-Lyon) (Duby 1978, p. 158). The Pax Dei forbade all violent actions of a
knight, including pillage and rape, against unarmed people, under which the clergy,
monks and peasants were understood. During the eleventh century, in a second wave
of the peace movement, the Truce of God (treuga Dei) was promoted, which provided
a total ban on warfare from Wednesday evening to Monday morning, during Lent and
Advent, the three great vigils and the feasts of the Blessed Virgin and the twelve apostles. Not much time was left for ghting. At the meeting Verdun-sur-le-Doubs in 1016,
it was provided that all knights had to swear oaths to comply with these rules. These
provisions were at the base of the ethos of chivalry.
This mass movement for peace, energised by the monastic movement, did not
last very long. After the eleventh century its heyday was denitively over. Gradually,
the task of providing peace was again taken over by strong secular rulers, such as the
king of England, the count of Flanders (Van Caenegem 1993) and by local princes in
Germany after the collapse of the First Reich.
The peace movement did not ban war from European history. The military energy
was refunneled to outside wars, especially to the crusades during the twelfth and
thirteenth centuries. From the fourteenth century on large dynastic wars started,
such as the Hundred Years Wars between French and English kings in the fourteenth
and fteenth century and the wars between Habsburg and Valois in the sixteenth
century. During the seventeenth century the west became the theatre of religiousdynastic wars, during the nineteenth century (till 1918) of national wars, and during
the twentieth century of ideologically inspired wars.
Nevertheless, we can credit the medieval peace movement with some lasting consequences for Western civilisation.
Few will question the benecial economic consequences of it. The drop in warfare made travelling much safer, allowed more long-term investment in industry and
agriculture, made peasants less dependent on the military protection of their lord,
allowed the expansion of large non-militarised settlements, which were devoted to
trade and craft. It is certainly not a coincidence that the total population started to
rise steeply from the twelfth century onwards, whilst the urban component in it rose
even faster (Cameron 1993, pp. 54-62; Bairoch 1988). Rather timidly during the last

158

New Perspectives on Political Economy

half of the eleventh century, but tempestuously from the rst decades of the twelfth
century, trade associations multiplied, fairs were organised, artisans were attracted
to cities, monetary circulation soared, risky ventures (the commenda) were set up.
The proximity in time between the reduction of warfare and the revival of trade and
urban life is too obvious to deny its causal relationship.
In order to reshape society, trade and industry not only need to be done, but
should also be regarded in society as respectable, even honourable activities. As long
as trade and craft are just tolerated by the leading clerical and military layers of society
as wealth producing machines, their long-term stability is not guaranteed because
short sighted political leaders may be tempted then to exhaust trade and craft for
short-term benets.
Moreover, when social respect for trade and craft is lacking, the elites of the trade
community will be steadily skimmed o in order to become part of the more respected
elites. This certainly happened often in continental Europe until the French Revolution. Merchants, once well o, often tried, sometimes in a piteous way, to enter into
the nobility, for instance, by marrying their daughter to an impoverished aristocrat
(Baechler 1975, p. 70).
About the question when and how a change to a positive valuation of trade and
work in general occurred in the West, two strongly diverging views prevail. Max Weber places this turn in the sixteenth century with the advent of Protestantism, especially its Calvinist-Puritan component. Due to their strong belief in predestination,
they developed a work ethic, conducive to the foregoing of short term benets and
preference for long-terminvestments (Weber 1967). Weber, who studied thoroughly
the historic evolution of the West, was, of course, well aware of the dramatic increase
of trade in the twelfth and thirteenth century. According to Weber, however, the ethic
of the Middle Ages remained basically hostile to trade, craft and entrepreneurship in
general. The trader, even when tolerated for economic reasons, remained a foreign
element within the medieval value system. Only within the protestant countries such
as the United Provinces, England and northern Germany, a social ethic rating such
activities positively developed. As a result, the constant skimming o from the merchant class by the nobility ceased. On the contrary, the merchant class became the
politically dominant class on its own merit.

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

159

Whether Weber was right about the religious origin of the commercial success of
countries like England and Holland is a question falling beyond our scope. We have
to deal with the other contention of Weber, i.e. the negative, or at least diminishing
attitude towards trade and work before Protestantism. Webers view probably holds
for the early medieval period, let us say, until 1100-1150. Most written sources of this
period, especially the biographies of saints (the vitae) treat commercial life with
disdain. Take, for instance, the vita of St. Godric of Finshale. This poor peasant
son, born around 1080 in Lincolnshire, started as a beachcomber, accumulated a little capital as a peddler, went as a dusty feet-merchant from market to market, fair to
fair, town to town. With his prots he started, together with other merchants, a shipping company, and engaged in coastal trade along the shores of England, Scotland,
Denmark and Flanders. After some years, Godric had become a very rich man. In the
present day U.S., Godric would be praised as an example for the American dream.
The vita has, however, another happy end. Godric, moved by grace, suddenly understood the vanity of his fortune. He turned over all his possessions to the poor and
became a hermit (Pirenne 1956, p. 82, see also other examples about the ignobilis
mercatura in Pirenne).
On the other hand, sources from the same period indicate a positive attitude towards a life of work and earning prots. The texts collected by Gratian (c. 1140, De
Matrimonio and Decretum) dene the status of laity as men, righteously married,
tillers of the soil, capable of adjudication amongst themselves, and with rights to
pursue their own aairs as possessors and users of worldly goods (Coleman 1988, p.
609). In the same period, the well known theologian Ivo of Chartres (c. 1040-1115)
implicitly rejected the three ordersview by holding that God created man in his own
image and rescued him from his pain, the one as well as the other. Both, the poor
and the rich, are equal in His love and for Jesus Christ there is no freeman nor serf,
because all the ones who participate in His sacrament are equal (Van der Ven 1968,
II, p. 39).
These texts reveal a positive view towards earthly life and towards the third, working order in general, which was no longer regarded as a mere food provider to the two
higher orders. During the thirteenth and fourteenth century a much more elaborated
positive evaluation of trade and artisanship specically would become predominant.

160

New Perspectives on Political Economy

The craftsman had allies in theology. Jesus was after all a carpenters son and
apprentice. Moral theologians began to regard manual work as no longer a penalty
for sin, but a positive means to salvation (Black 1984, p. 15).
Between Aquinas view on man with reason and hands, who had to meet his need
by some industry, and the later Renaissance cult of business (negotium, homo
faber) there was only continuity (Black 1984, p. 16). Sombart, the most famous
opponent of the Weberian thesis, is very convincing when he points to the ourishing literature in northern Italy, upholding without any hesitation classical middleclassvalues, such as hard work, prot making, long term perspective, prudence and
sobriety (Sombart 1915, pp. 103-124).
Thomas Aquinas writings in the thirteenth century still show a static view on
the position of each man and the wealth he deserved accordingly. Later schoolmen,
however, such as cardinal Cajetan, held that every man ought to have the possibility of
working himself up and becoming richer than he was (Sombart 1915, p. 246). Unlike
in the vita of Goderic, the merchant, who had become rich, could keep his fortune
without any remorse, provided he had made his prots in an honest way.
Sombart seems to be right when he advocates that these later schoolmen had
more sympathy for and understanding of capitalism than the 17th century zealot
preachers of Puritanism (Sombart 1915, p. 244). The aforementioned opinions show
that from the twelfth century on a deep intellectual revolution took place concomitant with the economic evolution, by which the values of military honour, subjection,
and fatalism were replaced by respect for peace, work, trade, and individual progress.

Medieval Horizontalism: The Rise of Associations

Civil society in the classical liberal sense is a non-organic notion. According to this
view, the organic picture of society as a teleological body in which individuals and
groups perform static functions towards the whole is misleading. Individuals and
groups do, of course, perform functions within society. Such functions are often deliberately conceived and performed by individuals in their interaction towards others.

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

161

Sometimes such functions are perceived only ex post, by social understanding, when
actions of some have unintended consequences for others. In both cases however, individuals or groups do not function for society but for benets and values, perceived
ex ante or only ex post within their mutual interaction.
Did medieval man conceive his individual or group-life as organic towards the
whole? Since the eighteenth century Enlightenment, most social theorists and historians answer this question armatively. The Enlightenment, with its preference
for mechanistic explanation and individual emancipation, blamed the Middle Ages
for its organicism. Nineteenth century romanticism on the contrary, gloried the
Middle Ages for it. Modern corporatist thinkers, such as Otto von Gierke (1841-1921),
Ferdinand Tnnies (1885-1933) and Emile Durkheim (1858-1917) found their inspiration in the warm organic group life of the Middle Ages, which was contrasted with the
cold rationalistic and atomistic life under liberal capitalism (Black 1984, pp. 210-236).
Even contemporary authors, such as the socio-linguist Michaud-Quantin, assume the
existence of a communitarian ethos in order to understand medieval social language
(Black 1988, p. 588).
There appears to be some weight to this view on the Middle Ages. In its thinking
about society, the medieval church used organic categories. The Catholic Church,
the extension of the invisible and eternal in time and place, was depicted as the body
of Christ, in whose mystery all faithful participated. The members of this body were
functionally related to the whole by their duties, their ocia. Individuals only entered the picture as occupants of these ocia. The individual as such, as denuded
from his ocia, was never opposed to the whole of society (Black 1988, p. 592; 1992,
p. 15; Bouckaert 1991, p. 156).
The organic analogy was also used for smaller entities, such as cities. The city was
often rather seen as a close community, as a near family, rather than as a civil, political
association. Henry of Ghent (c.1270) sees the city as men living together in civil
society and communion; for this could not exist unless bound together by supreme
friendship, in which each considered the other as a second self, by supreme charity,
by which each of them loved the other as himself, and by supreme benevolence, by
which each of them wished for the other what he wished for himself (Black 1998,

162

New Perspectives on Political Economy

p. 597). Parties (pars, partes) were regarded with a bad eye, because they divided
the body. According to Remigio de Girolami (c. 1319), the city is a whole which the
parts love more than themselves and to which they are more closely joined than to
themselves (Black 1998, p. 597; Skinner 1992, p. 65).
These opinions leave us with a picture of an organicist society, in which people
dened themselves merely as an element of a group, in which they were locked in
beyond their free will.
Against this picture, which has seduced so many social theorists, we must oppose, rst of all, the legal doctrine about associations, and secondly, some features of
medieval community life, as it probably was.
The medieval lawyers, especially the glossators of the Roman law, mostly took a
liberal position towards the question of the founding of new associations. The original texts of the Digest provided that craft workers could only form a college by permission of senate or emperor, with the exception of some listed crafts (Digest 3.4.1 pr).
The medieval glossators circumvented this legal obstacle by considering this latter
list as indicative, and thereby legalising all craft-guilds, without any further requirement (Black 1984, p. 19). The same view was adopted by Pope Innocent IV, who also
defended the individualistic position that corporate bodies could not be punished
(Black 1984, p. 21). Innocent IV and Bartolus, perhaps the most famous lawyer of his
time, both armed the right to freely enter and leave voluntary colleges. Bartolus
also opposed any regulation, by which the exercise of a craft was restricted to some
persons (Black 1984, p. 23). As far as medieval legal opinion was concerned, no static
or organic view on the formation and evolution of associations was exposed. On the
contrary, their views were quite close to the later liberal views on the freedom of association. Also their legal concept of an association was all but holistic. Bassianus for
instance, considered an association (universitas) as a collection of several bodies
distinct from each other. He considered the universitas neither as an individual,
nor as a species, but simply as a notion to indicate separate bodies which were joined
together (Black 1988, p. 598).
Though inuenced by Aristotelian holistic thinking, Thomas Aquinas also rejects
holism when he says, man is not related to the political community as to his whole

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

163

being and everything that is his, and therefore not all his actions need be classied
as praiseworthy or blameworthy in relation to the political community (Black 1988,
p. 600).
When considering the evolution of associations in medieval social history, one
cannot deny its astounding dynamism and variety. Twelfth century Europe was the
theatre of a real explosion of associations, not only in number but also in kinds. With
regard to teaching and scientic research there was the rapid spread of universities
from south to north, west to east. With regard to trade, there were the merchants
guilds, springing up in every city, organising fairs and providing a very eective adjudication system (Benson 1997, p. 43; Trakman 1983, pp. 7-21).
On the political legal level, we have to mention the boom of new cities, which
mostly had a voluntary origin in the famous communes (Bouckaert 1997). On the social level, we have to mention the founding of numerous hospitals and other religious
charities (Strayer 1985, p. 292).
This tremendous explosion shows that associative life in the Middle Ages was not
static at all. Apparently, social entrepreneurs were busy in all niches of society. One
should compare twelfth century Europe with a thrifty social laboratory rather than
with a static, organic entity.
When considering the relationship of individuals with their association, one also
should be cautious of presenting too static a picture. Firstly, most individuals must
have been members of several and very dierent associations. One could be a member
of his city, of his guild, of his confraternity, of his chapter, of his university, etc. It is too
simple to argue that one was born and died within his group. Usually, urban citizens
participated within a very varied group life. Secondly, demographic studies point out
that mobility, especially among intellectuals, but also among artisans, was quite high
(Berman 1983, p. 123).
It is true that often one or more sons became an apprentice in the same craft as
their father, and because of which one business remained sometimes within one family for generations. Other children, however, had to look for other job opportunities,
which they often found in other crafts, in trade, or within the wide ranks of secular
and regular clergy, which was, of course, not family based at all in its recruitment.

164

New Perspectives on Political Economy

It is true that medieval political literature emphasised the role of the community in the life of individuals and the duties of them towards the community. This
does not imply, however, a holistic political philosophy, according to which the individual is considered nothing more than the ephemeral manifestation of a collective
entity. The emphasis on the community was mostly related to the need for a joint
eort in order to preserve some goods, especially liberties, for individuals, which
they cannot preserve by their isolated eorts (Black 1988, p. 596; 1992, pp. 18-41).
The good of the community (bonum commune) was not perceived as something
distinct from the good of the individual. Remigio de Girolami expressed the relationship between the individual and the common good as follows: Let the citizen,
however poor in himself, strive to make his commune ourish, for in this way he
himself will ourish (Black 1988, p. 596). John of Viterbo said about the city: A
city is called the liberty of citizens or the immunity of inhabitants for that reason
walls were built to provide help for the inhabitants. City means: you dwell safe from
violence. Civitas, id est ci (tra) vi(m)(hab)itas. For residence is without violence, because the ruler of the city will protect the lowlier men lest they suer injury from the
more powerful (Black 1992, p. 19). Such statements about the community and the
common good do not reect holism at all. It would be easy to translate them in
modern methodological individualist notions such as economies of scale and public
or collective goods.
To conclude this section, it must be argued that neither medieval social history,
nor medieval political theory provides us with a picture of a static organic society,
in which the individual was virtually nonexistent but considered himself only as an
epi-phenomenon of the group to which he belonged. We perceive rather the emergence of a society, in which the medieval individual became gradually conscious of his
possibilities to use the dynamism of joint eorts in order to improve his status (libertas) and his material wealth. Group life had, of course, another outlook than in the
modern liberal society. It was far more religiously tainted and had often monopolistic traits. All this does not justify, however, the picture of medieval organicism. This
seems rather to be a myth made up for nineteenth century anti-liberal, ideological
purposes.

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

165

Is There a Medieval nomos?

Order within civil society rests upon a set of common rules, which do not force individuals into a specic, goal-directed strategy, but which allow individuals to pursue in
an orderly and peaceful way their own goals. Such rules are subservient to a multitude
of very diverse goals, plans and life-styles within a free society. We perceive such rules
and their supporting institutions in the traditional bodies of private law, articulated
on the European continent in written codes and contained in commonlaw countries
by a body of precedent law. Though these traditions show national dierences, they
are, nevertheless, subservient to one gradually globalising order. They rest upon similar principles, while the national dierences are overcome by the tradition of the law
of legal conicts (international private law). Perhaps this perception of the modern
liberal nomos is too legalistic. Modern sociological and economic literature stresses
the importance of underlying values and ways of social interaction, which may be as
important as the formal rules of the law. Fukuyama, for instance, stresses the importance of trust (Fukuyama 1996), Ellickson the importance of basic social moralities
(Ellickson 1991), Haberman the importance of conventional rules in Confucian China
(Haberman 1995, p. 73), Macauley the importance of reputation in business relationships (Macauley 1963). How the legal component relates to moral components within
the nomos of modern society is a question beyond our scope. There is, however, a
large consensus to perceive such a cluster of legal rules and moral values as underlying the modern global civil society. The question is whether there was something
similar in the Middle Ages. Again, much seems to point to the opposite.
Many parts of the medieval legal order reect more a patchwork quilt-type of a
small, concrete legal mini-order rather than a broad nomos. This seems to be the
case for the manorial law, which aected, needless to say, the daily life of the vast majority of the peasant population. The rules could dier from manor to manor, while
the jurisdiction on demesne matters rested entirely with the lord of the manor. According to his whims, the practice of the manorial courts could dier from manor to
manor. Manorial law concerned very practical regulations of the management of the
realm, such as the use of the commons, of monopolised goods (pond, woods, mills,
mines); the rules about manorial labour, duties or rents; easements between estates,

166

New Perspectives on Political Economy

etc. The property of the peasants was not submitted to the abstract rules of markets,
but rather to internal family rules such as the retrait lignager, obliging the vendor
of land to oer it rst to family members. It looks as if the bulk of the population
was caught in the small cages of very restricted and concrete legal orders, looking
much more like Oakeshots enterprise associations than a civil association. From a
sociological viewpoint medieval society can be qualied overwhelmingly as a peasant society, i.e. a society in which the local community (parish, village, manor) is
the central economic, ritual, cultural, and social control unit and in which relationships among the inhabitants are based on personal contacts (for an overview on the
peasants society literature see Macfarlane 1978, pp. 7-61).
Even the cities, though the most dynamic actors in medieval society, appear rather
as closed and concrete legal orders. Each city had its own, sometimes very detailed
regulations on trade, taxation, the use of the public domain, the entry of crafts, etc.
They acted, in fact, as a large articial family, thereby subduing their subjects to severe social control. Cities intervened deeply in economic life, such as, for instance,
through the so-called staple rights (vente aux tapes), according to which shippers
of vessels of wheat could be obliged to cede a part of their load (one sixth or one quarter), to be sold later after an interval of some weeks. By doing this the city disposed
of permanent reserves of wheat (Bouckaert 1997, p. 234).
The absence of an abstract nomocratic rule, allowing individuals to pursue their
own goals, is perhaps most obvious in the religious practices of the Middle Ages. The
tolerance espoused by the church authorities had a meaning totally dierent from
the later modern, liberal principle of tolerance developed by John Locke and John
Stuart Mill. Medieval tolerance consisted of a virtue to be practised by the Christian
faithful, imposing on them a certain moderation in their battle against evil. Often
one had to tolerate evil, i.e. not to intervene violently when even having the means to
do so, because the harm of intervention could be worse than the evil one wanted to
eradicate. Tolerance was a permissio comparativa. It was the outcome of a balance
made by the Christian ruler between the evil to repress and the evil of repression
(Berjczy 1997).
The strategic character of medieval tolerance is clearly shown by the attitude of
the church towards heretics. They were excluded from any policy of tolerance, unlike

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

167

for instance Jews, Muslims, or prostitutes. The evil of heresy, including the danger of splitting the community of the faithful (universitas delium) outweighed apparently the evil of violent persecution and repression.
The evolution concerning religious tolerance has deeply aected the general perception of the Middle Ages and the periodisation of history. It is very common to
outline post-medieval history on this matter as follows: the religious totalitarianism (theocracy, hierocracy) of the Middle Ages led, after some shattered attempts of
reformation during the fteenth century (conciliarism of Constanz), to a split in
Christianity and to the many religious wars in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries; a real civil society-solution nally emerged in England, where strong religious diversity created the dilemma of either endless civil war or tolerance as an
overarching constitutional principle.
When we add together what we mentioned about the medieval peasant society,
about the strictly controlled cities, and about the lack of religious tolerance, we must
conclude that the emergence of a nomos of a liberal civil society was only enabled
by a total breakaway from medieval conceptions and social structures. We will contend this belief in the following three sections. Although the mentioned elements,
picturing the Middle Ages as the opposite of a civil society rest upon many historical facts, we see more of a continuity between the philosophical, legal, and political
traditions in the Middle Ages and the later emergence of a ourishing civil society in
the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, than a real breakaway.

Medieval Humanism

As we mentioned already at the end of section 3, the church had been able, during
the preceding centuries (500-1000) to integrate the invading pagan, Germanic, Slavic
and Hungarian tribes within a culture of Christian universalism. Unlike the pagan
religion of the barbaric tribes and antique cities, the Christian gospel taught that
salvation was possible for the whole of humanity because everybody can participate
through his faith in Gods love. In this way Christianity constituted in the culture of
the West a profound anti-tribal and anti-racist intellectual tradition. If Christianity
was profoundly tolerant of accepting people to its womb, the question, however, re-

168

New Perspectives on Political Economy

mained how tolerant Christians would be towards the ones who preferred to remain
outside Christianity (Jews, Muslims, pagans), and the ones who espoused religious
views regarded as heterodox (heretics).
Although no stable constitutional practice of religious tolerance originated during the Middle Ages, the philosophical bases of it on which later liberalism would
build were developed during this era. Two doctrines should especially be mentioned
with regard to this, i.e. the doctrine of natural law and the distinction of crime and
sin.
Natural law theory, brought to its medieval heights by Thomas Aquinas, implied
that man, as a rational creature, was able to discover by reasoning and by experience
alone basic moral truths necessary for a viable society. In order to open himself to
the mercy of God one also had to learn the divine law revealed in the bible and ecclesiastical tradition (Aquinas 1952, pp. 208-209, 221-223). The distinction between
natural and divine law provides a natural base for a constitutional rule of tolerance,
for it implies that faith, however necessary for salvation, is not necessary for an orderly society. Provided they respect the rules of natural law, heathens, Jews, Muslims,
and Christians should be able to live together peacefully. This distinction also provides the philosophical base for the later separation of state and religion, allotting to
secular authorities the maintenance of at least the natural law-order and to churchauthorities the preaching of the Gospel, including the divine law.
Building further on the teaching of the medieval Schoolmen, the Dutch lawyer
Hugo Grotius split natural law from theology by stating that natural law was also
valid for people who did not believe in God at all (etiamsi daremus quod sine summo
scelere dari nequit, non esse Deum, Grotius 1993, p. 10). Locke, exiled from England, lived in Holland as a guest of Philip of Limborch, a member of the liberal
Arminian party, to which Grotius belonged also. This probably provides us with the
historic link between medieval natural law thinking and modern liberal tolerance.
Parallel with the distinction of natural law and divine law, medieval philosophers,
especially Abelard and Petrus Lombardus, distinguished crime from sin. All crimes
were sin, but not the inverse. Many sins, such as, for instance, thoughts of disbe-

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

169

lief, can only be judged by God and not by human jurisdictions, neither secular nor
canonic. All acts and thoughts, which are not suciently externalised towards others
(operationes ad alterum) should, therefore, remain beyond the reach of criminal
sanctions. Eventually, they could be administered by the priest by his sacramental
power and be sanctioned by penitence, but not by secular sanctions (Nemo 1996,
p. 281). However unclear the distinction between forum internum and forum externum might have been, it provided the intellectual base for the distinction between mere immoral and illegal acts, between moral, religious and social sanctions
and criminal sanctions, and nally as well as for our much cherished freedom of
thought.
The question remains, however, why these humanistic tenets within medieval
Christian philosophy did not develop into constitutional practice. The answer must
be sought in the interaction between principles and self-interest. Principles will only
prevail in practice when the actors perceive some self-interest in the preservation of
the principle. The principle of respect for property nds numerous defenders into
the wide ranks of individual owners, who experience from day to day the benets
of property and can themselves imagine how bad life would be without respect for
property rights.
During the Middle Ages society was homogeneously Christian, while the authority of the church as such was seldom contested. In these circumstances it was hard
for church leaders to perceive some interest in a policy of tolerance. The use of violence, willingly oered to the church by secular rules, was a very easy solution in
which no harm for the church itself was perceived. Only later would more and more
Christian thinkers, like Erasmus of Rotterdam, become aware of the fact that this created the opportunity for rulers to abuse religion and church authority for their own
political purposes. In protestant countries the threat of constant civil war created a
self-interest in tolerance for the dierent religious parties. In Catholic countries we
have to wait until the nineteenth century before the church perceived, as a result of
the teaching of catholic liberals such as Lammenais and Montalambert, the many
opportunities of a liberal constitution.

170

New Perspectives on Political Economy

8 The Ius Commune of Europe

With regard to the development of law, the Middle Ages were thoroughly polycentric:
legal rules, notions, theories, and procedures were developed in many centres, often
without territorial monopoly power. Such centres were the papal curia for canon
law, the universities for Roman law, the secular rulers for feudal law, the city magistrates for urban law, the consular courts for commercial law, the manorial courts
for manorial law. It is puzzling how such a panoply of law-producing centres could
lead towards a general and consistent cluster of legal rules constituting a nomos
for an abstract order (see above, section 6). Most legal historians, however, agree
that during the concerned period (1073-1400) a legal tradition, common to the whole
Latin West (ius commune) came about (Berman 1983, p. 120; Van Caenegem 1988).
However paradoxical this may sound, the formation of the body of a European legal
tradition originated because of this polycentrism and not against it. The paradox can
be explained by two major features of medieval legal polycentrism: 1) some centres of
law production were of a non-territorial character, so they were in a constant competitive relationship with other law producers; this was the case for canon law, Roman
law and commercial law; 2) the territorial law producers were so manifold that ample
room was left for experiment, innovation, and imitation; this was the case for urban
law, manorial, and feudal law. We will show this by briey dealing with canon law,
Roman law, urban and manorial law.
From the beginning of the twelfth century, the production of canon law developed
at a greater speed. The popes enacted decretal after decretal, but even more important were the eorts to systematise the already past decretals into one coherent body
of canon law. This was especially the result of the patient work of Gratian, leading to
the Decretum in 1140. This work, generally recognised as the authoritative statement
of the canon law, was later on constantly glossed and commented, giving birth in this
way to a very rich and consistent body of law (Berman 1983, p. 202). This legal revolution is of course a by-product of the more fundamental papal revolution, which
started in 1073 with the papacy of Pope Gregory VII, the famous Cluniac monk Hildebrand. This pope profoundly altered the image of the church and its relationship
with the secular world. Under his papacy the church appropriated itself an image

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

171

of a well-structured body, separate from secular power, with its own hierarchy and
discipline, and with a strong commitment to change the world according to the Christian gospel. The papal revolution had deep political consequences. From then on a
strong transboundary power was constituted, limiting the power of secular rulers,
even in non-spiritual matters. The papal institutions claimed to be the head of the
respublica Christiana, in which they exercised legislative power, while the secular
rulers within this respublica acted only as executive agents, owing obedience to the
authority of the pope. For two centuries (1100-1300) this papal supremacy was a political reality. Counts, dukes, kings and emperors feared the dictates of the pope. Popes
could plunge a whole country into disorder and civil war by their decisions. The popes
succeeded in annihilating the power of the German emperor. They only had to bow
for the much more ecient and less scrupulous power of Philip The Fair, the French
king who submitted the papacy to his political strategy (Spruyt 1996, p. 96).
Besides this political eect, Nemo attaches a more profound meaning to the papal
revolution and the ensuing growth of canon law. According to him, this revolution
brought about a reconciliation between the Roman legal tradition, based on reciprocity, corrective, and distributive justice, and the Christian faith based on innite
compassion (misericordia) with those suering in the world (Nemo 1996, p. 272).
Through changes in theology, such as the introduction of purgatory, many moral
Christian notions were rendered measurable. Penitence became apportioned to the
gravity of the sins. A faithful Christian was able to expiate his sins and to assure his
salvation by a virtuous life and giving sacrices to the church. In short, the papal
revolution realised the Christianisation of the legal legacy of antiquity and the juridication of Christian morality. In this way Western civilisation was enriched by a
fusion of Rome and Jerusalem.
Within the sphere of legal practice, the courts of canon law arrogated themselves
a very wide jurisdiction. First of all, they claimed exclusive jurisdiction on all church
matters, which constituted an important part of social activities when taking into account the immense properties of churches and abbeys. Secondly, they claimed jurisdiction on all matters of lay people, which had a religious dimension. Examples of this
were marriage law, because marriage was a sacrament; testamentary cases, because a
will was seen as a religious act; all cases of contract and property in which a breach of

172

New Perspectives on Political Economy

pledge of faith was involved; criminal cases such as adultery, assault against a cleric,
sacrilege, sorcery, usury, fornication and homosexuality (Berman 1983, p. 261). Because of these materiae mixtae, litigants had often the choice to bring their case for
a canonic or a secular court. Due to their intellectual superiority, the legal opinion espoused by canon law gradually spread throughout most courts of Europe and became
a part of the ius commune. Examples of this are: 1) the doctrine pacta nuda, relieving contracting from formalities and holding that a contract is concluded by mutual
expressions of will alone; written documents are only necessary eventually for providing evidence; 2) the peaceful possessor of a good cannot be dispossessed from it in
a violent or surreptitious way even when the dispossessor was the true owner (actio
redintegranda); 3) with regard to evidence law, ordeals were forbidden for priests at
the Council of Laterans (1215), which in turn led to the entire disappearance of ordeals; 4) wills can be made nearly without formalities, even orally, provided a witness
(e.g., the priest, who heard the last will) can testify to it. Many of these innovations
still prevail in present civil law.
During the same period of the papal revolution, a complete copy of the Corpus
Iuris Civilis of Justinian was discovered in northern Italy. The texts of Justinian were
awarded a status on law which was equivalent to the status of the Bible in religion.
They were studied and discussed systematically at the medieval universities (universitas magistrum et scholarum), which originated in northern Italy (especially
Bologna), and spread rapidly during the twelfth and thirteenth century throughout
Europe. The Roman law studied by medieval professors and their students was in
fact a dead legal system. It was not practised at all in eleventh century society, except in some regions in a very primitive way (vulgar Roman law). Yet it was seen as
the law, the product of human reason. The nearly biblical authority of the Roman
law, of course, stimulated its spread throughout legal Europe. Two other elements,
far more of a structural kind, should be mentioned in this respect. Firstly, Roman
society of the classical era (0-200 AD) had important similar traits to the medieval
world of the twelfth and thirteenth centuries. Both were worlds of an intense commercial and social interaction within a very broad geographical and cultural space.
The abstract rules of the Roman law, especially of its intertribal component, the
ius gentium, were consequently very useful for the nascent great society of the me-

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

173

dieval pax Christiana. Secondly, the Roman law was not handled as a series of texts
with a xed meaning. The scholars of Roman law cherished the idea of the law as a
corpus, i.e. as a coherent body with underlying principles. Apparent contradiction
could thus be solved by reasoning towards these principles, by which some statements in the Roman texts could be put aside (Berman 1983, p. 140). Especially the
second generation of scholars, the post-glossatores or commentatores, took a lot
of liberty in interpreting the texts of the Digest. This allowed the scholars to adapt
the Roman law to present needs, while at the same time using the prestige of antiquity of the Roman law. We mentioned earlier (section 5) the subtle way by which
glossatores such as Bassianus reinterpreted the regulation on permissions to found
an association.
Another example of the inventiveness of the post-glossatores is seen within the
crucial notion of individual property. Roman law itself did not provide a denition for
a property right. It did not even know the notion of a right itself. Ius meant rather
a collection of rules and not a right. In feudal and manorial law, nothing similar to
a property right existed. All entitlements on land were implicated within a complex
web of reciprocal duties between lords and vassals, and between lords and (free and
unfree) tenants. Yet in the beginning of the fourteenth century, through reasoning
and discussion, the post-glossatores, more particularly the famous Bartolus, dened
property as a right to use, enjoy, and dispose freely over a good, provided the owner
did not act against another legal rule (Bouckaert 1990, p. 785). This denition of
property triumphed nally with the introduction of the Civil Code in 1804, in which
it is nearly literally adopted in art. 544. The Roman law view on property was during
the preceding centuries constantly promoted in legal discussions before courts, which
greatly helped to erode the feudal-manorial property regime on land.
While canon law and Roman law relied on the transboundary, religious and intellectual authority of the church, the medieval urban law relied on the territorial
authority of the city magistrates. During the urban revolution in the rst half of the
twelfth century, many cities succeeded to be granted in charters the right to legislate
on a wide series of subjects (public administration, private law, procedure, criminal law) (Bouckaert 1997, p. 221). This thorough decentralisation in law-making did
not evolve, however, into the legal patchwork quilt we might expect at rst sight.

174

New Perspectives on Political Economy

Among the dierent urban laws, mostly codied within charters, one can discover
wide families of urban law, within which strong similarities of rules and procedures
prevailed. In Flanders, for instance, most charters of the cities, granted in the twelfth
century, were modelled after the charter of St. Omer, granted in 1127 by count William
Clito (Berman 1983, p. 370). In the German empire about eighty new cities took over,
without being forced, the laws of Magdeburg. This city on the Elb had been granted
a charter in 1188 (Berman 1983, p. 376). Apparently the cities perceived the benets
of a more or less similar body of rules between the dierent cities. This bottomup harmonisation of urban law also allowed for a process of constitutional learning.
In the cities of Flanders, which originated quite early, the city constitution did not
provide for a distinction between legislative and administrative power on the one
hand and judiciary power on the other. All power was concentrated in the hands
of powerful aldermen (scabini), recruited from the wealthy patrician class. This
led, during the fourteenth century, to bloody class struggles between patricians and
guilds and among the guilds themselves. In the duchy of Brabant, however, cities
were younger and provided in their charters for a separation between legislative, administrative power and the judiciary. They also provided for much more democracy
in the election procedures. Apparently, Flemish cities learned from this, and introduced similar systems at the end of the fourteenth century (Bouckaert 1997, p. 233).
Manorial law was probably the least nomocratic legal order during the Middle
Ages. Yet, the picture we touched upon in section 6, i.e. manorial society as a collection of cages in which peasants were locked in, has to be amended substantially.
Manorial law itself evolved thoroughly during the twelfth and the thirteenth century.
The rights of the tenants were strengthened by changes either brought about through
royal intervention (e.g. the Statute Quia Emptores in England; the enfranchisement
of serfs in France by Louis X and Philip the Long) or by the fact that serfs had an easy
route to the cities (Stadtluft macht frei). Manorial justice, a prerogative of the lord
of the manor, evolved gradually to participatory adjudication, by which other, often
elected, inhabitants of the manor acted as judges (Berman 1983, p. 325). Around 1450
serfdom was completely abolished in Western Europe. Peasants could freely leave
the manor and were rarely submitted to labour duties. The erosion of the subjection
of the peasantry, the reciprocal and participatory character of manorial law, and the

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

175

many routes of escapes from the manor also destroy the picture of the Middle Ages
as a peasant society. Based on ample social data, such as appearing from parish
registers, court rolls, deeds, etc., Macfarlane shows, very convincingly, that medieval
England (13th-15th century) was a rather open society, which had a mobile population, a ourishing market for land, an individualistic system of heritage and a free
status for the individual tenant (Macfarlane 1978). One can question whether this
individualistic character of English agriculture was as unique as Macfarlane suggests.
Probably also other parts of Western Europe would t this picture too. In the west of
Flanders for instance, in an area called Franc de Bruges, all farmers enjoyed a status
of freemen, granted to them by the abbeys, in exchange for help in winning troughs
and marshland from the sea. It is true, however, that this liberalisation of the peasantry did not occur in Eastern Europe, where lower urbanisation oered fewer escape
routes and the nobility was given free reign by the emperor, spending all his energy
in Italy pursuing his Roman dream (Spruyt 1994, p. 109).

The Rule of Law in the Middle Ages

A civil society not only needs a nomos, imposing some basic ethical and legal standards to the interaction of, for the rest left free, individuals. It requires also as its
constitutional cornerstone rules and institutions which prevent political power from
destroying the nomos instead of upholding it. This constitutional cornerstone, usually called rule of law, limited government, Rechtstaat, tat de droit, only appeared as a systematised doctrine in the seventeenth and eighteenth century, with
the works of John Locke and Montesquieu. Again, the question arises whether this
doctrine owes its origin to post-medieval roots and experiences, such as the religious wars, Puritan-Calvinist constitutionalism (p.ex. monarchomachs, Althusius),
the Levellers movement and the Enlightenment; or can we trace it further back into
the Middle Ages. Again the answer is positive: between (some currents in) medieval
political thought and the later rule of law-theory, there is continuity, not a break.
The medieval roots of the rule of law should be sought in the tradition of natural,
canon, Roman, and feudal law.

176

New Perspectives on Political Economy

According to natural lawtheory, the ruler is bound to the principles of natural law.
Lack of respect for them entitled his subjects to a right of resistance. This right could
be active (revolt) or passive (non-payment of taxes among other things). According to
Aquinas, this right had to be used with prudence. When a revolt against an unlawful
ruler would create an even greater harm to the common good, restraint was to be
recommended.
This limitation of power and ius resistendi was elaborated by Gratian in canon
law. With regards to the question whether the prince acted according to natural
and divine law, the pope was considered the supreme judge. The ius resistendi expressed also a power relationship between popes and secular rulers. The canonists,
however, were quite consequent by holding that the ius resistendi was opposable
to the pope himself too (Berman 1983, p. 145). The pope was also subject to natural and divine law. The canonists did not elaborate formal procedures to materialise
this right of resistance against the pope. For this, we have to wait until the fteenth
century with the movement of conciliarism in Konstanz. Nevertheless, it is clear that
since the twelfth century a theory of limited government was developed within the
most dynamic institution of that time. In this respect, the doctrine of the Renaissance political theorist Jean Bodin of Princeps legibus solutus est rather seems to
be a break from the awakening rule of law tradition (Nemo 1996, p. 284).
The tradition of Roman law is often blamed for having promoted the absolute
power of kings and emperors by taking the Byzantine emperor Justinian as its constitutional model (Ullman 1975, p. 85). This is undeniably true. However, the theory
of iurisdictio, developed by the Roman law scholar Azo (1198-1230) contributed also
to the rule of law-doctrine. Iurisdictio is the publicly established power and duty to
pronounce judgement and to establish justice. As such, iurisdictio means the use
of power according to the ius, i.e. legitimate power. Imperium or dominium, i.e.
the power of the sword, is a species of iurisdictio. Iurisdictio contains imperium
and not vice versa. This means that the power of the sword can only be exercised
according to the law (ius).
To the question what was the source of the lawmaking power of the ruler, Azo
answered that the source was in the corpus, the universitas, the communitas.

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

177

Jurisdiction, consequently ascended from the people to the emperor and not vice
versa (Berman 1983, p. 292).
As already mentioned earlier, by far the most eective promoter of the rule of
law was the feudal structure of political power based on the idea of reciprocity. Unlike many canon law and Roman law theories, the feudal law aected very practically
the power relationship between the eective local rulers, such as dukes and counts,
and their subjects. During the twelfth, thirteenth, and fourteenth century, the feudal
principle of reciprocity between lord and vassal was gradually extended towards the
relationship between ruler and subjects in general. The Magna Carta provided not
only that the government of the king had to be in consent with the barons, but it
provided also general liberties for all freemen in the kingdom. For instance, it states
that no free man shall be taken, imprisoned, diseased, outlawed, exiled or in any
way destroyed except by the lawful judgement of his peers or the law of the land.
The Hungarian Golden Bull of 1222 granted rights and liberties, similar to the ones
mentioned in the Magna Carta, to the bishops and the higher and lower nobles of
our realm. This in fact meant a respect for the rule of law towards all free men in
the kingdom. In the duchy of Brabant, the famous charter of the Joyous Entry of 1356
granted extensive liberties to all free citizens and a government based on the consent
of the most important organised bodies (cities, church, guilds, nobility) within the
duchy.
The feudal roots of the rule of law, which were based on reciprocity, and the canon
law roots of the rule of law, which were based on respect for natural and divine law,
were probably merging with each other during the thirteenth and fourteenth century.
The ius resistendi appears in very important law books such as the Sachsenspiegel
of Eike von Repgau (early thirteenth century) and the De legibus et Consuetudinibus
Angliae, ascribed to Bracton (Berman 1983, p. 293). It is dicult to say where these
authors found their inspiration: in canon law or feudal law? Probably in both. It
is, however, dicult to deny that a rule of law-doctrine was in the making during
the Middle Ages. The rise of absolutism and state sovereignty would interrupt this
process in most European countries. This is, however, another story.

178

New Perspectives on Political Economy

10

Conclusion

History is a gallery of paintings, with few original works and many copies, said Alexis
de Tocqueville in his analysis of the causes of the French Revolution. Are we able to
compare some characteristics of our time with those of the Middle Ages? Are some
situations in our time only copies of medieval pictures? Answering such questions
is a very speculative business. In order to stress the relevance of our views on the
medieval roots of our civil society and also to stress the fragility of the latter, we must
take the risk of making some comparisons.
After the collapse of the socialist totalitarian world, the present international
world looks medieval in two respects.
Firstly, on the international level a relative stability persists thanks to the so called
pax Americana, clothed or not clothed in a United Nations envelope. The United
States, as a military power, is able to exert a certain hegemony on the world but is
not able to (and hopefully not willing to) dominate and rule the world. On one
hand, we are left with a polycentric international system (many sovereign states)
which does not fall, on the other hand, into a Hobbesian war-like situation due to
U.S. hegemony. The medieval counterpart of this has to be sought in the respublica
Christiana during its eective period (1073-1300). The hegemonic power of this era
was, without any doubt, the pope and his powerful bureaucracy, disposing, not over
armies, but over an immense religious-moral authority to keep the most powerful
candidates for domination, especially the Holy Roman Emperor, under control.
Similar to present day pax Americana, the respublica Christiana provided some
international order and containment of conict, without real international domination.
Secondly, the numerous political entities of our time (ca. 200 nation-states) coexist in a world of growing interaction between individuals, enterprises, and voluntary
associations. This puts the nation-states under strong competitive pressure for investments in capital goods and probably, in the near future, for skilled labour (human
capital). The nation-states who either have given up largely liberal constitutionalism
or have never known it, are by this competitive pressure forced to factually liberalise

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

179

their policies. This picture can be compared to the medieval patchwork of political
entities, in which duchies, counties, bishoprics, cities, and city-leagues coexisted in a
world of increasing interaction with merchants, artisans, lawyers, artists, clerics, and
scientists across the borders of their polity. The gradual emergence of a wide civil
society within the respublica Christiana also forced many rulers to adopt a policy of
economic tolerance and scal restraint. While we live in a globalisation of human
interaction, the Middle Ages certainly lived in a Western European continentalisation of human interaction.
These two parallels between our time and the Middle Ages make it very interesting to look for the main causes of collapse of the respublica Christiana after the
thirteenth century. This may enable us to watch with particular attention any similar
evolution in our time which might endanger the ongoing process of globalisation.
Basically, the medieval order of the respublica Christiana collapsed because one
player, i.e. the king of France, was able to break the power of the arbiter of the order,
and to reduce the arbiter to a tool of his policy. This happened during the fourteenth
century, when Philip the Fair and Guillaume Nogaret overpowered Pope Boniface VIII
and brought the papacy to Avignon (Spruyt 1994, p. 153). The elimination of the arbiter and the gradual weakening of a supranational code of behaviour (ius naturae,
ius gentium) plunged Europe into an open Hobbesian situation, pushing each country into a war-taxation-bureaucracy cycle (Tilly 1975). The wars between the castle
nobility during the tenth and eleventh centuries, suppressed by the Peace of God and
the Landesfrieden, were now replaced by a war between powerful monarchist war
machines. This was most pronounced in France, Spain, Sweden, and Prussia. Countries like England and Holland, which preserved large parts of their medieval rule of
law tradition, were able to stop the war-taxation-bureaucracy cycle. This led gradually, after many wars and revolutions, to the pax liberalis of the nineteenth century
(1814-1914).
Can we perceive similar tendencies in our time comparable with the factors which
brought the respublica Christiana to its collapse in the fourteenth and fteenth century? The danger that the present hegemonic power, the U.S., turns into an imperialistic one, trying to rule eectively the whole world, like was the ambition of the medieval Holy Roman emperors or of some popes, is very unlikely. Internal and external

180

New Perspectives on Political Economy

opposition to such plans is far too strong. A dash for power by other national states
is even more unlikely, as other states will form counterbalancing coalitions.
The major danger for the present international order and, consequently, for the
continuation of the global civil society probably resides in the formation of strong
regional blocks like NAFTA and the EU. Such blocks, which originated paradoxically
as free market areas and contributed a lot to the formation of transboundary civil
societies, may evolve into superstates in which local autonomy is entirely suppressed.
The emergence of even one such block, for instance the EU, may have the same eect
as the dash for power of Philip the Fair and France at the beginning of the fourteenth
century. It would, on one hand, destroy the international discipline now provided
by the U.S.-hegemony. On the other hand, such blocks would be able to limit the
competitive pressure on national states by reducing the number of political decision
centres from the present two hundred to, say, ve. Such an oligopolisation of political
power would not only stop the emergence of global civil society, but also trigger a
dangerous logic of war.
A historian is a prophet in restrospect, said the German philosopher and historian Wilhelm von Schlegel. Let us hope that the scenario, mentioned in this conclusion, proves to be a false one.

Bibliography
[1] Anderson, Perry. 1974. Lineages of the Absolutist State. London.
[2] Baechler, Jean. 1975. The Origins of Capitalism. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
[3] Bairoch, Paul, Jean Batou, and Pierre Chvre. 1988. Les Populations des villes
Europennes de 800-1850. Geneva: Librairie Droz, Geneva.
[4] Bejczy, Istvan. 1997. Tolerantia: a medieval concept. Journal of the History of
Ideas, Vol. 58, No. 3.
[5] Benson, Bruce. 1989. The Enterprise of Law: Justice without the State. San Francisco: Pacic Research Institute.

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

181

[6] Benson, Bruce. 1997. Justice without government: The Merchant Courts of Medieval Europe and their Modern Counterparts. In The Voluntary City, ed. San
Francisco: The Independent Institute.
[7] Berman, Harold J. 1983. Law and Revolution, The Formation of the Western Legal
Tradition. Cambridge Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
[8] Black, Antony. 1984. Guilds and Civil Society in European Thought from the
Twelfth Century to the Present. New York: Cornell University Press.
[9] Black, Antony. 1988. The Individual and Society. In The Cambridge History of
Medieval Political Thought, ed. J.H. Burns. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
[10] Black, Antony. 1992. Political Thought in Europe 1250-1450. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
[11] Bouckaert, Boudewijn. 1997. City air sets one free. Medieval cities as voluntary
political and economic communities. In The Voluntary City, ed. San Francisco:
The Independent Institute.
[12] Bouckaert, Boudewijn. 1997. Between the Market and the State: the World
of Medieval cities. In Values and the Social Order: Voluntary versus Coercive
Orders, ed. G. Radnitzky. Aldershot: Avebury.
[13] Bouckaert, Boudewijn. 1991. Corporate Entity : Myth, Fiction or Reality? Israel
Law Review, Vol. 25.
[14] Bouckaert, Boudewijn. 1990. What is property. Harvard Journal for Law and
Public Policy, Vol. 13, No. 3.
[15] Cameron, Rondo. 1993. A Concise Economic History of the World: From Paleolithic Times to the Present. New York: Oxford University Press.
[16] Coleman, Janet. 1988. Property and poverty. In The Cambridge History of Medieval Thought, ed. J.H. Burns. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press.
[17] Duby, Georges. 1978. Les Trois Ordres ou limaginaire du fodalisme. Paris: Edition Gallimard.

182

New Perspectives on Political Economy

[18] Ellickson, R.E. 1991. Order without Law: How Neighbours settle disputes. London: Harvard University Press.
[19] Fukuyama, Francis. 1996. Trust: The Social Virtues and the Creation of Prosperity, New York: Free Press.
[20] Ganshof, F.L. 1982. Quest ce que la fodalit? Paris: Tallandier.
[21] Green, David G. 1993. Reinventing Civil Society: The Rediscovery of Welfare
Without Politics. IEA, Choice in Welfare Series, nr. 17, London.
[22] Grotius, Hugo. 1993. De Iure Belli ae Pacis Libri Pres, in quibus ius naturae et
gentium item iuris publici praecipua explicantur. Ed. Robert Feenstra, Aalen.
[23] Habermann, Gerd. 1995. Chinese Thought and European Liberalism. In Values
and the Social Order: Society and Order, ed. G. Radnitsky. Aldershot: Avebury.
[24] Hayek, Friedrich A. 1973. Law, Legislation and Liberty, Vol. 1 Rules and Order.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
[25] Hegel, Gotfried-Wilhelm. 1820. Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts oder
Naturrechts und Staatwissenschaft im Grundrisse. Berlin.
[26] Heirbaut, Dirk. 1997. Over heren, vazallen en graven. Het persoonlijk leenrecht
in Vlaanderen ca. 1000-1305. Algemeen Rijksarchief, Studia 69, Brussel.
[27] Heyn, Udo. 1982. Pax et Justitia : Arm Control, Disarmament and the Legal
System in the Medieval Reich. Peace and Change: A Journal of Peace Research,
Vol. VIII, No. 1, Spring.
[28] Higgs, Robert. 1987. Crisis and Leviathan. Critical Episodes of American Government. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
[29] Himmelfarb, Gertrude. 1995. The De-Moralisation of Society: From Victorian
Virtues to Modern Values. IEA, Choice in Welfare Series, nr. 22.
[30] Inman, Robert P., and Daniel L. Rubinfeld. 1998. Federalism. In B. Bouckaert
and G. De Geest, The International Encyclopedia of Law and Economics, London: Edward Elgar.

Bouckaert: The Roots of our Liberties: On the Rise of Civil Society

183

[31] Macauley, Stewart. 1963. Non-Contractual Relations in Business: A preliminary


study. American Sociological Review, Vol. 28, No. 1, p. 55.
[32] Macedo, Stephen. 1989. Capitalism, Citizenship and Community. In Ellen
Frankel Paul, Freed. D. Miller Jr., Jerey Paul, John Ahrens (ed.), Capitalism,
Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
[33] Macfarlane, Alan. 1987. The Cradle of Capitalism: The Case of England. In Jean
Baechler, John Hull and Michael Mann, eds., Europe and the Rise of Capitalism,
Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
[34] Macfarlane, Alan. 1978. The Origins of English Individualism. Oxford: Basil
Blackwell.
[35] Mencken, H.L. 1991. A New Dictionary of Quotations. New York: Alfred A.
Knopf.
[36] Nemo, Philippe. 1996. Athnes, Rome, Jeruzalem: Trois Composantes de
lIdentit Europenne. The European Union and the Nation State, Paris: Groupe
ESCP.
[37] Oakeshot, Michael. 1975. On Human Conduct. London: Clarendon Press.
[38] Pasukanis, Evgeny. 1970. La Thorie gnrale du droit et le Marxisme. Paris:
Etudes et Documentation Internationales.
[39] Petrella, Riccardo. 1993. Limits to Competition. The Group of Lisbon.
[40] Pirenne, Henri. 1956. Medieval Cities. New York: Doubleday Anchor Books.
[41] Skinner, Quentin. 1992. The Italian City Republics. In Democracy: The Unnished Journey 508 DC to AD 1993, ed. John Dunn, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
[42] Sombart, Werner. 1915. The Quintessence of Capitalism: A Study of the History
and Psychology of the Modern Business Man. London: T. Fisher Unwin.
[43] Spruyt, Hendrik. 1996. The Sovereign State and Its Competitors, Princeton New
Jersey: Princeton University Press.

184

New Perspectives on Political Economy

[44] Strayer, Joseph R. 1985. Hospitals and Poor Relief. Dictionary of the Middle
Ages, New York: Charles Scribners Sons.
[45] Thireau, Jean Louis. 1993. La doctrine civiliste avant le Code Civil. La Doctrine
Juridique, Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.
[46] Tiebaut, Charles. 1956. A pure theory of local government expenditures. Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 64, October.
[47] Tilly, Charles, ed. 1975. The Formation of National States in Western Europe.
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
[48] Trakman, Leon E. 1983. The Law Merchant: the Evolution of Commercial Law.
Colorado: Rothman.
[49] Ullman, Walter. 1975. Law and Politics in the Middle Ages: An Introduction to
the Sources of Medieval Political Ideas. London: Hodder and Stoughton.
[50] Van Caenegem, Raoul C. 1993. Democratie en Rechtstaat in het twaalfde
eeuwse Graafschap Vlaanderen. The Legal History Review, p. 205.
[51] Van Caenegem, Raoul C. 1992. An Historical Introduction to Private Law. Cambridge: University Press.
[52] Ven Vander, F.J.H.M. 1968. Geschiedenis van den Arbeid. Antwerp.
[53] Weber, Max. 1967. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. London:
Unwin University Books.
[54] Webber, Carolyn, and Aaron Wildawsky. 1986. A History of Taxation and Expenditure in the Western World. New York: Simon and Schuster.

Anda mungkin juga menyukai