Anda di halaman 1dari 30

The place of the Posterior Analytics

in Aristotles thought, with particular


reference to the Poetics
Richard McKirahan

Introduction
The Posterior Analytics (APo) contains a treatment of the nature of scientific thought and of science (epistm) itself. In my view it implies
a method for presenting science, a form in which a body of scientific
knowledge is organized and ideally should be set out. The APo is not
primarily about obtaining scientific facts, although it has important
implications about the nature of scientific facts, the kinds of scientific
facts, and the relations among scientific facts, and so it has consequences for the kinds of things that are investigated in scientific research. But
its main purpose is to discuss achieved sciences, not how to achieve
them.
The APo model for presenting sciences is founded on a distinction
between principles (primary facts/propositions) and provables (propositions/facts that depend on the principles1). There are strict conditions on principles. (They must be true, primary, immediate, better
known than, prior to, and explanatory grounds for the conclusions
derived from them.2) Each science treats a distinct subject matter or
genus (genos). There are three different kinds of principles: definitions

I speak of facts or propositions as suits the context.

APo I 2, 71b20-2

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

76

Richard McKirahan

and existence-claims, which are proper to a single genus, and common principles that apply to a plurality of genera). In addition, Aristotle places strict conditions on acceptable procedures for deriving
provables from principles: they must be derived by means of syllogistic
arguments based on relevant principles. Such proofs are called demonstrations (apodeixeis).
A traditional problem is how to account for the fact that none of
Aristotles scientific works follows the APo model. This is clearly true.
Even if some parts of some works show a tendency towards APo organization,3 it remains that no entire work of Aristotles is in the form
demanded by the APo for an achieved science. Here are three possible
explanations. First, Aristotle wrote the APo late and didnt go back and
redo his earlier scientific works according to its specifications. But the
APo is regarded as an early work, and I know of no one who has proposed this explanation, nor will I propose it. Second, Aristotle wrote the
APo early and subsequently in doing scientific work he abandoned the
straitjacket imposed by the APo model. Third, Aristotle wrote the APo
early and did not abandon it; some of the APos leading ideas influence
his scientific work, even though he did not arrange his scientific works
in the form described there. This paper is intended to provide support
for this third interpretation.
People who adopt the third interpretation need to face the question
of why Aristotle didnt go all the way and arrange the works in the way
described in the APo. Here are some ingredients of a possible explanation. First, the important scientific work is done in reaching the principles; the remaining task of constructing demonstrations based on the
principles is trivial. To reach the principles we first need to ascertain the
propositions that constitute the science: the body of necessary propositions involving subjects and attributes in the subject genus of the science
in question. This is the research phase. Then comes the organizational
phase4 in which we determine which of the facts are principles and then
construct demonstrations. In terms of the distinction Aristotle makes
between the that (to hoti) and the why (to dihoti),5 we first ascertain

See, e.g., Jope (1972).

I do not mean to suggest that we must complete all research relevant to the science
before beginning work on organizing the body of knowledge into a deductive system.

Cf. APo II 1-2.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

The place of the Posterior Analytics in Aristotles thought 77

that something is the case and then ascertain why it is the case, which
is done by finding a demonstration of the fact in question.
But there is reason to think that the work of constructing demonstrations that begin from already known principles is entirely mechanical
and trivial. Let me explain. Syllogistic arguments are very restricted
in form. Each syllogism consists of two premises and one conclusion.
Premises and conclusion are in subject-predicate form, and each one of
them must have one of the following forms: A necessarily belongs to
all B or A necessarily belongs to no B. The only syllogistic moods acceptable in demonstrations are Barbara and Celarent.6 It follows that the
process of constructing proofs is trivial once we have the principles.7 If
the principles are finite in number, there can be only a finite number of
demonstrations. In view of this, the scientific work is done in ascertaining the principles; the rest is gift wrapping.
Further, Aristotle has philosophical reasons that would lead him
to believe that this situation obtains. For example, he believes that all
propositions in syllogisms predicate an attribute of a subject,8 that all
deductions can be reduced to syllogisms,9 and that proofs are only finitely long.10 He believes that some of a subjects attributes hold of ne-

This is Aristotles basic model, as discussed in APo I 14. It agrees with his conviction that science deals with universals, not particulars, and per se relations, not
accidental ones. It is so restrictive a model that it does not even account for the
most elementary proofs in geometry; and this raises important problems for the
theory of demonstration that go beyond the scope of this paper. See McKirahan
1992: Chapter 12 for discussion of some of them.

We first look for pairs of principles in which the subject term of one is the predicate
term of the other. If both principles are affirmative, then they are the premises of a
syllogism in Barbara which demonstrates its conclusion. If both are negative, then
no syllogism is possible. If one principle is positive and one negative and a syllogism can be formed (that is, if the middle term is the predicate of the affirmative
principle and the subject of the negative principle), then either we have a demonstration in Celarent or we have a syllogism that is not a demonstration (we have a
first step towards a demonstration, where there are one or more middle terms that
need to be filled in). We then follow the same procedure for the set of propositions
consisting of all the principles and all the conclusions of the preceding demonstrations.

APr I 1-4

Every demonstration and every deduction takes place through the three figures
(APr I 23, 40b20-2).

10

APo I 19-22

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

78

Richard McKirahan

cessity and others do not,11 and of the former he believes that some are
naturally prior to others in the sense that the truth of the others depends on the truth of them.12
My account distinguishes two phases of scientific work: gathering
relevant information, and organizing it into the form of a finished science. The preliminary work (research phase) aims to determine the
facts that fall within the scope of the science, and does so in part on the
basis of observations, as outlined in APo II 19, and in part on the basis
of endoxa the opinions of the many and the wise. The criteria here are
truth and relevancy.
The organizational phase has two parts: first, determining which
facts (perhaps more precisely, the true propositions that express those
facts) are principles, and second, forming the demonstrations, which
we have seen is trivial. The first part of the organizational phase is not
trivial. I believe that it has four parts. First, it requires determining
which facts/propositions follow syllogistically from which. This work
13
falls under the heading of dialectic. When this work has been done,
we have candidate demonstrations, but we do not yet know which candidate demonstrations are genuine demonstrations. The reason for this
is that, as Aristotle recognizes, there are situations where there are two
propositions each of which is a premise in a candidate demonstration
of the other, as in the case of the non-twinkling planets discussed below.
Since a given proposition cannot be both a principle and a provable, the
two candidates cannot both be genuine demonstrations. In other words,
logic is not enough to determine which propositions are principles.
The second part is to determine which among competing candidate
demonstrations give the true explanations of their conclusions. At least
two kinds of work are involved in making this determination. First, Aristotle specifies some features of demonstrations that restrict the field.
Most notably, he holds that a proof that isosceles triangles have angles
equal to two right angles is not a proper demonstration; the property
in question belongs primarily to triangles and in consequence belongs

11

APo I 6, 74b10-12

12

See the discussion of the cause of the fact that the planets do not twinkle at APo I
13, 78a22-b3.

13

Top I 2, 101a36-b4, APr I 30, 46a3-30. This role of dialectic is discussed in McKirahan (1992), 261-2.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

The place of the Posterior Analytics in Aristotles thought 79


to the different kinds of triangles.14 The point is not that it is false that
isosceles have angles equal to two right angles, or that this fact cannot
be proved, but that the proper way to prove it is to prove first that the
property in question belongs to triangle, and then, in what I call an application proof, to apply that result to the various kinds of triangle.15
This consideration eliminates certain candidate demonstrations, and
with them certain candidate principles.
Another kind of work that needs to be done to determine which candidate demonstrations and principles are genuine ones is indicated in
16
the treatment of the non-twinkling planets. Here we have two candidate proofs, one proving that the planets do not twinkle because they
are near and one proving that the planets are near because they do not
twinkle. Aristotle declares that the latter is not a genuine demonstration because it is not because they do not twinkle that they are near,
but it is because they are near that they do not twinkle.17 The candidate
proofs that show that the moon is eclipsed18 because it is in the middle
and that the moon is in the middle because it is eclipsed are similar. In
discussing this example Aristotle explains that the latter is not a genuine demonstration because that being eclipsed is not the cause of its
being in the middle, but that this is the cause of its being eclipsed is
obvious.19 By obvious Aristotle presumably means that it is more intelligible (better known in nature as opposed to better known to us),
since principles are better known in nature than conclusions derived
from them and thus are also explanatory grounds of those conclusions.
Aristotle does not give sufficient further information on the critical matter of criteria for determining which propositions are more intelligible
than others to enable us to know how far he progressed on the difficult
question of deciding which facts are more obvious than others, in this
specialized sense of obvious.20

14

APo I 4-5, especially 74a32-b4.

15

McKirahan (1992), Chapter 14

16

APo I 13, 78a30-b4. The treatment of the sphericity of the moon at 78b4-13 is similar.

17

78a37-8

18

Or, suffers eclipses.

19

98b21-2

20

I discuss this issue in McKirahan (1992), Chapter 17.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

80

Richard McKirahan

The third task in the first part of the organizational phase of a science
is essentially one of collation. It is a matter of seeing which propositions
are premises of one or more demonstrations (and consequently explanatory grounds of the conclusions of those demonstrations) and are the
conclusions of none. These are the indemonstrable propositions, which
are found in the principles. Well, not exactly. There remains the fourth
task, in which we transform the indemonstrables into the three kinds of
principles: definitions, existence-claims, and common principles. I shall
not treat existence-claims or common principles, which do not present
great difficulties.21 But the question of definitions is not so easy, since
the method of forming definitions by collating all the unprovable premises in which the definiendum occurs conflicts with Aristotles standard
view of that definitions are in the form of genus + differentiae, where
the first differentia is a differentia of the genus and each subsequent differentia is a differentia of the immediately previous differentia.22
I am concerned here primarily with the form of definitions.23 The
problem is that there is no guarantee and in fact no reason to suppose
that definitions produced by this method of differentiation (which is
designed to identify the definiendum by stating how it is different from
other entities) I call these thin definitions will provide as much
information as is contained in all the propositions that contain the unprovable facts about the definiendum I call these fat definitions. On
this matter I will summarize an argument I have given elsewhere.24
As I said above, the prevailing model in the APo for the form of
definitions is the genus + differentiae model. APo II 13 presents two
incompatible conceptions of this kind of definition. According to one,
we begin from the genus, divide the genus by coordinate differentiae
that exhaust the genus; begin again from the differentia that includes
the definiendum and divide it by coordinate differentiae of it; proceed
down this line of division until we reach a differentia that is coextensive
with the definiendum. The definition is the proposition that predicates

21

I take up this issue in McKirahan (1992), Chapter 18.

22

See McKirahan 1992, 111-19, with references to Topics IV and Metaphysics Z 12.

23

In particular, largely because of lack of space, my discussion does not address the
treatment of definition in APo II 8-10, which I have discussed elsewhere: McKirahan (1992), Chapter 16, also Chapter 10, especially p.202 and Chapter 13, especially
pp.167-9.

24

McKirahan (1992), Chapter 9

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

The place of the Posterior Analytics in Aristotles thought 81

the genus and all the relevant differentia of the definiendum (97a23b6). (E.g., an isosceles triangle is a polygon that has three sides, exactly
two of which are equal. Genus: polygon; first differentia: having three
sides; final differentia: having exactly two equal sides.) Since the definition proceeds along only one line of division, in which each differentia
entails all the preceding differentia along with the genus, the definition
boils down to identifying the definiendum by only one term.25
The other conception of definition found in APo II 1326 calls for us
to proceed by identifying attributes each of which holds more widely than the definiendum, but which when taken together do not hold
more widely than it. The definition is the proposition that predicates all
of the differentiae of the definiendum. For example, the number three
is odd, prime in the sense of not being a product of other numbers, and
prime in the non-standard sense of not being the sum of other numbers
one not counting as a number.
A problem for both accounts is that they fail to distinguish between
essential attributes and non-essential necessary attributes. There is
nothing in either account that might exclude the property of having
angles equal to two right angles from being an element in the definition
of isosceles triangle, although the APo makes abundantly clear that this
is a provable attribute of triangles, not a definitional property. In addition, the first approach involves another serious problem. In general
there is no reason to suppose that all the demonstrable facts in which
a given subject or attribute appears are consequences of the fact that a
single differentia is predicated of it.
Aristotle eventually recognized the problem. In de Partibus Animalium I 2-3 he takes up once again the doctrine of genus + differentia
definitions, and offers some devastating objections. One of his objections is relevant to the point just made. Discussing the definition of man
as a succession of differentiae along a single line of division: animal,
footed, two-footed, etc. he says: Proceeding successively it reaches the
final differentia ... . This is having toes only; or the entire combination
if man is the subject of division, for example, it should form the conjunction footed, two-footed, having toes. If man were merely something
that has toes, in that case having toes would prove to be the single

25

Aristotle makes this point in Metaph Z 12, especially 1038a25-6.

26

In fact, it is found only here. Cf. Metaph Z 15, 1040a14-15.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

82

Richard McKirahan

differentia. But as it is, since he is not, there must be many differentiae


not under a single line of division.27
The right way to proceed, he now holds, is not to take successive
differentiations of the same line of division or to begin with one line of
division and at some point take a different tack, such as dividing terrestrial animals into footed and footless, but to divide the original ge28
nus by many differentiae right from the start. By making use of many
differentiae simultaneously, we can group animals according to their
natural kinds, for instance, birds or fish, whereas some dichotomies
split such groups for example, the division of all animals into terrestrial and aquatic groups water birds with fish, an absurd result.29 In
fact the method proposed is nothing unusual, but just what the many
do in using a number of criteria in distinguishing birds as one class of
animal and fish as another.30 Moreover the differentiae state essential
properties; in the terms I have been using, these are primary properties as opposed to provable ones. Even though the property of having
angles equal to two right angles identifies triangles among rectilinear
figures, it is not a differentia of triangle.31 On the other hand, in the kind
of definition outlined in de Partibus Animalium, we divide by essential
features, not accidental ones, not even per se accidents (that is, demonstrable attributes). Further, the assertion that defining man solely in
terms of the line of division that ends in having toes is inadequate
since man is not merely an animal having toes implies that the definition of man must either state or imply everything that man is: all the
attributes that necessarily belong to man, by virtue of his essence. And
this is enough to establish that de Partibus Animalium definitions, unlike
the APo definitions, are able to do the work required by the theory of
demonstrative science.
I have spent so long on the matter of definition because it is central
to the case study that will take up the rest of this paper.

27

PA I 3, 644a2-8

28

PA I 3, 643b23-4

29

PA I 3, 642b10-13; cf. b33-4.

30

PA I 3, 643b10-13

31

PA I 3, 643a28-31

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

The place of the Posterior Analytics in Aristotles thought 83

The importance of the APo model in Aristotles other works


My hypothesis is that even though no work of Aristotles is a demonstrative science set out the way the APo prescribes, an examination of
Aristotles works reveals that much of his discussion proceeds with
APo considerations in mind, conducting explorations designed to lead
to definitions and to explanations, for example, and in some cases to
settling questions of existence. And if it appears uncontroversial that
Aristotles explorations tend in these directions, my hypothesis provides an account of why Aristotle proceeds the way he does (so differently from modern scientific explorations).
In fact Aristotle makes prominent use of key concepts of the APo in
other works: definition, per se, necessity, qua, existence, principle, common, axiom, demonstration, nous, the subject/attribute distinction, the
essence/accident distinction, etc. And these concepts play key roles in
his treatment of many fields. This is particularly notable in key passages of the Physics Metaphysics, and de Anima. It is plausible that central aspects of the APo model of science remain controlling factors in much of
Aristotles later work considerations and objectives that govern the
kinds of questions he asks and his interest in certain kinds of topics. In
many cases it is plausible to hold that even if the Aristotelian treatises
do not contain demonstrations, they contain preliminary work towards
such a presentation. If this is right, then it is defensible that Aristotle
never lost sight of the importance of the APo, even though he did not
complete the job of presenting any science in systematic demonstrative
form.
Why, then, didnt he go the whole way? Two explanations are likely.
Either he did not suppose that the preliminary work was complete, or
if in some cases he did suppose it was complete, he did not take the
trouble to redo his conclusions into proper demonstrative form a
philosophically uninteresting task, as I pointed out above.
Another measure of the importance of the APo is the way Aristotle
returns in later works to central topics in the theory of demonstrative
science. In several cases we find him giving penetrating philosophical
examinations of such topics and developing his ideas on them beyond
what we find in the APo. As we have seen, this holds for his discussion of definition in de Partibus Animalium I which in fact criticizes
the view of Metaphysics Z 12, which itself draws the logical conclusion
of the view of definition by differentiae along a single line of division
that we find in the Topics and the APo, namely, that such a definition
boils down to identifying the definiendum by a single differentia (the

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

84

Richard McKirahan

ultimate differentia). Other topics broached in the APo and discussed


and developed more fully elsewhere include essence (e.g., Metaphysics Z), the principle of non-contradiction and the law of the excluded
middle (Metaphysics 4-8), necessity and causes (Physics 2) and nous (de
Anima III 4-8). (This list of topics as well as the passages referred to are
strictly for the sake of examples.) From this point of view, it is worth
taking seriously the hypothesis that key concepts of the APo remained
important for Aristotle later in his career and that even where he revises his views, the revisions are intended as amendments to a basically
sound approach to knowledge than as refutations of it.

Aristotles Poetics
The work I have chosen to talk about is an outlier: the Poetics. I will
begin by justifying my decision to consider it in this context, since it is
clear that poetry is not a science as Aristotle defines the term. On the
other hand, it is an art, skill, or craft (tekhn), and the APos account of
how we reach scientific principles is also an account of how we reach
the principles of arts as well. The works title is Peri Poietiks, a prepositional phrase missing its noun. The noun to be supplied is tekhns.32
Aristotles two sustained discussions of how we attain knowledge of
scientific principles, explicitly state that his account holds for principles
of arts as well as of sciences.33 So for Aristotle, arts, like sciences, are
organized bodies of knowledge, the difference between them being that
arts have products separate from the producer, whereas sciences aim at
knowledge, not at anything external.34 Like scientists, artists can give
accounts, justifications, or explanations of what they do. The accounts
are based on knowledge of a certain kind knowledge of principles
and consist in deriving conclusions from those principles.

32

In fact, Diogenes Laertius refers to the work as Pragmateia tekhns poitiks (Lives of
the Philosophers V 24).

33

APo II 19, 100a8-9, where the difference on this score between arts and sciences
is said to be that the subject matter of the former has to do with generation (peri
genesin), while the subject matter of the latter has to do with being (peri to on), and
Metaph A 1, 980b27-2a3, where Aristotle uses an example taken from the art of
medicine to illustrate points common to both arts and sciences.

34

Compare the distinction between productive and theoretical knowledge in


Metaph E 1.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

The place of the Posterior Analytics in Aristotles thought 85

I aim to show that the Poetics focuses first on definition and second
on using the relevant definition as a basis for deriving further features
of poetry. Of the three kinds of principles identified in the APo, only
definitions are prominent in the Poetics.35 If we read the Poetics with this
in mind, we will easily notice that definitions are absolutely central to
the work. Once this is noticed, it may strike us as an odd way to study
36
the nature of poetry. And it is especially odd in a work whose purpose
(among other things) is to tell us how to go about writing good poetry,
an aim announced in the opening sentence of the work (1447a9-10).
After five chapters of introductory remarks about several genres of
poetry, Aristotle announces that he will focus on tragedy, and return
to epic and comedy later on (1449b21-2). In the remaining twenty-one
chapters of the surviving first book of the Poetics tragedy is given seventeen (Chapters 6-22), epic two (Chapters 23-4), and the final two are
devoted to questions that concern both genres and to a comparison of
the two. Comedy was treated in the lost second book.

35

This is unsurprising and in my view it is no reason to reject the viewpoint I am


offering. The other two kinds of principles are common principles and hypotheses. Aristotle gives three examples of common principles: the principle of noncontradiction, the law of the excluded middle, and the principle that if equals are
subtracted from equals the remainders are equal. Of these, the last is applicable in
mathematical sciences, but (presumably) irrelevant in poetry; hence it is not mentioned. Moreover, Aristotles observation that sometimes sciences neglect to state
their most obvious principles, which he says is the case for equals subtracted from
equals (APo I 10, 76b16-21) holds a fortiori for the other two common principles.
Euclid does not state them, although he implicitly employs them presumably
because they are not specifically mathematical. And it seems clear enough that the
discussion of those principles (which finds a place in the Metaphysics) has no place
in a treatise on poetics. As to hypotheses they are existence claims for the basic
entities in a science: points and lines in geometry, units in arithmetic, etc. Aristotle
famously says that nothing prevents some sciences from neglecting to mention
some principles, for example, they may neglect to hypothesize that the genus exists if it is evident that it exists, for it is not equally evident that number exists and
that hot and cold do (76b16-19). In the context of the poetics he will have considered it very evident that, say, tragedies exist, and also plots, meter, and the other
terms he treats. So we are left with definitions.

36

A quick look through the poetry section of the local public library revealed many
books of poetry but not a single attempt to define it.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

86

Richard McKirahan

The Definition of Tragedy


Chapter 6 begins with a definition of tragedy:
Tragedy is (1) the representation (2) of an action that is (3) serious37
and also, (4) as having magnitude, (5) complete; (6) in language with
pleasurable accessories, (7) each kind brought in separately in the
parts of the work; (8) in a dramatic, not in a narrative form; (9) with
incidents arousing pity and fear, wherewith to accomplish its catharsis
of such emotions.38

The appearance of a definition proves little relevant to my cause; what


matters is how the definition is derived and what use is made of it. The
definition is based on what is said in the previous chapters, as Aristotle
points out in introducing the definition: Let us speak of tragedy, taking
up the definition of its essence from what has been said (1449b22-4).
This is true for almost all the elements of the definition, the only exceptions being pity, fear, and catharsis. In what follows I will examine the
discussion in the earlier chapters and how the definition emerges from
it. I will then show that Aristotles treatment follows the pattern prescribed for scientific definitions in de Partibus Animalium I. I will end by
pointing out that most of the rest of the discussion of tragedy is based
on the definition he has attained in this way and on the conclusions of
proofs that use the definition as a basis not in a way that would constitute the Poetics as a completely worked out demonstrative art, but in
a way that shows how the questions he asks and the approach he takes
are grounded in ideas that go back to the APo. It is too much to say that
the entire contents of the Poetics is APo-based, but much of the discussion and virtually the entire framework of the account of the nature of
tragedy are founded on the APo and its elaboration in de Partibus Animalium I, and the other elements are made to fit in.

37

Spoudaios (opposite of phaulos) in some contexts means serious and in others means
morally good. It is important to keep the translation consistent, and I adopt serious throughout.

38

This translation is based on The Revised Oxford Translation.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

The place of the Posterior Analytics in Aristotles thought 87

The Ingredients of Aristotles Definition of Tragedy


Seven of the nine ingredients of the definition emerge from the opening
chapters (all but the notion that tragedies have parts (7) and that they
have to do with pity, fear, and the catharsis of these emotions (9)).
Chapter 5, drawing on earlier chapters, says that tragedy and epic
have in common that they are a representation of serious actions,39
in speech with meter. They differ in that epic has a single meter and
contains narrative, whereas tragedy does not have a single meter and
the characters speak the words. They differ in length; whereas tragedy
aims to cover the events of one day or a little more, epic has no time
limit. Some of their parts are the same, but tragedy has some of its own
(1449b9-17).40
This points to tragedys being (1) the representation (2) of an action that is (3) serious; (4) as having magnitude, being (5) complete,
(6) in language with pleasurable accessories (here, meter), and (8) in
a dramatic, not in a narrative form. Further, the reference in Chapter
5 to parts (mer) of tragedy anticipates the reference to parts (moria)
in (7), where Aristotle says that each kind [of language is] brought in
separately in the parts of the work, and points to the parts of tragedy
catalogued in Chapter 12, where in fact one of the ways in which the
transition from one part to the next is marked is by a change in meter).
In other words, eight of the nine ingredients of the definition of tragedy
in Chapter 6 are anticipated in Chapter 5. But where does Chapter 5 get
them? Most come from a threefold classification of kinds of representation41 made in the first three chapters of the work. My interest in these
classifications is in how they work separately and jointly to produce
the definition of tragedy (and by implication, the definitions of comedy
and epic as well).
Chapter 1 tells us that tragedy employs rhythm, words, and harmony, Chapter 2 that it represents people doing serious things, and
Chapter 3 that it is dramatic, not narrative. Versions of all three of these
claims turn up in the definition of tragedy in Chapter 6. But tragedy is

39

The Greek can also mean serious persons.

40

Melody and spectacle, two of the six parts of tragedy identified at 1450b7-10, are
absent from epic.

41

This is how I translate mimsis for present purposes. I do not claim that it is the best
translation.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

88

Richard McKirahan

not unique in any one of these three respects. Not only tragedy but also
comedy, dithyramb and nomes employ rhythm, words and harmony;
not only tragedy but also epic represents serious people; and not only
tragedy but also comedy is dramatic. Still, tragedy is unique in the particular combination of the alternatives. Let me explain.
Chapter 1 states that the medium, the objects, and the manner are the
only differentiae of literary forms (1447a16) and Chapter 3 concludes
with a formal declaration that the discussion of the number and kinds
of differentiae is complete (1448b2-3). Further, Chapter 1 classifies literary forms by the medium in which they operate (rhythm, words and
harmony), Chapter 2 classifies them by their objects (serious or unserious people, or alternatively people who are better than us, like us, or
worse), and Chapter 3 by their manner (narrative or dramatic).
No single one of these classifications is sufficient to define or demarcate tragedy, epic, or comedy. All three classifications are needed
to distinguish these literary forms from others. In Chapter 1 we learn
that tragedy and comedy along with dithyrambs and nomes are distinguished from the other genres in that they employ all three media
rhythm, words and harmony. Within this division, tragedy and comedy are distinguished from dithyrambs and nomes in that the latter two
genres employ rhythm, words and harmony all together, while tragedy and comedy do not. Aristotle does not emphasize the place of epic
poetry in this arrangement, but he makes it clear enough that it falls
under a different classification (the classification of arts that employ
words and meter i.e., rhythm42 but not harmony43). Chapter 2 informs us that tragedy and Homeric epic depict agents who are better
than us, while comedy and certain other works depict those who are
worse. And Chapter 3 says that in epic the poet sometimes narrates
and sometimes takes the part of the characters, whereas in tragedy and
comedy the characters are presented doing the actions themselves. Aristotle does not proceed as thoroughly or as systematically as we might
wish. Chapter 1 classifies a large number of kinds of mimsis according
to their medium, but the number is markedly reduced in Chapter 2,
while the only genres mentioned in Chapter 3 are Homeric epic, tragedy and comedy. Since Aristotles concern in the Poetics is just these

42

Cf. 1448b21.

43

Cf. 1447b11-20.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

The place of the Posterior Analytics in Aristotles thought 89

three genres, this narrowing of focus from Chapter 1 to Chapter 3 is


understandable, but it presents some disadvantages.
For one thing, it belies Aristotles promise in the opening words of
the Poetics to discuss each of the species of poitik. For another, it focuses so narrowly on features relevant to the three preferred species that
it is unclear how some of the other species could fit the mould for
instance, how Chapter 3s distinction between narrative and dramatic
form could apply to instrumental music. It is likely that the classifications introduced in Chapters 2-3 are brought in precisely with epic,
tragedy and comedy in mind. In any case, one thing that is clear is that
Aristotle did not make the effort to apply the classifications introduced
in Chapters 2-3 to most of the species of poitik treated in Chapter 1.
Another problem is that even in Chapter 1, which contains the most
detailed classification scheme, Aristotle does not go into as much detail as we might expect. He recognizes flute-playing, lyre-playing, and
pipe-playing as different species of poitik, and although he reasonably
groups them together as involving rhythm and harmony but not words,
he does not give us any further tools for distinguishing these arts from
each other. Likewise, he seems to recognize genres of poitik that differ by having different meters (elegiacs, iambic trimeters, etc.), and to
classify them all as employing rhythm and words but not harmony, but
he does not help us discriminate among them. I suppose he could have
done so if he had wanted, but the main purpose of Chapter1s classification seems to be to isolate tragedy and comedy, and not to worry so
much about the rest.
Also, Aristotle is remarkably casual about the species of mimsis
that he does classify, even in Chapter 1. He begins with an initial list of
six: epic, tragedy, comedy, dithyramb, flute-playing, and lyre-playing
(1447a13-15). Later on he adds pipe-playing (1447a25-6), then dancing (1447a27), the mimes of Sophron and Xenarchus (1447b10), Socratic dialogues (1447b11), trimeter poetry (1447b11), elegiac poetry
(1447b12), the kind of mixed rhapsody that Chairemon composed in
the Centaur (1447b21-2), and finally nomes (1447b23). Some of these
are added in order to show that a particular classification is instantiated, but not all. (Pipe-playing fills the same niche as flute- and lyreplaying and so adds nothing to the scheme). Further, Aristotle makes
it clear that even with these additions, the list of species is incomplete:
after mentioning flute- and lyre-playing, he adds and any other arts
that have a similar dunamis (1447a24-5), and after mentioning trimeter poetry and elegiac poetry, he speaks loosely of any of the other
such things (1447b12).

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

90

Richard McKirahan

We are left with the uneasy feeling that Aristotle did not do an exhaustive survey of all forms of mimsis, and that there may be some
forms not covered by the classification; that is to say, the classification
may not be based on a good empirical study of existing genres. On the
other hand, there is but little attempt to prove that the divisions found
in Chapters 1-3 are the only possible divisions, or that they are the only
correct ones, so there are no good theoretical grounds for accepting the
classification, either.
In this connection it is worth calling attention to Aristotles comment
about people who make visual representations like painting, that some
represent through art and others through habit (1447a19-20). This parenthetical phrase, which Lucas (Lucas 1968, 56 ad loc.) calls quite irrelevant, in fact raises a problem of demarcation. Painting, or poetry that
is done through habit, will use the same medium, and may depict the
same characters and do so in the same manner as that which is done
through art. But then the classifications of Chapters 1-3 are not classifications of arts any more than of habits. That is, the differentiae divide
up two distinct genera. A similar problem is raised by the statement
that most of flute- and lyre-playing are mimeseis (1447a15).
We may suppose that Aristotle could have cleared up some of this
confusion had he wished. But apparently he did not wish to, presumably because of his pressing interest in only three forms of poitik: tragedy, comedy and epic. In these circumstances it would be foolish to
assume that the classifications we find in Chapters 1-3 will be without
problems. We may be in a situation where the best interpretation will
be the one that requires the least damage control.
Now to the classifications themselves. Aristotle begins Chapter 1 by
saying that he will treat poitik and its species (1447a1), goes on to list
six forms of poitik (epic, tragedy, comedy, dithyramb, flute-playing
and lyre-playing) (1447a13-15), and specifies that they are all mimseis
(1447a16). He then says that these arts (tekhnai: 1447a21) differ in three
respects: in the media they employ, the objects they represent, and the
manner of their representation (1447a16-18). Next he illustrates the first
of these respects by means of a comparison with other arts: just as some
people represent many things by means of colors and shapes, and others do so by doing things with their voice, so the arts mentioned above
make their representations in rhythm, words and harmony (1447a1822). It is clear that the arts mentioned here for the first time are also
kinds of mimsis. Are they also kinds of poitik? I think the answer must
be Yes, since painters and sculptors certainly make things their art
has a product. And Aristotles Greek would support this answer, since

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

The place of the Posterior Analytics in Aristotles thought 91

he uses the words agalmatopoios for sculptor (Pol VIII 5, 1340a38) and
eikonopoios for portrait-sculptor or -painter (Poet 1460b9).
A consequence of this commonly held interpretation is that the extent of poitik is left quite open. There could be other and quite different arts that also count as forms of poitik; indeed, all arts could
conceivably turn out to be forms of poitik. Further, the line between
mimsis and poitik is left unclear. All forms of poitik are mimseis, but
could it not also be that all mimseis are also forms of poitik? I must set
these questions aside. The text does not help us further, for Aristotles
interest in epic, tragedy and comedy leads him to restrict his discussion
of media to the media relevant to those three particular forms of poitik
and mimsis, and rhythm, words and harmony have nothing to do with
painting, sculpting, and making whatever mouth sounds Aristotle may
have had in mind.
Aristotle now returns to the six species of poitik and declares without argument that they all make their mimsis in rhythm, words, and
harmony (1447a21-2). The preposition in (en) signals that Aristotle
is referring to the medium.44 Here begins the division of mimsis, or
of poitik, or, more precisely, of a certain incompletely specified set of
forms of poitik.45 These three media are found either separately or in
combination.46 The distinction separately/in combination is evidently intended to be mutually exclusive47 and jointly exhaustive,48 which is
appropriate for a set of coordinate differentiae of a genus. Separately
refers to cases where only one of the three media occurs: for example,
genres that employ rhythm but no words or harmony. In combination
refers to cases where more than one of the three media are employed.
There are seven possible cases where one or more of these three occur.
Of the seven, Aristotle mentions five, although he says that two of the
five have no names. As to the remaining two, Aristotle may have deliberately avoided mentioning them, supposing that they are not real

44

This word is the distinctive element in the phrase en heterois, with which Aristotle
originally introduced the notion of media (1447a17).

45

Several commentators (Solmsen (1935), Else (1957), 67, and Battin (1975)) have attempted to force this set into the procrustean mold of dichotomous division.

46

khris memigmenois (1447a22).

47

Any form of poitik that employs the media separately does not employ them in
combination, and vice versa.

48

Any form of poitik employs either one medium or more than one.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

92

Richard McKirahan

options. In both missing combinations, harmony is present and rhythm


is absent, and Aristotle may simply not have recognized the possibility of there being any genre of poitik that employs harmony without
rhythm.49
My claim is that Aristotle carefully worked out a theoretically complete division according to three lines of differentiae, where each line is
divided by differentiae that are mutually exclusive and jointly exhaustive. In this theoretical discussion he found that the six forms of poitik
he listed at the outset did not cover all possible cases, so he added other
forms where possible, and also admitted that some of the classifications
50
had no names.
Tragedy and comedy are located in the same division within this
classification: they make use of all three media. They are not alone in
this. Dithyramb and nomes also employ all three (1447b24-7). A further
distinction subdivides this class into genres that employ all three simultaneously (hama) and genres that employ them kata meros (1447b27-8).
This distinction too is evidently intended to be mutually exclusive and
jointly exhaustive.51 By genres that employ all three media simultaneously Aristotle means that they never use any of the three without the

49

Harmony cannot stand by itself, since all music is associated, if not with words,
with rhythm, and for the same reason words plus harmony cannot exist without
rhythm Lucas (1968), 62.

50

That is not to say that they are empty. To the contrary, the kind of poitik that employs words alone without rhythm or harmony covers a range of works, such as
the mimes of Sophron and Xenarchos and the Socratic dialogues; it simply has no
name, since prose or logos psilos covers non-mimetic writings as well. Likewise,
the kind of poitik that employs words and rhythm or meter without harmony,
covers much of what we call verse (trimeter, elegiac, etc.) but some of the verse it
covers is non-mimetic, such as Empedocles writings, which Aristotle says is natural science rather than poitik. Epic poetry which is composed in dactylic hexameter and is a form of mimsis, falls under this division. I will need to refer to these
two nameless kinds of poitik in what follows. For convenience I shall call them
mimetic verse and mimetic prose.

51

The distinction presents difficulties. The hama category might seem to cover any
genre that employs all three simultaneously in any part, so that comedy and tragedy would qualify, since they employ all three simultaneously in the stasima. And
kata meros might seem to apply to genres that employ all three media, but not all
simultaneously. However, the particles and connectives prove that tragedy and
comedy fall under the heading kata meros, dithyramb and nomes under hama. And
this accords with another and equally acceptable way of understanding hama and
kata meros which I adopt in my interpretation.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

The place of the Posterior Analytics in Aristotles thought 93


others.52 Tragedy and comedy fail to qualify since the dialogue sections
of those genres are in spoken verse but are not in general sung, so they
employ only rhythm and words, not harmony. Likewise, kata meros [sc.
pasin] means not that the genres in question never use all three media
together; it means that they do use them all together, but not all of the
time. Tragedy and comedy qualify because and not in spite of the fact
53
that the stasima employ rhythm, words and harmony.
Aristotle does not give a complete classification of poetic forms. In
order to classify all poetic forms, including lyric poetry, which the commentators complain that Aristotle omits to mention, it would be necessary not only to identify the basic meters, but also to discuss their
possible or actual combinations.54 The case is the same with the subdivision of the forms of poitik that employ all three media, only in this
case it is worth Aristotles trouble to do so, and he does do so, since it is
here that tragedy and comedy are located.
I have argued that Chapter 1 classifies forms of poitik with respect
to the media they employ, and does so by use of three simultaneous differentiae: rhythm, words, and harmony. The classification is not fully
carried out, but it is carried out far enough to let us see that tragedy and
comedy both fall under the same heading, and epic under another. To
specify by way of summary, epic is the form of mimetic verse composed
in dactylic hexameter, and thus employs rhythm and words, while both
tragedy and comedy employ harmony as well as rhythm and words,
and do so kata meros which I have taken to mean that all three media
are used simultaneously in some parts of a comedy or tragedy but not
throughout.
This is as far as Chapter 1s classification takes us. Chapters 2 and
3 introduce different classifications. These chapters are less thorough
than Chapter 1, and focus on the three genres that interest Aristotle the
most. Chapter 2 claims that those who represent people doing things
(agents) must represent people who are either serious or bad (1448a12) a claim he shortly afterwards modifies (1448a4-5) saying that they

52

All three media are used continuously throughout (Lucas (1968), 61).

53

This interpretation accords with 1449b29-31.

54

Think of Chairemon (1447b20-3). That worthy did not confine himself to a single
meter, but jumbled them all together in his mixed rhapsody The Centaur. He too
should be called a poet (poits), but it will not do to call him an elegiac poet or a
trochaic poet, or to name him by any other single metrical form.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

94

Richard McKirahan

must represent people who are either better than or worse than, or
similar to ordinary people55 another division that is intended to be
mutually exclusive and jointly exhaustive. He goes on to say that tragedy and Homeric epic depict agents better than us, while comedy and
certain other works depict agents who are worse. From Chapter 3 we
learn that in epic the poet sometimes narrates and sometimes takes the
part of the characters, whereas in tragedy and comedy the characters
are presented performing the actions themselves.
I do not propose to make sense out of the bafflingly simplistic claim
at the heart of Chapter 2, that some genres, including tragedy, make
their characters better than people of nowadays and others, including
comedy, make them worse (1448a16-17). But whatever Aristotle may
have meant by it, it provides a means to distinguish tragedy from comedy the principal task left over from Chapter 1.
However, it is crucial to notice that Chapter 2 does more than this.
It does not present a dichotomous division of the category forms of
poitik that employ the media of rhythm, words and harmony and do
so kata meros, i.e., tragedy and comedy. The classification it presents is
said to apply to all forms of mimsis (1448a1), and in particular to all the
forms of mimsis previously mentioned: Each of the mimseis that have
been mentioned will have these differentiae, and will be different by
reason of representing different things in this way (1448a7-9). This division is coordinate, not subordinate to Chapter 1s division by media,
and here lies the solution to another problem, namely, why Aristotle introduces a further coordinate division, in terms of manner (dramatic
or narrative) in Chapter 3.
Here is the problem. Chapter 1 groups comedy and tragedy together, apart from epic. Chapter 2 groups epic and tragedy together, apart
from comedy. Chapter 3 again groups tragedy and comedy together
(as dramatic forms), as opposed to epic (which is narrative). Now if the
divisions of Chapters 1-3 were successive rather than coordinate, this
would be a problem, since all the work needed to differentiate epic, tragedy and comedy would be complete by the end of Chapter 2. Chapter
3 would be redundant, and hence unneeded according to the account
of dichotomous definition. But it is not a problem on the reading I am
recommending.

55

beltionas kath hmas. According to Lucas (1968), 64 ad loc, this is equivalent to the
people of nowadays (tn nun): 1448a18.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

The place of the Posterior Analytics in Aristotles thought 95

There remains some work to be done, and with a little generosity


we can find it completed in Chapter 3,56 which identifies three manners. On the prevailing interpretation,57 which I follow, one manner
is dramatic, and there are two kinds of narrative: the Homeric kind, in
which the poet at times narrates and at times speaks the words of the
characters, and the kind where the poet maintains the part of narrator
58
throughout.
The present interpretation accounts for the most important features
of the three divisions found in Chapters 1-3. It shows why they all appear all three are needed to mark off epic, tragedy, and comedy from
each other and also from the other forms of poitik. It takes into account
the fact that as we move from Chapter 1 to Chapter 2 to Chapter 3 the
discussion becomes increasingly centered on just those three forms, but
it also leaves room for the other forms as well: we may suppose that
had he wished to, Aristotle could have completed the divisions so as to
include the missing kinds of poitike, and doing so would not interfere
with what we have, but rather would supplement it.
On the present interpretation, then, Chapters 1-3 present three coordinate classifications of mimeseis of which the first two classifications

56

The crucial lines, 1448a20-4, are difficult and have been taken in different ways. On
any account, there are three manners.

57

See Lucas (1968), 67.

58

The only authors mentioned in Chapter 3 are Homer, Sophocles and Aristophanes.
I take it that the latter two are representative of tragedy and comedy, and I suppose
Homer is meant to represent epic in the same way. But these are the only three genres
that appear, and unless we can find some way to deal with the remaining forms of
poitik, Aristotle is in trouble. Not only is the division incomplete, but the attempt
to demarcate epic, tragedy and comedy from other forms of poitik founders.
But Aristotle may have had legitimate reasons for not mentioning other
genres. In the first place, the present division may not be meant to be a division
of all forms of poitik but only of those that employ words. Painting, dancing
and instrumental music could simply be excluded from the division. (See p. 97
below.) Further, Aristotle may have thought that the other forms of mimetic verse
which until now have not been distinguished from epic either do not fall into
this division either, or, if they do, that they fall under the non-Homeric manner of
narrative. This claim does not apply to dithyrambs, but this is not a problem for
my interpretation, since they were classified differently than epic in Chapter 1.
But it plausibly applies to elegiac poetry, which is the only other genre of mimetic
verse that Aristotle names. (Chairemons aberrant mixed rhapsody is hardly a
genre (1447b20-2).) And Aristotle might have supposed that no other variety of
mimetic verse had the particular kind of narrative that epic does.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

96

Richard McKirahan

employ multiple differentiae simultaneously: the three differentiae of


medium are rhythm, words and harmony; the three differentiae of object are people that are better than, worse than, and similar to us. The
classification of manner is presented as a dichotomy. Aristotle seems to
hold that each form of mimsis occupies some place in the first of these
classifications and also in the second. When it comes to the third classification, his focus on the three particular genres he wants to discuss
leaves much unclear. As we have it, the classification by manner seems
to apply only to those forms of mimsis that employ words. Either, then,
the classification by manner does not apply across the board, or it does,
but either the other forms of poitik fit into the plan as we have it and
Aristotle has neglected to say where they fit, or they fall under other
differentiae which he has failed to mention.
However we come down on this issue, the differentiae of tragedy,
comedy, and epic are clear. Epic (or Homeric epic) is the form of poitik
that (1) with regard to media, employs meter (i.e., rhythm) and words
but not harmony; (2) with regard to objects, represents people better
than us; (3) with regard to manner, employs the kind of narrative in
which the poet at times narrates and at times becomes someone else.
Tragedy is the form of poitik that (1) with regard to media, employs
meter (i.e., rhythm), words and harmony, but not always together; (2)
with regard to objects, represents people better than us; (3) with regard to manner, employs dramatic presentation. Comedy is the form
of poitik that (1) with regard to media, employs meter (i.e., rhythm),
words and harmony, but not always together; (2) with regard to objects,
represents people worse than us; (3) with regard to manner, employs
dramatic presentation.
It is clear that the classifications we find here are not what Aristotles
discussions of dichotomous division call for. In the following section
I will show that they agree perfectly with the model of classification
sketched in the de Partibus Animalium. As I pointed out earlier, Aristotle
says little about his new approach to classification; a good deal remains
to be filled in. But what he does say accords perfectly with the classification of forms of poitik in the first three chapters of the Poetics,
and the way that the Poetics goes about defining tragedy helps fill in
some gaps in the dePartibus Animalium account. Poitik is divided by
multiple differentiae medium, objects, and manner right from the
start. Each of these differentiae is in turn divided by differentiae of its
own. Two small problems remain.
First, it is not clear whether every form of poitik occupies a spot in
each of the three main branches (medium, objects and manner); those

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

The place of the Posterior Analytics in Aristotles thought 97

that do not employ words may have no place in the division according to manner. But perhaps this is not a problem: it is equally unclear
whether every species of animals will have a place in every one of the
main branches of the classification of animals. Still, it may be a problem,
and at least it is an untidy situation.
Here is one way to tidy it up. Aristotle emphasizes that privatives
can occur as legitimate differentiae in the new method of classifica59
tion. It will then be possible to have none of the above as a differentia at any point in a division. Narrative and dramatic are mutually
exclusive differentiae. If they apply only to epic, tragedy and comedy,
or only to those forms of poitik that employ words, Aristotle will permit the heading of manner to be divided initially by the differentiae
dramatic/narrative/neither, which will make room for all the forms
of poitik. This subdivision of genres that employ all three media may
seem arbitrary and ad hoc, but I do not think it is. I claimed above that
Aristotles special interest in tragedy, comedy and epic leads him to
neglect making a thorough classification of the forms of poitik. Recall
that he identifies flute-playing, lyre-playing and pipe-playing as distinct arts, and recognizes others too. This is proved by the etc. clause
at 1447a24-5. All these arts fall under the heading of genres that employ
rhythm and harmony but not words. In order to distinguish these arts
from one another, Aristotle would have had to draw further distinctions
within that heading, possibly somewhat like modern classifications of
musical instruments into stringed instruments, wind instruments, etc.,
with further subdivisions brought in as needed. I suppose he chose not
to do so because it would have taken him too far afield from the genres
he is set to discuss: tragedy, comedy and epic.
Likewise, Aristotle recognizes forms of poitik that can be identified
by the meter employed (elegiac, trimeter, etc.) what I call mimetic
verse. They all belong to the classification of genres that use rhythm
and words but not music. Again, Aristotles present concern is not to
identify all possible or actual metrical forms, and he does not do so. But
again, had he wanted to, he could have made the attempt. And again I
suppose his reason for not doing so is that it would have taken him too
far from his brief.
But I need to say a little more, since epic is part of his brief, and
epic belongs in this division. How then could Aristotle demarcate epic

59

PA I 3, 643b24-6

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

98

Richard McKirahan

from other poetic verse forms? An obvious way to differentiate mimetic verse is by the kind of meter employed: elegiac couplets, iambic trimeters, dactylic hexameters, etc. Aristotle says that people do in
fact distinguish genres of verse by their meter, but complains that there
is something misleading in calling anyone who composes in dactylic
hexameter an epopoios a title inappropriate to those like Empedocles
who do compose in that meter, but who are not really poets poitai
because their work is not a form of mimsis. Aristotle invites us to
distinguish between poets who employ hexameters and others who use
the same meter, reserving the title epopoios for the former. Admittedly
epic was not the only genre composed in dactylic hexameters. I do not
know how Aristotle would have dealt with the Homeric Hymns for
example, or the Works and Days. Could he have brushed them aside
as easily as he did Empedocles? But just as tragedy and comedy are
not yet distinguished one from the other at the end of Chapter 1, and
it requires a different line of division (in Chapter 2) to separate them,
epic too can be marked off from other genres of hexameter poetry by
further divisions. Alternatively, the opening lines of chapter 6 suggest
that Aristotle thought of mimtik in hexameters as equivalent to epic,
so the problem I just identified may have not been a problem for him,
or may have been invisible to him.
And now the second problem. We saw that the division of media in
Poetics Chapter 1 (possibly the division in Chapter 2 as well) puts the
multiple differentiae to work in a particular way. It does not simply
take the differentiae as exclusive alternatives as happens in dichotomous division, but it considers their possible combinations one, two,
and three at a time. Is this procedure compatible with the new method
of classification?
I believe it is. The solution is an extension of the solution to the previous problem. If painting, say, employs certain media and represents
certain objects, but does not involve manner as Aristotle conceives it,
we saw that we can deal with that fact by putting it into the none of the
above heading, which is at the very beginning of the division of manner. The same will apply in the present case too. The three differentiae
of medium are not mutually exclusive. So the initial division of media
will be into not three but a maximum of eight mutually exclusive classes, ranging from the class that has rhythm, words and harmony (that
is to say, all three types) through the three classes employing two of
the three differentiae, the three classes employing just one of the three
differentiae, and finally the class that employs none of the three. Some
of these combinations are not instantiated and may be impossible, or

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

The place of the Posterior Analytics in Aristotles thought 99

they may have been inconceivable to Aristotle. But that is no objection


any more than it would be an objection to his scheme of classification
of animals that no animals are three-legged. In both cases, the classification scheme can make room for those kinds of entities should they
occur, but whether they actually do occur or can occur is a matter for
other kinds of consideration. If it turns out that some combinations are
impossible, then we do not list them. All we require and all we ought
to list are the mutually exclusive classes that jointly exhaust the initial
classification.
So it seems that the classification of forms of poitik in Chapters 1-3
follows the approach to division and definition heralded in the de Partibus Animalium an account different from the one given in the APo,
where division by dichotomy is the preferred way of reaching definitions. As I pointed out a little earlier, the approach found in the de Partibus Animalium is a modification of the principal method of division
found in the APo.
The definition of tragedy one more time
Back to the definition of tragedy: (1) the representation (2) of an action
that is (3) serious and also, (4) as having magnitude, (5) complete, (6) in
language with pleasurable accessories, (7) each kind brought in separately in the parts of the work; (8) in a dramatic, not in a narrative form;
(9) with incidents arousing pity and fear, wherewith to accomplish its
catharsis of such emotions.
(1): tragedy is a representation. This is clear from the start, where we
are told that tragedy as well as epic, comedy, dithyramb, flute playing
and lyre playing are all representations (mimseis) (1447a13). In effect,
mimsis is the genus of tragedy.
(2) (3): tragedy is the representation of an action that is serious.
Chapter 2 begins by stating that the forms of mimsis with which he is
chiefly concerned represent people performing actions (mimountai prattontas), and that some agents are good/serious (spoudaios) while others
are the opposite (kakos), so that the people represented are either better
than we are, or worse, or like ourselves (1448a1-5). The chapter concludes by saying that tragedy represents people better than us. From
this to the claim that it represents spoudaios actions is a very small step
a step that Aristotle himself makes in Chapter 6 where, in expounding the definition, he speaks of both actions and people who perform
actions without noting any difficulties in the transition. So it is clear
that (2) and (3) are differentiae of the genus mimsis.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

100

Richard McKirahan

(4) - (5): tragedy is the representation of an action that has magnitude


and is complete. Chapter 5 offers a further criterion to distinguish tragedy from epic. These genres are the same in that each is a representation of spoudaios people or actions and they both employ speech that is
in meter, but they differ in three ways. Epic is in one kind of verse as
opposed to more than one, it is narrative as opposed to dramatic, and it
covers a longer span of time, tragedies tending to cover events of only
one day or a little longer, while there is no determinate length of time
in which the events of an epic occur (1449b9-14). Aristotle discusses
criteria (4) and (5) in Chapters 7 and 8, re-phrasing the relevant parts
of the definition as follows: tragedy is the representation of a complete
and whole action that possesses a certain magnitude (as opposed to
an action that is complete and possesses magnitude). By introducing
the notion of whole, or rather, by specifying that the actions represented in tragedy are complete in that they are whole, Aristotle implicitly raises the issue of the parts of which the whole is composed,60 and
so he goes on to talk of a tragedy as representing an action that has a
beginning, a middle, and an end, and gives these terms meanings that
make sense in terms of the nature of tragedy. In effect, he uses them to
specify the nature of the actions that make suitable subjects for tragedy.
So I take it that Chapter 5, with its discussion of the length of a tragedy
implicitly introduces the notion of parts.
(6): By pleasurable accessories that accompany the language Aristotle explains that he means rhythm and harmony (1449b28-9) in
other words, (6) repeats the result attained for tragedy in Chapter 1
(1447b25-7).61
(7): each kind brought in separately in the parts of the work. I discussed this matter in connection with Chapter 5.
(8): in a dramatic, not a narrative form. This result was attained in
Chapter 3.
Consequences of the definition
If the Poetics follows the APo model of science, the definition of tragedy
should be the basis from which other attributes of tragedy are derived

60

See Metaph 25-6.

61

At 1447b25 Aristotle substitutes melos (melody) for harmonia (harmony), but evidently intending no difference in meaning.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

The place of the Posterior Analytics in Aristotles thought 101

by demonstrations. This is more or less true for the rest of Chapter 6,


which begins with the following inference: since (epei) tragedy represents people performing actions (prattontes), spectacle (ho ts opses
kosmos) must (ex ananks) be a part of tragedy (1449b31-3). The inferential conjunction since and the reference to necessity (that is, the necessity of logical consequence) indicate that he is arguing, not simply
asserting. And the mention of people performing actions takes us back
to element (2) in the definition of tragedy. The actors are visible, and
the spectacle they present is necessarily to some extent an element in
the total effect. The question is [only] whether opsis refers only to the
appearance of the actors, who were richly attired, or includes all that
we mean by spectacle.62
From the fact that tragedy represents people performing actions Aristotle concludes further (eita) that melody (melopoia) and diction (lexis)
must be parts of tragedy as well, because they [the authors] make their
representation (poiountai ten mimsin) in these (1449b33-4). He next
briefly defines what he means by diction (namely, putting words into
verse), and declines to define melody on the grounds that it is obvious63 (1449b34-6). Melody and diction are consequences of element (6):
rhythm and harmony. Melody and harmony seem to be synonymous
in the Poetics, and diction, defined as putting words into verse, is a matter of selecting words that fit into the rhythms required by the conventions of tragedy.
Another inference follows, again beginning since (epei) (1449b36).
The conclusion is the claim that tragedy has six parts: plot (muthos),
character (thos), diction, thought (dianoia), spectacle (opsis), and melody (melopoia) (1450a7-10). That diction, spectacle and melody are necessary features of tragedy has already been established, so the long since
clause (which occupies almost ten full lines, down to 1450a7) should
establish that plot, character and thought are necessary too. And that
is what it does. The argument for these features depends on the first
two elements of the definition: tragedy is the representation of an action. It follows that it has agents, and as human beings these agents
have characters (the). This point was made in Chapter 2: agents must
be either good/serious or bad (spoudaios, phaulos), and ones character
is determined accordingly, since (gar) it is by badness and goodness

62

Lucas (1968), 99

63

Cf. APo I 10, 76b16-21.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

102

Richard McKirahan

that people differ in their character (1448a1-4). Likewise, the agents


actions are based on thought (as expressed in the words they speak
in the play, especially in arguing for their position or stating their opinions (1450a6-7)). Aristotle holds that thought and character are closely
connected, as he indicates in saying that the agents success or failure
is determined by these two factors.64 Finally, there is plot, which was
mentioned in the first sentence of the work, but has disappeared from
view ever since. Here it is called the representation of the action, which
sounds identical with the first two elements in the definition of tragedy;
the difference is indicated in the specification that the plot is the way
the events are combined (sunthesis tn pragmatn). I suppose that Aristotle might regard Euripides Electra as a tragedy that represents the
action that is the revenge of Electra and Orestes on Clytemnestra for
murdering Agamemnon, and that the plot is the way that the various
incidents are structured in that particular play, while Sophocles Electra and Aeschylus Libation Bearers represent the same action, but their
plots are different since they structure the events differently.
I have shown that the definition of tragedy is a fat definition, largely based on a series of coordinate divisions of the genus mimsis, and
that from this definition Aristotle infers a series of conclusions about
tragedy which he summarizes in the list of six parts of tragedy. My
final point will be to show that even though what we may call the demonstrative part of the Poetics ends with the identification of the six
parts, its results form the backbone of the rest of Aristotles treatment
of tragedy.
This is easy to see. The remainder of Chapter 6 ranks the six parts in
order of importance, and Chapters 7-22, which constitute the remainder of the treatment of tragedy, are devoted to a discussion of the parts:
plot above all (Chapters 7-11, 13-14, 16-18). The very brief Chapter 12
talks of parts of a different kind, the structural parts of tragedy: prologue, episode, stasimon, etc., while the rest of the treatment of tragedy
takes up the three most important parts after plot: character in Chapter
15, thought in Chapter 19, and diction in Chapters 20-2. Spectacle is not
discussed. It is dismissed at 1450b16-20 as the least artistic of all the
parts and as having the least to do with poitik on the grounds that

64

Success and failure refer to and point ahead to the discussion of the structure of
tragic plots later in the work, which gives particular emphasis to stories in which
the main character has a change of fortune from good to bad or vice versa; this
change is the action which the plot represents. Cf. 1450a3-4.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

The place of the Posterior Analytics in Aristotles thought 103

the tragic effect is quite possible without a public performance and


actors, and besides, the getting-up of the spectacle is more a matter for
the carpenter (skeuopoios) than of the poet. The closest there is to a reference to the remaining part, melody, is the brief discussion of choral
songs in Chapter 18. Since melody is by no means restricted to tragedy,
it is not surprising that it receives so little attention.

Conclusion
In reading the Poetics a few years ago I was struck by how Aristotelian a
work it is, and in trying to pin down in what way it is Aristotelian and
at the same time why it is so bizarre as either a history of literature or
as a manual on how to write successful tragedies although it claims
to treat those topics too I found that those elements (the historical
and the how-to aspects) are subordinate to the definition of tragedy
which Aristotle takes such great pains to discover. The centrality of
definition, and therefore of essence, is in my opinion the Aristotelian
kernel of the work, and the work done in reaching this kernel and seeing what follows from it are reminiscent of many of Aristotles other
writings. Once this connection became apparent and also the close links
to the APo approach to science, it turned out that the Poetics began to
look more central to Aristotles work than many have thought. Scholars of Aristotle are familiar enough with disparaging remarks about
the Poetics. (I recall my mentor Gwyl Owen once dismissing the Poetics
as an inferior appendix to the Rhetoric.) I see this paper as a step not
only towards rehabilitating that work as significantly Aristotelian (if
such rehab work is even necessary), but also of exploring how themes
prominent in Aristotles early work develop and continue to affect the
65
work of his later years.

65

I wish to thank the organizers of the conference for inviting me and for arranging
the publication of the proceedings. I am also grateful to David Reeve for his useful comments (some of which have led me to rethink and rewrite certain parts of
the paper for the published version) and to the participants in the conference for a
lively and helpful discussion of my paper. I owe particular thanks to Jim Lennox
for an after-hours discussion which clarified my thinking about the relation of APo
II 8-10 to the paper, and to Gisela Striker for references to some passages of Aristotle that have an important bearing on the thesis of my paper.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

104

Richard McKirahan

References
Battin, W.P. 1975. Aristotles Definition of Tragedy in the Poetics, Journal of Aesthetics and
Art Criticism 33:155-70, 293-302.
Else, G.F. 1957. Aristotles Poetics: The Argument (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press).
Heath, T.L. 1949. Mathematics in Aristotle (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Jope, J. 1972. Subordinate Demonstrative Science in the Sixth Book of Aristotles Physics,
Classical Quarterly 22: 279-92.
Lucas, D.W. 1968. Aristotle: Poetics (Oxford: Clarendon Press).
McKirahan, R. 1992. Principles and Proofs. Aristotles Theory of Demonstrative Science
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press).
Ross, W.D. 1949. Aristotles Prior and Posterior Analytics (Oxford: Oxford University
Press).
Solmsen, F. 1935. The Origins and Methods of Aristotles Poetics, Classical Quarterly 29:
192-201.

Brought to you by | University of Oklahoma Libraries


Authenticated
Download Date | 10/25/14 11:09 PM

Anda mungkin juga menyukai