Anda di halaman 1dari 9

Alberto Pérez-Gómez

MODERN ARCHITECTURE, ABSTRACTION, AND THE POETIC IMAGINATION

From the day when I came to love the Life,


from the day when my heart came to love the Truth,
I no longer have trust in anything in the world
I have no trust in the world.
In the whole world and its works
I have no trust in the world.
After my soul alone I go searching about,
which to me is worth generations and worlds.
I went and found my soul
what are to me all the worlds
I went and found Truth
as she stands at the outer rim of the worlds.

Mandaean poem

For a gnostic thinker must be able to forget that the cosmos does not emerge from consciousness, but that man's
consciousness emerges from the cosmos. He must, furthermore, be able to invert the relation of the Beginning and the
Beyond without becoming aware that he destroys the mystery of reality by his speculative inversion.

E..Voegelin, The Ecumenic Age

1 When we open our eyes every morning to find the world organized in recognizable and
relatively predictable patterns of phenomena, we are witness to a mystery that has always
baffled artists, scientists and philosophers. Our potential to deal simultaneously with the specific
and the mutable on one hand, and the ideal and the universal on the other, has been described
by phenomenology as the most significant characteristic of human perception, as the very
condition of meaning revealed in the immediacy of the world-as-lived. We do not invent
categories and deduce meanings through some kind of a priori, intellectual or associationist
operation, although the capacity of the human mind to do so has created much confusion.
Primarily we are capable of perceiving the ideal in the specific. It could be said, therefore, that
the world is "given" with meaning, and that the meanings discovered in other universes of
discourse, i.e. science, art, philosophy, or dreams, must be regarded as rooted in the primary
realm of experience, in our irreducible encounter with the real. The world, according to Edmund
Husserl, is given to man as a collection of "intentional objects," meaning that these are
permanently open to both their individual specificity and their ideal essence. The mutable
primary structure given to perception, the realm of ever changing colours, variable dimensions
and elastic time, dependent on the weather, the seasons and human desire, carries with it the
secondary structure of invariancy and geometrical space and time.

2 The traditional mission of the arts has been to make explicit the ideal and eternal through an
interpretation of the given in the specificity of perception, providing humanity with a sense of
belonging to a meaningful collective realm, transcending our limitations as finite and corruptible
individuals. In this most profound sense, regardless of the secondary functional utility (or
uselessness) of artifacts, art has always been a primary form of knowledge. Humans could thus
orient themselves in the world and perceive the meaning of existence, otherwise confused in
the continuously mutable reality of everyday life. The painter, sculptor, or architect has been
concerned with the revelation of the truth of reality, with the stabilization of meaning. The arts
are thus, by definition, concerned with essence and in this sense they are also concerned with
abstraction. Differences between figurative and non-figurative art are merely a question of
degree. Indeed, it could be stated that of all the arts concerned with the visible world,
architecture is the abstract one. Painting and sculpture have been traditionally more interested
in the specific, while the task of architecture has been to put forward a geometrical order. In all
instances, however, traditional art was a mimesis of the primary reality given to perception.
Even the most conventional forms of figurative painting were never a mere reproduction of the
external world, but the embodiment of an idea, understood not as a Platonic autonomous
reality, but in its etymological sense as the "image" of "intentional objects." Reciprocally, the
geometry that constituted the essence of architectural "ideas" (plans, elevations, and much
later, sections) in traditional pre-nineteenth century architecture, always made reference to the
external world, particularly to the order of nature understood as the purposeful design of a
Creator. Architecture was the least figurative but the most concrete of the arts, the building of a
reality immediately given to perception.

3 The abstract geometrical order that generated the plan, elevation or volumetric reality of
architecture always maintained its concrete referential residue until late in the eighteenth
century. The circle of Stonehenge was the circle of the heavens, as was the sphere of Boullée's
cenotaph to Newton. The circle and the square, the figures circumscribing so many versions of
the Vitruvian man, were symbolic of the primary dualities of experience, male and female, the
earth and the sky, and the hope of reconciling them always prevailed --as did the expectation of
squaring the circle in the work of alchemists and mathematicians until the problem was proven
impossible in the nineteenth century. It must be remembered that the geometry of the architect
was always dependent on intuition. It was the geometry of the world-as-lived, a discovery of its
constant forms given to man in embodied perception. As a result of the transformations evident
in the theoretical works of Jacques-Nicolas-Louis Durand which I have examined elsewhere, and
after the questioning of the inveterate cosmological picture in the early nineteenth century,
several conditions became clear: 1) architecture could not simply perpetuate tradition through
its "making"; the classical order and proportions lost their absolute validity; 2) the cosmos that
traditional architecture "imitated," to become the ordered place of ritual through the
implementation of metaphor, was no longer a cultural reality given to perception; and 3)
technology developed as a utopia and became the universal mentality of the modern world,
effectively cancelling out the traditional order of nature and drawing its potency and
pervasiveness from the human power of abstraction. Without man's capacity to functionalize
lived experience, through the power of infinitesimal calculus and non-Euclidean geometries, the
technological domination of nature would have been impossible. The new theoretical disciplines
no longer needed to be coherent with intuition, as long as they could operate as instruments for
the effective domination of nature. The architect discovered his or her power to invent orders,
perhaps epitomized by Durand's empty orthogonal grid, or began to see architecture as simply
a formal problem, and celebrated the ability to perceive history as a residue of material "styles."
The concern of most serious architects was to find the most rational style or combination of
styles, to design buildings whose meaning would depend exclusively on the syntax of an
architectural formal "language."

4 Charles-Francois Viel, an architect and critic contemporary of Durand, was also concerned with
style. Viel, however, postulated a radical criticism of the architecture of Durand's Ecole
Polytechnique, subjected as it was to reductionism and technological intentionality. He came to
the realization that theory and practice could not be separated. A rational theory, subjected to
mathematical logic, would never produce meaningful architecture. A true theory of architecture
could not be a set of prescriptions for technological operations; theory could only explain why,
but never reduce practice to a methodology. In order to learn his metier, the architect had to
make. Traditional apprenticeship could not be substituted by the new mathematized theories.
The assumption that a knowledge of these methods of "composition" could allow an
inexperienced architect to dictate to masons and other craftsmen how to make a meaningful
architecture, was a dangerous fallacy. The architect had to possess innate talent, but in order to
become knowledgeable he had to experience the complexity of architecture in the flesh. Viel
was bringing to consciousness an attitude that had always underlied the Western architectural
tradition but that had become increasingly obscured since the Renaissance, when architecture
was "promoted" to the sphere of the liberal arts and endowed with a specific theoretical
discourse. This old-standing relationship between theory and practice had become totally
missed or falsified in the early nineteenth century.

5Once perceived in conjunction with his criticism, Viel's concern with style becomes particularly
revealing to us. He never understood style as a conceptual or functionalized a priori language.
Viel wrote that style must be pure and rigorously observed, consisting in the choice and
disposition of the different parts of a building. In light of his emphasis on the architect's role as a
traditional builder (as techne-poesis), of his re-evaluation of the profound continuity between
theory and practice, and of his observation that style was dependent in part on the "place"
where the building was made, Viel's preoccupation with style must be regarded as an early, if
partial, articulation of the necessity of order for a new architecture. Style may be
"conventional," but it is never arbitrary or a simple question of subjective choice. This order
could no longer depend on Vitruvian theory, nor should it be misguided by reductionism or
technology if the architect wished to avoid the transformation of building into a meaningless
process of assembly of normalized elements.

6 In many ways the dilemma initially confronted by Viel is still with us today. The contemporary
architect must attempt to put forward an abstract order that is not yet known, which cannot be
drawn from a defunct belief in pre-established harmony, but that nevertheless must be gleaned
from perception, and not postulated a priori, as a solipsistic construct. This is indeed the task for
the modern architect's personal imagination, one that is fraught with perils. The architect must
discover order that transcends historical styles, while recognizing that meaning in architecture
can only be grasped (and therefore must necessarily stem from) within our constructed history,
the culture which is our true nature. She must search for such an order implementing the power
of abstraction which is the gift of post-Euclidean geometries, but without creating an
architecture that speaks only about meaningless technological processes; in other words,
without losing the world-as-lived as a primary horizon of meaning.

7 The limitations of abstraction as an artistic paradigm are well known. Even though a certain
order such as twelve-tone music or a Mondrian painting may be postulated as an abstraction of
a shared, historic, lived reality, often its universality is gained at the expense of meaning. In
architecture, abstraction was identified by the modern movement with technological
intentionality. Only a material "shelter," devoid of ornament, could carry any meaning for a
positivistic mentality. The resulting buildings of the international style have been frequently
accused of representing simply a technological process (efficiency and economy), with no
regard for human values and cultural continuity. Clearly, structures generated by the logic of
determinism usually ignored archetypal meanings associated with architectural elements such
as entry, wall, window, roof or floor.

8 This criticism is in great measure fair. Cities all over the world continue to loose traditional
qualities to become anonymous and inhospitable. It is not difficult to demonstrate that late
twentieth century collective pathologies are related to an alienating urban and architectural
environment that promotes isolation and that speaks merely of processes or techno-political
values. It is also easy to imagine how a world that engenders poetic reverie and invites a
meditative living in the "thick present" may be more liberating from our anxieties. In a sense,
humanity must dwell poetically (to paraphrase Martin Heidegger) to be truly human (at least in
the sense that we now recognize as human), and the poetic order of architecture must be
capable of making human purpose evident by reconciling, in a single, incandescent vivid
present, the reciprocity of life and death. Human institutions, represented by architecture, must
reveal an order that transcends the present and therefore must have roots in the past. But it is
now clear that the alternatives proposed by all sorts of "post-modern" formalisms, regardless of
their origin in historical styles, fractal geometry or molecular biology, are very shallow. The
seeming inability of the architect to create space that gathers the order of the cosmos (as a
total picture) and becomes laden with culturally relevant meaning is as much a feature of
contemporary culture as a properly architectural or formal problem. Our architecture must be
ours, even if this means that our fragmented creations can only suggest the possibility of
completion, or reflect merely a sliver of light, rather than the bright, positive luminosity of a
scientific or theological certainty. It is fallacious to pretend that the archetypal meaning of entry
is recovered by placing a classical pediment over a door. It is irrelevant to add neon or wood
ornament to an architecture generated by the parameters of technology. What the best modern
architects have managed to accomplish on occasion, as in the case of Le Corbusier's convent of
La Tourette, for example, has been to discover a truly original abstract order, still rooted in the
continuity of our cultural situations (institutions), and becoming meaningful through its appeal
to primordial shared experiences of human beings as embodied, spatially oriented individuals.
The surreal accommodations and rejections of ritual, the creation and enhancement of
expectations through their displacement and reversal, the presentation of mystery, the
enigmatic reconstitution of hierarchical spatial qualities attained through the modulation of light
and shadow, etc. all result in the poetic reconciliation of a seemingly self-referential, abstract
formal structure with its roots in the continuity of culture.

9 In order to elucidate further both the potential and the dangers of abstraction in architecture
today, it is interesting to draw some parallels between these architectural intentions and certain
attitudes that Hans Jonas, Elaine Pagels, and Eric Voegelin have described in their respective
studies of gnosticism, that "religion" which swept much of the Mediterranean world in the early
Christian era. Gnosticism was characterized by a profound suspicion of the most common
beliefs about the world at that time, much like the situation in which enlightened contemporary
man seems to find himself. Gnosticism represented the first form of an authentic post-
modernity, repudiating both the exhausted logos of Greek origin, which after the Sophists'
excesses seemed unable to explain any further the crucial problems of the human condition,
and the irrational mystery cults (including dogmatic Christianity) which had emerged all over
the Ancient world to replace or complement Greek rationality. Gnostic believers claimed that
true knowledge could only take the form of personal revelation. Man is actually fooled by the
world and dogmatic opinions into believing that God inhabits the visible universe. The earth is
not sacred, but rather its opposite. It is merely a dungeon or prison whose marvels detract man
from searching for the true God within. Man is in fact removed from God by the architecture of
the cosmos.

10 Operating within this gnostic world-view, art and architecture as mimesis in the traditional,
classical sense would also be a deception. This nihilistic, acosmic world-view opens us to two
options: either an ascetic denial of the very possibility of architecture as a cosmic place, or the
personalization of values leading to "anything goes," as long as it is generated by a genuine
discovery of order as a form of self-knowledge. These must be recognized as the two primary
options which seem to be open to modern artists and architects alike.

11 The first option should be acknowledged as a possibility for modern art, although perhaps it
has already been explored to its limit by Marcel Duchamp. This option might be the most
appropriate answer to recent European phenomenological criticism.A critique of the
irreconcilable difference between traditional art as a revelation of the truth of reality preserved
in symbolic representation, and the fallacies of formalism, aestheticism and self-referentiality in
modern art, should probably accept the impossibility of an architecture of cultural continuity, if
this is understood as the conventional building of public institutions in the present
contemporary city.

12 From my optimistic outlook, it is the second option, the discovery of order as a form of self-
knowledge, that interests me more. Having to think and write in the paradoxical void, full of
anguish and hope, which is North America today, I am inclined to believe that the culture of
modernity is perhaps yet to be built. This assertion must necessarily be qualified. Our
relationship to history must be radically different from that which became the norm during the
nineteenth and twentieth centuries as a result of the technological obsession with the future
and a progressive outlook. Nevertheless, we still must act in an epoch of incomplete nihilism,
and we need our stories (retrieved from our tradition) in order to imagine and project better
alternatives for human dwelling. History may have ended, but historicity (narrative) is
unavoidable to articulate appropriate human action. In this context, the personal search for
architectural order that the construction of a modern culture demands necessarily threads
dangerous waters: for the genuine architect the line between sense and non-sense is thin.

13The dimension of this line is analogous to the distance between structural linguistics and the
understanding of language through hermeneutics espoused by Paul Ricoeur. Ricoeur points out
that "there is no symbolism before man speaks, even if the power of symbol is grounded much
deeper." But language itself, "as a signifying milieu," must always be referred back to existence.
Guided by hermeneutics, architecture cannot claim to be a positive science and is unable to
avoid the "risk" of interpretation, the circle in which human knowledge is caught. This circle is
formed by the conjunction of the work of interpretation and the interpreted being.
Hermeneutics, however, will refer architectural order back to an existential function. For a
linguistic philosophy, like early Wittgenstein's for example, all interpretations are equally valid
within the limits of the theory which formulates given rules of reading. In architecture, personal
discoveries of order may also seem to be equally valid, but these will remain mere syntactic
(language) games until they are shown to be grounded in a particular existential function.

14 In view of this necessary qualification of personal discoveries of order, the "gnosticism" that
might lead to a meaningful modern architecture must be elucidated further. In his major study
on order and history, Eric Voegelin takes an extreme view and sees gnosticism in the Ecumenic
Age (the time which roughly extends from the rise of the Persian to the fall of the Roman
empires) as a thoroughly negative, self-referential, intellectual dead end. Whether assuming the
forms of libertarianism or asceticism as it did in Antiquity, or the "modern forms of constructing
systems which are believed to contain the ultimate truth and must be imposed on recalcitrant
reality by means of violence (such as a marxist or progressive reading of history)," gnosticism,
according to Voegelin, assumes that the devotee is dispensed of the responsibilities of
existence in the cosmos. In this light, gnosticism would be a failure and a trap. Man's existence
is, necessarily, participation in reality. It imposes the duty of exploring the intelligible structure
of reality and of spiritually coping with "the insight into its movement from the divine Beginning
to the divine Beyond."

15 It is indisputable that the question of grounding that may allow the inhabitant effective
participation in the work (rather than mere aesthetic contemplation or delight as it has been
speculated since the eighteenth century) is the critical issue in modern architecture. Classical
architecture followed from Philo of Alexandria's cultural reconciliation of Judaism and Platonism
that amounted to a rationalization of the symbols of "divinity as experienced" by pre-classical
and non-Western cultures. Philo's work profoundly influenced Western cultural developments:
classical architecture always assumed that there was an order to imitate, and that the order
could be revealed rationally in the geometry of the architectural idea. Non-classical
architecture, as the possible architecture of gnosticism and, in this sense, the architecture of
modernity, must assume that the world is chaos, understood not as the opposite of order, but
using the word in its more precise etymological sense, a gap between two significant moments
of human history. This would open up architecture to the possibility of cultural recovery,
entailing a re-orientation that would stem from addressing the events of Being directly, avoiding
the mediation of classical rationalism.

16 In gnostic religions, the apparent order of the world was regarded as evil; it was in fact the
opposite of the divine. This is very different indeed from the common perception of
contemporary society that regards the world merely as a neutral, material reality to be
exploited by technological processes. In spite of the dangers of gnosticism expressed by
Voegelin, our experience of reality as given in our life, i.e. personal existence, is godless, in
tension with the order of history. Human existence, the "in-between" consciousness and the
cosmos, is perceived in accordance with Heidegger's celebrated formula: we are too late for the
gods and too early for Being. This experience commands the artist to undertake the risks of
gnosticism as he squarely faces historical reality in his search for Being. Drawing from a gnostic
insight, the contemporary architect can take his concern with abstraction far beyond the
reductionism of technology, which it superficially resembles. The external reality of man is not
neutral for gnosticism; it is rather the negative of the sacred, but pregnant with value. This
dualistic mood creates in the artist and the architect a consciousness of man's capacity to
transcend the dis-order or gap of contemporary technological culture. The suspicion of the
primacy of perception in the constitution of meaning that originally motivated technological
reductionism and scientism can now be taken one step further to become a suspicion of the
given technological reality. As Gianni Vattimo has pointed out, technology itself is "weak" and
the paradigmatic function of art is precisely to show this weakness --not to posit a "new myth,"
but rather to demythify technological rationalism construed as absolute truth and purpose of
human civilization. This amounts to dealing with the distortions and risks of gnosticism by
subverting our cultural dysfunctions from within our historical present, and not by fantasizing an
escapist vantage point that would make it possible for us to act outside of our time and place,
regardless of whether this may be the "reactionary" classicism of the Prince of Wales, or the
"progressive" cosmological assumptions of recent scientific extrapolations in architecture. The
eighteenth century could still at least argue the possibility of divine intervention in a world
plagued by famine and disease, but the argument can hardly be entertained in the twentieth
century where reality has become efficient mass homicide, potential universal suicide and, at
best, genetic engineering.

17 Overcoming cosmic determinism could mean that the artist invents self-referential systems of
signs; that these signs don't belong to the world anymore, and that they do not signify anything
but what they are: lines or sounds. This is obviously a risk, represented in the failure of
"formalist" architecture. The "gnostic" architect might be led to espouse the intention of self-
referentiality, as absurd in scientific disciplines as it is in art. A truly self-referential order, if it
were possible, would simply be outside of the realm of meaning; as an intention, it falls into an
epistemological trap. We should not forget that the ground of all meaning is in perception, and
that meaning is always given as a pair. Intentional objects, the authentic phenomena of our
experience, are never "simply what they are." The objective world doesn't exist. This is, in fact,
the illusion.

18 In spite of the relative risk of non-sense, the "gnostic" architect, operating from his radical
solitude, will be in a better position to reveal true hope, and to suggest the possibility of
genuine transcendence as an invisible "signified" behind the realm of the visible order of signs.
Personal knowledge is raised into an ontological position, as it was, for example, in Valentinian
gnosticism. This knowledge is not secure but it is a necessary alternative to non-existing rituals
(the invisible dimension that allowed traditional architecture to become a cosmic place) as a
vehicle to keep alive our hope for salvation. As a form of genuine interpretation rather than
arbitrary invention, the authentic symbols of a true architectural order can show that
"archaeology, teleology and eschatology," the different modalities of existence as identified by
Ricoeur, dealing with the past, the future, and the beyond, point to a single ontology. Through
the richest symbols the unity is assured, leading the way toward the emergence of new
meanings (the future) and the resurgence of archaic fantasies (the past), revealing the
eschatological dilemma (death) in all its brutal absurdity.

19 The discovery of meaningful architectural order should occur in the realm of perception,
through the operations of making, of "concrete poetry" or poesis, derived from the challenge of
materials and techniques. Such a discovery can be associated at different levels with the notion
of architectural interpretation of historical documents such as drawings, models or buildings.
This association, of course, should not be literal. The understanding of our making, here and
now, as a historical phenomenon is our only possibility for a genuine symbolic intentionality,
leading in fact to the rejection of historicism and nostalgic revivals as false forms of cultural
continuity. The operation just sketched is qualitatively different from the invention of any a
priori conceptual orders by a mind engaged in a purely intellectual operation analogous to
mathematical logic or planning. Embodied making, involving a mind in a body, its flesh,
pleasure and pain, searching for an order rooted in history, perception and materiality, is the
opposite of the construction of an object or building through the implementation of conceptual,
methodological tools, and formalist or technological processes. The product might represent a
technique in the first instance, but the personal techniques endowed with a theoretical and
historical content, and implemented in the project as deliberate acts of discovery, will become
pregnant with meaning.

20 Following this process, the discovery of original architectural orders may come about as a
seemingly self-referential exploration, as a syntactic analysis of an architectural order of the
past that answers a meaningful question from the present. This should be accomplished with
full acknowledgement of architectural intentions in history, not so much what meaning a
historical architect intended, but rather how the essence of the work embodies its cultural
horizon, how a world that answers to our questions may be shared as it appears "in front" of the
work." History, in this (hermeneutic) sense, is the legitimate theory of architecture, providing
fundamental orientation, constituting the intellectual framework for an embodied mind to
address the fullness of reality through the work. That which is permanent and eternal in a work
of architecture transcends the particular meanings addressed by the architect to his
contemporaries. The products of the poetic imagination of the great architects in history now
constitute our "tradition." We should emphasize that the most fundamental mystery of
architecture as a symbolic ordering of man's world is indeed this ambiguous dimension that
makes an architecture foreign in place and time not only accessible but meaningful to us.

21 The danger of these explorations in search of order, particularly when they are not motivated
in the first instance by an external architectural program (entailing necessarily a "re-design" of
human situations or institutions) or a real place (a specific site), is obviously the loss of context
or cultural continuity. Witness the problem of meaninglessness in modern "painting" and
"sculpture." While the abstraction of Euclidean geometry never "lost" the world, the abstraction
of abstractions, i.e. projective and non-Euclidean geometries, certainly lose sight of the world
and must live (or perhaps die) with the crisis of intuition. In the same way, the newly discovered
architectural orders, although rooted in the perception of architectural ideas embodied in pre-
existing artifacts, are also the result of an abstraction of abstractions and can often become
estranged from the continuum of culture. The very genuine possibility of questioning the
survival of culture in its traditional form justifies this "violence" exerted upon the generation of
architectural form. Nevertheless, as I have already suggested, the danger of non-sense is
omnipresent; architecture cannot be self-referential. While the manner of making buildings, the
ornamental vocabulary, and the like were always learned by the architect through his
apprenticeship and rooted in tradition, the symbolic intention that guided his decisions
depended on his perception of a meaningful place (site) within a hierarchical cosmos and of a
meaningful institution (situation). This led the architect to a representation of the institution's
intersubjective or public qualities in a building appropriate to the site within a historic culture.

22 It must be emphasized, however, that today the external conditions which made this
traditional architecture possible are generally lacking. Society denies the very necessity of
symbolic ordering as a source of coherence and ultimate transcendence. The public place for
ritual, where the truth of reality was gathered, cannot simply be "designated" in the
contemporary city. Only the fragmented shadows of traditional rituals remain. For example, the
archetypal meanings associated with "communion," as a sharing of nourishment and life among
peers, might be perceived as underlying a modern banquet, but sharing the bread hardly
contributes to modern man's understanding of the human condition or elucidates his
relationship as an individual to a totality, as it did in the prytaneum of the Greek polis. Although
one can and must acknowledge the rampant irrationality of modern man, it would be practically
impossible to describe an authentic modern culture as a framework of traditional institutions, as
a public realm allowing for the transcendence of human mortality through the individual's
participation in ritual. One can also doubt whether the u-topic space of modernity leaves room
for qualitative "place" in the traditional sense. "Contextualism" in design has therefore a very
limited scope. The reality is that the space of New York is not all that different from the space of
Tokyo, half a world apart. This is particularly striking when one compares any two modern cities
with two traditional cities such as, for example, Florence and Siena during the fifteenth century,
separated by a mere sixty kilometers and belonging to the same cultural tradition.

23 While it is true that man expelled God from science and philosophy in the early nineteenth
century, it is also possible to say that God has abandoned man, leaving only His trace in the
order of history. Building itself is synonymous in our world with technological process, not with
the poetic making of Creation. The builders of our inhuman cities are not architects, nor
engineers for that matter, but disembodied logical minds that respond only to statistics
manipulated by political or economic forces, and will perhaps soon be substituted by their
epitome, the computer. Conversely, "professional" architects are rarely ever builders in the real
sense. When not involved in business or project management, what they usually produce are
"re-presentations" of "real buildings," images that are either delusions or platitudes, and which
we all have already seen because they are the result of planning and thus, by definition,
preconceived. It is in this sense that conventional representation, assuming the neutrality of
projections and media vis-a-vis the represented building, leads by necessity to an inauthentic
"architecture" predicated on reductionism. This is true regardless of whether the project
happens to be presented in carefully rendered form or through detailed working drawings.

24We could conclude, then, that "embodied making" can occur more readily at the level of
drawing or model, under the immediate control of the architect. Projects intended as
explorations into the possibility of an architectural order grounded in techne-poesis, in human
action itself, even run the risk of avoiding an allusion to "building" altogether, in the
conventional sense, as something external to the project. The use of imaginative projections,
ambiguities of scale, and modes of perception would obviously impede a conventional reading
of plans, sections, elevations, and models as objects, in terms of a projection of our body-image
in a Cartesian space. This constitutes in itself a critical dimension, since such "clear reading"
has become during the last two centuries the first expectation of architects and laymen alike, in
their search for perfectly intelligible and predictable planning. Treading upon this ambiguity and
its "common sense" rejection, the modern architect must attempt to discover and re-establish
the ground of meaning.

25 The risks to falsify architectural meaning must be acknowledged and never simply ignored.
Only in this way will preconceptions be banished. It is abundantly clear that even if the architect
perceived the meaning of a certain urban site, that is, the qualitative specificity of place, and
believed in the potential and appropriateness of his programmed institution in the continuum of
culture, the metaphor that summarized the relationship of his project with the world, i.e. reality
as a whole, would not be capable of generating the architectural form itself. Architecture is
obviously not only a formal problem, but the formal problem remains even if the articulation of
a symbolic intention in the world were to suggest a possible course of action. The abyss
between the order perceived by man and the disorder of the world is perhaps an
insurmountable cultural obstacle. When architecture is understood as the making of a building
in the world, the necessity of grounding in a "figural" horizon is unquestionable. This demands a
design of possible rituals and institutions that refer critically to the given structures of our
present day culture and articulate human action poetically. But the architect must avoid at all
costs repeating cliche's and making an "architecture" that is simply redundant or alien to our
time and place; he must avoid "real possibilities" when they are certainly untruth, and should
concentrate on "possible realities" even if they are only uncertain truths. From this perspective,
and reminding ourselves that architecture has never been, nor should it be, all building, but only
the symbolic, intersubjective order that allows for the perpetuation of culture, it appears that it
is the question itself that should be reformulated. The issue is perhaps no longer to design a
building on a site; John Hejduk has told us, after producing a marvelous project, that the site
where the torture chambers of the Gestapo once existed should remain vacant, occupied only
by a sign that names it. The issue is rather to reveal the ground for a potential architectural
order.

26 Theoretical projects, from Piranesi's Carceri to the present, employ man's modern power of
abstraction to produce a criticism of conventional architectural ideas (figurative forms of
representation) beyond the potential reductionism of descriptive geometry. Once the traditional
symbolic geometry was functionalized, the essential, "abstract" language of architecture had to
be implemented in forms controllable by the architect's embodied presence, transcending the
limitations implied by a prescriptive "theory" (methodology) that was finally imposed upon
architecture through the nineteenth century processes of production and is still today often
taken for granted. This quest for "abstraction" in architecture is therefore not a reduction in the
scientific sense, but an attempt to deal with essential meanings that would be lost or
compromised by the disorder of the world.

27 In its most authentic forms, modern art since the early nineteenth century has abandoned the
Renaissance paradigm which assumed that the representation of visible appearance had
ontological value. Modern art has had to choose between the specific and the universal to
concern itself with meaning. In a broad historical perspective this dialectic is artificial and
should be transcended, but during the last two hundred years it has been a cultural condition of
the crisis. Just as surrealism is limited by the world itself, and by a precarious faith in the
existence of meaning in the world (God's creation), abstractionism is limited by the possibility of
losing the world, and by the equally precarious "gnostic" faith in the existence of meaning in the
ideas of man (God's creator). It is important to point out that a motion towards one pole of the
dialectic seems to immediately demand the other. Furthermore, a reconciliation is more likely to
succeed in construction, i.e. authentic architecture, than in the other arts (painting and
sculpture as defined in the Renaissance). The devaluation of external reality as represented
visible appearance, brought about by its "objectification" in the modern world, is irreversible.
The ontological value of figuration could not be taken for granted since the early eighteenth
century. This places architecture in a privileged position of authenticity among the arts, when
facing squarely the problem of meaning vis-a-vis the general displacement of the "poetic" to a
falsely inconsequential position in our modern technological mentality.

29 An objectified abstract architectural order discovered through drawing or model demands


"de-objectification," engaging the spectator through the projection of his body image into
qualitative spaces of inhabitation. Conversely, an exploration into the qualities of space, light,
shadow and texture that respond to a particular situation in a figurative universe demands an
objectification through an historically appropriate architectural order. Sometimes a
reconciliation seems successful (let me cite Le Corbusier's La Tourette again), but this is not the
rule. The architecture we make should appear as an order of the "in-between." It cannot be
simply an object among other objects in the continuum of geometric space. Aestheticism or
formalism is obviously not the answer. But conversely, architecture cannot deny or elude
objectification, becoming a vague exploration of spatial qualities, or rest on assumed archetypal
meanings. It must be both, acknowledging man's creative power but also addressing the
primary realm of meaning in existence. It must indeed occur in the coalescence of creation and
interpretation.

30 The generation of architectural order cannot simply be mimesis of a cosmos. Such cosmos,
the "great chain of being," is gone forever; we are condemned to live in the absence of gods.
The "composition" of architectural elements or fragments with assumed absolute semantic
contents is therefore a fallacious form of representation. An architecture to transcend our
cultural crisis must still be primarily embodied in projects that question implicitly the very
possibility of their transformation into "real buildings" by being true constructions. In order to
attain the inveterate symbolic status of architecture, these projects must furthermore be
revealed as a mimesis of history; a history whose function is precisely to open up possibilities
for the future. Meaningful contemporary architecture must refer back not to the order of
"nature" which will ultimately remain alien to man, but to the order in history, the order
unquestionably evident in that which humanity has already made, that which man can truly
know. This architecture is mimesis understood as an interpretation of human order embodied in
art, in its artifacts and dramatic situations; mimesis as the rhythmic gestures and motions of a
dancer describing the order of the city as a labyrinth, as the expression and intonation of the
actor reciting a tragedy. Like the ancient daidala or art objects of the Iliad, this mimetic
operation, resulting from the demiurgic actions of a technician-magician, will produce a
mysterious emanation of Being, the concrete poetry of reason, illusory perhaps, open to good
and evil, but absolutely crucial for the survival of humanity.

http://www.tu-cottbus.de/BTU/Fak2/TheoArch/Wolke/eng/Subjects/971/Perez-
Gomez/perez-gomez_t.html

Anda mungkin juga menyukai