Anda di halaman 1dari 15

Original article

Qualitative interviewing as measurement nup_436 112..126

John Paley MA
Senior Lecturer, Department of Nursing and Midwifery, University of Stirling, Stirling, UK

Abstract The attribution of beliefs and other propositional attitudes is best under-
stood as a form of measurement, however counter-intuitive this may
seem. Measurement theory does not require that the thing measured
should be a magnitude, or that the calibration of the measuring instru-
ment should be numerical. It only requires a homomorphism between
the represented domain and the representing domain. On this basis,
maps measure parts of the world, usually geographical locations, and
belief statements measure other parts of the world, namely peoples
aptitudes. Having outlined an argument for this view, I deal with an
obvious objection to it: that self-attribution of belief cannot be an exer-
cise in measurement, because we are all aware, from introspection, that
our beliefs have an intrinsically semantic form. Subsequently, I turn to
the philosophical and methodological ramifications of the measurement
theoretic view. I argue, first, that it undermines at least one version of
constructivism and, second, that it provides an effective alternative to the
residually Cartesian philosophy that underpins much qualitative
research. Like other anti-Cartesian strategies, belief-attribution-as-
measurement implies that the objective world is far more knowable than
the subjective one, and that reality is ontologically prior to meaning. I
regard this result as both plausible and welcome.

Keywords: philosophy of science, qualitative research, epistemology,


methodology, subjective experience, social constructionism.

The claim that qualitative interviewing is a form of antonyms, and as measurement is a form of quantifi-
measurement appears bizarre for two reasons. First, cation, qualitative methods and measurement must
as qualitative and quantitative are methodological be mutually exclusive alternatives. This is the meth-
odological reason. Second, qualitative techniques
Correspondence: Mr John Paley, Senior Lecturer, Department of (including interviews) deal with phenomena
Nursing and Midwifery, University of Stirling, Stirling FK9 4LA, meaning and experience, for example which are
UK. Tel.: +44 (0) 1786 466399; fax: +44 (0) 1786 466344; e-mail: intrinsically resistant to quantification, and which
j.h.paley@stir.ac.uk therefore cannot possibly be measured. This is the

112 2010 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2010), 11, pp. 112126
Qualitative Interviewing as Measurement 113

ontological reason. Nevertheless, I propose to


Measurement theory
argue in favour of the claim, even if it seems
counter-intuitive. Consider a body whose temperature is 20Celsius.
The plan of the paper is as follows. I begin with basic Obviously, the body does not have any intrinsic prop-
measurement theory, using the most familiar and erty of a twentyish nature; and, if the scale is changed
obvious example: quantitative measurement by to Fahrenheit, making the temperature 68, it will have
numerical scales. During this discussion, it will become no intrinsic property of a sixty-eight sort of character
evident that measurement is just one kind of repre- either. So what kind of claim does an attribution of
sentation, and that it belongs to a specific category of temperature make? How is the assignment of a
representation based on homomorphism. It will also number made? What exactly are we doing when we
become apparent that some forms of homomorphic measure anything? And what conditions must be met
representation are non-numerical. I illustrate this idea if measurement is to be possible? It is the business of
by describing a particular type of non-numerical mea- measurement theory (Stevens, 1946; Roberts, 1979;
surement, namely maps. Next, I suggest that attitude Suppes et al., 1989) to answer questions such as these.
measurement is a form of semantic mapping and Measurement always involves two domains, X and
that, consequently, the concept of homomorphic rep- Y, with X being mapped on to Y in a way that makes
resentation applies here, too. Because attitude mea- it possible for Y to represent X (the relevant sense of
surement involves the attribution of belief, it is only a represent will be further specified). In numerical
short step from here to the claim that belief attribu- measurement, X will be an empirical system of
tion involves non-quantitative measurement and, cor- objects, and Y will be the domain of real numbers. If X
relatively, that the procedures we adopt in order to satisfies certain conditions, then a relation of homo-
attribute beliefs for example, qualitative interview- morphism will obtain between X and Y, with the con-
ing constitute a measurement process. sequence that reasoning about Y can act as a
This discussion, taking up the first half of the paper, surrogate for reasoning about X (Swoyer, 1991).
may test the patience of readers who are primarily For example, let X be the domain of all bodies
interested in qualitative methods, as the argument is a which have mass. None of these bodies has an intrin-
series of stepping stones: measurement theory, to sic property of 11-ness (lbs) or 5-ness (kg), but the
homomorphic representation, to maps, to attitudes, to members of this domain do nevertheless have weight
belief attribution, to qualitative interviewing. In the relations with one another. For example, if two
second half, however, I turn to four matters of more objects, A and B, are concatenated that is, joined
immediate interest to qualitative researchers, arguing: together their combined weight will be greater than
that people generally, and interview respondents in the individual weight of either one (A + B > A, and
particular, do not have introspective access to their A + B > B). Similarly, if A is heavier than B, then there
own beliefs; that the measurement theoretic view is some finite number, n, such that the concatenation
undercuts at least one form of constructivism; that the of B with itself n times exceeds the weight of A (that
adoption of this view would require us to rethink the is, Bn > A). Or, finally, if A is heavier than B, then it
cognitive dynamics of interviewing; and that attach- will always be possible to determine a third object, C,
ing meaning to experience can be identified with which when concatenated with B is equivalent in
having certain beliefs about it. weight to A (C is such that B + C = A). Effectively,
The paper covers a fair amount of ground, and I then, the domain can be ordered by means of two
have resisted suggestions that it should focus on fewer relations, heavier than and equal in weight to, with
topics. My aim has been to provide a sketch of the all its members being locatable in a sequence running
main idea, indicating what I take to be some of the from heaviest to lightest.
consequences and connections. I acknowledge that It is in virtue of these relations that the measure-
several questions are left unanswered, but I hope to ment of weight is possible. All the members of X can
answer them on another occasion. be placed in an ordered sequence, and they have a

2010 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2010), 11, pp. 112126
114 John Paley

series of concatenation relations with each other. If precisely what it is we are measuring. For example, in
this is true, however, there is necessarily a homomor- order to measure temperature, it is not necessary to
phism between X and Y, the domain of real numbers. know that the numerical assignment represents the
For these numbers can also be placed in sequence, mean kinetic energy of the molecules in the substance
from largest to smallest, and also have parallel rela- concerned. Indeed, the mercury thermometer was
tions with one another, with addition corresponding invented in 1714, well in advance of the development
to concatenation. So, for example, the sum of any of kinetic theory over a century later (Middleton,
two numbers, a + b, will always be greater than either 2002; Mller, 2007).
a or b; if a is greater than b, then there is always some
finite n, such that bn > a; and if a is greater than b,
Non-numerical measurement
there is always a third number, c, such that b + c = a.
Both domains, then, can be ordered in the same way. Qualitative studies typically ascribe beliefs, experi-
Given this domain homomorphism, it is possible to ences, and meanings to respondents. It might seem, as
assign each member of X to a member of Y. The I have already conceded, wildly implausible to
procedure for achieving this requires the selection of suppose that these ascriptions take the same form as
one object in X to serve as the conventional unit of attributions (in numerical terms) of weight, resistance,
weight (the standard kilogram, for example). An arbi- or temperature to physical bodies. However, let me
trary number, usually 1, is then assigned to this object. confirm that this is the claim I am defending. In the
The initial assignment having been conventionally first instance, the argument is presented in the context
agreed, the remaining members of X can be assigned of beliefs or, more generally, propositional attitudes.
corresponding numbers, in a manner which is fixed by Later, I will indicate (if only briefly) how this argu-
the initial assignment itself. Any object which is ment can be extended to meaning and experience.
equivalent in weight to the concatenation of two stan- The idea that propositional attitudes are measure-
dard units will be assigned the number 2, and so on, ment predicates is not new. In various forms, it has
equivalently, for every object in the domain. The been suggested by several philosophers (Churchland,
result is a comprehensive series of one-to-one corre- 1979; Field, 1981; Stalnaker, 1984; Dennett, 1987;
spondences between the members of X and the Davidson, 1989), but it has recently been presented in
members of Y. a systematic form by Matthews (2007). What moti-
The homomorphism between X and Y makes pos- vates Matthews account is scepticism about what he
sible surrogative reasoning (Swoyer, 1991). We can calls the received view of propositional attitudes.
reason indirectly about members of domain X by According to this view, to make an attribution of
reasoning directly about members of domain Y. belief to say A believes that p is to say that A
The homomorphism guarantees that the relations adopts a certain orientation towards the proposition
between objects in X will be represented and pre- p. The received view assumes that p is a representa-
served in Y, and that inferences about members of Y tion in As mind, and that A can adopt a range of
can be translated into inferences about the members attitudes towards it: believing, disbelieving, hoping,
of X. Although we habitually think of magnitudes and so on. Matthews reasons for rejecting this view
such as weight as being intrinsically numerical, in fact are beyond the scope of my paper, but one of them is
they are not.The habit only arises because surrogative that there is no good evidence that these representa-
reasoning is so successful (Matthews, 2007). tions exist. Although I do not have the space to
Once this systematic correspondence is established, develop this line of thought, I would still like to plant
empirical procedures are used to determine what the suggestion that representations in the mind are
numeral should be assigned to what specific object: equivalent to numbers in the object. Just as the
scales in the case of weight, a thermometer in the case number 5 is not in a physical object that weighs 5 kg,
of temperature. It should be noted that these assign- so the proposition p is not in a person who believes
ments can be carried out even if we do not know that p.

2010 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2010), 11, pp. 112126
Qualitative Interviewing as Measurement 115

As a preliminary observation, nothing in measure- two stops east on the Central Line, change at
ment theory requires that the representing domain, Y, Holborn, then travel one stop north on the Picca-
should be the domain of real numbers: the require- dilly). This is the equivalent of surrogative reasoning
ment is only that there should be a homomorphism in numerical measurement (because A is twice as
between Y and the represented domain, X. In order to heavy as B and half as heavy as C, I would need four
establish that such a homomorphism exists, it is nec- of B to match the weight of C).
essary to prove a representation theorem (Suppes & It is admittedly unusual to think of maps as a form
Zinnes, 1963) specifying the conditions X must fulfil if of measurement; some authors have objected to
it is to be represented by a structure such as Y. using the term in the absence of quantification (Dez,
However, it is not necessary that the represented 1997). However, as Matthews (2007) observes,
property in X should be a magnitude, or that Y should nothing of substance hangs on the terminological
be a number-like sequence. issue, as numerical measurement is a special case of
Maps are an example of non-numerical measure- morphism representation. Recently, van Fraassen
ment. The London Underground map, for instance, is (2008, pp. 1645) has offered a definition of measure-
a representing domain, Y, which measures the empiri- ment which is premised on the same idea: measure-
cal network of lines and stations, X. As with other ment is an operation that locates an item (already
forms of measurement, only certain relations in the classified as in the domain of a given theory) in a
empirical domain are preserved by the Y domain logical space (provided by the theory to represent a
specifically, the sequence of stations on each line. range of possible states or characteristics of such
Other features of the network, such as the distance items). . . . As a special case, the logical space can be a
between stations, are not mapped (just as a thermom- scale. Whether the term measurement is reserved
eter measures only a single property of physical for this special case, or whether it is applied to the
objects, temperature, and excludes others). There is superordinate category of homomorphic representa-
obviously a one-to-one correspondence between sta- tion, is more a question of lexical preference than a
tions in the network and the relevant symbols on the metaphysical issue.
map, and therefore a relation of homomorphism
between the two domains.
Attitudes
Notice three consequences of this homomorphism.
First, any station in the network can be located on the We measure the temperature of a physical object by
map. This is equivalent to assigning a numeral to a locating it on a numerical scale. We measure the posi-
physical object when measuring temperature. Second, tion of a London Underground station by locating it
on the basis of the map, it is possible to attribute an on a network diagram. We measure a belief by locat-
indefinite number of relational properties to each ing it in a semantically specified network of sentences
station. For example, Oxford Circus has the following which begin, typically, with a phrase such as she
properties: it is on the Victoria, Central, and Bakerloo believes that . . .. In all these examples, there is an
lines; it is between Bond Street and Tottenham Court empirical domain, X (physical objects, stations,
Road on the Central Line; it is two stops from persons), a property-to-be-measured of the domains
Charing Cross on the Bakerloo Line; and so on. members (temperature, position, belief), and a repre-
Making these attributions is equivalent to noticing senting domain, Y (positive real numbers, the London
the substantive relations between physical objects in Underground map, the spoken or written sentences of
respect of, say, weight (A is twice as heavy as B, half as a language). In each case, Y defines a conceptual
heavy as C, and equal in weight to the combination of space into which items of X are plotted, in respect of
D and E). Third, the map can be used for surrogative the property concerned.
reasoning, which is what the visitor to London does I acknowledge that this is an unusual way of
when planning a journey on the network (to travel looking at beliefs, so let me first talk about attitudes.
from Oxford Circus to Russell Square, I must travel The history of attitude measurement begins with

2010 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2010), 11, pp. 112126
116 John Paley

Thurstone (1928), and attitude remains a distinctive Earls Court It is not possible to make a reasonable
and indispensable concept in social psychology medical diagnosis without anatomy.
(Eagly & Chaiken, 1993) following a resurgence of Gloucester Road Of all the basic sciences, anatomy
interest in the last twenty years (Wittenbrink & is the most clinically relevant.
Schwarz, 2007). This history echoes the development South Kensington Anatomy is only of benefit in
of other, non-psychological, forms of measurement in certain medical specialities.
theoretically interesting ways. For example, it is Sloane Square Most medical conditions do not
unclear precisely what the concept refers to. While require a great knowledge of anatomy.
an attitude can be defined as a psychological Victoria The principles of medicine are not founded
tendency, a state that is internal to the person on anatomical knowledge.
(Eagly & Chaiken, 1993), the underlying structures St Jamess Park Anatomy is time wasted in the
and mechanisms implicated in this state cognitive, medical curriculum.
physiological (Pratkanis & Breckler, 1989), or
biological (Bickle, 2003) are open to question. It will be evident that, in this sequence, there is a
Similarly, in the period during which technologies gradual shift from a very favourable attitude towards
for measuring temperature were being developed, it anatomy to a very unfavourable one, the shift taking
was not evident (until the development of kinetic place gradually by degrees (the example does not
theory) what underlying structures and mechanisms include all the items; in the full instrument the steps
could be identified with heat. Moreover, the debate are more gradual, more nuanced). In effect, each item
about the best method of measuring temperature, represents a carefully defined point on a continuum
extending from the creation of the water thermom- between maximally positive and maximally
eter in the 16th century to the invention of the negative.
mercury thermometer in 1714 (Middleton, 2002), is Or, to vary the metaphor, each item represents a
echoed in the current debate about the most reliable station on the line running from pro to con. This is
means of measuring attitudes (Wittenbrink & not an analogy, but a direct parallel. The Y domain, in
Schwarz, 2007). the Thurstone case, is a semantically specified
Thurstone scaling provides an instructive link sequence of sentences whose function is to define the
between Y domains consisting of numbers or maps, relations between possible judgments, just as the Y
and Y domains consisting of semantically specified domain in the London Underground map consists of
language structures.Thurstones strategy is to devise a a network diagram whose function is to define the
carefully graduated sequence of statements, such that relations between stations. In the same way that the
the sequence defines a logical space representing pos- position of South Kensington can be specified as
sible judgments with respect to a particular topic. between Gloucester Road and Sloane Square on the
Unlike Likert (1932) scaling, which requires an aggre- District Line, so the position of Anatomy is only of
gate score summed over all items of the instrument, a benefit in certain medical specialties can be specified
Thurstone scale invites assent to only a single item as falling between the two items either side of it. And
(or, more realistically, a small number of consecutive just as the London Underground map can be used for
items). The strength of the attitude is represented, surrogative reasoning (somebody travelling east on
not (as in a Likert scale) by the cumulative score over the Central Line, whose destination is Russell Square,
all items, but by the assented-to statement itself, as the is unlikely to leave the train before Holborn), so the
sequence proceeds from most favourable item to least Thurstone scale can be used to make inferences of a
favourable item.The example below, from Moxham & different kind (someone who has assented to It is not
Plaisant (2007), is part of a Thurstone scale designed possible to make a reasonable medical diagnosis
to measure the attitudes of medical students towards without anatomy is unlikely to endorse proposals to
anatomy (District Line underground stations not reduce the amount of anatomy teaching in the
included in original). medical curriculum).

2010 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2010), 11, pp. 112126
Qualitative Interviewing as Measurement 117

Parenthetically, it is worth noting the fact that Thur- London Underground map, so that individuals can be
stone scales are a precursor of item response theory located at a particular point in that space, with some-
(IRT) which now dominates the field in psychology thing analogically like a you are here arrow. In
and education (Embretson & Reise, 2000; de Ayala, everyday encounters, however, the representational
2008), and which has been applied to health outcome space is more usually implicit left unelaborated
measures (Hobart & Cano, 2009). An account of IRT because adjacent belief stations can be taken as read
is beyond the scope of this paper, but the idea that unless there is reason to distinguish carefully
statements of belief can be ordered in semantic space, between the belief being expressed and another with
like stations on the District Line, remains the crucial which it might otherwise be confused.
theoretical axiom linking Thurstone scales to IRT and This is true of numerical measurement as well as
the related technique of Rasch modelling (Reeve & belief measurement. One informs the patient that her
Msse, 2004). weight is 56 kg, omitting to point out that this is
midway between 54 kg and 58 kg, or that it differs
from 60 kg by 4 kg, or that it is double 28 kg. In both
Beliefs
cases, the implied logical space is still there and can
Thurstone scale items are statements expressing be elaborated if necessary. In effect, every attribution,
beliefs, placed in a sequence which reflects the logical of either a belief or a physical property, is defined by
relations between them, and defining a calibrated the relations obtaining between the range of values it
semantic space that discriminates between one belief does not have and the value actually assigned.
and another. The extent to which this discrimination So the shift from statements of belief incorporated
involves nuance and fine-tuning varies, depending on in a Thurstone scale to attributions of belief made in
the intervals between items, intervals which in Thur- everyday life is not a major one. The scale is an instru-
stone scaling are specified through a numerical ment in which belief statements function as items cali-
assignment, but which roughly correspond to intui- brating a conceptual space, which is explicitly
tions about logical distance. For instance, there is a elaborated to an appropriate degree of resolution. In
smaller distance between anatomy is only of benefit everyday belief attribution, the semantic space is
in certain medical specialities and most medical con- usually implicit, and the amount of resolution or fine-
ditions do not require a great knowledge of anatomy, tuning will vary with context. However, in other
than there is between, say, the principles of medicine respects, it is not obvious why it should be necessary
are not founded on anatomical knowledge and of all to insist on a difference. In both cases, to attribute a
the basic sciences, anatomy is the most clinically rel- belief is to report the findings of an exercise in mea-
evant. In principle, one could fine-tune to a much surement. It is to plot the individual concerned on to
greater degree, distinguishing between (for example) a map, a representational Y domain, which exhibits
the medical specialties which require anatomical relations corresponding to those in the relevant X
knowledge and those which do not. In a discussion, domain. It is to make an implicit or explicit compari-
one might do this, but in scaling there are lower limits sons between people positioned at various locations
of resolution beyond which further discrimination is in logical space, and to anticipate ways in which their
impractical or pointless just as it would be imprac- behaviour might be different. It is to undertake a
tical and pointless, in a health care context, to cali- Mercator-like projection of internal states of the
brate a thermometer to three decimal places rather person into a semantic array, a sort of network
than one. diagram of language.
This is one difference between the measurement of Three corollaries of this line of thought are worth
belief in attitude scaling and the measurement of emphasizing. First, in the measurement of belief, we
belief in everyday encounters. The other is that, in are ourselves the instruments: we are biological
scaling, the representational space is explicitly and devices that are generally reliable in ascertaining and
fully elaborated, the attitudinal equivalent of the reporting the propositional attitudes of ourselves and

2010 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2010), 11, pp. 112126
118 John Paley

others (Matthews, 2007, p. 155). Some of this measur- belief states are very different (Churchland, 1981;
ing activity is conscious, but most of it is not. This is Bechtel & Abrahamsen, 2002; Bickle, 2003).This is not
true of all forms of measurement, whether it is making to adopt eliminative materialism (there are no such
inferences about other peoples beliefs, estimating the things as beliefs). Rather, it is to adopt agnostic mate-
speed of an approaching car before crossing the road, rialism, awaiting definitive evidence as to what these
or gauging the dimensions of a puddle as one steps underlying mechanisms actually are, on the under-
over it. standing that our measurement practices are unlikely
Second, the point of belief measurement, and the to change. This resembles the period after the inven-
measurement of other propositional attitudes such as tion of the mercury thermometer, but prior to the
desires and intentions, is presumably to anticipate development of the kinetic theory of heat.
what others will do. As Matthews (2007) observes,
beliefs are aptitudes, internal states that are apt to
Self-attribution and introspection
produce predictable types of behaviour in particular
situations. There is nothing deterministic about this: There is an obvious objection to the position I have
aptitudes do not unfailingly bring about the effects sketched. On the measurement theoretic view, the
with which they are associated, but are typically fact that beliefs are expressed in sentences is a conse-
subject to the presence or absence of countervailing quence of the act of measurement. Just as weight and
beliefs and desires. However, there are good evolu- temperature are not intrinsically numerical, so beliefs
tionary reasons why a generally reliable capacity to are not intrinsically sentential. But surely this cannot
attribute propositional attitudes to other people be right. It may look momentarily plausible in the
should have developed in an intensely social species context of attributing beliefs to others, but it looks
(Carruthers, 2009), including the Machiavellian intel- much less plausible in the context of attributing
ligence hypothesis, which proposes that this mind- beliefs to oneself. On the contrary, each of us knows
reading ability evolved to deal with the social from introspection that our beliefs are sentential. A
complexity of primate groups (Byrne & Whiten, 1988; persons expression of her own beliefs cannot involve
Whiten & Byrne, 1997). Still, whatever its evolution- anything that counts as measuring (let alone self-
ary provenance, belief attribution appears to be a nec- measuring) because she has direct access to them and
essary component of the ability to predict other knows from experience that they do, essentially, have
peoples behaviour. semantic properties.
The third corollary is that the semantic properties of So the semantic nature of ones own beliefs cannot
belief attributions the way they are articulated in be the product of a belief-measuring instrument, or
she believes that sentences are not necessarily the way in which that instrument is calibrated. When
properties of the beliefs themselves. When weight or someone reports that she has a particular belief, the
temperature is attributed to an object, the measure corresponding sentence or at least a semantically
predicate has a numerical form, but the object does qualified item of some sort is present to her mind.
not itself have a number in it; its heat and mass are Having the belief just is being aware that this item,
not intrinsically quantitative.This is equally true when together with its semantic properties, is part of ones
a belief is attributed to an individual. The belief predi- mental fixtures and fittings. Introspective experience
cate has linguistic properties, but the belief itself is not apparently confirms this: it is tempting to say: look,
linguistic; there are no semantically qualified items in here is the belief in my head, and it has an overtly
the person concerned. At least, given the current state linguistic form.
of neuroscience, we have no reason to think there are, This intuition, that we have introspective access to
and many reasons to think there are not. As Church- our own beliefs, is certainly a powerful one. It is, of
land (1986) notes, there is nothing in the brain which course, classically Cartesian because it implies
even remotely resembles sentence-like structures, and that the mind is transparent to itself, employing
the evidence implies that the mechanisms underlying inner perception, or some other form of mental

2010 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2010), 11, pp. 112126
Qualitative Interviewing as Measurement 119

self-awareness, and providing incontrovertible evi- inner speech; such beliefs are legitimately attributed
dence of the linguistic structure of belief. However, to us even when we are asleep. Fourth, each of us has
Descartes is hardly alone in assuming that the an even larger number of beliefs which we have never
attributes of ones own beliefs, judgments and deci- articulated for example, that no elephants live at the
sions are transparent in a way that those of other North Pole, and that London is bigger than St
people are not (Ayer, 1963; Rorty, 1970; Audi, 1993; Andrews (Cohen, 1995). Some of these beliefs we
Dretske, 1995; Shoemaker, 1996; Moran, 2001, unambiguously act on: it is not possible to roast the
Goldman, 2006 are among the modern philosophers Sunday joint in a dishwasher (Manfredi, 1993); or
who take a similar view). Indeed, this transparency ping pong balls will melt if dropped on the fire. As
seems so obvious that denying the possibility of Moran (1999, p. 187) says, tacit beliefs can be per-
immediate, introspective access to propositional atti- fectly real beliefs, which interact with relevant desires
tudes is hugely counterintuitive (Carruthers, 2009). to produce action; and, in some cases, solving a
Even so, there are good reasons to deny it. problem can require the making explicit of a tacit
A preliminary observation is that obviousness is belief which has prevented a solution being reached
not much of a guide. As Churchland (1988) notes, (Moran, 2001). These examples demonstrate that
numerous things have seemed obvious that subse- propositional attitudes are not intrinsically semantic,
quently proved to be false. For a European living that believing can be decoupled from inner speech
between about 500 CE and 1500 CE, it seemed acts (Marcus, 1983). More generally, they count as
obvious she could see with her own eyes that the persuasive evidence against the claim that having a
heavens formed a revolving sphere around the Earth; belief necessarily entails having an identifiable phe-
it still seems obvious to many people that some organ- nomenal state, a view that has few adherents today
isms are too complex to have evolved. These are two (Moran, 2001, p. 28).
examples of failed theories however obvious. The The distinction between having a belief and cur-
Cartesian claim that introspective access to proposi- rently articulating a belief in inner speech is clearly
tional attitudes is possible part of folk psychology crucial. On the anti-Cartesian view, the sentences one
(Dennett, 1989; Ramsey et al., 1990; Davies & Stone, calls to mind in introspection are no more than effects
1995) may be another. An inner perception is no of the auditory or visual imagination. Indeed, phe-
doubt different from an outer perception (of the nomenologically, much of what we habitually call
revolving heavens), but there is an extensive social thinking appears to be just that: the imagination of
psychological literature confirming that it is easy to be what sentences would sound like if spoken, or look
wrong about ourselves, and about our beliefs, experi- like if written (Hurlburt & Schwitzgebel, 2007). Argu-
ences, feelings and motives (Nisbett & Wilson, 1977; ably, Cartesians have confused expressive with consti-
Ross & Nisbett, 1991; Wilson, 2002; Haybron, 2007; tutive, the (occasional) sensory accompaniment of
Schwitzgebel, 2008). Even if we do have a Cartesian propositional attitudes with the attitudes themselves
ability to introspect our own states of mind, it is (so (Carruthers, 2009).
the evidence demonstrates) a remarkably fallible one. Analogously, there is a distinction between Edin-
Here, then, are some considerations implying that burgh Castle and a description of it provided by the
propositional attitudes are not semantically qualified. guide. The properties of the description are not the
First, believing is not peculiar to language users properties of the castle. The description consists of
(Marcus, 1983); for example, beliefs are reasonably sentences uttered with a certain pitch, timbre, and
and non-anthropomorphically attributed to animals. intonation, linguistic items which can be semantically
Second, pre-linguistic infants have beliefs, in particu- and syntactically parsed. None of which applies to the
lar those concerning the differences between inani- large stone building at the western end of the Royal
mate objects and people (Gopnik & Meltzoff, 1997). Mile. But this is typical of differences between the
Third, we all have an indefinitely large number of thing representing and the thing represented (compare
beliefs which we are not currently articulating in the differences between the Underground map and

2010 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2010), 11, pp. 112126
120 John Paley

the Underground itself). In general, the attributes of Consider two different types of constructivism.
the latter cannot be read off from the attributes According to the first, social reality is constructed by
of the former, irrespective of whether the representa- individuals. Social facts and institutions are, in some
tional item is a number, a map, a sentence, or an act of ill-defined sense, the creation of individuals, on the
auditory imagination. This would be like claiming that basis of experience, meanings, or perceptions. Accord-
an object is intrinsically twenty-ish because it has a ing to the second, some impersonal force culture,
temperature of 20Celsius, or that Marble Arch is society, discourse, language constructs representa-
intrinsically red because it is on the Central Line. tions: meanings, theories, subjectivities. The distinc-
So introspective access to inner speech is not iden- tion between personal agents constructing realities
tical with introspective access to the beliefs which and impersonal agents constructing representations
inner speech may be employed to represent. Inner (Mallon, 2008) marks a fundamental divide between
speech is a form of verbal imagination: I imagine approaches to constructivism, constructionism, or
hearing a sentence that I attribute to myself social constructionism (terminology varies across dis-
(Machery, 2005, p. 477). These sentences naturally ciplines). The claim I shall defend is that the belief-
possess semantic attributes, but it does not follow that as-measurement view undermines one version of the
the beliefs they represent possess semantic attributes first of these approaches.
as well. This applies to self-attributions of belief as In both versions of constructivism, there are numer-
much as it does to the situations in which we attribute ous variations on the theme. The impersonal agent
beliefs to others. There is, effectively, a seductive illu- view is adopted by authors as diverse as Parsons
sion at work here. We enjoy introspective access to (1951), Foucault (1986), and Gadamer (2004), each of
something, but that something turns out to be an act whom takes a different view of the agent concerned
of auditory imagination, an extract from inner speech respectively: social systems, discourse, tradition and
which represents a belief or some other propositional the nature of the constructing process socializa-
attitude. The propositional attitude itself, despite the tion, the constitution of subjectivities, historicity (for
illusion, is not something we can introspect directly. comments on the methodological parallels between
Parsons and Foucault, see Mouzelis, 1995). The per-
sonal agent view resolves into a number of different
positions, but I will distinguish between writers who
Constructivism
suggest that the constructing is done by meanings
The story so far. For the most part, we know what we (Schutz, 1967; Collin, 1997), and writers who argue
believe, but it does not follow that we know what that behaviour is the key mechanism (Blumer, 1969;
beliefs are. Attributions of belief, to oneself or others, Goffman, 1990). My remarks are directed at those
involve a type of non-numerical measurement, locat- who favour the meanings view, and I have phenom-
ing the individual concerned in a representational Y enological and naturalistic inquiry authors princi-
domain consisting of sentences (rather than maps or pally in mind.
numbers), sentences which may be spoken, written, or According to Schutz, social reality is rooted in
articulated in inner speech, and which specify the meanings attached to everyday life by the individual.
conceptual inter-relations of items in the X domain He defines meaning as a certain way of directing ones
(that is, the beliefs themselves). These attributions can gaze at an item of ones own experience (Schutz, 1967,
be used in surrogative reasoning, to anticipate peo- p. 42, italics in original), and refers to meaning-
ples behaviour and to identify their tacit beliefs. endowing acts of which I become aware by a reflexive
Having sketched an argument for this view, I will glance (p. 36). He concludes that a phenomenological
conclude the paper with some brief comments on its sociology will study social behaviour by interpreting
implications for our understanding of qualitative its subjective meaning (p. 11). Schutz goes a step
research, first from a philosophical perspective, then beyond Weber, for whom meaning is the inside of
from a methodological one. outward behaviour, but it is evident that both

2010 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2010), 11, pp. 112126
Qualitative Interviewing as Measurement 121

authors are thinking in Cartesian terms, social reality does. It is easy to forget this. For example, Collin
being the product of meaning-assignments in indi- (1997) observes that money tokens are valueless in
vidual consciousness. In a similar way, Lincoln & themselves:but we bestow value upon these valueless
Guba (1985, p. 83) see reality as a construction in the tokens by collectively believing them to possess value
minds of individuals, with meanings being attached (p. 3, italics original). However, belief per se achieves
to the phenomenon; they infer that it is dubious nothing. It is behaviour, the physical exchange of
whether there is a reality; if there is, we can never goods for tokens, that determines social reality. One
know it. This is an unambiguously Cartesian position. might summarize this by saying, somewhat cavalierly,
The idea that there are conscious acts of meaning- that reality is not a construct of meaning; rather,
attachment or meaning-endowment, achieved by the meaning is a construct of reality.
direction of an inner gaze, is as metaphorical and as
uninformative as a construction in the mind, but
The cognitive dynamics of interviews
serious attempts to unpack this imagery are surpris-
ingly hard to find, and the solipsistic and/or idealist Any act of measurement requires the calibration of Y
implications are rarely commented on (Fay 2003). space, and a method for plotting members of the X
Still, the picture of meaning as a sort of mental ray is domain into it. The method consists of a causal trans-
clearly unsatisfactory, especially if an entire social action between the object being measured and an
world is to be founded on it. A less opaque and more instrument which fixes the point at which this object is
plausible analysis is provided by Collin (1997), who located in the Y domain. This being the case, it is
translates meaning talk into propositional attitude clearly necessary to ensure that the causal transaction
talk. On this analysis, to attaching meanings is to takes place in a reliable manner that is to say, a
have certain beliefs and desires, which do not require manner which identifies the relevant point in Y space
a reflexive glance; consequently, the phenomenal correctly. The history of thermometers, for example, is
aspect falls away (p. 119). This view is consistent with a history of attempts to identify a suitable thermo-
that of Lincoln & Guba (1985), whose examples of metric material, one which would respond to tem-
multiple realities always concern groups of people perature changes in a regular and controllable fashion
with conflicting beliefs. (I will take Collins translation (water and alcohol were explored before mercury
as a legitimate point of reference for now, but I will proved to be the most dependable).
say more about the relation between belief and In the measurement of belief, the same require-
meaning towards the end of the paper.) ments apply; in particular, there must be a predictably
However, if the measurement view outlined above accurate transaction between instrument and subject,
is correct, the attribution of belief cannot serve as a so that the belief can be precisely plotted into the
basis for the construction of reality. First, attributions representational domain. In the context of attitude
of belief logically presuppose reality. At least, they scaling, and questionnaire design more generally, this
presuppose a reality in which certain forms of behav- is widely acknowledged, and recent years have seen
iour for example, measuring are already meaning- increasing interest in the response process specifi-
ful; so the source of that meaning cannot be belief cally, the ways in which respondents process question-
attribution. Second, if we are agnostic about the naire items cognitively with a view to improving the
underlying nature of beliefs, we presumably cannot quality of research instruments. Conventional pretest-
explain how they construct reality, although we ing is now regarded as inadequate, and various alter-
should perhaps leave open the possibility of a neuro- natives have been studied: statistical modelling,
logical construction of reality (Reyna, 2002; Aden- cognitive interviews, evaluation of response latency,
zato & Garbarini, 2006; Rilling, 2008), a biological field experiments, and different methods of adminis-
form of reductionism. Finally, in construing beliefs as tration (Tourangeau & Rasinski, 1988; Schuman &
aptitudes, the measurement theoretic view entails Presser, 1996; Sirken et al., 1999; Tourangeau et al.,
that, if anything constructs social reality, behaviour 2000; Presser et al., 2004).

2010 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2010), 11, pp. 112126
122 John Paley

This literature demonstrates that response is highly which attempts to evaluate these snap judgments.
sensitive to changes in question wording, question Qualitative authors prefer to invest their faith in the
order, formatting, and interviewer tone, and that interviewers social skills (Kvale & Brinkman, 2009).
subtle variations in syntax, semantics, and pragmatics Underlying the qualitative methodologists per-
can affect the respondents understanding of the spective is an image of what the in-depth interview
questions she is asked. Cognitive approaches to achieves. Where the structured interview compels the
survey methodology have proposed testable explana- respondent to express herself through a grid, which
tions of this response sensitivity, focusing in particular forces the data into certain shapes, an in-depth inter-
on the cues available to the respondent, and the view permits the data to flow naturally. Qualitative
extent to which the interviewees retrieval of informa- interviewers seek to avoid imposing a grid of any
tion is reconstructive and inferential. The cues deter- kind; hence the insistence on respondents using their
mine what is relevant when answering a given own words, and the requirement that interviewers
question which beliefs the respondent samples on abstain from overly specific questions which might
that occasion and largely account for response insta- cue the respondent towards categories which do not
bility (Tourangeau et al., 2000). As a consequence, fit her spontaneous understanding. It is as if there is
measurement errors can be traced to psychological an inner fountain of experience, which the inter-
and communicative processes (Ongena & Dijkstra, viewer attempts to tap directly, instead of forcing
2007), and survey questions can be analysed in terms it into predetermined conceptual channels. The
of the cognitive operations they are likely to evoke qualitative interview attempts to . . . uncover [the
(Lessler & Forsyth, 1995; Chessa & Holleman, 2007). subjects] lived world prior to scientific explana-
Moreover, an understanding of the cognitive pro- tions . . . [It] gives a privileged access to peoples basic
cesses implicated in answering questions has made it experience of the lived world (Kvale & Brinkman,
possible, in many cases, to control and reduce 2009, p. 1/29). The implied contrast, between imposed
response errors (Belli et al., 2001; Willis, 2005). structure and natural flow, is endemic to qualitative
This literature is rarely acknowledged in qualitative philosophy.
research (Hammersley, 2008). Indeed, those who On the measurement theoretic view, however, the
write on qualitative methods implicitly reject the cog- contrast represents a bogus dichotomy. There is no
nitive approach, believing that it is inappropriate to inner fountain (or, if there is, we have no idea what it
see social interaction as bias which can potentially is like), and nothing that counts as access.Any report
be eradicated (Mason, 1996, p. 40). For Mason, it is of propositional attitudes, whether third person or
better to understand the complexities of the interac- first person, is an exercise in measurement, the plot-
tion, rather than pretend that key dimensions can be ting of individuals on to a conceptual map, a Y domain
controlled for (p. 401). Ironically, cognitivists and of sentences. Not recognizing this leads to a casual-
qualitative methodologists agree about the signifi- ness in reports of qualitative studies, reports in which
cance of context, and about the importance of constru- the cognitive dynamics of interviews are left opaque
ing interviews as social interaction. But they disagree (recent examples in nursing: Lee & Weiss, 2009; Lindh
about the extent to which it is possible to study the et al., 2009; Rowse, 2009; Tregunno et al., 2009). There
cognitive dynamics of interviewing systematically.The are few, if any, clues concerning the way in which the
cognitivists believe that rigorous enquiry into seman- pragmatics of the interview precipitate the partici-
tics and pragmatics is possible, and that response error pants responses.
(bias) can be reduced by applying the results of these The implication of the measurement theoretic view
enquiries to the design and conduct of interviews. is that this opaqueness is both unsatisfactory and
Qualitative writers, meanwhile, believe that judg- unnecessary. Research into the cognitive dynamics
ments about semantics and pragmatics can and must of qualitative interviews, building on cognitive
be made in situ, on the basis of spot assessments approaches to survey work, will provide greater trans-
(Mason, 1996, p. 44). There is no tradition of research parency; greater transparency will make it possible to

2010 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2010), 11, pp. 112126
Qualitative Interviewing as Measurement 123

determine the relationship between the micro- transcript: I felt that he was in love with me. I know
management of interviews and outcomes. It will also that he was, he was in love with me, I wouldnt have
help to reduce response error, however unpalatable felt like that if . . . it wasnt both ways . . . (p. 139). In
that concept may be to qualitative writers at present. this case, the propositional attitude marker, I know,
replaces a more hesitant statement of the belief, he
was in love with me; a further belief (specified, this
Belief and meaning
time, without a marker) is offered in support of this
Throughout this paper, I have exploited the assump- claim: [I believe that] I wouldnt have felt like that if
tion that the attribution of belief to respondents is a it wasnt both ways. As this example suggests, self-
significant output of qualitative interviewing. attributions of belief are pervasive in qualitative
However, the extent to which identifying beliefs is studies.
the principal objective of qualitative research might This should not be surprising. Qualitative research-
be questioned. There are, of course, studies explicitly ers, as Smith et al. (2009) observe, are interested in
designed to elicit beliefs about, for example, health how people make sense of things, how they invest
and illness (Nettleton, 2006; Schofield et al., 2007; them with meaning. But what sort of achievement is
Hjelm et al., 2009), but are there not numerous other making sense? What counts as investing with
forms of qualitative data: reports of sensation and meaning? It is unexpectedly difficult to find attempts
emotion, narratives, generalization about events and to answer this question in methodological texts.
circumstances, anxieties, anticipations, aspirations, Despite its importance to qualitative studies,
agitations? Can the measurement theoretic view be meaning remains a largely unexamined concept. My
generalized to all of these? suggestion, akin to Collins (1997), is that meaning is
We should not underestimate the degree to which the projection of belief. The HIV-positive respondent
respondent accounts, as well as corresponding third- interprets the behaviour of his partner, interprets his
person ascriptions made by researchers, incorporate own feelings, in terms of a belief: he was in love with
statements of belief, implicitly or explicitly. Take, as an me. The meaning he ascribes to the experience just is
example, this excerpt from an interview transcript in the belief which he has formulated, and which he
which an HIV-positive gay man talks about an unpro- subsequently expresses to the interviewer (of course,
tected sexual relationship: I suppose I wanted sometimes the belief is verbalized for the first time
to . . . please him, I wanted to, I suppose it was some- during the interview). This, in the context of qualita-
thing that I could give him that . . . I felt nobody else tive studies, is the paradigm case of attaching a
could, I suppose that was my way of trying to show meaning to experience. Or so I would argue.
him how much I cared (Smith et al., 2009, p. 138; However, there is more to be said about generaliz-
italics not in original). Here, the respondent prefaces ing the measurement theoretic view. I do not imagine
three narrative claims with the propositional attitude that meaning-as-belief is the whole story, but space
marker, I suppose. This marker belongs to a class prevents extended discussion here. Meanwhile, for a
including I believe, I imagine, and I assume, all of comparable approach to the idea that all first-person
which can be followed by that and a noun clause data are the result of measurement, and should not be
expressive of what is believed, imagined or assumed. regarded as a set of introspective, epistemologically
Yet the presence of such a marker is not necessary to privileged reports, see Piccinini (2009).
convey the fact that a belief is being expressed. The
absence of I suppose in this excerpt would not signal
Endnote
an absence of belief. On the contrary, it would signal a
more confident belief, a firmer commitment to the Even if, for lexical reasons, measurement is
interpretation being offered (in contrast with I restricted to cases in which the Y domain is that of
suppose, which implies a certain tentativeness). real numbers, there is no metaphysical reason to dis-
Compare this passage with another from the same tinguish between numerical measurement as a special

2010 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2010), 11, pp. 112126
124 John Paley

case and homomorphic representation as a superor- Byrne R. & Whiten A. (eds) (1988) Machiavellian Intelli-
dinate category. Moreover, the arguments in the gence: Social Expertise and the Evolution of Intellect in
Monkeys, Apes and Humans. Cambridge University Press,
second half of the paper are unaffected. If semantic
Cambridge.
properties are characteristic of the representational Carruthers P. (2009) How we know our own minds: the
domain, not of beliefs, then it is hard to see how relationship between mindreading and metacognition.
meanings can construct reality. And if the causal Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32, 121139.
exchange between subject and instrument determines Chessa A.G. & Holleman B.C. (2007) Answering attitudinal
response, then it is hard to see why this dynamic questions: modelling the response process underlying con-
trastive questions. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 21, 203
cannot be studied systematically. Constructivism and
225.
the fountain of experience are both residues of Car- Churchland P.M. (1979) Scientific Realism and the Plasticity
tesianism, but the measurement theoretic view has an of Mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
anti-Cartesian corollary: the objective world is more Churchland P.M. (1981) Eliminative materialism and the
knowable than the subjective one, and reality is onto- propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 78, 67
90.
logically prior to meaning.
Churchland P.S. (1986) Neurophilosophy: Toward A Unified
Science of the Mind/Brain. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Acknowledgements Churchland P.M. (1988) Matter and Consciousness: Revised
Edition. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
I would like to express my thanks to several people, Cohen L.J. (1995) An Essay on Belief and Acceptance. Clar-
especially Trevor Hussey, Mark Risjord and Peter endon Press, Oxford.
Collin F. (1997) Social Reality. Routledge, London.
Allmark, who provided sharp questions and/or
Davidson D. (1989) What is present to the mind. In: The
helpful comments on an earlier draft of this paper. I Mind of Donald Davidson (eds J. Brandl & W. Gombocz),
am also grateful to two anonymous referees from pp. 318. Editions Rodopi, Amsterdam.
Nursing Philosophy for their cogent appraisals, Davies M. & Stone T. (eds) (1995) Folk Psychology. Wiley
although I apologize for not following all their Blackwell, Oxford.
Dennett D. (1987) The Intentional Stance. MIT Press, Cam-
suggestions.
bridge, MA.
Dennett D. (1989) The Intentional Stance. MIT Press, Cam-
References bridge, MA.
Dez J. (1997) A hundred years of numbers: an historical
Adenzato M. & Garbarini F. (2006) The As If of cognitive introduction to measurement theory. Studies in the
science, neuroscience and anthropology. Theory and Psy- History and Philosophy of Science, 28, 167185, 237265.
chology, 16, 747759. Dretske F. (1995) Naturalizing the Mind. MIT Press, Cam-
Audi R. (1993) The Structure of Justification. Cambridge bridge, MA.
University Press, Cambridge. Eagly A.H. & Chaiken S. (1993) The Psychology of Atti-
de Ayala R.J. (2008) The Theory and Practice of Item tudes. Wadsworth, Belmont, CA.
Response Theory. Guilford Press, New York. Embretson S.E. & Reise S.P. (2000) Item Response Theory
Ayer A.J. (1963) The Concept of A Person. St Martins Press, for Psychologists. Psychology Press, New York.
London. Fay B. (2003) Phenomenology and social inquiry: from con-
Bechtel W. & Abrahamsen A. (2002) Connectionism and the sciousness to culture and critique. In: The Blackwell Guide
Mind: Parallel Processing, Dynamics, and Evolution in to the Philosophy of the Social Sciences (eds S.P. Turner &
Networks, Second edn. Blackwell, Oxford. P.A. Roth), pp. 4263. Blackwell, Oxford.
Belli R.F., Shay W.L. & Stafford F. (2001) Event history Field H. (1981) Postscript to mental representation. In:
calendars and question list surveys: a direct comparison of Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology (ed. N. Block),
interviewing methods. Public Opinion Quarterly, 65, pp. 112114. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
4574. Foucault M. (1986) The Foucault Reader. Penguin, Har-
Bickle J. (2003) Philosophy and Neuroscience: A Ruthlessly mondsworth.
Reductive Account. Kluwer Academic Publishers, van Fraassen B.C. (2008) Scientific Representation. Claren-
Dordrecht. don Press, Oxford.
Blumer H. (1969) Symbolic Interactionism: Perspective and Gadamer H.-G. (2004) Truth and Method. Continuum Inter-
Method. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, NJ. national, London.

2010 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2010), 11, pp. 112126
Qualitative Interviewing as Measurement 125

Goffman E. (1990) The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life. Matthews R.J. (2007) The Measure of Mind: Propositional
Penguin, Harmondsworth. Attitudes and Their Attribution. Oxford University Press,
Goldman A. (2006) Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psy- Oxford.
chology and Neuroscience of Mindreading. Oxford Uni- Middleton W.E.K. (2002) A History of the Thermometer and
versity Press, Oxford. Its Use in Meteorology. John Hopkins University Press,
Gopnik A. & Meltzoff A.N. (1997) Words, Thoughts, Baltimore, MD.
and Theories. Bradford Book, MIT Press, Cambridge, Moran R. (1999) The authority of self-consciousness. Philo-
MA. sophical Topics, 26, 179200.
Hammersley M. (2008) Questioning Qualitative Inquiry: Moran R. (2001) Authority and Estrangement: An Essay on
Critical Essays. Sage, Los Angeles, CA. Self-Knowledge. Princeton University Press, Princeton,
Haybron D. (2007) Do we know how happy we are? Nos, NJ.
41, 394428. Mouzelis N. (1995) Sociological Theory: What Went Wrong?
Hjelm K., Bard K., Berntorp K. & Apelqvist J. (2009) Diagnosis and Remedies. Routledge, London.
Beliefs about health and illness postpartum in women Moxham B.J. & Plaisant O. (2007) Perception of medical
born in Sweden and the Middle East. Midwifery, 25, 564 students towards the clinical relevance of anatomy.
575. Medical Education, 20, 560564.
Hobart J. & Cano S. (2009) Improving the evaluation of Mller I. (2007) A History of Thermodynamics:The Doctrine
therapeutic interventions in multiple sclerosis: the role of of Energy and Entropy. Springer, New York.
new psychometric methods. Health Technology Assess- Nettleton S. (2006) The Sociology of Health and Illness.
ment, 13(12), iii, ixx, 1177. Polity Press, Cambridge.
Hurlburt R.T. & Schwitzgebel E. (2007) Describing Inner Nisbett R.E. & Wilson T.D. (1977) Telling more than we can
Experience? Proponent Meets Sceptic. Bradford Books, know: verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological
MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Review, 84, 231259.
Kvale S. & Brinkman S. (2009) InterViews: Learing the Craft Ongena Y.P. & Dijkstra W. (2007) A model of cognitive
of Qualitative Research Interviewing, Second edn. Sage, processes and conversational principles in survey interview
Los Angeles, CA. interaction. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 21, 145163.
Lee S.-Y. & Weiss S.J. (2009) When east meets west: inten- Parsons T. (1951) The Social System. Glencoe Free Press,
sive care unit experiences among first-generation Chinese Glencoe, IL.
American parents. Journal of Nursing Scholarship, 41, Piccinini G. (2009) First-person data, publicity & self-
268275. measurement. Philosophers Imprint, 9(9), 116. Avail-
Lessler J.T. & Forsyth B.H. (1995) A coding system for able at: http://hdl.handle.net/2027/spo.3521354.0009.009
appraising questionnaires. In: Answering Questions: Meth- [accessed 28 December 2009].
odology for Determining Cognitive and Communicative Pratkanis A.R. & Breckler S.J. (eds) (1989) Attitude Struc-
Processes in Survey Research (eds N. Schwarz & S. ture and Function. Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ.
Sudman), pp. 259291. Jossey-Bass, San Francisco, CA. Presser S., Rothgeb J.M. & Couper M.P. et al. (eds) (2004)
Likert R. (1932) A technique for the measurement of atti- Methods for Testing and Evaluating Survey Question-
tudes. Archives of Psychology, 140, 553. naires. Wiley Science, Hoboken, NJ.
Lincoln Y.S. & Guba E.G. (1985) Naturalistic Inquiry. Sage, Ramsey W., Stich S. & Garon J. (1990) Eliminativism and the
Beverly Hills, CA. future of folk psychology. Philosophical Perspectives, 4,
Lindh I.-B., Severinsson E. & Berg A. (2009) Nurses moral 499533.
strength: a hermeneutic inquiry in nursing practice. Reeve B.B. & Msse C. (2004) Item response theory mod-
Journal of Advanced Nursing, 65, 18821890. eling for questionnaire evaluation. In: Methods for Testing
Machery E. (2005) You dont know how you think: intro- and Evaluating Survey Questionnaires (eds S. Presser, J.M.
spection and language of thought. British Journal for the Rothgeb, M.P. Couper et al.), pp. 247273. Wiley-
Philosophy of Science, 56, 469485. Interscience, Hoboken, NJ.
Mallon R. (2008) Naturalistic approaches to social construc- Reyna S.P. (2002) Connections: Brain, Mind and Culture in A
tion. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at: Social Anthropology. Routledge, London.
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/social-construction- Rilling J.K. (2008) Neuroscientific approaches and applica-
naturalistic/ [accessed 28 August 2009]. tions within anthropology. Yearbook of Physical Anthro-
Manfredi P.A. (1993) Tacit beliefs and other doxastic atti- pology, 51, 232.
tudes. Philosophia, 22, 95117. Roberts F. (1979) Measurement Theory. Addison-Wesley,
Marcus R.B. (1983) Rationality and believing the impos- Reading, MA.
sible. Journal of Philosophy, 80, 321338. Rorty R. (1970) Incorrigibility as the mark of the mental.
Mason J. (1996) Qualitative Researching. Sage, London. Journal of Philosophy, 67, 399424.

2010 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2010), 11, pp. 112126
126 John Paley

Ross L. & Nisbett R.E. (1991) The Person and the Situation. Suppes P. & Zinnes J. (1963) Basic measurement theory. In:
McGraw-Hill, New York. Handbook of Mathematical Psychology, Vol I (eds R.
Rowse V. (2009) Support needs of childrens nurses involved Luce, D. Krantz & E. Galanter), pp. 176. Wiley and Sons,
in child protection cases. Journal of Nursing Management, New York.
17, 659666. Swoyer C. (1991) Structural representation and surrogative
Schofield I., Kerr S. & Tolson D. (2007) An exploration of reasoning. Synthese, 87, 449508.
the smoking-related health beliefs of older people with Thurstone L.L. (1928) Attitutdes can be measured. Ameri-
chronic obstructive pulmonary disease. Journal of Clinical can Journal of Sociology, 33, 529554.
Nursing, 16, 17261735. Tourangeau R. & Rasinski K. (1988) Cognitive processes
Schuman H. & Presser S. (1996) Questions and Answers in underlying context effects in attitude measurement. Psy-
Attitude Surveys. Sage, Thousand Oaks, CA. chological Bulletin, 103, 299314.
Schutz A. (1967) The Phenomenology of the Social World. Tourangeau R., Rips L.J. & Rasinski K. (2000) The Psychol-
Northwestern University Press, Evanston, IL. ogy of Survey Response. Cambridge University Press,
Schwitzgebel E. (2008) The unreliability of naive introspec- Cambridge.
tion. Philosophical Review, 117, 245273. Tregunno D., Peters S., Campbell H. & Gordon S. (2009)
Shoemaker S. (1996) The First Person Perspective and Other International nurse migration: U-turn for safe workplace
Essays. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. transition. Nursing Inquiry, 16, 182190.
Sirken M.G., Herrman D.J., Schechter S., Schwarz N., Tanur Whiten A. & Byrne R. (eds) (1997) Machiavellian Intelli-
J.M. & Tourangeau R. (eds) (1999) Cognition and Survey gence II: Extensions and Evaluations. Cambridge Univer-
Research. Wiley Blackwell, Oxford. sity Press, Cambridge.
Smith J.A., Flowers P. & Larkin M. (2009) Interpretive Phe- Willis G.B. (2005) Cognitive Interviewing: A Tool for Improv-
nomenological Analysis. Sage, London. ing Questionnaire Design. Sage, Thousand Oaks, CA.
Stalnaker R. (1984) Inquiry. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Wilson T.D. (2002) Strangers to Ourselves: Discovering the
Stevens S. (1946) On the theory of scales of measurement. Adaptive Unconscious. The Belknap press of Harvard
Science, 103, 667680. University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Suppes P., Krantz D., Luce R. & Tversky A. (1989) Founda- Wittenbrink B. & Schwarz N. (eds) (2007) Implicit Measures
tions of Measurement, Vol II. Academic Press, New York. of Attitudes. Guilford Press, New York.

2010 Blackwell Publishing Ltd Nursing Philosophy (2010), 11, pp. 112126

Anda mungkin juga menyukai