Anda di halaman 1dari 120

The Question of Heidegger

a critical review of the literature


What follows is a critical review and bibliography of the literature on
Heidegger and technology. It covers primarily works in English and
ranges roughly over the last decade and a half Though not exhaustive, it
indicates the major problems and main currents of discussion during this
period with some reference to earlier and non-English literature. It also
examines translations and relates the issue of technology to the Heidegger
corpus as a whole.
Exhaustive coverage would have been difficult for more than one
reason. First, the philosophy of technology as found in Heidegger and else-
where touches on at least four distinct but interrelated philosophical con-
cerns: science and politics along one axis, art and religion along another.
In each case there is no easy way of deciding how far to venture into these
often independently examined concerns although some venturing is man-
ifestly necessary. Second, Heidegger's thought is beginning to influence
more systematic work in the philosophy of technology as well as in the
four related areas just mentioned. But it is not always easy to say where
Heidegger's influence is explicit enough to merit review under present cir-
cumstances.
Oversights and limitations of access and diligence aside, the direction
of this review has been determined by a desire to illuminate in what ways
Heidegger's work can advance a philosophical understanding of technol-
ogy within the scholarly community. Questions thus broached are of two
sorts: (l)What is Heidegger's understanding of technology and how does
that understanding figure in his thought as a whole? (2)How much of what
Heidegger says is true, or how can it help guide our own thought and ac-
tion within a manifestly technological but nonetheless uncertain world?
Clearly it is through an engagement with such questions that Heidegger
will come to exercise an influence within the scholarly community. Just as
clearly it is only through such scholarly influence that Heidegger's
thought may one day have a general social or cultural impact.
To attempt a survey which serves these intentions while remaining
within reasonable bounds frequently requires graceless presentation and
peremptory argument. On other occasions many of our judgments would
need to be more carefully nuanced or given detailed support. While regret-
ting such specific debilities in the present instance, we nevertheless have
often embraced the virtue of brevity, given the volume of material to be
detailed, hoping that this approach will be justified by the larger argu-

PHILOSOPHY TODAY SUMMER 1987


and Technology #
by Albert Borgmann
with the assistance of Carl Mitcham

ment thus made possible. A further shortcoming of this review is the un-
even depth of scrutiny. Occasionally minor efforts get more attention than
substantial and penetrating works. Here too contingencies of access and
attention have played a role; and again our overriding concern was to pro-
vide a coherent and illuminating account of Heidegger's thought on tech-
nology and of the wider response to his thought.
The present study has also involved some division of labor, although
each author has read and contributed to the whole. Borgmann was respon-
sible for the initial draft of Part One, Division A, dealing with technology
as it comes into focus between science and politics and as it explicitly ap-
pears in Heidegger's work; Mitcham for developing the original idea of
Part One, Division B, on technology as contrasted with art and religion.
Borgmann has, however, done the major share of the whole text while
Mitcham has concentrated on the bibliography.
Full documentation for works directly relevant to themes of this re-
view can be found in the bibliography, including a few works not discussed
directly in the text. To maintain the unity of this bibliography and its abil-
ity to serve as an independent guide to the literature, incidental references
are documented by endnotes.

Part One
REVIEW OF THE LITERATURE
A. Technology Between Science and Politics

Although technology is a primary Heidegger and science before turning


theme in the work of Heidegger to work that bears explicitly on Heideg-
more so than in any other major philos- ger and technology. This will lead to a
opher it is not always discussed as consideration of discussions concerning
such. Heidegger himself at times sub- Heidegger and politics.
sumes it under a discussion of modern
natural science. His critics often dis- 1. Heidegger and Natural Science
cuss it in association with politics. Ac- No one disputes the close tie be-
cordingly, we will begin with remarks tween modern science and technology.
on the literature that deals with But precisely how a person under-

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

99
Stands the connection depends on prior main helpful terms to locate this issue
conceptions of each. It is thus helpful to generally and in Heidegger's thought
distinguish provisionally three senses though "realism" has been used both
of science: (l)science as a human ac- more narrowly and more broadly in the
tivity or enterprise, (2)science as a col- philosophical literature than it is being
lection of laws and theories, and (3)sci- employed here. What is at stake, at any
ence as the application of laws and rate, is the kind of claim science can
theories to practical endeavors. What make on and about the human world.
most divides the scholarly community As Robert Pirsig has written in his
with regard to the philosophy of natural philosophical novel, Zen and the Art of
science is a question concerning the Motorcycle Maintenance, "The scien-
status of science in its second or central tific point of view has wiped out every
sense: Are scientific laws and theories other view to a point where they all
general, though not exclusively reveal- seem primitive, so that if a person
ing, descriptions of the way the natural today talks about ghosts or spirits he is
world really is? Or are they merely considered ignorant or maybe nutty."^
useful fictions or instruments that But did this dominance of science come
allow us to predict and control physical about because human beings were im-
events? The answers determine pressed by the knowledge of reality of-
whether one adopts an (inclusive) fered by science (realism), or did
realism or some kind of instrumen- human beings commit themselves to
talism in the interpretation of science. science because of the power it could
Although this may appear to be a provide (instrumentalism)?
fairly academic question, in fact it is If scientific knowledge tells us
debated passionately with working something real and crucial about the
scientists and philosophers of science world, then such knowledge cannot
often committed to a realist interpreta- readily be abandoned without also giv-
tion of scientific knowledge and ing up on the ideal of homo sapiens;
humanists prone to adopt some version whereas if scientific knowledge is
of instrumentalism. Gerald Holton has merely an instrumental construct, ef-
given a vivid picture of the heat of this fective in achieving some limited prac-
controversy in "On Being Caught Be- tical purpose, one is free to limit or re-
tween Dionysians and ApoUonians."' ject the claims of science at will. Once
The controversy has since been overta- the illusion of the innocence or innocu-
ken by the current of deconstruc- ousness of scientific knowledge is aban-
tionism, hermeneutics, and post- doned,^ the easiest way of limiting the
modernism that threatens to inundate force of science appears to be in-
the proponents of the scientific method strumentalism.
and of rigorous, analytic philosophy.^ In this light, the question of the
The new divide does not entirely line up epistemological status of scientific
with the Dionysian/ApoUonian split nor knowledge has deep implications for
with the instrumentalism/realism dis- the character of our time and for the
tinction. Alliances often cross the re- science-technology relationship within
cent divide. Quine's thought, e.g., flows it. And if Heidegger's thought is as
in both directions. comprehensive and provocative in
But the crucial issue of the status of these regards as is frequently held,
science in the modern world remains. Heidegger's work ought to have some-
"Instrumentalism" and "realism" re- thing important to say about the ques-

PHILOSOPHY TODAY
tion of science. But is Heidegger any- concern with science was explicit
thing like a philosopher of science? "On enough to merit the appellation of a
the longest day he ever lived," answers philosophy of science. In this phase
William J . Richardson, "Heidegger Heidegger (1916) made "an attempt to
could never be called a philosopher of apply Husserl's general programme of
science" (1968, p. 511; cf. p. 535). Cer- logic as theory of science to particular
tainly this is true in the sense that problems" (Kisiel, 1973, p. 225), viz., to
Heidegger is not at all interested in log- an analysis of the different concepts of
ical reconstructionist projects or time operative in the sciences of phys-
analyses of the internal structure of sci- ics and of history. In Being and Time
entific explanations. Nevertheless, (1927), however, Heidegger moved
Joseph Kockelmans (1970a and b, 1984 away from a logical conception of sci-
[chapter 10], and 1985), Theodore ence to an existential one. In this sec-
Kisiel (1970a, 1973, and 1977), Kockel- ond phase of Heidegger's analysis of
mans and Kisiel together (1970), and science, the origin and foundation of
Hans Seigfried (1978) all directly chal- science is explicated as a mode of
lenge this contention. human being-in-the-world (Kisiel, 1973,
Kockelmans admits that "Heideg- pp. 227-230). Seigfried even goes so far
ger has never developed a systematic as to claim "that the prime purpose of
philosophy of science" (1970b, p. 184; the elaboration of the Being question in
cf. Kockelmans and Kisiel, eds., 1970, Being and Time is the radical and ulti-
p. 146) but also maintains that Heideg- mate foundation of the sciences" (1978,
ger had "a rather sophisticated knowl- p. 327). This is an extravagant thesis,
edge of the sciences" and "as a philoso- argued at length only to be taken
pher . . . concerned himself regularly back in a footnote (p. 331, note 14).
with the meaning of modern science" In fact Being and Time, in its radi-
(1984, p. 209). Kockelmans' Heidegger cal ambition, means to probe the foun-
and Science (1985) recycles, systemati- dations of human existence so deeply
cally restates, and extends twenty that science, conceived as a human en-
years worth of study on this topic. terprise, is illuminated and determined
Kockelmans stresses Heidegger's gen- in its fundaments along with all other
eral and externalist approach to sci- aspects of the human. At the core of
ence, places it in its historical and human reality lies the hermeneutic or
philosophical background, and deals interpreting activity, as primordially
especially with the status of the histori- present in practical engagements. Sci-
cal and social sciences. He is sugges- entific theory is derived from practice;
tive on the relation between what it is but one aspect of the hermeneutic
Heidegger calls the historical sciences sphere. "Scientific research," says
and what in the Anglo-American tradi- Heidegger, "is not the only manner of
tion are called the social sciences. Yet Being which this entity [Dasein or
on the whole his book remains above human being] can have, nor is it the
the fray and might well be described as one which lies closest" (1927, p. 11).
an eminent scholar's dissertation The existential conception of science
exhibiting both the strengths and weak- thus indicated is fleshed out in What is
nesses of that genre. a Thing? (lectures from 1935-1936) by
According to Kisiel (1973), Heideg- delineating the a priori structure
ger's thought about science has gone (called "mathematical") which pre-
through three stages. In the first, the determines the modern scientific ap-

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

101
proach to reality and its possible find- nates the existential-hermeneutic con-
ings. With its goals of objectification ception of science.
and control, this structure is said to re- Nevertheless, many explicators of
veal the close kinship between science and commentators on Heidegger's phi-
and modern technology. And yet, as losophy of technology continue to repre-
Heidegger himself concludes already sent Heidegger as holding solely an
near the end of Being and Time, "a existential conception, albeit in a
fully adequate existential interpreta- mathematical version, i.e., Joseph
tion of science cannot be carried out Kockelmans (1966), Richardson (1968),
until the meaning of Being and the 'con- Edward Ballard (1970), John Sallis
nection' between Being and truth have (1970), Magda King (1973), Michael
been clarified in terms of the temporal- Zimmerman (1977a and b), and Harold
ity of existence" (p. 408 [357], italics in Alderman (1978). This is all the more
original). remarkable because Kisiel's major dis-
tinctions have been available since 1962
The last remark points toward
in Karlfried Grnder's less complete
what Kisiel calls the third stage of
and more opinionated version.
Heidegger's examination of science, in
which science becomes not simply one European studies have perhaps
existential possibility of being-in-the- been less guilty of neglecting the epoch-
world, but a temporally or historically al character of science (and technol-
given actuality that rules the present ogy). Consider, for instance, Jean-
age. The scientific character of reality Frangois Jobin (1975) and Massimo De
is now no longer the result of an ap- Carolis (1978) two analyses which
proach that human beings are merely recognize the historical cast of modern
able to take, but one that they are des- science (and technology). In English,
tined to pursue, an epochal feature of however, the lone notable exception
the history of Being. "This history ulti- until recently has been the Dutch-
mately grounds itself not in the ground- American Andrew G. Van Melsen's
ing project of Dasein but in an epochal early (1961), ambitious attempt to inte-
movement that takes its course beyond grate Heidegger's mathematical and
human control" (Kisiel, 1973, p. 232).' epochal characterizations of modern
science and technology into a neo-
Kisiel's distinctions are crucial for Thomist framework. But like much
clarifying the relation of science to neo-Thomist philosophy of science this
technology in Heidegger's thought. effort has been largely ignored by the
Heidegger's philosophy of technology secular academic community and vi-
comes to the fore in the third of Kisiel's tiated by its own optimistic belief in an
stages (in the 1950s), and hence it is the easy resolution of the tensions between
epochal sense of natural science in re- science and politics.
lation to which Heidegger speaks of What are the epistemological impli-
technology as "manifesting the initially cations of the interpretation of natural
hidden character of modern science" science as a mode of being-in-the-world
(Kisiel, 1970, p. 179). Accordingly, com- which is also a "historically evolving
mentators such as Patrick Heelan (par- context-dependent articulation of multi-
ticularly 1972a), John Macquarrie ple horizons" (to use Heelan's descrip-
(1975), and Francis F . Seeburger (1976) tive phrase)? Heidegger himself does
acknowledge the historical framework not provide an unambiguous answer.
to which the later Heidegger subordi- Indeed, perhaps the chief reason for the

PHILOSOPHY TODAY
prevalence of existential interpreta- regarding the question of realism.
tions is an ambiguity in Heidegger's Holism does well in showing how a dog-
final view of science (and technology). matic and ahistorical ("metaphysical"
In Being and Time Heidegger ar- or external) realism comes to grief
gued that "only as long as Dasein is . . . through an infinite regress in its at-
'is there' Being" so that "Being (not en- tempt at stating conditions of reality.
tities) is dependent upon the under- But holism is in turn threatened by sub-
standing of Being ; that is to say Reality jectivism unless it admits an internal
(not the Real) is dependent upon care" realism, i.e., a way of distinguishing
(p. 255 [212]). Such a view of the recip- within a praxis or interpretive context
rocal interdependence of the structure what is real and what illusory. But in
of consciousness and reality as deter- Rouse's essay, as in any orthodox
mined by the practical interests or con- holism, this distinction is subjectively
cern (Sorge) of Dasein readily lends it- grounded, or vague, or begged.
self to an instrumentalist epistemology. A contrary position is that of Albert
This, for instance, is the interpretation Hofstadter' as reaffirmed by Bernd
of Joseph Rouse (1981), who uses Magnus,' which argues that Heidegger
Heidegger's Dasein-analysis to provide is at bottom a realist. Indeed, following
a theoretical foundation for Thomas the celebrated "turn" in his thinking,
Kuhn's avowedly anti-realist theory of Heidegger offers a self-interpretation of
the structure of scientific revolutions. the Being and Time passage quoted
(Kisiel [1977] has argued the same above which points in this direction. In
point about the compatibility of Heideg- the Letter on Humanism Heidegger
ger's view of science and that of the maintains that what he was trying to
historical structuralists, although in a say was that Being itself gives Dasein
more sophisticated form.) Rouse sees its (Being's) own reality, thus laying
in Heidegger's ideal of authentic exis- the basis for a realist epistemology.
tence, in the appreciation of contigency "The sentence does not mean that the
which comes to the fore only during Dasein of man in the traditional sense
crisis situations, a more general ver- of existentia . . . is that being through
sion of Kuhn's idea of the tensions be- which Being is first fashioned . . . does
tween revolutionary and normal sci- not say that Being is the product of
ence. man" (1947, p. 216). Interestingly
Rouse's contribution is competent enough, in his first published article on
and original in placing scientific prac- "The Problem of Reality in Modern
tice in the richly developed context of Philosophy" (1912) Heidegger also re-
Heidegger's Dasein-analysis. But his fers favorably to the critical realism of
achievement suffers from three de- a contemporary author and to that
ficiencies. (l)Rouse has paid little at- "Aristotelian-scholastic philosophy,
tention to the explicit remarks in Being which has always thought realistically"
and Time on the philosophical founda- (p. 70). At the same time, even if
tions of science. (2)The existential ex- Heidegger is ultimately realist in his
plication of science that Rouse provides aspirations, it is also clear that he feels
assimilates science so fully into Da- compelled to reject the realist claims of
sein's ways of being in the world that science.
the distinctiveness of scientific practice Thus along with his development of
disappears. (3)Finally his position suf- the epochal conception of science as a
fers from the general ailment of holism historical given, Heidegger remains

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

103
critical of the claims and views of sci- which are embedded in the primordial
ence. "Science does not think" is his level of practical being-in-the-world?
overquoted remark (1954, p. 8). (For a As Roger Waterhouse argues (1981,
good explication of this statement, see pp. 164ff.), Heidegger's phenome-
Kisiel, 1970a, pp. 173ff.) This critical nological description of our practical
attitude is uncritically accepted by too engagements is unnecessarily thin, and
many Heidegger scholars when they the abstraction of the (scientific) pre-
envision their work as opposed to that sent-at-hand wholly from the (practi-
of Anglo-American mainstream philos- cal) ready-to-hand is based on an
ophers who generally hold science in overly simplified dichotomy. Primor-
high regard. An instrumentalist view dial encounters with the world are mul-
permits the quickest and easiest attack tiform and various, and derivative or
on the overly expansive claims of sci- founded ones can be derived or founded
ence, and that view is conveniently in more than one way.^
akin to elements in Heidegger's exis- At another place, Gadamer (1977)
tential and mathematical interpreta- elaborates the need for humanistic
tion of natural science. (and hermeneutic) self-knowledge
Though critics of science and tech- called forth by the conquest of nature
nology are glad to repeat Heidegger's achieved through science and technol-
warning that science is not reflective, it ogy. But is Gadamer's attempt to make
remains doubtful whether the critique aesthetic (hermeneutic) knowledge the
of objective knowledge as eventuating critical judge of natural science not
necessarily in scientific technology is just as invidious as the rejection of the
always conscious of its own reflective humanities by scientism or technicism?
limitations. "I am convinced," writes As Waterhouse says, perhaps too
one of the great Heidegger followers, crudely: "Natural scientific knowledge
does exist, and it is in some sense cor-
that Heidegger's discovery will rect or true a sense which it is in-
later become a part of the com-
cumbent upon Heidegger to explicate
mon knowledge of humanity, for
we see with increasing clarity before he can establish that it is in-
today as he has taught us to see ferior to or false in the face of his
that Greek metaphysics is the higher sense of truth" (p. 154).
beginning of modern technology. The truth is that a pluralist histori-
Concept formation, born of West- cism of science is just as compatible
ern philosophy, has held through a
long history, that mastery is the with a temporally structured (or even
fundamental experience of reality progressively developing), multifa-
(Hans-Georg Gadamer, 1975, ceted realism as with strict historicist
p. 494). instrumentalism as Kisiel (1977) in fact
shows very well. And Heidegger's her-
Is it true that all concept formation meneutic principle which construes
must be equated with domination? Is it human participation as one constitutive
not possible for science to arise existen- element of being-in-the-world can be
tially from a manifold of practical en- argued to imply a critical realism over
gagements without promoting the any nominalist instrumentalism. After
dominating possibilities of such engage- all, Heidegger never argues that Da-
ments especially since Heidegger sein is the sole constitutive element.
later emphasizes precisely the non- Certainly Charles Hartshorne's conten-
dominating aspects of crafts and art, tion from 1937 that Heidegger's

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

t Ayl
phenomenology does not adequately ac- scholars until recently have not con-
count for "the conception of the world tributed much to this salutary con-
order, so clearly independent of man as troversy. Within the last eight years,
that order seems to be," can be an- however, two substantial contributions
swered only on such a basis.' to this issue have appeared, both
Carl Friedrich von Weizscker deeply influenced by Heidegger.
(1982), who traces the changes in
The first is Richard Rorty's Philos-
Heidegger's view of natural science in
ophy and the Mirror of Nature (1979). It
ways similar to Kisiel, emphasizes that
is a radical critique of modern philoso-
the later Heidegger no longer attempts
phy, inspired by "the three most impor-
to raise a Maginot line against the force
tant philosophers of our century
of the sciences (pp. 90-92). Heidegger
Wittgenstein, Heidegger, and Dewey"
acknowledges the power and the unique
(p. 5). In the context of our discussion
status of natural science. But, Weiz-
we might say Rorty is concerned to
scker argues, Heidegger is unable to
show that philosophers in the modern
recognize what in the sciences gives
period have typically emulated the co-
them their privileged rank, just how
gency and universality of claims that a
scientific truth is related to other kinds
proponent of an exclusive and dogmatic
of truth, and to what extent scientific
realism would ascribe to the sciences.
truth bears on our total view of the
In the case of the sciences, that rigid
world (pp. 92-96). Natural science,
and narrow view has impoverished our
especially in the paradigmatic form of
culture by devaluing the poetical and
physics, is concerned "to discover ulti-
religious understanding of the world. In
mate fundamental laws" (pp. 93-94);
philosophy, however, we find the worst
this concern (a) establishes natural sci-
of two worlds, pseudoscientific rigidity
ence as continuous with philosophy, (b)
and cultural impotence. Philosophers
makes impossible the delimitation of
achieved rigor by inventing their own
science as a regional ontology, i.e., as
peculiar problems and procedures and
one approach to reality that is coordi-
so creating a distinctive profession. But
nate with others, and (c) encompasses
in doing so they excluded themselves
humans in the study of nature and
from the conversation of humanity and
makes untenable the distinction be-
forfeited the possibility of contributing
tween the philosophical a priori and the
to that conversation.
scientific a posteriori investigation of
human existence (pp. 95-96). "I am jus- Rorty tries to show that this self-
tifying here only," concludes Weiz- imposed exile from the common cul-
scker, "what has been occurring for a ture is coming to an end through de-
long time in today's science, against velopments within and without
untenable philosophical defensive posi- mainstream philosophy; within profes-
tions" (pp. 95-96). sional philosophy through the dawning
The status of science in contempo- realization that the traditional tasks
rary philosophy and culture is deeply are not solvable nor worth solving; out-
controversial today and it is so in a side professional philosophy through
positive way. The controversy has led the great outsiders who are recom-
to a breaking of the mortal rigor that mending new ways of reflection and
had increasingly paralyzed the cultural discourse. Rorty gives his case a fine
openness and influence of modern phi- historical sweep and presses it through
losophy. Except for Kisiel, Heidegger detailed, painstaking analyses. One

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

105
should certainly hope that his book will A book that speaks both in a
have its intended liberating effect. liberating and in a fruitful way about
Heidegger, science, and contemporary
And yet Rorty's accomplishment
culture is Patrick Heelan's Space Per-
suffers from its own formalism and pal-
ception and the Philosophy of Science
lor. He finally urges philosophers to
(1983). Here, at last, we have a master-
join again the conversation of human-
ful and definitive synthesis of
ity, and he believes that the health of
phenomenology, Heideggerian her-
that conversation requires openness,
meneutics, and Anglo-American philos-
pluralism, and interesting novelty. But
ophy of science. The Heideggerian in-
must one not reply that this conversa-
spiration comes mainly from the her-
tion is no less ahistorically conceived
meneutic forestructure that is sketched
and no more worthy of our engagement
in Being and Time which corresponds
than modern professional philosophy?
to the existential notion of science men-
And as regards Heidegger particularly,
tioned above. But here, as in so many
is not John Caputo right in complaining
other regards. Being and Time is rich
that Rorty has entirely missed or mis-
and open to the point of ambiguity.
understood the urgency and profound
Heelen repeatedly (pp. 194 and 266)
realism of the later Heidegger's
quotes Heidegger's important addition
thought?^^
to his hermeneutic project which
What has been lost in and through should have forestalled a subjectivist
Rorty's "critique of philosophy" (the or instrumentalist interpretation of his
apt subtitle of the German translation view of science the remark, i.e.,
of The Mirror of Nature) is the deep no- where Heidegger insists that the fore-
tion of experience. In professional phi- structure must be worked out "in terms
losophy experience is the staging area of the things themselves." At the same
for the manoeuvres that are to put phi- time Heelan criticizes the later Heideg-
losophy in sole possession of the foun- ger's confusion of science with its mod-
dations of reality. Rorty's critical dis- ern cultural practice, a confusion that
solution of this sort of philosophical im- moves science too close to technology
perialism at the same time discredits (pp. 17-19, 217, 223). Accordingly,
the concept of experience. The loss of Heelan gives science a realist place
experience in turn prevents the in- within his encompassing and cir-
tended recovery of history. Experience cumspect realism; he calls it "hori-
is our capacity for the unforethinkable zonal" or "hermeneutical" realism.
things and events that constitute the Science within horizonal realism is not
substance of history. Without experi- a threat to our appreciation of reality
ence, history shrinks to the inconse- but an extension and enrichment of our
quential commerce of human subjects, world appreciation.
to the anemic if busy conversation of The real openness and fertility of
humanity that Rorty envisages. In this Heelan's theory of science lies in its
way, sterility threatens to overtake the historical sensitivity though there are,
powerfully liberating movement of at least in Heelan's parlances, traces or
Rorty's book. Not surprisingly, what admixtures of subjectivism and essen-
Rorty has to say (p. 359) about contem- tialism. Reading this text from the his-
porary culture and technology is, torical viewpoint, at any rate, one can
though pointing in the right direction, perceive the outlines of the history of
miniscule and indirect. technology in a way which is consonant

PHILOSOPHY TODAY
with Heidegger's understanding of the sions of Heidegger on technology. We
history of Being and yet discloses im- now turn to this body of scholarship.
portant new vistas and provides needed
corrections. Roughly speaking Heelan's
account of science and of space percep- 2. On Technology: Translation and Exposition
tion outlines and proposes a sequence Beginning in the 1930s Heidegger's
of pretechnological, technological, and thought focuses more and more on
metatechnological spaces and ways of technology as the phenomenon that is
being in the world. Given the project of distinctive of our era and crucial to its
the book, Heelan could not go very far destiny. In his inaugural lecture, "What
in tracing the implications of his views is Metaphysics?" (1929), science and
for technology. The crucial thing is that technology are first explicitly linked
he opens up fruitful possibilities for the and criticized as a way of knowing. The
philosophy of technology, possibilities Introduction to Metaphysics, from 1935
that no longer suffer from a fatally (but not published until 1953), considers
facile and shallow vision of science and technology a central cause of mass so-
history. ciety and planetary exploitation. In the
Another remarkably sensitive and two Nietzsche volumes, based on lec-
clear-headed analysis of Heidegger's tures from the late 1930s and early
view of science which correctly iden- 1940s, technology is prominently as-
tifies the weakness of Rorty's position sociated with the will to power and
(see his note 6) and expresses sym- nihilism. The Letter on Humanism
pathy with Heelan's (see his note 18) is (1947) conceives technology as "in its
David A. Kolb's brief but powerful essence a destiny within the history of
"Heidegger on the Limits of Science" Being" and more specifically as
(1983). Kolb, like Heelan, steers a "grounded in the history of
course between instrumentalism and metaphysics" (p. 220). Holzwege
reductive scientific realism toward (1950), the first post-war collection of
what he terms a "limited scientific essays (all originally composed in the
realism." Not only does Kolb provide 1930s and 1940s) relates technology to
many helpful contrasts between this modern mathematical science and con-
and more standard views as well as di- trasts it with art and poetry. The sec-
rect suggestions about how to think a ond post-war collection, Vortrge und
limited scientific realism in an authen- Aufstze (1954), contains the key essay
tically Heideggerian manner, but he is "The Question Concerning Technology"
also explicitly aware that "the limits of and others, again linking technology to
science are bound up with the larger metaphysics while contrasting it with
problem of technicity, under whose call art, poetry, and non-discursive thought.
science is both done and interpreted" In virtually all subsequent publications
(p. 53), although he does not investi- What is Called Thinking? (1954), The
gate this larger issue at any length. Question of Being (1955), Der Satz vom
Of course, it was not possible or Grund (1957), Identity and Difference
even desirable for the scholarly com- (1957), Discourse on Thinking (1959a),
munity to await the clarification of On the Way to Language (1959b), etc.
Heidegger's view of science before these themes remain prominent. And
turning directly to Heidegger's concern Heidegger's last reported composition
with technology. And there has been a (1977b) asks a conference on his work
steady steam of expositions and discus- to address the issue of technology.

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

107
Thus, although only two essays, Wolfgang Schirmacher's Technik und
viz., "The Question Concerning Tech- Gelassenheit (1983). But in such neglect
nology" and "The Turning" (meaning Heidegger scholars have been doing no
away from technology), are explicitly more than reflecting the larger
devoted to it, technology is a primary philosophical community; the philoso-
issue in all of Heidegger's work sub- phy of technology is only now develop-
sequent to 1930. Yet in Heidegger schol- ing into a vigorous discipline.
arship technology figures as only one In the U.S.A. work on Heidegger's
among many topics, and a rather inci- philosophy of technology has no doubt
dental one. In the two major studies of been further hampered by a lack of
Heidegger's thought as a whole Wil- translations. One important document,
liam J . Richardson's Heidegger: "The Age of the World View," has been
Through Phenomenology to Thought available since 1951. Another, "The
and J . L . Mehta's Martin Heidegger: Principle of Ground," appeared in part
The Way and the Vision'^ technology in 1974. But a translation of the two es-
is conspicuous by its absence. In intro- says explicitly devoted to technology
ductions to Heidegger, Thomas Langan did not appear until 1977 at least
(1959), W. B. Macomber (1967), Werner partly because of a churlish refusal by
Marx (1971), Walter Biemel (1976), Heidegger's English executors to allow
Winfried Krnzen (1976), and George anyone other than the inner circle
Steiner (1979), technology is given rights to translation. Yet it is really
some mention though its treatment re- only in light of these two texts that the
mains perfunctory. More typical are numerous allusions to technology in
Marjorie Grene's complete ignoring of most of Heidegger's late (and even
technology in her article on Heidegger early) work can be adequately ap-
in the Encyclopedia of Philosophy preciated.
(1967) and Arne Naess' (1979) similar A translation of The Question Con-
treatment in The Biographical Supple- cerning Technology and [four] Other
ment to the International Encyclopedia [closely related] Essays was finally
of the Social Sciences. Of three impor- brought to completion by William
tant and representative Heidegger an- Lovitt. This translation project had
thologies that have appeared here and been in the works at least since the late
in Germany, Otto Pggeler's contains 1960s when it was in the hands of Bernd
no contribution on technology at all,'^ Magnus. Lovitt is exceptionally well-
while the two others (Michael Murray, versed in the Heidegger corpus and its
ed., 1978 and Thomas Sheehan, ed., historical background and he is fully
1981), contain only single essays de- aware of the poetic character of
voted in part to technology and in an Heidegger's language and of the prob-
expository manner at that. The newly lems that therefore arise for the trans-
founded annual Heidegger Studies con- lator. Heidegger is extremely sensitive
tains one article on technology in the to the literary connotations of words.
first of the two volumes published so He reawakens diverse relationships
far, Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann's through etymological analysis at the
(1985) "Kunst and Technik." This too is same time that he creates new allu-
an expository piece. Monograph excep- sions and linguistic denotations through
tions to this kind of oversight are quite stipulation and the morphological mod-
recent primarily John Loscerbo's ification of common words. All this is
Being and Technology (1981) and done in part with a pedagogical intent.

PHILOSOPHY TODAY
viz., to embody thought in a rich net- its cognates are used to render the
work of meaning. many related forms of stellen, the root
However, the connotative networks of Gestell, for which they then suggest
of words do not coincide from one lan- "Set" (with a capital S) as a colloquial
guage to another. Thus relative to the and suitably allusive possibility. In a
networks that Heidegger has carefully subsequent translation, in fact,
worked out for the key terms Gestell Mitcham and Jim Grote adopt "setting-
and Bestand any English word will be up" for Gestell (see Andre Malet, 1984,
much impoverished in some significa- in section B, 2 of the bibliography).
tions while possessing a wealth of Similar points could also be made with
others that are unwanted. A translator regard to Bestand, for which "re-
has to choose between a fairly common sources" is a readily available English
word which, being part of our lives, has equivalent.
many helpful connotations along with Lovitt's approach, by contrast, puts
quite a few misleading ones, and a re- artificial roadblocks on the path to a
condite or neologistic word which is un- wider reception of Heidegger's thought
tainted by inappropriate meanings, but on technology, making him appear
also sterile. Lovitt, in translating Ges- more arcane than he really is. (Lovitt's
tell as "enframing" and Bestand as translation is nevertheless preferable
"standing-reserve," follows the latter to the much more outrageous artificial-
course. ity of rendering Gestell by "composi-
This is unfortunate. It is not faithful tion" on the basis of construing "Ge"
to Heidegger, who uses emphatically as "com" and ''steir as "position"
common words in his analysis of tech- which is found in Joseph Fell [1979],
nology, even when he was not always pp. 247ff.) Otherwise the translation is
happy with his own choices. Of Gestell well done. It reflects Heidegger's lapi-
he admits that it is "an expression dary style. Generally it preserves the
which has often been laughed at and is natural flow of his reasoning, although
perhaps somewhat clumsy" (1967a, p. inappropriate reverence toward
278). But the fault, if there is one, lies Heidegger's wording sometimes leads
in the fact that Gestell is too common to awkwardness.'' And it is generous
and homey a word. "Framework" is a with German parentheses and helpful
ready and appropriate word adopted by notes.
Joan Stambaugh (Heidegger, 1957b, pp. Because the translation of "Die
35ff.) and Albert Hofstadter (Heideg- Frage nach der Technik" has been so
ger, 1971, pp. 64 and 84ff.) in translating long in coming and because Heideg-
two other works in which Gestell fig- ger's thought as a whole is alien to the
ures prominently. (For some reason philosophical temperament in the
Stambaugh later abandons this render- United States, it is understandable that
ing in favor of "enframing" [Heideg- many felt called upon to provide
ger, 1973, p. 66].) Carl Mitcham and straightforward expositions of Heideg-
Robert Mackey independently made ger's analysis of technology. Along with
the same suggestion, while drawing at- those to be found in books (see the Lan-
tention to the English phrase gan to Steiner list given above), Magda
"framework of thought" (1972, p. 26). King (1973), Lovitt (1973), and Harold
See also, in this regard, note 14 of the Alderman (1978) all concentrate on
Mitcham-Mackey-CarroU translation of "The Question Concerning Technol-
Simon Moser (1971), where "set" and ogy," providing little more than an En-

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

109
glish paraphrase with a few glosses. ogy," recapitulates Heidegger's analy-
Six articles draw on a larger collection sis of the physis-techne relation, that is
of sources or on some lesser known techne as a response to Being as phys-
essay of Heidegger's, but remain is. It then continues with a discussion of
mostly expository; these are John Sal- the beginnings of modern technology in
lis (1970), Michael Zimmerman (1975, Descartes and its philosophical con-
1977a and b), John Loscerbo (1977), summation with Nietzsche.
Lovitt (1980), and Parvis Emad (1981). Part two, a "First Approach To-
These expositions are careful and ward the Question of the Essence of
generally faithful, but one still has to Modern Technology," contains Los-
wonder what purpose is served by cerbo's analysis of roughly the first
scholarship at the level of Diogenes two-thirds of "The Question Concerning
Laertius. All the same, the availability Technology" (up through paragraph 61,
of some Diogenes Laertius or the first half of p. 24 in Heidegger,
Heideggerianus might have helped 1977a). Loscerbo defers his discussion
Friedrich Dessauer (1956) avoid his of the latter third of Heidegger's essay,
more blatant misinterpretations of which deals with technology as a histor-
Heidegger. And it is still true that ical destiny and "the danger" and "sav-
Heidegger's thought is not easily under- ing power" present in this destiny for
stood and is forbidding in its elaborate part three, a "Second Approach To-
situating of technology in the history of ward the Question of the Essence of
Being. Heidegger's actual analyses of Modern Technology." (It is not clear
technology moreover are radical, prog- why Loscerbo refuses to follow Heideg-
rammatic, and provocative; and while ger's own break in his essay at para-
including brief and telling illustrations graph 59, p. 23 in Heidegger, 1977a.)
drawn from the concrete everyday In both of these discussions of "The
world, they fail to place technology in Question Concerning Technology" Los-
the contemporary social and political cerbo brings in related texts. Two ex-
setting. But paraphrases, summaries, amples of his creative use of otherwise
and synopses do not overcome the overlooked texts in this area: "What
genuine limitations of Heidegger's are Poets for?" (from 1946; included in
work. Instead, they tend to provide a Heidegger, 1971), and "On the Essence
pale and muted version of Heidegger of Truth" (1943; included in David Far-
which, if anything, encourages the sec- rell Krell, ed., 1977).
tarianism that still plagues his recep- Despite its promise and Loscerbo's
tion in America. Explication must be obvious, thorough acquaintance with
coupled with adaptation and applica- the Heidegger corpus, his book is ulti-
tion if this is to be avoided. mately disappointing. It ends abruptly,
The strengths and limitations of the without any real insight, with a boring
conventional expositions are once more and overbearing emphasis that technol-
demonstrated in Loscerbo's monograph ogy must be recognized as Ereignis
on Being and Technology (1981). One (event, happening) a term which,
strength of his book is that, as the title like most others, Loscerbo refuses to
readily implies, it situates technology translate. (Loscerbo likewise has a
at the heart of Heidegger's thought. pedantic propensity for always using
Loscerbo divides his study into three German instead of English titles.) For
parts. Part one, "Preparation for the all those texts it consults, it limits itself
Question Concerning Modern Technol- largely to paraphrase, and it discusses

PHILOSOPHY TODAY
the issues only at the most rarefield the Anglo-American tradition.But his
level of "Being." It refuses to engage analysis of technology continues to be
the wide range of theoretical and prac- ignored in these beginnings despite all
tical issues called forth by Heidegger's the expositions. Merely expository
technology analysis, and confirms the work, moreover, courts the danger of
worst fears about the in-bred character providing unwitting and simplistic re-
of much of Heidegger scholarship. solutions of the ambiguities in Heideg-
With regard to the historical back- ger's position. Surely the way to make
ground of Heidegger's concern with Heidegger's thought on technology ef-
technology, more work is needed. Con- fective and fruitful in the English-
sider Heidegger's explicit acknowledg- speaking world is first to deal with
ment that his turn toward technology in scholarly or social issues that are felt
the 1930s was influenced by Ernst to be crucial in their own right, and
Jnger's Der Arbeiter: Herrschaft und then to show in detail how they are il-
Gestalt (1932). In the winter term of luminated and advanced when Heideg-
1939-1940 he devoted a university semi- ger's insights are brought to bear on
nar to this work. And in a contribution them. Theodore Kisiel (1977) has ven-
to a Jnger Festschrift he wrote that tured efforts in this direction, as have
"'Die Frage nach der Technik' owes Albert Borgmann (1971, 1972, 1978a,
enduring advancement to the descrip- 1980a, and 1984) and the best of those,
tions in Der Arbeiter'' (Heidegger, such as Michael Zimmerman, who are
1955, p. 45; cf. also pp. 43 and 61 and dealing with ecological issues (see his
Heidegger, 1973, p. 85). Although occa- 1983a and 1983b, the latter of which is
sionally remarked, this decisive influ- discussed in section 3 below). Another
ence has gone largely unstudied ex- case in point would be the Canadian
cept for two related and somewhat conservative political philosopher G.
ideologically oriented works, Jean- Grant who, when defending a tradi-
Michel Palmier (1968) and John Orr tional conception of justice against the
(1974).The only available English ultimate challenge of modern technol-
translation from Der Arbeiter is of the ogy, acknowledges the need to rely on
key sections 44-57 on "Technology as Heidegger's understanding of technol-
the Mobilization of the World Through ogy as "the deepest account of moder-
the Gestalt of the Worker" in Mitcham- nity" (Grant, 1974, p. 88). If such en-
Mackey, eds., (1972). What is needed in deavors are successful, readers will on
this area is the kind of in-depth study of their own return to the original Heideg-
Heidegger's philosophical background gerian texts. If such exercises are not
such as has been provided by David possible, Heidegger's thought is incon-
Farrell Krell with regard to the Heideg- sequential at least for now.
ger-Jaspers relationship, by Hermann
Mrchen on the Heidegger-Adorno re- 3. Heidegger Studies in the Philosophy of
lationship,'' and in an unsympathetic Technology and Environmental Ethics
Marxist vein by parts I and III of As suggested above, Heidegger's
Roger Waterhouse's A Heidegger thought requires the test and enrich-
Critique (1981). ment of independent concerns and ex-
Turning finally to the task of adap- periences if it is to gain a wider influ-
tation and application, Heidegger's ence. The encounter with nature in its
thought is beginning to gain some re- wildness has been a formative experi-
spect from prominent philosophers in ence in the self-understanding of this

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

111
country. The second half of this en- Deep, Long-Range Ecology Movement"
counter has taken the shape of the tech- and by Christopher Stone in Should
nological domination and despoliation Trees Have Standing?'^ Heidegger's
of the natural environment. Philoso- thought would be most helpful where
phers of ecology and environmental Stone, for instance, is most perplexed,
ethics in this country have vigorously when he stresses how the anthropocen-
responded to these developments. Ac- tric position is both ethically unsatis-
cordingly one would expect ecology and factory and practically overpowering.'^
environmental ethics to be fruitful Heidegger's thought allows us to see
fields of exchange between American human imperialism within the long his-
philosophy and Heidegger's thought on tory of subjectivism and in the
technology. framework of technology with its re-
George Seidel (1971) is among duction of all natural forces to re-
those who have made a start on this ex- sources.
change. His essay contains the usual
Stone's essay shows how unfortu-
anemic though competent summary
nate is the inability of the many ex-
and exposition of Heidegger's thought,
positors of Heidegger to make his
but only the most tentative application
thought part of the national conversa-
to ecology. More incisive is Joseph
tion. Jurisprudence, the area of Stone's
Grange (1974) who considers magic
concern, is an effective social force in
and sees its supposedly unobtrusive
this country; it is open to philosophical
and careful connection with the proces-
reflection and so should be an appropri-
ses of nature as a counterforce to tech-
ate channel for Heidegger's influence.
nology. Magic is viewed as akin to
Laurence Tribe (1974), an important
Heidegger's notions of letting-things-be
writer in this field as it relates to ecol-
and of care. But for this suggestion to
ogy and technology assessment, is in
be persuasive a more carefully cir-
cumscribed notion of magic would be fact aware of Heidegger (p. 1334) al-
required. One might, after all, take though he makes but limited use of his
magic d la Francis Bacon as a primi- thought.
tive and misguided version of technol- Another point of contact between
ogy. Furthermore, the Heideggerian Heidegger and ecology is the problem
notion of care (Sorge) does not have the of how to inhabit the earth, an issue
uniformly benevolent connotations that environmentalists sometimes dis-
some commentators too quickly attri- cuss under the heading of "reinhabiting
bute to it; often it means something America.'"' Here Heidegger's remarks
more like worried concern. on dwelling (1971, pp. 143-161) are perti-
In a later article Grange (1977) nent. Hwa Yol Jung (1972 and 1974) has
brings Heidegger's thought to bear made helpful use of Heidegger along
more sharply on the problem of ecol- this line. In a later plea written with his
ogy. His distinction between dividend wife (Hwa Yol Jung and Pette Jung,
(anthropocentric) and foundational (re- 1975), his work has become excessively
spectful) ecology is crucial to an analy- preachy though this is less true of a
sis of ecological concern. The distinc- subsequent coathored work (1976)
tion has been drawn elsewhere, how- which attempts to draw political impli-
ever, and in a more provocative, con- cations. Heidegger's words on dwelling
crete, and circumspect manner e.g., have also evoked a forceful response in
by Arne Naess in "The Shallow and the John Caputo (1971) and Paul Colaizzi

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

-I -I o
(1978), with Wolfgang Schirmacher hope that Heidegger's thought will now
(1982b) following suit. become part of a wider conversation.
Given that Heidegger counts for lit- 4. Further Interpretations of
tle in the general intellectual communi- Heidegger's View of Techology
ty of this country, a consequential dis- In addition to the discussions of
cussion of Heidegger and ecology must Heidegger that have been inspired by
attain at least the level of current dis- an ecological concern, there is a vari-
cussions on the foundations of ecology ety of more or less substantial, histori-
before striving to advance the issue. It cal and systematic critiques and de-
is remarkable, for instance, that the velopments of his thought. The variety
customary treatments of Heidegger indicates that Heidegger is becoming a
have failed to impress the Co-Evolution ferment in contemporary thought on
Quarterly (now Whole Earth Review) technology. But the lack of a common
and The Whole Earth Catalog (and its direction in this variety and of well ar-
updates), the most vigorous and well- ticulated and substantial conclusions
read publications in the area of alterna- shows that the reception of Heidegger
tive technology, despite Mitcham's ef- is still in an early phase or that there is
forts to draw Heidegger to the attention no profound and powerful thrust to
of Stewart Brand, the editor and found- Heidegger's view of technology.
ing genius of these enterprises.
Beginning with slender efforts,
Nevertheless, as in the discussion there is A.F. Lingis's proposal (1968) to
of Heidegger's thought on science, explore an approach to technology that
there is now, if not a treatise, a survey differs from Heidegger's. After a spir-
and review that may at last move the ited exposition of Heidegger's view, he
discussion fruitfully forward. Zimmer- points to the "alterity of the other"
man (1983b) in a lengthy article in En- (p. 136) as a phenomenon which resists
vironmental Ethics has provided a technological reduction and may afford
thoughtful, nearly complete account of a point of departure for a more reflec-
the themes and the development of tive discourse about technology. An at-
Heidegger's thought on nature, nature's tempt by Robert Goff (1968) to relate
fate, and on the place of animals and Heidegger and Wittgenstein by means
humans in nature. Drawing on a larger of a philosophical anlaysis of tools fails
study (1981) discussed below, Zimmer- to engage issues in the philosophy of
man shows how Heidegger overcomes technology in any fruitful manner.
the subjective and voluntaristic Dean Franks (1971) uses the distinction
liabilities of his early thought and between the assertorical and prob-
deepens his insight into the mutual be- lematical to illuminate Heidegger's
longing of the natural environment and (1954 and 1966) remarks on technology.
humankind. He defends the later Though the distinction recalls Kant's
Heidegger against the major misun- two types of hypothetical imperative,
derstandings, and although his discus- Frank employs it in an everyday sense.
sion of the literature does not go very Technology is said to be assertorical in
far, he has marked and properly placed pretending to precision, unity, and con-
most of it through footnotes. The scope sistency, thereby hiding its deeply
and quality of Zimmerman's review as questionable or problematical charac-
well as the prominent and appropriate ter. But Frank's muddled and poorly
place of its publication permit one to formulated remarks throw little light

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

113
on this issue. Borgmann's (1975) point, man Dooyeweerd and did his disserta-
influenced by Heidegger, about the im- tion under Hendrik van Riessen, whose
portance of an experience of "the depth Filosophie en Techniek (1949)^''remains
of things" is little more than a sugges- a basic achievement. Schuurman be-
tion. Henning Ottmann (1980) goes gins with a philosophical analysis of
further in these respects by developing technology which sticks close to en-
a concept of praxis as an alternative to gineering experience and perceptions,
technology. and then moves to consider the inter-
Thomas Fay (1977) attempts a pretations of this experience by those
more substantial expansion of Heideg- he styles transcendentalists (Friedrich
ger in his study of the Heideggerian Georg Jnger, Heidegger, Jacques
critique of logic, which he also presents Ellul, Hermann Meyer) and positivists
as a critique of technology. (Norbert Wiener, Karl Steinbuch,
Georg Klaus). Finding both approaches
Thus, linguistic analysis, the de- wanting, he offers his own, religiously
velopment of metalinguistics, and affiliated "liberating perspective."
symbolic logic are all a part of the With Loscerbo (1980), Schuurman
more general movement of the argues that "Heidegger's view of tech-
metaphysics of the 'Will to Will,'
which has produced modern tech- nology cannot be understood in isola-
nology. As Heidegger notes, tion from his entire philosophy of
'metalanguage and the sputnik, Being" (p. 80). Like Loscerbo, he there-
metalinguistics and rocket tech- fore undertakes to situate Heidegger's
nology are really the same thing.' analysis of technology within his
It is the Ge-Stell, the drive toward framework of ontological concerns.
domination, of technicity (Tech- And in this, Schuurman is at least more
nik) which impels it to develop a
language which will be pure in- limpid than Loscerbo although it
strument, that is, formalized lan- does not take much to exceed Loscerbo
guage (pp. 88-89). on this score. However, whereas Los-
cerbo refuses to venture any criticism
Fay's book is not quite as oracular as of the master, Schuurman is perhaps
this passage makes it sound. Indeed, too quick to do so. At the same time, in
the problem is just the opposite; it re- fairness, some of his points are sound:
mains almost wholly at the level of ex- Heidegger's weakness on the history of
position, and again (from the present science and technology, his lack of ap-
perspective) neglects the potentials for preciation of the benefits of technology,
engagement with the philosophy of and the impotence of his responses.
technology. Borgmann (1978b) concen- Overall, however, because of the limi-
trates on symbolic logic as a topic in tations of his particular framework, it
Heidegger's work, claims it to be a is not clear that Schuurman in any sig-
focus of Heidegger's thought on tech- nificant way advances the integration
nology, and attempts to set this focus in of Heidegger into a larger conversa-
wider scholarly and everyday contexts. tion.
A major work with substantial in- Another, quite different effort in
tentions is Egbert Schuurman's Tech- this direction can be found in Carl
nology and the Future (1980). Schuur- Mitcham's state-of-the-art overview of
man is a Dutch engineer, philosopher, "The Philosophy of Technology" (1980)
and now senator who was also a student and a subsequent related essay entitled
of the neo-Calvinist philosophy of Her- "What is the Philosophy of Technol-

PHILOSOPHY TODAY
ogy?" (1985). Mitcham's more descrip- Feeling the world and fucking the
tive placing and counter-posing of world is the only preparation for
Heidegger's analyses to other tradi- death. Authentic embodied exis-
tence is making love to the world
tions in the philosophy of technology . . . Ecstasy, self-transcendence,
aims to defend the basic legitimacy of love-making they all go to-
the hermeneutic and questioning ap- gether. This way of going is our al-
proach. But the actual substantive ternative to bad faith, technology
achievement of this effort remains and death-evasion (p. 92).
slight.
William Barrett (1978) has underta- In the end Colaizzi's book winds up as
ken an extended study of the problems abstract in its heat as more pedestrian
of freedom and technology in contem- expositions in their blandness and as
porary society, and Heidegger's some of the political analyses, yet to be
thought is clearly in evidence. From considered, in their superciliousness.
the reviews, it is also apparent that Webster Hood (1972) sets off
Barrett's work commands attention.'' Heidegger's conception of technology
His analyses are ambitious, often con- against that of Aristotle, to whom he
crete, and sometimes witty. But the credits the traditional idea of technol-
final gains are slim because of the fre- ogy as neutral instrument. This is a
quently cavalier and distracted way in confusing move. In "The Question Con-
which Barrett proceeds. cerning Technology" Heidegger begins
by affirming the correctness of the defi-
Colaizzi's book-length analysis of nition of technology as neutral instru-
technology and dwelling is likewise ment, and then provides an elaborate
strongly influenced by Heidegger. Al- interpretation and illustration of Aristo-
though Colaizzi defines technology tle's fourfold causality in order to ex-
(with Ellul) as "that attitude 'which plore the nature of instrumentality. The
most efficiently effects efficiency in result is precisely to undercut the shal-
some activity'" (p. 8), he attributes its low and conventional understanding of
origin (adapting Heidegger) to "that what an instrument is, and to reveal
endeavor which in bad faith seeks to technology as a kind of substantive
surmount death" (p. 10). Colaizzi then truth. Hood's comparison also errone-
criticizes the common repression of our ously assumes that Heidegger is inter-
awareness of death in a relentless and ested in technology taken in the broad
bitter attack on the establishment of anthropological sense which covers all
psychologists, scientists, professional making and using of artifacts. But tech-
philosophers, politicians, and corporate nology for Heidegger is always modern
executives. In its fervor and its con- technology, and it is pointless to ask
crete illustrations the study clearly how Aristotle understood that.
stands out from among more lackluster With regard to the issue of tech-
scholarly efforts. But the very barrage nological instrumentality, Simon Moser
of accusations is so furious that no (1971, pp. 144-146) has disputed the
energy remains for sustaining the con- adequacy of Heidegger's analysis, but
tentions or penetrating to viable alter- his refutation is little more than a reit-
natives. And his attempt, in the second eration of the conventional wisdom
half, to sketch ways of "dwelling" in Heidegger is calling into question.
the same areas of psychology, philoso- Something similar goes for Dessauer
phy, etc. sounds like a parody: (1956) who, as the founding "philoso-

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

115
pher of technology," was nevertheless and original synthesis and elaboration
the first to isolate Heidegger's analysis of two Heideggerian themes the self,
of technology for special treatment. seen in light of the analysis of Dasein in
Given Hood's assumptions, how- Being and Time, and the epochal char-
ever, it is consistent that in his elabora- acter of Being and its truth. The appli-
tion of Heidegger's theory of technol- cation of this ontology to modern tech-
ogy he should turn to the categories of nology suffers from the Heideggerian
Being and Time which are conceived as confusion of science and technology
timeless a priori structures and thus and from the austerity of Ballard's per-
consonant at least in principle with spective and concepts. It does high-
Hood's largely ahistorical approach. light, however, the impoverishment
The elaboration first sketches five ontic and violent imbalance of the technolog-
(or surface) characteristics: ''technics ical culture. "Technism" is Ballard's
(tools, implements, apparatus, title for the pure and extreme danger
machines), products (consumer and that our age faces, and what Ballard
nonconsumer goods), nature (material has to say about technism can be read
and power), theory (the role of sci- as commentary on Heidegger's
ence), and intersubjectivity (the social framework, one that shows more con-
organization of labor)" (p. 354). To be cretely and in detail how the
sure, these circumscribe a fair re- framework constitutes the ultimate
search program, but Hood does not ad- peril to human existence.
vance it beyond the confines of Being But there is also a significant dis-
and Time and tentative considerations. agreement between Ballard and
He rightly sees that the ontic structures Heidegger on the danger of technology.
require an ontological (or depth) Like most critics of technology, Ballard
grounding. Guided again by Being and adds to his presentations of the subtle
Time he takes such grounding in an and concealed liabilities of technology
existential sense to be the freeing of en- a trumpet call of warning that requires
tities for their being by humans. And little reflection and subtlety to be
the later Heidegger does in fact use a heard. It proclaims the physically self-
similar formula to suggest a way for destructive tendency of technology
dealing with technology: to let things of (pp. 228-233). This is a difficult and
technology be in a spirit of detachment dubious issue for philosophers for two
(1959a, pp. 53-55). But Hood ignores, reasons. First, it is embedded in
first, that Heidegger's grounding of numerous empirical questions that few
technology has sharply divided diag- philosophers take the time to consider,
nostic and therapeutic aspects and, sec- far less to answer. Second, the plain
ond, as regards therapy, that there is urgency or factual straightforwardness
much variety and uncertainty in of this point, if such it is, often seems to
Heidegger as we shall see below. be invoked from a diffidence as regards
In Edward Ballard's Man and the clarity and force of the more com-
Technology (1978), Heidegger's influ- plex and reflective arguments. Heideg-
ence is strong though it remains in the ger, at any rate, sees the danger of
background. The greater part of the technology not in overt self-destruction
book consists of the development of an but in its subtly subversive force,
ontology to guide us "toward the mea- coupled with outward stability and an
surement of a culture," as the subtitle indefinitely long reign (1973, pp. 95-96).
indicates. The ontology is a forceful Accordingly, Heidegger considers the

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

ii
danger of the atom bomb to be secon- intemperate style and peremptory post-
dary (1966, pp. 55-56; 1977a, p.28). ure tend to confirm the worst suspi-
This same problem is at the center cions of Heidegger's critics.
of Wolfang Schirmacher's Technik und And yet the larger program of
Gelassenheit (1983), which is revised Schirmacher's project is eminently
from the second part of his 1980 disser- reasonable and appropriate. His book,
tation with a new introduction and con- as the subtitle says, proposes a "Zeit
clusion. The main body of the text kritik nach Heidegger," a critique of
(pp. 116-230) is an analysis of the basic our times after and according to
principles of Greek and medieval Heidegger. The idea is to be guided by
metaphysics being, time, non-con- Heidegger and to pass beyond his in-
tradition, identity, etc. designed to sights (pp. 11-15). What we are to take
provide the basis for a new approach. from Heidegger is the radicality of his
The force and quite often the heat of his critique of metaphysics and technology,
argument spring from Schirmacher's his attention to the possibility of a turn
conviction that technology has become of affairs, and his recommendation of
lethal or suicidal (pp. 7-36). This simplicity and detachment. But we
danger, he concludes, requires extraor- must go beyond Heidegger in being
dinary radicality of thought. The only more alive to the urgency of our im-
thinkers who come close to such tren- mediate situation and in coming to
chancy are Spinoza, Schopenhauer, and positive terms with technology, in seek-
especially Heidegger. All other at- ing a "technology of life" (pp. 231-261).
tempts, however well-intentioned or In contrast to Schirmacher's fiery
novel (Hans Jonas' among them tract, Phillip Fandozzi provides a
[pp. 236-237]), are waved aside as treatise about and beyond Heidegger
naive, futile, or discredited. But both that is less ambitious and yet spirited,
the beginning and the end of Schir- circumspect, and instructive. In
macher's reasoning are weak. A page Nihilism and Technology: A Heidegge-
of anecdotal evidence (p. 232) and an rian Investigation (1982), Fandozzi con-
occasional reference (p. 14, n. 11) is all fronts Heidegger's position with more
that is adduced to demonstrate the im- or less independent evidence regarding
pending catastrophe. And the final pro- the character of our time, evidence that
posals of reform seem vague or un- is drawn from literature, philosophy,
realistic (pp. 257-259) as has also been and social science. Fandozzi ably
noted by Friedrich Rapp (1984). Should shows that Heidegger's view of the
one object, however, that his proposals modern period as issuing at once in
are not politically feasible, Schir- nihilism and technology is widely trace-
macher is ready with the reply that able and shared. Heidegger's thought,
"the criterion of 'political feasibility' according to Fandozzi, surpasses the
can only be removed, not fulfilled" insights of his contemporaries and pre-
(p. 237; cf. p. 242). By squaring radical- decessors in radicality and comprehen-
ity, Schirmacher renders his position siveness. But it fails to attend
immune to all empirical tests and adequately to features of our time that
reasonable objections. Thus in the de- are evident in the work of others i.e.,
tails of execution, he rejects what the attractiveness of technology and
Heidegger's thought on technology the experience of meaninglessness.
most needs careful testing, elabora- Especially the former of these traits is
tion, and development. Schirmacher's an obvious datum that needs

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

117
philosophical attention, and almost all holds, is not explainable as rule appli-
scholars have overlooked Heidegger's cation.
oversight on this point. In his own detailed analyses, Ihde
The most important work on tech- examines the import of technological
nology of Heideggerian inspiration in instruments on our being-in-the-world,
this country is assembled in Don Ihde's particularly of instruments which serve
Technics and Praxis (1979). It is, as the investigation and information-gather-
author indicates (pp. xxvi-xxviii), a ing purposes. These examinations are
tentative study. It is also a slim vol- inspired by Heidegger's tool analysis,
ume, excessively repetitious, and un- and the most pervasive feature they
settled in its final orientation. And al- discover is an amplification-reduction
though it alludes to much scholarship, structure. Instruments tend to bring
it actually makes use of very little. But one side of a phenomenon sharply and
unlike comparable efforts, it is cos- closely into focus at the expense of
mopolitan in its large views while other sides and of the fullness of experi-
showing care and imagination in detail. ence. This is a significant result that
Ihde traces through the history of could be radicalized, generalized, and
philosophy a division between a preoc- clarified as to its substantive signifi-
cupation with mind, theory, and sci- cance. Ihde stresses that the import of
ence, on the one hand, and with body, technological instruments is "non-neu-
perception, and praxis, on the other tral"; they effect "significant transfor-
(pp. xviii-xxii). He attributes the ne- mations" (1979, pp. 54 and 66). At this
glect of technology as a philosophical level the point may be true but trivial,
problem to the dominance of the and he leaves matters with this vague
former concern, and places Heidegger suggestion. In spite of such reserve,
and his interest with technology Ihde's investigations point up a direc-
squarely on the latter side of this tion of concreteness, patience, and orig-
hiatus. Ihde suggests that praxis, the inality that future research must follow
embodied concern with one's world, to test and elaborate Heidegger's
may be irreducible to theory and at the views. And indeed, Ihde (1983) himself
same time provide the appropriate has already begun to do precisely this.^'
basis for an understanding of technol- Hans Jonas' work may also be
ogy. In a subsequent study on "The His- mentioned in this context because his
torical-Ontological Priority of Technol- contributions to the philosophy of tech-
ogy," included in Existential Technics nology are substantial, and he is well
(1983), a second collection of essays on acquainted with Heidegger. Although
these same themes, Ihde argues this the Festschrift for his 75th birthday^'
issue in still greater detail does not contain an essay devoted to
Ihde thus shares with Hubert the philosophy of technology, it is clear
Dreyfus (1980) the view of Heidegger from his intellectual autobiography
as a proponent of what Dreyfus calls (1974, pp. xi-xviii) that Jonas conceives
"practical holism." According to prac- an "ethics of technology" as the culmi-
tical holism, human being-in-the-world nation of his life's work. His thought
is structured by a background of prac- has moved from a hermeneutics of
tices which cannot be translated into a early Christian theology and gnosticism
set of beliefs, and is therefore not sub- to the philosophy of biology and finally
sumable under a theory. The pivotal to facing "the moral challenges of mod-
phenomenon is skill which, Dreyfus ern technology." Moreover, not only

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

11Q
are Jonas' early historico-theological years later. It contains four previously
studies undertaken under the decisive published essays in the context of a sys-
influence of Heidegger, but his later tematic inquiry, and it begins with a
movement from a philosophy of biology commentary on some lines from Sopho-
to a concern with technology in signifi- cles' Antigone that recalls a commen-
cant ways mirrors Heidegger's transi- tary made by Heidegger four decades
tion from the Being and Time analysis earlier (Heidegger, 1953 [written 1935],
of the life-world to "The Question Con- pp. 123-138). Further, in his ethics of
cerning Technology." technology, with its stress on the con-
In those essays which bear most di- scious exercise of human responsibility
rectly on technology, however, Jonas in the face of awesome powers, one can
acknowledges no debt to Heidegger. detect echoes of Heidegger's proto-ethi-
And in a 1964 essay on Heidegger (see cal notion of resoluteness (see espe-
Jonas, 1964, in section B, 2 of the biblio- cially p. 35). Similarly, the derivation
graphy), apart from specifying the of purposiveness from an analysis of a
early influence of Being and Time, he tool (a hammer) is reminiscent of
presents a sharp nd impassioned Being and Time (pp. 52-53). And, fi-
critique of Heidegger's fundamental nally, Jonas' radical concept of history
position, seeing it as devoid of norms shows Heidegger's abiding influence.
and thus an easy prey to Nazism a On the whole, however, Jonas goes
contention which remains to be touched his own way, and it is a more tradi-
on below. Yet as has been suggested tional and conservative one than
about a 1959 essay, Jonas' analyses of Heidegger's and that of the early
the nature of technology "may be read Jonas. Jonas does stress the unpre-
initially as giving historical content to cedented nature of our situation in his
this [i.e. to what Heidegger calls the] great book. But the novelty is a factual
technological attitude toward the or empirical one; it is the givenness of
world" (IVIitcham and Mackey, 1972, the immense physical and perhaps to-
p. 26; cf. p. 27). In his more metaphysi- tally destructive power that humans
cally oriented analyses (1959, the first have acquired through science and
and third essays of 1974, and 1979), the technology. As mentioned earlier, this
development of modern science is des- overt danger seems secondary to
cribed, in historical particulars, as dis- Heidegger. To be sure, Jonas implicitly
solving the order and firmness of the agrees with Heidegger that technology,
world, thus initiating and serving the at least when taken to Utopian ex-
boundless technological manipulation tremes, suffers from a decisive instrin-
of reality. Jonas brilliantly provides de- sic debility. Jonas shows this in his
tail and substance to Heidegger's thesis critique of Karl Marx's and especially
on the rise of the technological Ernst Bloch's Utopia of a life free from
framework in the modern era, some- labor (pp. 193-198).
thing that Heidegger himself had un- Though Jonas' analysis is impor-
dertaken in the lecture course What is a tant and striking, it unduly restricts the
Thing? (1962). critical examination of technology and
Jonas' magnum opus on The Im- makes it appear as though a technologi-
perative of Responsibility: In Search of cal life where labor is still common and
an Ethics for the Technological Age fi- necessary would remain protected
nally appeared in Germany in 1979 and from the most quesionable force of
in a shorter English translation five technology. In fact the critical edge of

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

119
Jonas' concept of technology is dulled signal contribution not only to the ex-
in this book. Though he refers in pas- tension of Heidegger's thought on tech-
sing to technology in the spirit of his nology but also, in an essay on "Heideg-
third essay from 1974 as a revolution- ger's Philosophy of Technology" (1979,
ary and irresistible force (pp. 127-128), pp. 103-129), to our understanding of its
his hopeful ethics for technology origin in Being and Time. He does so by
clearly requires a more restricted examining the connection between
status for technology, and such a re- Being and Time and "The Question
striction of discovery and knowledge, Concerning Technology." Technology is
needs no fervent hope. And Jonas ap- not a thematic concern of Being and
propriately draws such consequences Time; SO it is remarkable that writers
(pp. 166-169). But at the end he is left such as Grange, Barrett, Colaizzi, and
with a rather bland statement regard- Hood have drawn such extensive inspi-
ing the impact of technology on our ration primarily from this early mag-
lives (p. 169). num opus. Their critical tools are taken
One would have to conclude that mainly from Heidegger's analysis of
Jonas' book is less radical in its analy- "the they," his title for levelled-down,
sis and less concrete in its proposals everyday existence. Positive orienta-
than Heidegger's work, though the lat- tion in the face of the distractions of
ter is in turn much more programmatic technology is taken from Heidegger's
and sketchy than Jonas' considerations. notions of authenticity and resolute-
Moreover, The Imperative of Responsi- ness. As Arne Naess (1979) notes, these
bility is truly a masterwork; it is a are also the Heideggerian categories
book of obvious warmth, wit, and wis- which have been most influential on the
dom, characteristics one would hesitate social science analysis of industrial so-
to ascribe to Heidegger's writings. ciety.
But whereas the significance of
5. Being and Time and Technology Being and Time for an understanding
Not so long ago it was a com- of technology remains largely implicit
monplace of Heidegger scholarship that in the analyses mentioned above, Ihde
the thought of the later Heidegger, broaches the issue directly. The sec-
after he had taken the celebrated turn tions of Being and Time he considers
in his thought during the thirties, con- most relevant center on the tool analy-
stituted his crucial and lasting achieve- sis, which he rightly admires as a
ment. His discussion of technology is model of phenomenological examina-
part of this mature period. But lately tion. There is an obvious connection be-
Being and Time has returned to the tween technology and the handling of
center of scholarly attention, and those tools, certainly just as obvious as that
who have been impressed with Heideg- between "the they" and industrial mass
ger's discussion of technology have society. Ihde elaborates this connection
begun to link it with the early master- by showing how the phenomenological
piece. distinction between noesis and noema
To be sure, of two major English (roughly, attitude and object) is main-
commentators on Being and Time, only tained from Being and Time to the
Richard Schmitt (1969) gives technol- essay on technology. This is a striking
ogy much attention and this in a dis- demonstration of how much continuity
cussion of the relation betwen tools and there is in the craft of Heidegger's
things.^ Don Ihde, however, makes a thinking throughout the profound de-

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

ion
velopments of insight. There are, as grily characterize the attitudes of the
Ihde notes, also differences. The tone of timber and mining interests or the
wholeness and approval in the tool Army Corps of Engineers in precisely
analysis yields to a sharply critical such terms. But to what extent is na-
view of technology; and the distinction ture equally disclosed as resource in
between contemplative science and cir- both craft and modern technology?
cumspective praxis in Being and Time Especially does this become a question
is collapsed in the Gestell which is the when Heidegger immediately observes
origin of both science and technology. that "the botanist's plants are not the
Ihde perhaps overestimates the flowers of the hedgerow; the 'source'
radicality of the early science/praxis which the geographer establishes for a
distinction. Both approaches to reality river is not the 'springhead in the
are, after all, grounded in human exis- dale'" (ibid,).
tence. More important, Ihde seems to Ihde claims (pp. 109-110) that the
misalign the insights of Being and Time later Heidegger plays down the differ-
with those of the later Heidegger. The ences "between scientific technology
later analyses of technology are truly and the older handwork technology."
anticipated in Being and Time with the But he does so only at the highest level
analysis of "the they" an everyday of thought. Both the silversmith's work
existence which exhibits the levelling and that of the electrical engineer are
down, the restlessness, and the aggres- modes of disclosing reality albeit
siveness of modern technology. It is very different ones. Already in 1935
precisely this affinity which accounts Heidegger spoke of "modern,
for the guidance other authors have mathematically structured technology,
found in the they-analysis. The analysis which is something essentially different
of the handling of tools looks at an em- from every other hitherto known use of
phatically premodern technological set- tools" (1953, p. 162; Heidegger's
ting, and thus anticipates the "thing" italics). Wolfgang Schirmacher (1973)
analysis (in 1971, pp. 145-182). Like the has it that Heidegger regarded his
thing, a hand tool is the inconspicuous analysis of the "craftsman society" in
focus of a world. Jug and bridge, two Being and Time as "intentionally ana-
things Heidegger examines at length, chronistic" (p. 387, n. 3). He refers to
as well as horse, bull, plow, and clasp the then unpublished Spiegel interview.
all mentioned as examples of emi- The published version has no such re-
nent things (1971, p. 182) surely mark, although we know from a sample
evoke the same world as that of the page, reproduced in Der Spiegel (May
shoemaker in Being and Time (1927, 31, 1967, p. 3), that Heidegger heavily
p. 95-102 [67-72]). revised the transcript of the interview
As in other regards. Being and for publication.
Time is ambiguous here. Illustrations A more sophisticated and sensitive
are drawn from both the pretechnologi- analysis of what Being and Time has to
cal workshop and the railway station. say about technology is from Hubert
At one point Heidegger says with ap- Dreyfus (1984). Dreyfus begins by lay-
parent approval that for circumspec- ing out the arguments for and against
tive concern "the wood is a forest of the idea that Being and Time promoted
timber, the mountain a quarry of rock; technology in the distinctly modern
the river is water-power . . . " (p. 100 sense. In response, his own hypothesis
[70]). Nowadays, environmentalists an- is that "the analysis of equipment . . .

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

121
is neither pre-technological nor fully Like Ihde, Zimmerman identifies
technological, but rather, that Being two major strands in Western philoso-
and Time plays a transitional role in phy: one theoretical-ontplogical,
the history of the being of equipment" another practical-dramatic. The idea of
(p. 25). authenticity, Zimmerman argues, u
Dreyfus substantiates this thesis by nites these. Heidegger's understanding
constructing from Heidegger's hints a of this concept, which Zimmerman pre-
three-stage history of the being of sents as continuous with others in the
equipment loosely coordinate with the Western philosophical tradition,
epochs in the history of Being. These nevertheless undergoes a deepening
are: (l)the period of craftsmanship ex- and development sometime around
pressed in the Greek notion of techne, 1936. Partly as an outgrowth of his mis-
(2)industrialization and its attitude of taken involvement with Nazism and his
pragmatism, and (3)cybernetic control studies of Nietzsche, Heidegger seeks
articulated in systems theory. Each to purge residual elements of subjec-
period is characterized by a different tivism from his earlier conception of
conception of nature as physis, raw authenticity. Earlier works identify au-
material, and Bestand, respectively thenticity with a willed resoluteness,
as well as different ideals of human use later ones with a detached waiting or
fitting response, needs satisfaction, non-willing. In Being and Time the in-
and exploitation. Read in light of this authentic world of "the they," and
epochal history of Being, ''Being and thereby mass industrial society, seems
Time appears in the history of the to be constituted by an individual re-
being of equipment not just as a transi- fusal of self-knowledge. In the more
tion but as the decisive step towards mature works Heidegger seems to say
techno-logy, (A step Heidegger later "that people are inauthentic because
tries, unconvincingly, to read back into they live in a world where authenticity
Nietzsche)" (p. 32). has become nearly impossible. Inau-
thenticity has become destiny, not
Another important study bearing something elected. In a modern indus-
on the relationship between Being and trial world where everything is under-
Time and technology is Michael Zim- stood to be a commodity, individuals
merman's Eclipse of the Self (1981). treat themselves and others as objects"
This is not just an academic work, but (p. xxv). In making this argument,
one which has grown out of and contrib- Zimmerman, again with Ihde, also
uted to a serious personal search for demonstrates the strong continuity
authenticity. It is also a well-re- within Heidegger's development.
searched analysis of the concept of au- So does Fandozzi, who also sees in
thenticity as it develops in Heidegger. the inauthenticity of "the they" the fea-
As such it renews and explicitly formu- tures of technological everyday exis-
lates the issue of the relevance of the tence (1982, pp. 74-79) which is charac-
they-analysis to the understanding of terized by a superficiality that oscil-
the technological society. Ironically, lates between tranquillity and busy-
Zimmerman's conclusion implies that ness. But if we see the phenomenon of
Heidegger's later conception of inau- technology as it emerges in Being and
thenticity may be more adequate for Time together with the rise of nihilism
grasping the character of technological as pictured in non-Heideggerian ac-
life than that found in Being and Time. counts, it appears, so Fandozzi argues.

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

199
that Heidegger's notion of inauthentic- Reinhart Maurer picks up Gnter
ity fails to account for the attractive- Rohrmoser's (1969) idea of Marcuse as
ness of technology, and it also becomes "the applied Heidegger" (1970, pp. 239
evident that the authenticity of anxiety 240) in the sense that Marcuse provides
and resoluteness is not the only possible a parallel in social philosophy to
countermove to inauthenticity (pp. 117 Heidegger's philosophical theory. By
121). Fandozzi goes on to explicate way of agreement, Modesto Berciano
from the interstices of the arguments in (1980) presents Marcuse as "the pre-
Being and Time a mode of inauthentic- mier Marxist Heideggerian" who has
ity which revels in the procurement nevertheless overlooked Heideggerian
and gratification of unlimited pos- notions which could be of use to Marx-
sibilities and a counterexperience of ism. Heidegger and Marcuse agree in
meaninglessness in which the futility their analysis of modern technology as
and vacuity of technology begin to an- an eroding and levelling force. But,
nounce themselves (pp. 121-129). Maurer contends, Heidegger leaves his
proposals for reform at the level of an
individualistic ethics (pp. 242 and 243)
6. Heidegger, Marcuse, and Marx whereas Marcuse presses for social
Work on Heidegger and Herbert transformation, calling for a new sci-
Marcuse stands at the borderline of ence and technology (pp. 243-245). It re-
problems of technology and politics. mains unclear, however, whether this
What Heidegger's and Marcuse's inves- means merely a redirection of present
tigations have in common is a recogni- science and technology or a basic re-
tion of technology as a fundamental structuring; and if the latter, it is even
philosophical problem. But Marcuse's less clear how such a stupendous enter-
decided and widely discussed political prise could be initiated other than by a
views inevitably link reflections on more personal alteration in thought and
technology to those of politics. In his attitude.
most patently political book Marcuse, Theodore Kisiel (1970b) provides
following the Frankfurt School of social the best outline of this arguement be-
theory, criticizes social science tween hermeneutic philosophy (in the
positivism in a fashion which exhibits tradition of Husserl-Heidegger-
many similarities to Heidegger's criti- Gadamer) and critical social theory
cisms of metaphysical thinking. At one (Marx-Marcuse-Habermas-Apel). Is
point, in fact, he quotes Heidegger with the real way out of modern scientific-
approval (1964, pp. 153-154) although technological domination some recon-
the Frankfurt School thinks little of the struction of theory, or is it social
later Heidegger and less of his politics, praxis? "It seems that phenomenology
early or late.'' Yet as Rolf Ahlers (1971, stands or falls on its commitment to the
p. 585), Michael Zimmerman (1979a, priority of receptivity, which strikes
p. 246), and Roger Waterhouse (1981, Marcuse as 'quietistic indifference'"
pp. 115ff.) all remind us, at one point (Kisiel, 1970b, p. 159). Be that as it
Marcuse considered Heidegger the may, Maurer shows that Marcuse has
most fundamental influence on his own been uncertain and unpersuasive in de-
position (cf. also Marcuse, 1977a and limiting the social classes or groups
1977b, pp. 28 and 37). And Zimmerman who could initiate reform.
at least sees a continued dependence of Paul Piccone and Alexander Delfini
Marcuse on Heidegger. (1970) likewise see a dependence of

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

123
Marcuse on Heidegger, but in entirely Marcuse's student, William Leiss, ar-
negative terms. For them Being and gues that despite "certain inconsisten-
Time is an apology for bourgeois soci- cies in Marcuse's work" he comes
ety, influenced by and aimed at the down finally in favor of an instrumental
early Georg Lukacs (p. 39). The first view of technology, contemporary prob-
part of this thesis goes back to Lukacs lems being the result of a corruption of
himself and the initial attempt by a historically specific social structures.'^
Marxist to develop a comprehensive Patrick Murray (1982), however, main-
critique of Heidegger.'^ The second part tains that Marcuse's most fundamental
is left unsubstantiated. Piccone and insight concerns the need for a qualita-
Delfini's portrayal of Heidegger's view tively new science and technology, one
is one-sided and marred by serious er- which transcends the limitations of En-
rors, which has earned them the con- lightenment conceptions of rationality.
tempt of Zimmerman (1979a, p. 262, In a comparison of the Frankfurt
n. 42) though he makes no attempt to School's critique of instrumental reason
discuss their substantive issues. In with Heidegger's critique of science
their view, Marcuse's One-Dimensional and technology, Murray points up sig-
Man recapitulates Heidegger's analysis nificant similarities: both identify sci-
of "the they," and in seeking to under- ence with technology, conclude that sci-
cut the material basis of society, Mar- ence is inherently dominating, and find
cuse loses the foundation of a genuine seeds of the technological attitude to-
and penetrating dialectical analysis. ward the world in Greek philosophy. He
Along this same line one should cite could also have noted that the "level-
Valentino Gerratana (1977), who di- ling" of the world by "subjective" or in-
rectly compares Heidegger and Marx strumental reason as analyzed by the
by means of a sarcastic castigation of founders of the Frankfurt School'^ re-
Heidegger as a romantic, reactionary sembles Heidegger's Bestand as
critic of capitalism and technology. grounded in the Gestell; that "objec-
Maurer's circumspective essay tive" reason or Kantian Vernunft ap-
should have laid the foundations for pealed to by Horkheimer-Adorno is
more advanced and systematic assess- functionally parallel to Heidegger's
ments of the common concerns of Denken; and that in the end Hor-
Heidegger and Marcuse; Piccone and kheimer, Adorno, Marcuse, and
Delfini's article, perhaps just because Heidegger (like Kant before them) all
of its breezy and facile one-sidedness, turn for salvation to art and the aesthe-
might have served as a stimulus to tic experience.
such developments. The creative ele- These points have now been sub-
ment, however, has been all on the side stantiated in great depth and detail as
of Marcuse scholarship. Jrgen Haber- regards the relationship of Heidegger
mas, for instance, in "Technology and and Adorno in a 1980 study by Hermann
Science as 'Ideology'" (1970) has Mrchen which traces the theme of
shown incisively and in a helpfully power and domination through the writ-
elaborate historical context how Mar- ings of the two thinkers. In a second
cuse wavers between a radical concept book, published in 1981,'^ Mrchen at-
of technology as incorporating a specif- tempts posthumously to engage Adorno
ic form of political domination and and Heidegger in the dialogue they had
technology as a neutral means which in different ways refused to enter (see
can serve whatever political purposes. Schirmacher 1982a, pp. 387-391). The

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

194
convergence of thought that underUes material in footnotes. As Zimmerman
Adorno's polemics and Heidegger's himself modestly admits (p. 246), it
total silence shows that Marcuse's oc- nevertheless remains "not . . . much
casional abandonment of the Enlighten- more than an introduction," although
ment commitment to the instrumental perhaps one of the best.
neutrality of science and technology is The idea, alluded to above, that
not without parallel in the Frankfurt Being and Time is a response to
School, and the complaint of Hans-Die- Lukacs' History and Class Conscious-
ter Bahr that it is all the fault of ness (1923) requires further considera-
Heidegger's influence is not accurate.^^ tion. This is a possibility considered
In this area as in others, then, and questioned by Kostas Axelos (1966,
Heidegger scholarship has remained on pp. 9-10, n. 6) and touched on by Zim-
a provincial or expository level, except- merman (1979b, p. 259, n. 10). But its
ing the work of Mrchen who wrote his most detailed support is to be found in
dissertation under Heidegger in 1928 Lucien Goldmann (1977), who specifies
(Schirmacher, 1982a, p. 389). On the three places in Being and Time where
specific topic of Heidegger and Mar- he thinks Heidegger has referred to
cuse, Ahlers' article continues as a Lukacs' History and Class Conscious-
pioneering effort, supporting Maurer's ness. There is no independent evidence
findings, which have become the ac- that Heidegger had read Lukacs at that
cepted view of the matter. Yet although time. But certainly it is true that there
Ahlers discusses Heidegger's critique are remarkable similarities in the at-
of science and the limitations of his tempts of both philosophers to over-
political views, he fails to take up the come the subject/object dichotomy in-
extensive and helpful prior work of herited from Cartesianism Lukacs
Karlfried Grnder (1962) and Alexan- by an appeal to social praxis, Heideg-
der Schwan (1965). Hans Sachsse (1973) ger to practical engagements with
presents another brief and balanced ex- things. For Lukacs the encounter be-
position of Heidegger and Marcuse on tween human beings and social entities
technology which is of interest for its (from economic goods to institutions
emphasis on Marcuse's persistent be- and cultures) is different in kind from
lief in the perfectibility of technology that between human beings and natural
(p. 375), a point made before by Mauer objects; it is also phenomenologically
(1970, p. 242). Efraim Shmueli (1975) richer and more primary than Zuhan-
advances against both Heidegger and denheit. Social entities are reified per-
Marcuse the charge that they fail to ap- sonality while humans themselves are
preciate the real achievements of tech- historical creatures from the moment
nology how it strengthens philosophi- of their birth-encounters with their par-
cal reflection by making it at once ents (and the parental histories).
more possible and necessary. In fact, Knowing subject and object known are
this is a persisitent theme directed by moments of a social history and thus
more vulgar Marxist and other critics dialectically interrelated.
against Heidegger as well as against Goldmann's own sympathy with
anyone else who questions technology. Lukacs and his criticism of Heidegger
Finally, Zimmerman's exposition for lacking any true conception of so-
(1979a) draws on more primary cial encounter or action ignore Lukacs'
sources than some previous work, and repudiation of his own early work. It
acknowledges much of the secondary fails to take seriously Marx's own occa-

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

125
sional statements in support of the pri- short, pithy, and appreciative state-
macy of technopraxis.^' And it neglects ments Heidegger has made about
to show how the practical engagements Marx. For Heidegger, Marx is one of
with things or the theoretical encounter the most perceptive witnesses of the
with natural objects can be grounded in modern era, but one who fails to pene-
socio-praxis. The critical issue is car- trate and understand what he sees.
ried forward, however, by Waterhouse, Axelos draws from the Marxist corpus
who points to a lack of symmetry in to illustrate the kinship of Heidegger's
Heidegger when he provides for "no and Marx's concern with the alienating
genuine initial relationship to people, force of technology. Axelos' own specu-
corresponding to the ready-to-hand re- lations throughout the book move at the
lationship to things" (1981, p. 174). For highest level of Heidegger's thought,
Waterhouse, where the history and destiny of Being
are at issue; his reflections are also
The shift from practical, engaged elegant and witty in an intellectual
involvement with things to disin- vein. But one is much reminded of
terested, unengaged, manipulation Kant's strictures against dogmatic
is an aspect of a fundamental so- thought which indulges in great claims
cial change the penetration of a
precapitalist economy by a value without regard to possible experience.
system based only on cash. The Axelos is cautious in his own way, to be
shift is not due, as Heidegger be- sure. His thesis, if there is one, is that
lieves, to some moral decline the essence of technology and the des-
caused by the corrupt ideology of tiny of Being are yet to be thought.
science, but to economic factors Still, Heideggerian exercises of this
which Heidegger does not begin to sublime sort readily deteriorate into a
understand (pp. 172-173).
game whose principal rule is one-up-
Goldmann and Waterhouse thus con- manship, an implicit contempt of those
firm the primacy of Marxist scholar- who are ignorant of the distinction be-
ship in the area of the Heidegger/Marx tween Being and beings; who plan, or-
relationship. There simply is no ganize, and do research; who believe in
Heideggerian critique of Capital com- scientifically ascertainable truth and a
parable to Waterhouse's critique of transcendent good.
Being and Time unless one stretches No one, of course, has been bolder
things and counts Jean-Paul Sartre's than Heidegger in the endeavor to
Critique of Dialectical Reason.^^ This penetrate the highest and most
undercuts Richard T. DeGeorge's ear- abstract matters of Being, time, and
lier (1965) complaint about the inade- thought. But Heidegger was always an
quacy of the Marxist response to explorer. He never simply put the lan-
Heidegger although it remains true guage of Being through its rhetorical
that Soviet and East European criti- paces. Many of his explorations ended
cisms are "shallow, polemical, beside in failure, no doubt. Moreover, the en-
the point, and poor Marxism" (p. 294). terprise remained for him questiona-
This remark leads us, finally, to the re- ble. He was always determined to face
lation of Heidegger's thought on tech- up to concrete reality, to gain "Insight
nology to Marx himself. into That Which Is," as he entitled the
Kostas Axelos in the lead essay series of his most important lectures on
(1966, pp. 3-42) of his collection on technology (1977, p. ix). In the seminar
Marx and Heidegger assembles the on Heraclitus conducted with Eugen

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

19
Fink in his last years, it is the old Jacques Ellul can be read as support-
Heidegger, not Fink or the students, ing Heidegger's thesis on both points,
who insists on immediacy and con- and that Ellul has given the Marxists a
creteness and a regard for the scien- much more serious reading than they
tific and technological world (Heideg- have given him.^ The Marxist treat-
ger and Fink, 1979, pp. 12-14, 71-73, 87 ment of Ellul is nothing short of a scan-
88, 109, 127, 137 ff., 158 ff.). The refer- dal of scholarship that continues to go
ences to concrete phenomena are never unreported, and one to which followers
more than exemplary and provocative, of Heidegger would do well to call at-
but they are crucial elements in tention.
Heidegger's thought.
Like his essay on Heidegger and 7. Technology and Politics
Marcuse, Zimmerman's (1979b) article For many, Heidegger's involve-
on Marx and Heidegger is as sober as ment with the Nazi movement in 1933
Axelos' book is flighty. Its virtue is that 1934 is the focus for judging both his
it does remain close to the ground. For philosophy and his politics. Discussion
one who is uninformed in either Marx, of this issue surfaced in France im-
Heidegger, or modern technology it mediately after World War II,"' no
provides an initial orientation, sketch- doubt partly because it was the French
ing the positions of the two thinkers, who occupied southern Germany and
drawing together apposite quotations, thus supervised and ratified the de
and alluding to many of the pertinent Nazification proceedings which tempo-
secondary sources (though not, for rarily deprived Heidegger of his right
some reason, to Axelos' contribution). to teach.^' Discussion revived in the late
But scholars who are conversant with 1960s,at which time it was also taken
any of the three foci will not be aided in up again in the United States.
their area of expertise. Such expository Some of Heidegger's critics have
work continues to be justified only by taken his brief foray into politics to be
the current primitive state of relevant incontrovertible evidence for the va-
scholarship. In a later article evi- cuity at best and fraudulence at worst
dently part of a series on the relation of his work. Alexander Schawn (1974,
between Heidegger and Marx or the p. 151, note 15) and Reiner Schrmann
neo-Marxists Zimmerman (1984) (1978, pp. 193-194, notes 4 and 5) pro-
examines the work of Karel Kosik and vide ready references to and brief dis-
his appropriation of certain themes cussions of this school of thought
from Heidegger. Zimmerman's deft ex- which has been strongly restated by
position once again confirms the Henry Pachter (1976), Stephen Eric
superior creativity of Marxists over Bronner (1977), and Roger Kimball
Heideggerian scholarship in this area. (1985). This position has been wreathed
The two central and related issues with unintentional irony by Stanley
between Heidegger and Marx the Rosen (1969 in section B, 2 of the biblio-
relative primacy of techno-praxis ver- graphy, especially p. 119) who argues
sus socio-praxis, and technology as the prominent influence of the anti-Nazi
Gestell versus technology as economic nihilist Ernst Jnger, and Leo Strauss
formations remain to be addressed (1971, p. 2) who implies a comparison
in depth from a Heideggerian perspec- between Heidegger's political involve-
tive. It can be noted in passing, how- ments and Husserl's conversion to
ever, that the sociological studies of Christianity.

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

127
Pachter's more popular "Heideg- political sensibility. Bronner is also
ger and Hitler: The Incompatability right in scoring Heidegger's and his fol-
[sic] of Geist and Politics" (1976) re- lowers' tendency to skip needed clarifi-
minds us of the deeply corrupting force cations through a retreat to a misty and
that the Nazi ideology had on German occasionally haughty mysticism.
culture and literature and of the dis- But so far, nothing of consequence
tressing lack of judgment or integrity has been decided. And on the substan-
among many of the writers and artists tive points, Bronner is as likely mista-
of the time. Pachter also shows that the ken as Pachter. Brenner's distinctive
murky and contemptuous spirit of the claim that Heidegger in the face of a
Nazis did not come from nowhere. And troubling social and political world re-
surely Heidegger's thought and ways of treated to an ahistorical and transcen-
speaking were not immune to these de- dent concept of Being (1977, pp. 155-57,
plorable tendencies of the intellectual 162) is extraordinarily wrong-headed.
life of Germany. But Pachter goes How does this claim accord with
much further and tries to show that the Heidegger's thought on modern tech-
work of the early and middle Heidegger nology? Bronner (1977, p. 157) replies
drew its central inspiration from this with a single passage from Heidegger's
unenlightened, misanthropic, ir- essay "Gelassenheit" (1959a).
rationalism and vigorously promoted it. This is typical of Brenner's selec-
To substantiate this Pachter must re- tive and disjointed reading of Heideg
sort to clearly mistaken and tenden- ger. Brenner's scholarship is really de-
tious readings of Heidegger. Thus plorable. But again he is right (1979) in
Heidegger's analysis of "the they" is replying to Thomas Sheehan's (1979)
denounced as contempt for common dissections and vitriolics that his thesis
people (pp. 52-53). In light of the cannot be dismissed on technical
critique of contemporary culture to be points. How then is a controversy like
mentioned below, as well as in the con- this to be settled? Surely no knock-
text of Heidegger's own later writing, down drag-out resolution is possible,
Pachter's interpretation appears en- far less desirable. The emphasis must
tirely one-sided. Similarly, when one shift from whether Heidegger is right
considers the work of thinkers such as or wrong to what matters as regards
Roberto IVlangabeira Unger, Alasdaii our time and its well-being. Dispute
]V[acIntjn:-e,'' and Richard Rorty (1979), should yield to conversation, and
one would hesitate to join Pachter in Heidegger should be brought into the
thinking (pp. 52 and 54) that a critique latter as one from whom we have learn-
of the Enlightenment and its concept of ed or whose harmful influence we
reason and humanism must be insidi- should guard against.
ous on its face. The possibility of harm seems neg-
Bronner (1977) urges much the ligible when we consider Heidegger's
same claims as Pachter though with standing in the conversation of human-
greater attention to Heidegger's writ- ity. He is simply not heard in any
ings and less familiarity with their cul- forum that really matters. This is cer-
tural context. He properly emphasizes tainly to the detriment of the universe
Heidegger's petty-bourgeois back- of political discourse. Provided he is
ground which, as Heidegger's student ever to be heard in that universe, his
and friend IVEax IVIller agrees (1986, contribution will be received more
pp. 16-17), has influenced Heidegger's clearly and readily if the nature and

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

128
circumstances of his entry into the however, Heidegger did not promote
political arena in 1933-1934 are fully un- the Nazis' party program. His own plan
derstood. was inspired by the misgivings and as-
Undoubtedly Heidegger's reception pirations that he later worked out in his
in the scholarly community of this critique of technology and suggestions
country was so late and slow because of for reform. But at the time his project
lack of information and because of mis- was vague and fraught with am-
information about his involvement with biguities. It appears to have left little if
the Nazi regime. The relevant facts any impression on the reshaping of the
continue to be ascertained and ap- German universities under Hitler.*^
praised. Beda Allemann's paper (1969) Still, to the Nazi authorities it was suffi-
presents a summary and review of ciently puzzling or troubling to lead to
what was known by the late sixties. In Heidegger's isolation and to his break
1972 Karl A. Moehling in his disserta- with the Nazis in 1934. Ott's account is
tion reviewed and reproduced hitherto gaining wide acceptance in Germany
unknown documents from official files but appears to be slow in finding its
and from Heidegger's pen. A summary way into this country.'^
of the dissertation appears in Sheehan's On the personal side, it is difficult
anthology of 1981 (pp. 31-43). In 1976, to be just in one's appraisal. With nota-
Der Spiegel published an interview of ble exceptions, Heidegger does not
Heidegger's given in 1966, in which seem to have been mean-spirited, vin-
Heidegger once more defended his in- dictive, or antisemitic during his al-
volvement with the Nazis. In 1981 Jas- liance with the Nazis. Neither did he
pers' opinion of this affair came to show good judgment or moral courage
light.'' An earlier written defense of (Mller, 1986, p. 28). He was naive to
Heidegger's from 1945-1946 along with the point of being culpable and at a cru-
his inaugural address as rector of the cial moment lent his influence to a per-
University of Freiburg in 1933 was pub- nicious movement. Yet finally, as G.
lished in 1983 by his son Hermann (see Steiner (1978, pp. 166ff.) points out,
Heidegger, 1933 for details). The most what is most distressing is not the in-
painstaking work is being done by Hugo volvement with the Nazis, but Heideg-
Ott who has been uncovering material ger's failure later to denounce the at-
to this day (and has lately announced a rocities of the Third Reich. Carl Fried-
book on the subject); and there is fi- rich von Weizcker, Max Mller, and
nally a measured and insightful apprai- Ute Guzzoni similarly have deplored
sal of the evidence by Otto Pggeler.'^ Heidegger's refusal to recognize his
Ott's research should move both error and to apologize for it.^^ Others in
the friends and the foes of Heidegger to his position, Albert Speer, e.g.,^' have
revise their standard position. The admitted their mistakes. But Heidegger
former have followed Heidegger in to the end wavered between aloof si-
claiming that he reluctantly and on the lence and defensive statements that
entreaties of Nazi opponents took on the contain self-serving inaccuracies.
burden of the rectorate to save what Inevitably the personal failures
could be saved. In fact, however, shade over into philosophical ones. For
Heidegger intended to use the Nazis' Kimball (1985) Heidegger's "sub-
rise to power as a vehicle to reform the sequent withdrawal from political ac-
German university system and German tivity is even more questionable than
culture itself. Contrary to his critics. his brief period of political engage-

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

129
ment" (p. 17) and reveals Heidegger's epoch as does the work of the great
despair at being unable to influence thinker or of the artist. And Schwan
technology politically. But even if with further shows that Heidegger sees the
Heidegger one were to insist on the present era as incapable of great politi-
priority and dignity of thought over cal work just as it is unable to create a
against political activism, there would great, i.e., epochal, work of art.
remain the need to consider reflec- Schwan's analysis has two interre-
tively the significance of the Nazi reign lated shortcomings: he pays little at-
of terror within the history of Being and tention to Being and Time and does not
technology. After all, Heidegger in the give technology its due. In the chapter
Nietzsche volumes (1961) devoted hun- which summarizes Heidegger's apprai-
dreds of pages to the analysis of sal of the contemporary political situa-
nihilism and the will to power. And he tion (1965, pp. 126-145), Schwan stresses
has adverted to concrete phenomena the pointless and hopeless uniformity
such as the atom bomb (1971, p. 166), that Heidegger sees beneath the varied,
cybernetics (1966, p. 58), and rocket well-intentioned, and apparently con-
bases (1976a, p. 277) as manifestations trary political currents. Technology is
of the calamity of technology. In fact, examined later and more incidentally
there are passing remarks of Heideg- (pp. 146-150). Schwan sees this unifor-
ger's on the connection between Nazi mity in the context of the history of
ideology and technology (1953, p. 166; Being as the final result of
1976a, p. 280; 1977a, p. 152). But the metaphysics, of the restless will to will
thinker who has so often scored the and its calculative thinking. But as em-
forgetfulness of the Western tradition phasized earlier, Heidegger also turns
appears to have been entirely oblivious directly to an analysis of the character
to the holocaust, an event that has sha- of our time, and though that investiga-
ken the foundations of hope and reason tion is informed by his view of the his-
in the 20th century.'^ tory of Being, it has its own dignity and
Those who defend Heidegger's ac- terminology.
tions as a limited or inconsequential As Pggeler (1972, p. 45) stresses,
mistake^' argue that his philosophical Heidegger's sole question, the question
work at this time was either politically of Being, is for the modern era the
neutral or should have suggested a dif- question of technology. This question,
ferent political course. Heidegger him- as Heidegger (1976a, p. 279) implies,
self is on record as proclaiming the requires its own approach: "The tradi-
apolitical nature not only of his own tional metaphysical mode of thinking,
thought but of all philosophy. Schwan which terminated with Nietzsche, no
rejects such arguments (1974, pp. 150 longer offers any possibility for ex-
151). His earlier book (1965) has the periencing in a thoughtful way the fun-
general merit of establishing that, con- damental traits of the technological
trary to initial appearances, there is age, an age which is just beginning."
something like a pervasive political Pggeler (p. 45) rightly holds that the
philosophy in Heidegger's thought. idiosyncrasy of the task allows us in
More specifically, it has shown that some degree to disengage the analysis
Heidegger thinks of traditional politics of technology from the review of the
as the working out of truth; the deci- history of Being. Schwan doubts this
sive political deed of a great leader or (1974, p. 160); but even if Schwan is
statesman defines the character of an correct, it remains true that Heideg-

PHILOSOPHY TODAY
ger's critique of the modern age, seen 251-252). If we recognize "Heidegger's
only from the viewpoint of blindness to the peculiar features of so-
metaphysics, must appear peremptory cial phenomena" (p. 252), we can un-
and one-sided. It becomes provocative derstand his turn to the Nazi move-
and instructive only when his reflec- ment. Its totalitarianism is just the de-
tions on technology are given proper at- nial of a social realm of freedom, and
tention. Heidegger, calling the people to reso-
When this is done, one can also luteness, treats society as if it were one
begin to see some political relevance in individual (pp. 251-252).
Being and Time. Heidegger's early Michael Zimmerman, though
book is deeply ambiguous, and had he deeply sympathetic to Heidegger's phi-
published nothing more, we would be losophy, sees an analogous susceptibil-
hopelessly puzzled about Heidegger's ity of Being and Time to Nazi ideology
judgment of the contemporary world. (1974).
To draw out the political import of
Being and Time without reference to At one point. National Socialism
the later Heidegger may yield an inter- might have seemed to offer to re-
pretation which agrees with the text solute, owned Dasein a vision into
the authentic destiny of Germany.
and provides something like an expla- That this was emphatically not the
nation of why Heidegger supported the case came only gradually to be
Nazis. But if it is at odds with the later evident in his 1930's; to have sup-
Heidegger's thought, such an interpre- posed it to have been the case in
tation certainly fails to be faithful to the early 1930's can only mean
Heidegger's philosophy as a whole. The that owned Dasein can make mis-
problem is, of course, not just one of takes (p. 104).
consistency and scholarship. If the
later Heidegger's thought casts impor- Although Schmitt's view of the re-
tant light on the character of our time, lation between individual existence and
then those interpretations of Being and "the they" can be supported textually,
Time which are consonant with the other readings are also available. In a
later thought are more likely to do the sense, "the they" is prior to the indi-
same. vidual. The individual exists first, most
By contrast, Richard Schmitt's of all, and often forever in the mode of
(1969) reading of the social import of "the they" (1927, p. 167 [129]). And
Being and Time takes no guidance though the analysis of "the they" is
from the later Heidegger. He recog- sharply critical in its tone, Heidegger
nizes that Being and Time addresses insists, as he has done throughout his
social phenomena in the analysis of career, that his purpose is reflection,
"the they" and of being-with. But such not evaluation. Inauthenticity, he says
social phenomena, Schmitt argues, are (and "the they" is a mode of it), is not
always seen as more or less degenerate a lesser or lower kind of being (1927,
modes of individual existence. Heideg- p. 68 [43]).
ger fails to see the distinction between It is not enough, however, to show
social practices (which, we might say, that Schmitt's interpretation is one-
afford a possibility space) and the use sided. We must determine why this is
an individual makes of them (the ac- so. One reason, to be sure, is that it al-
tualization of a particular location with- lows Schmitt to undercut an anarchist
in the possibility space) (pp. 245 and reading of Being and Time which, he

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

131
admits (p. 250), is at first sight much currents, is surely designed to move
more consonant with the analysis of au- critical reflection to a deeper level.
thentic individual existence, but would This call to radical criticism will
throw no light at all on Heidegger's seem vacuous, however, if not arro-
political involvement of 1933. More im- gant^ unless one remembers that under
portant, what appears to guide the title of technology Heidegger has
Schmitt's critique is the liberal demo- given an instructive, concrete outline of
cratic notion of the state.^^ In this view how to proceed. Pggeler urges this
the state is to provide the means (a point (1972, pp. 44-45 and 59-60), though
possibility space) for the good life, but without helpful elaboration and there-
is not to prejudge in any way the indi- fore, perhaps, unconvincingly. Schwan,
vidual ends to be served by those at any rate and not surprisingly, sees in
means. The good life is a matter of in- the question of technology merely an
dividual choice, of how one decides to aspect of the question of Being.
actualize the opportunities afforded by Wolfgang Schirmacher (1973), by con-
the state. Such is also Schwan's orien- trast, has energetically pleaded the so-
tation, and it comes clearly to the sur- cial relevance of Heidegger's critique
face in his list of the central problems of technology. But neither here nor in
of a practical (i.e., moral, social, and Schirmacher's later book (1983a) is
political) philosophy (1974, p. 171). Both there a hint of how Heidegger's propo-
Schmitt and Schwan correctly sense sal is to be elaborated; far less is there
that Heidegger, early and late, has re- any indication of how it could lead to
servations about this conception of the the "design for social action" which
state, and those doubts are radically Schirmacher announced in 1973.
formulated but only implicitly sup- We can connect Heidegger's analy-
ported in Heidegger's thought. sis of technology more specifically with
One can criticize liberal democracy the concept of liberal democracy by
either because it fails to live up to its saying that the latter has been sub-
own standards, or because it is al- verted or perhaps specified by technol-
together mistaken. Criticism and prati- ogy (in Heidegger's sense), and as such
cal reforms at the former level may be the liberal state is far from neutral as
urgent and worthy of our best efforts. regards the good life (as if, indeed, any
But Heidegger dismisses them one and state could ever exhibit such neutral-
all, to which Schwan reacts with indig- ity). Rather, contemporary liberalism
nation and also with a certain glee be- promotes and all but enforces a novel
cause he takes Heidegger's dismissal and peculiar way of living. The they
as evidence of the political and social analysis in Being and Time, as seen
barrenness of his thought. Heidegger above, traces important and still
throughout his career has used the noteworthy features of the resulting so-
dubious pedagogical device of exasper- ciety. Dreyfus (1980) makes this point
ation, the provocative use of terms and and also shows that to this social diag-
phrases to goad his readers into radical nosis there belongs in Being and Time a
reflection. But this Socratic approach negative and unhelpful therapy: The in-
may well offend as many as it awak- dividual in the resolute experience of
ens. Heidegger's radical critique of lib- anxiety has the ability to extricate him-
eral democracy which, as Schwan well self or herself from this society. But
shows (1965, pp. 126-145), includes all once freed, he or she has nowhere to
presently notable political systems and turn (p. 21).

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

132
This pivotal if helpless position of ger's political philosophy is unhelpfully
the individual is obvious and widely ac- austere and abstract. A reading of
knowledged, e.g., by Schmitt (1969), Heidegger's position which is confined
Pggeler (1972, pp. 16-17), and Karsten to textual analysis reduces Heidegger's
Harries (1978). Both Pggeler and Har- thought to dogmatic rigor. Here, as al-
ries see beginnings of an orientation for ways, the radical and suggestive force
the solitary individual in Being and of Heidegger's thought comes to frui-
Time. Pggeler refers (1972, p. 17) to tion only through a dialogue between
the concept of the people and its destiny Heidegger and strong, independent con-
which Being and Time abruptly intro- temporaries. Schufreider is not one of
duces as a context of individual exis- them, nor is he a spokesman for any of
tence. Harries takes up this theme and them.
shows in detail how Heidegger's inau- But whatever the truth regarding
gural address as rector at the Univer- the founders of political communities in
sity of Freiburg serves as a bridge be- the past. Harries (like Schwan, 1965,
tween these political suggestions of pp. 126-45) stresses that the later
Being and Time and the later view of Heidegger considered the modern era
politics of which Schwan has made so incapable of establishing the epochal
much, where politics is the work of work of truth, politically or artistically
truth that institutes an entire epoch. (pp. 324-325). Harries also recognizes
Harries claims that among the found- that this incapacity is only the reverse
ing deeds of thinkers, poets, and politi- side, in Heidegger's view, of the reign
cians, "the work of the statesman is of technology (p. 323). But he takes this
given a privileged place" by Heidegger view of Heidegger's to be a "retreat
(p. 316). And he concludes that Heideg- from politics" (p. 323). Like Schmitt,
ger unhappily applied the notion of the he implicitly urges against Heidegger
political leader, whose fundamental the liberal democractic "separation of
truth all others must follow, to Hitler the ethical and the political" and ac-
(pp. 319-320). cuses him of an anti-pluralistic bias
This thesis is vehemently attacked (p. 327).
by Gregory Schufreider (1981), who But merely to state a thesis is not
shows that Harries' point is not sup- to establish it. Has Heidegger overesti-
ported by Heidegger's text. Schuf reider mated the power of technology? At the
contends that Heidegger distinguishes very least he is not alone in his posi-
between the modern state and the polls tion. Langdon Winner's Autonomous
and that the latter is never the creation Technology (1977) substantiates the
of an individual but arises out of the fact both that radical analyses of tech-
struggle of many founders. Though nology are by no means apolitical and
Schufreider is correct on these points, that the theme of technology as an all-
the vehemence and insistence of his at- overpowering force has a rich litera-
tack give a narrow and unbalanced ac- ture in political thought. Though
count of Harries' position, not- Heidegger is only a peripheral figure in
withstanding Schufreider's disclaimer Winner's study (Ellul, if anyone, is the
that he did not want to discuss "the hero), the book is an important, indi-
whole of Professor Harries' interpreta- rect contribution to Heidegger scholar-
tion, some of which is useful and in- ship because it sets Heidegger's reflec-
sightful" (p. 25). More important, tions in the context of modern political
Schufreider's own picture of Heideg- thought as a whole. It thus overcomes

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

133
the provincial isolation of so much ex- in its various disclosures to call upon
pository work and prepares the ground human existence in a subversion of all
for a more penetrating view of Heideg- grounds and fundaments. Practically
ger's thought and of the phenomena at this amounts to a playful and anarchist
issue. Along the same line, there is also subversion of teleology and accounta-
much criticism of the technological cul- bility. A less abstract, but ultimately no
ture by men like John Kenneth Gal- more persuasive, argument for Heideg-
braith, Staffan Linder, Daniel Boorstin, ger as anarchist is found in Graeme
Tiber Scitovsky, and Fred Hirsch that Nicholson (1971).
chronicles the erosion of traditional What allows Schrmann to arrive
forces and the levelling of distinctions.^^ at this intrinsically pluralistic and
Finally, there are many empirical anarchist interpretation of Heidegger's
studies on the habits of consumption political views are nimble and cerebral
and time allocation in this country. All constructions clothed in fine
this and the details of Heidegger's anal- etymologies and supported by a selec-
ysis of technology would have to be con- tive reading of Heidegger's writings.
sidered before one could say confi- What Schrmann disregards is the call
dently of Heidegger's view, as Harries for concreteness and immediacy in
does, that "our world is too varied to be Heidegger's thought, its profound sense
understood in this simple manner" of seriousness and, sometimes, of dis-
(p. 328). Endless variety is all too com- tress. John Caputo has carefully sub-
patible with fundamental uniformity stantiated this point in his critique of
(For more on these issues, see R o r t y w h o also gives a playful read-
Borgmann, 1984). ing of Heidegger. The urgent aspects of
Strong claims for the political po- Heidegger's work are centered around
tency of Heidegger's thought are made technology, of which Schr mann takes
by Reiner Schr mann (1978) and Ber- little concrete notice. The unreal tone
nard Dauenhauer (1976). Schrmann of his essay is apparent when he says of
contends that the political implications Utopian constructions, of central au-
of (the later) Heidegger's thought must thority, and of other underlying static
be developed from "his fundamental ideals, that such "ideals, together with
philosophical project" by way of a mid- extrinsic legitimations of power, have
dle term between the thought of Being been destroyed by Heidegger's
and political thought (p. 195). This mid- phenomenology" (p. 214). Or when he
dle term can be obtained by conceiving asserts: "What indeed is a more power-
the ontological difference between ful challenge to the merry-go-round of
Being and beings, with its simultaneous reason in the calculi that have usurped
disclosure and concealment of the the title of philosophy, particularly in
world, as the symbolic difference. A the Anglo-Saxon world, than to say no
symbol is a paradigm of the manifest to philosophy's unconditional surrender
and the hidden. Moreover and deci- to technology?" (pp. 220-221). If these
sively, it is located in a practice and, are so powerful, why is no one con-
more precisely, in an "irreducibly cerned about such destructions and
polymorphous" practice (p. 199). Tak- challenges?
ing the ontological difference as the In a later essay (1981), Schrmann
symbolic difference, one no longer at- gives his anarchical reading of Heideg-
tempts to establish beings on the abso- ger a sense of greater urgency by argu-
lute ground of Being but allows Being ing that at the point of transition be-

PHILOSOPHY TODAY
tween epochs, the origin (understood as people's past, owing nothing of its own
arche) and principles of the waning resources to possibilities opened up for
epoch lose their force, and the time of it as a political enterprise by positive
transition appears to be precarious and accomplishments of that past, is politi-
perhaps harmful as does the thinking cal nonsense" (p. 640). One can give
which attends to the unsurpassable ori- different weights to the key terms and
gin (in the sense of Ursprung) of the so obtain different readings of this
new epoch (pp. 246-247). This point is proposition, but all would face the di-
given empirical color and life only lemma of "true but trivial" vs. "inter-
through direct and indirect references esting but false." The three conditions
to Foucault (pp.249 and 254, n. 8). that stress the (ironically) universal
Otherwise Schrmann moves along the historical character of politics overlook
historical and terminological paths that the possibility that a political move-
Heidegger has opened up. The latter ment may misunderstand itself ahistor-
Schrmann extends through ically in ways which are both legiti-
etymologizing of his own which gives mate and fruitful. As a fourth condition
his essay a hermetic quality and all but Dauenhauer states that a "defensible
hermetically seals it off from the wider politics for today and the foreseeable
contemporary conversation in social future must take into account the his-
and political philosophy. It should be torical collapse of liberalism under the
noted, however, that a fuller and more impact, on the one hand, of Marxian
final critique of Schrmann's views criticism and, on the other, of the
would have to consider his recently growth of technique" (p. 640). He ac-
(1986) translated book on Heidegger knowledges the need for the develop-
and politics. ment of this point but seems to con-
As Schr mann acknowledges (1978, ceive of such a project along the thin
p. 200), Dauenhauer already em- speculative lines which provide little
phasized that in Heidegger's (and Mer- orientation within contemporary politi-
leau-Ponty's) thought politics is essen- cal perplexity.
tially historical, and political philoso- Mark Blitz, in Heidegger's ''Being
phy must be based on a historical ontol- and Time" and the Possibility of Politi-
ogy. Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty cal Philosophy (1981), begins with a
have, Dauenhauer says, "destroyed, in more pointed awareness of the contem-
Heidegger's sense, the metaphysical porary perplexity than found in either
base which has dominated political Schrmann or Dauenhauer and then
thought since Plato." And positively proceeds with an analysis that neither
speaking, "they have provided insights belittles Heidegger's work by co-opting
into and clues pointing toward elements it for ideologies nor leaves it un-
which any defensible politics must em- criticized behind a veil of humble
body" (1976, p. 626). The latter can be exegesis. Blitz further explicitly ac-
thought of as necessary conditions for knowledges the issue of technology in
sensible modern politics. relation to politics both in general and
Necessary conditions often border in Heidegger while rejecting any argu-
on the trivial. Dauenhauer claims that ment from indignation with regard to
the delimitation afforded by his set of the particulars of Heidegger's life.
conditions "is by no means trivial." The distinctly modern political di-
The first says: "Revolution, in the lemma is precisely the result of science
sense of a radical rupture with a and technology, the success of which

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

135
both makes poUtical guidance all the Heidegger's alternative is all that
more crucial and undermines its tradi- much better, that "locating the useful
tional vitality. "Who now claims confi- in readiness-to-hand, and therefore
dently that more technically 'rational' more properly understanding the Being
control of men and affairs is appropri- of technology, would lead to a new sci-
ate when technology takes the lead both ence of, say, economics, or to a new
in shattering traditional mores and economic practice" (p. 67). In sum,
threatening ungodly destruction ?" "Heidegger's analysis . . . mistakes the
(p. 14). The situation calls for a "return decisive political things for ready-to-
to the original phenomena from which hand things" (p. 147). (Blitz's argu-
the meaning of politics, philosophy, and ments at this point might profitably be
science are first understood" (p. 15). A deepened by utilizing Dreyfus [1984] on
number of possible scholarly efforts the stages of the being of equipment.)
could be made in this direction from Blitz further carries his analysis
Leo Strauss' explorations of "the origin into what is among the most measured
of . . . political philosophy in the assessments of Heidegger's involve-
Greeks" to Heidegger's "radical ques- ment with National Socialism. On the
tioning of what and how things are" one hand, "Heidegger's activities
(p. 15). The uniqueness of Blitz's pur- hardly demonstrate that his under-
suit of the latter approach is that he standing of Being necessarily leads to
has been influenced by the former. "In Nazism, because the depth and extent
general, I will explore the possibility of his support for the regime was not
that Plato and Aristotle's understand- sufficient to sustain this claim"
ing of man, rethought in light of the is- (p. 212). On the other, Heidegger's fail-
sues raised by Heidegger, properly ac- ure to grasp political things in their
counts for the phenomena he dismisses true reality left him vulnerable to just
while illuminating areas he leaves in the kind of defective judgment he in
the dark" (p. 17). fact exercised. The attractiveness of
The essential thrust of Blitz's care- political things such as justice derives
ful and balanced analysis is that from a possible perfection which is at
Heidegger's phenomenology of Dasein once beyond human capacity and capa-
already presumes the primacy of a ble of serving as a guide toward the his-
technological world and thus fails to ap- torical exercise of that capacity. "In-
preciate the reality of political things, sofar as what attracts man can be for
especially justice. It is true that its own sake or can be for a god,
Heidegger implicitly criticizes modern Heidegger fails to clarify the status of
political philosophers such as Hobbes these possibilities." As a result,
and Locke. "What occurs among mod- "Heidegger's analysis of man's pos-
ern political philsophers, from the per- sibilities, and, especially, of the pos-
spective of Being and Time, is that sibilities that come to light as the vir-
human life is considered as a business tues of statemen and citizens, is imper-
enterprise, ultimately rooted in self-ac- fect" (pp. 253-254).
quisition and self-promotion, but the For all its sensitivity and modera-
readiness-to-hand of utilities is not tion. Blitz's book contains a strong and
grasped properly, enabling the results dogmatic assumption. The critical stan-
of natural technology to come to appear dard that remains in the background
paradigmatic for all efforts" (p. 66). and yet determines the evaluation of
But it is not at all clear, says Blitz, that Being and Time is a Platonist view of

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

136
politics. It is astonishing how an author Dallmayr is certainly correct in
who is so alive to the limitations of holding that Heidegger's ontology of
theory and science can be so naively freedom is an attempt to illuminate
confident of metaphysical and trans- freedom beyond the dilemma of arbi-
cendent norms. There is an analogy be- trary choice and submissive fatalism.
tween Heidegger and Blitz on the one Dallmayr speaks from a subtle and
side and Michael Walzer and Ronald comprehensive understanding of
Dworkin on the other that throws some Heidegger's thought. But his presenta-
light on Blitz's blind spot.'' Both tion remains airy and inconclusive. The
Heidegger and Walzer are resolutely concluding section of his essay begins
open to the concretness of the world with this claim: "The implications of
and the uniqueness of history. But such Heidegger's conception of freedom for
an orientation must seem inconclusive contemporary political and social
and even helpless in its openness when theory are numerous and, I believe,
compared with the unequivocal rigor of far-reaching" (p. 227). But is such a
the general and abstract norms Blitz contention at all credible when the dis-
and Dworkin claim for their side. The tinctive and tangible, i.e., technological
power of these norms is greater the setting of our social and political en-
more they remain in the background deavors, is almost entirely ignored?
and are vaguely appealed to. But the Dallmayr's nearly exclusive concentra-
thrust of much of the present feminist tion on the lofty and abstract issues of
and communitarian critique of the history of Being and on the bookish
liberalism is that such norms, once philosophy that is congenial to such
fully drawn into the foreground, turn concentration illustrates once more the
out to be oppressive when definitive melancholy truth that the fertility and
and vacuous when tolerant. Here the radicality of Heidegger's thought are
problem of technology becomes urgent. for the most part still lying fallow.
Oppressive norms in a contemporary Reinhart Maurer, in addition to his
setting come to be uniquely specified essay on Marcuse and Heidegger, has
by technology while vacuous norms also provided a comprehensive and bal-
serve to disguise the rule of technology. anced account of the practical (i.e.,
These problems remain concealed to moral) relevance of Heidegger's
Blitz and Dworkin. thought. Like Schrmann, Dauenhauer,
In a kind of postscript to Blitz and and Dallmayr he notes that Heideg-
related discussions, Fred Dallmayr's ger's apparently theoretical philosophy
"Ontology of Freedom" (1984) rejects contains "throughout a practical and
placing any emphasis on Heidegger's ethical claim" (1972, p. 434). What
Nazi mistake for illuminating either his Maurer sees more clearly than most
philosophy as a whole or the place of are two complex and decisive issues in
politics in his thought. After a review of Heidegger's view of technology. One is
the discussion of freedom in current the question of human freedom in light
Heidegger interpretations which in- of the destiny of technology; the other,
cludes helpful commentary on closely related, is the question of the re-
Pggeler, Schwan, and others not men- form of technology. In concluding divi-
tioned in the present survey sion A, let us try to answer the first of
Dallmayr turns to Heidegger's own these questions and at the same time
texts on freedom. In both cases there is draw together some of the strands of
cursory mention of technology. the foregoing discussion. The second

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

137
question will take us into division B of reply to his essay, Heidegger emphati-
this review. cally rejects the notions of partner,
cooperation and dialectical relation as
8. Destiny and Freedom Under Technology apposite to the relation between Being
Technology, Heidegger insists, is and humanity. These are categories, he
not an instrument at our disposal but says, that are applied to the problem
the last phase of the destiny of Being. from without and occlude the task or
At the same time, technology consti- thought by using customary and seem-
tutes the gravest danger to humanity. ingly obvious schemata of thinking.
In technology we demean ourselves by
These remarks are typical of the
becoming procurers of everything, pro-
ambiguous challenge that Heidegger
curing even ourselves as a resource
extends to contemporary thought. On
(1977a, pp. 26-27). From considerations
the one hand, a person can respond to
such as these Simon Moser concludes
the challenge (as many have done) in
that "the situation of man becomes
the hermetic way, by cultivating an
tragic, for ultimately Being itself pro-
esoteric vocabulary and mode of dis-
vokes man to provoke nature and he
course, by sealing the portals of the
cannot extricate himself from this situ-
Heideggerian sanctuary against the
ation under his own power" (1971, p.
spirits of ordinary thinking, and thus
148).
secluding Heidegger's thought. On the
But this is a one-sided reading of other, there is the response which takes
Heidegger. Almost all critics and com- Heidegger seriously when he says that
mentators acknowledge that for we are involved in the destiny of Being
Heidegger the destiny of technology and in the issue of technology, and con-
does not fatefully overpower humanity; cludes that hence we are entitled and
rather we are involved in the original enabled to consult our experiences.
issue of technology. Being needs hu- This is how we ought to begin to clarify
manity, as Heidegger says. Yet few the destiny of technology not through
scholars have paid attention to the diffi- another dialectical sally or conceptual
culty of the issue. Normally we cast it construction which would only conceal
in the disjunction of libertarianism vs. what is so deeply perplexing.
determinism. But Heidegger clearly in-
tends a third position, as Biemel (1976, To make a beginning with this ap-
p. 148) and Dallmayr (1984) have proach we must disengage the problem
pointed out. of science from that of technology. For
What concepts are appropriate to Heidegger, modern science comes out
this third position, and what kinds of of the destiny of technology. Hence he
experiences bear on it? Maurer (1972, often speaks and is as often taken as a
p. 432) approvingly quotes Lwith's scientific instrumentalist. But insofar
term of "a circle-like dialectic" as an as this may be true, he is nevertheless
expression of the human relation to no common instrumentalist since sci-
Being and claims that the relation so ence is a manifestation of Being
understood is a mediation which one hence ultimate and not subject to the
can appropriate or enact for oneself. guidance of higher ends, as instrumen-
Maurer (p. 441) goes on to speak of "a talists would have it. As witnesses of
certain partnership" between Being our time we must take the kind of qual-
and humans. But in an unpublished let- ified realist view of science that Weiz-
ter of August 3, 1977, to Maurer'' in scker and Heelan urge against

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

IQfi
Heidegger. This must, of course, be es- pretation of the world, Dreyfus argues
tablished on its own merits. with the Heidegger of Being and Time,
Supposing this can be done, we proceeds within a context of practices
must then square soft scientific realism which are not reducible to a theory be-
with Heidegger's thinking of Being. cause they involve skills. A fully and
This can be attempted in various ways. competently exercised skill, though it
One might take scientific realism as may have arisen from the application
historical in that both its way of seeing of rules, transcends those rules as it
and what is seen are taken historically, embodies "a single unified, flexible,
as constituting (part of) an epoch of purposive pattern of behavior" (1980, p.
Being. But since the physico-chemical 9).
laws, at least, are applicable to all Let us assume that skills are in-
prior epochs of Being, we must assume deed not reducible to theory in the
that the vision which our epoch affords sense of a system of rules or of for-
transforms and perhaps distorts all malized procedures; then the question
prior epochs. But this is a gratuitous, remains whether a skill such as skiing
since vacuously true, thesis. It seems is exercised within the theory of phys-
better to propose, along lines first laid ico-chemical lawfulness. And if this is
out by Oskar Becker (1969), that below the case, there is the further question
or above the historical there are endur- whether, in principle, it is the case
ing structures such as logic, mathema- without remainder. How could a nega-
tics, and the natural sciences. There tive answer be given? Such questions
are in these disciplines new ways of are controversial, to be sure, and fi-
seeing, but what comes into view at a nally belong to the controversy over the
certain time shows itself to have or to mind-body identity thesis. While we
approximate an enduring sameness. cannot enter that area here, it is worth
What may have prevented Heideg- pointing out a common misunderstand-
ger from accepting this view (apart ing of reductionism.'' It is often thought
from his phenomenological orientation, that once the possibility of reduction to
for which science in all senses is some- scientific laws is granted, the execution
thing constituted rather than simply of a reduction is, in principle, a "scien-
given) is the concern that modern sci- tific" and "mechanical" if not trivial
ence, far from enduring within history, matter. But the determination of the
is arrogating and dissolving historical conditions or explananda which con-
forces that we experience as significant strain laws to the explanation of
and dear to us in their own right. The phenomena is in regard to the most im-
specter of such reductionism is pre- portant matters of life a poetical or
sumably the spring of Ihde's tentative philosophical task rather than a ques-
and Dreyfus' determined efforts to de- tion of scientific knowledge, if by the
limit practice against rather than with- latter we mean knowledge of laws and
theories. Thus the reducibility of
in science. But Dreyfus' endeavor
phenomena to science leaves the
shows that such a move may be both
philosophical task of characterizing
impossible and unnecessary. He formu-
phenomena like practice and technol-
lates his argument as one against
ogy intact and unsolved.
theoretical holism. The latter holds that
our understanding of the world has Such a view of science meets the
been or could be translated into the charge that Heidegger underrates "the
form of posits or beliefs. But our inter- theoretical character of knowledge in

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

139
physics" (Moser, 1971, p. 149) or the science. This is what Marcuse did at
more tentative point that the later least at one point though, as Habermas
Heidegger eliminates the possibility "of points out 1970, pp. 85-89), uncertainly
any purely contemplative science" even then. Indeed, when one con-
(Ihde, 1979, p. 128). More important, it templates the task of reconstituting
frees us from the fatalistic interpreta- philosophically the sciences in their
tion of the destiny of technology which central sense, one may well yield to
is apparent in Jonas' earlier work fatalism. But on the realist view of sci-
where he essentially, if not doxographi- ence sketched above one is relieved of
cally, accepts the view that modern sci- this impossible burden and can turn
ence and technology both issue from one's attention either to delimiting sci-
the Gestell. Modern science is in the entific practice on political grounds be-
end cogent not as a social institution or cause it is demanding too much capital
in its technological application but in investment or is politically destabiliz-
its central sense as a body of laws and ing (nuclear weapons), or to the pos-
theories, where it not only commands sibilities of reforming technology or
devotion and gratitude (both of which both (since they may well be related).
could be withdrawn), but makes truth The more profound of these pos-
claims which exact assent and to which sibilities lies in the vicinity of that axis
instrumentalism is a futile protest. which connects Heidegger's reflections
If one takes science as an essen- on art with the problem of religion in
tially destructive and dominating force, his thinking. And so we come to the sec-
then the critical implication of this ond division of this review.
view should lead one to propose a new

B. Technology Between Art and Religion

Heidegger's thought on technology nings of a reform of technology which


as it extends between science and poli- would consistently and fruitfully cor-
tics is radically critical. But scattered respond to Heidegger's examination of
throughout his writings there are sug- technology. And the brevity and
gestions that a salutary turn from, or lacunae of this part will be forgivable if
perhaps through, technology to a new the systematic end of this review is
epoch of Being may come about. Art properly served, the concern, i.e., to il-
and divinity are the powers Heidegger luminate our time and to make room in
most often mentions as guides or cen- it for a more graceful life.
ters for another kind of thought and
life. A well-rounded review of the 1. The Turn from Technology to
Heidegger literature on technology re- Art and Divinity
quires therefore a consideration of When in interviews Heidegger was
what work has been done on Heideg- asked whether from his thought con-
ger's thought where it deals with art structive proposals could be derived,
and borders on religious concerns. It is his answers were emphatically nega-
not our intention to provide an exhaus- tive (Wisser, 1970, pp. 68-69; Heidegger,
tive or even comprehensive survey but 1976a, pp. 276-84). But in less guarded
to give a sense of the extent to which moments he has been more venture-
work in this area has uncovered begin- some. At one point he thought of the

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

140
poet as one who might reach through cal analysis of the situation as it is
the destitution of our time and make created by world civilization" (1972, pp.
room for the advent of divinity (1971, 35-36). Schwan himself at one time
pp. 91-142). Heidegger put this point agreed with Heidegger that the fourfold
more generally in the concluding part of earth and sky, of mortals and di-
of his first essay on technology where vinities might provide the dimensions
he suggests that in art another revela- of a political renewal (1965, pp. 172-75).
tion of Being might come about that Later he found the fourfold too arbi-
could save us from the danger of tech- trary and abstract to be helpful (1974,
nology (1977a, pp. 34-35), a suggestion pp. 166-71). "For a sufficiently con-
that Ihde takes up in urging artistic crete, complex and problem-conscious
practice as a counterforce to technol- practical philosophy" one that he
ogy (1979, p. 129). says includes "a fundamental clarifica-
At another time Heidegger sur- tion of the relation, viz., of the correla-
mised that in rural, traditional areas tion and difference, of thinking and act-
the powers of home and history may be ing, i.e., a philosophy of praxis
reawakened, a suggestion later re- Heidegger's thought provides no basis
tracted, as Pggeler points out (1972, p. (nor a 'concrete Utopia')" (1974, p. 171).
35). Then there is the proposal, em- Harries, again, sees in the fourfold a
phasized by Hood (1972, p. 362) and more hopeful opening for political re-
Grange (1977, p. 147), that we take an form than in Heidegger's view of tech-
attitude of detachment toward the nology which provides a "one-dimen-
things of technology, that we use them sional interpretation of the modern
as far as appropriate, but refuse them world," and is "only a caricature of our
in their exclusive claim, a proposal that world" (1978, p. 328). Pggeler, in spite
Marcuse raised to the gesture of the of the scepticism quoted above, holds
Great Refusal (Piccone and Delfini, out the possibility that concrete
1970, p. 44; Ahlers, 1971, p. 588). Finally analyses, which orient themselves by
there is the brief remark in the first the constellation of Being as it even-
essay on technology, elaborated by tuates in the framework and in the
Dreyfus (1980), that we can foster the fourfold can yield "obligations which
saving power "here and now and in lit- are not to be ignored" (1972, p. 49; cf.
tle things" (1977a, p. 33), a point more pp. 50 and 64).
often and forcefully made in the second It is clear from Heidegger's re-
essay on technology (1977a, pp. 43, 45 marks and from those of his critics that
and 49) where Heidegger explains that the concern with art and divinity is a
in those simple focal things the fourfold crucial if poorly articulated counter-
of earth and sky, mortals and divinities part to the analysis of technology.
and thus a richer and deeper world is Heidegger scholarship on art and reli-
gathered and disclosed. gion has done little to clarify and elabo-
How helpful are these proposals in rate the relation between these counter-
light of our perplexity and complex parts.
technological situation? Even
Pggeler, whom Schwan (1974), pp. 153 2. Art and Technology
and 159) accuses of being all too solici- Heidegger's concern with art and
tous of Heidegger's thought, feels his essays on art originate, as William
moved to admit that Heidegger "lacks Bossart (1968) and Christopher Nwodo
even the beginnings of an explicit politi- (1977) have pointed out, in that decisive

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

141
period 1935-1937 in which a turn in In the "Addendum" to the art essay
Heidegger's thought took place and the Heidegger likewise directs attention to
reflections on technology were ini- this sameness and difference when he
tiated. The failure of the Heidegger lit- notes that his use of Gestell,
erature to consider the art-technology framework, in the discussion of art and
relation emphatically and trenchantly truth (Heidegger, 1971, p. 64) is the
may in part be due to Heidegger's deci- foundation for that which "we used in
sion to publish the art and the technol- later writings as the explicit key ex-
ogy essays in different collections in pression for the nature of modern tech-
Holzwege (1950) for the former, Vor^ nology" (p. 84).
trge und Aufstze (1961) for the latter, If Heidegger's thought on art has
a pattern repeated with slightly differ- done little to inspire the literature on
ent combinations in the English Poetry, Heidegger and technology, neither has
Language, Thought (1971) and The it, taken by itself, had much impact on
Question Concerning Technology and aesthetics and art criticism. Excep-
Other Essays (1977), respectively. It is tions are Albert Hofstadter and
also true that the major art essay Richard Kuhns' anthology Philosophies
achieved something like final form of Art and Beauty that contains the
more than a decade before the basic first (and later much revised) transla-
technology essay. Nevertheless, as tion of Heidegger's seminal essay on
Heidegger has often said, difference "The Origin of the Work of Art" and
and sameness go together so that in Hofstadter's later treatise on Truth and
this case too there are connections to be Art where Heidegger's thought pro-
noticed and considered. vides a crucial impetus if not the finally
decisive position.'' Though Heidegger's
Heidegger himself, as pointed out
thought strongly informed Karsten
above, indicates the significance of
Harries' The Meaning of Modern Art,
these connections. In fact, the structure
the explicit discussion of Heidegger is
of the two primary essays is remark-
very limited.'' Heidegger's conception
ably similar. The art essay begins by
of art, along with the hermeneutics of
considering art-work as a thing in
Being and Time, was also one of the
terms of the four causes (Heidegger,
guiding insights of Hans-Georg
1971, pp. 26 ff.) but moves on to de-
Gadamer's Truth and Method (1975).
scribe art as a disclosure of truth. The
Though Gadamer's book has been
technology essay begins by referring to
widely influential of late, it is its her-
technology as a kind of means and
meneutic message, the linguistic and
again considers this in terms of the four
social constitution of truth, that was so
causes (Heidegger, 1977a, p. 6 ff) but
eagerly accepted, and much at the ex-
proceeds to describe it as challenging
pense of the thesis that Gadamer had
and revealing. At the conclusion of the
taken from Heidegger's thought on art,
technology essay, Heidegger says that
i.e., the recognition that there is some-
thing like substantive epochal truth
the decisive confrontation with that is disclosed to us in unforethinka-
[technology] must happen in a ble ways. It is precisely the ignoring of
realm that is, on the one hand, this latter point that gives deconstruc-
akin to the essence of technology tionism its peculiarly vapid and fash-
and, on the other, fundamentally
different from it. Such a realm is ionable playfulness. Henry Sen-
art (Heidegger, 1977a, p. 35). daydiego (1976) makes a direct attempt

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

1/19
to use Heidegger to reform public policy for those free creative acts which give
about funding for the arts. And Walter a work a self-sufficiency apart from
Biemel, while on the American univer- "the world of a particular historical
sity lecture circuit in 1978, developed people" (p. 65).
the Heideggerian notion that "painting If nothing else, Calvin 0. Schrg
is not only a pure representation but a (1973) and Christopher Nwodo (1977)
representation which presents itself" are correct on this point (as was
(Biemel, 1979, p. 278), referring to Hofstadter in his introduction to
works by Velazquez and Picasso. Heidegger, 1971, pp. xv-xvi), pointing
As in the case of technology, out emphatically that Heidegger's in-
Heidegger's philosophy of art has had terpretation of art is fundamentally in
its expositors and for the most part has service to his thinking of Being. In
been poorly served by them. Hans Schrag's words, Heidegger's project for
Jaeger (1958) is an early, competent "overcoming the inquiry standpoint of
paraphrase of "The Origin of the Work traditional aesthetics" is "of the same
of Art." E . F . Kaelin (1967) presents a cloth as . . . his 'destruction' of the his-
more lively and helpful exposition tory of Western metaphysics" (pp. 109
which is remarkable to this day for the 110). Schrg plays down, however,
way it sets off Heidegger's essay Heidegger's positive intentions and ig-
against Merleau-Ponty's work. Yet nores the unique status he grants to art.
Kaelin can be faulted for unquestion- For Nwodo, equally dramatically,
ingly placing Heidegger's essay in the Heidegger's analysis is not meant to
narrow and traditional framework of "produce any new theory of art" (1977,
aesthetics when it is clear not only p. 294). In an analysis which superfi-
from the thrust of Heidegger's reflec- cially parallels Theodore Kisiel's (1973)
tions but from explicit remarks (1971, distinction between Heidegger's logi-
pp. 79-81; 1977a, pp. 34 and 35; all avail- cal, existential, and epochal concep-
able in German at the time of Kaolin's tions of science, Nwodo names "three
writing) that Heidegger rejected and phases in Heidegger's thought-path to-
sought to break through the aesthetic wards Being" (p. 295) as stages for his
categories. reflections on art: (l)the existential
The same charge must be brought analytic of Dasein, (2)the revelation of
against William H. Bossart (1968). He the ontological difference, (3)the Ereig-
begins by outlining as a backdrop those nis or the event of appropriation.
passages in Being and Time that ex- The problem with this analysis (as
plain how humans take up with the with Bossart's) is that the distinction
world and then turns to one of the Hl- between the first two stages is unhelp-
derlin interpretations as the transition ful for a discussion of art in Heidegger.
piece to "The Origin of the Work of Art (Kunst) is conspicuous by its ab-
Art." The exposition of the latter essay sence in Being and Time, and poetry
is followed by an inquiry which at- (Dichtung) is only referred to once in
tempts to determine whether Heideg- passing as a kind of communication
ger's aesthetics covers all important which can be "a disclosing of exis-
views of art. Here Bossart finds tence" because the communication . . .
Heidegger limited by "metaphysical of one's state-of-mind [has] become an
prejudices" (p. 63), unable to account aim in itself" (p. 205 [162]). Nwodo has
for the art of the great eccentrics and to conscript "The Origin of the Work of
for those free creative acts which give Art" for service in the first phase of

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

143
Heidegger's thought, ignoring the fact One wonders what is more regret-
that the Introduction to Metaphysics, table, such outright lapses of scholar-
which stands for the second phase, was ship or the general failure of cir-
composed at the same time as the cumspection and incisiveness that
essay on art and makes essentially the speaks from Nwodo's remark: "We
same points as that essay. In particu- have tended to avoid controversies and
lar, the art essay explicitly formulates have concentrated upon portraying
what Nwodo calls the later ontological Heidegger's thinking as we understand
difference conception of art (1971, p. it" (1971, p. 303). At the same time, a
39). meticulous and critical approach can
The weakness of Nwodo's first two just as surely lead to unhappy and un-
distinctions is highlighted by Edward helpful results, as is evident in Sandra
Lawry (1978), who points out that as Lee Bartky's "Heidegger's Philosophy
discussed in "The Origin of the Work of of Art" (1981). The critical basis of her
Art" the work of art fits into none of the examination is the mainstream analy-
types of beings distinguished in Being tic philosophy of the late 1950s and
and Time. Art is neither something early 1960s and the metaphysical tradi-
ready to hand nor present at hand, and tion generally. Hence as a matter of
it is certainly not Dasein. "A work of course she employs concepts and as-
art is neither thing nor equipment." It cribes to Heidegger views that he has
is "in some mysterious way between radically criticized and vigorously re-
them." It is "like equipment because it jected. Like Kaelin and Bossart, she
has a function;" but unlike equipment unhesitatingly puts Heidegger in the
"art works flaunt their material" (p. framework of traditional aesthetics
190). The art work, as Harold Alder- (pp. 257 and 273) and invokes among
man (1973) earlier notes in a perceptive others the notion of the Romantic and
analysis that moves from thing to art to modern artist (pp. 272-73) to, of all
poetry, is "the most thingly of things" things, commend Heidegger for "an ac-
(p. 157). count of the artwork which grants
At the same time, it does make legitimacy to the conception of the art-
sense to attend expressly, as Nwodo ist as seer and prophet," totally una-
does, to Heidegger's consideration of ware of how such praise clashes with
Being as the event of appropriation. Heidegger's critique of modern subjec-
This consideration constitutes the tivism and his misgivings about art
thought of the later and last Heidegger since at least Hegel's time (1971, pp. 79
where he speaks with the greatest clar- 81). In the same unquestioning spirit
ity and force about our historical situa- Bartky attributes to Heidegger a
tion. Nwodo sketches this period in the search for the (metaphysical) essence
narrowly Heideggerian discourse that of art (pp. 257 and 267) and the employ-
ment of a naive phenomenology to-
characterizes both this and his earlier
gether with blindness to the hermeneu-
(1976) essay. When he finally places art
tic circle of interpretation (p. 272 and p.
in this third stage of Heidegger's
274 note 12). This is like taking Einstein
thought, he does so by quoting a re-
to task for failing to recognize the rela-
mark of Heidegger's (1971, p. 86) that
tivity of motion.
Heidegger had intended as a clarifica-
tion of the essay that Nwodo had used In the first English monograph to
to illustrate the status of art in the first address Heidegger's philosophy of art,
phase. Joseph Kockelmans (1985) continues to

PHILOSOPHY TODAY
exhibit the weaknesses of the exposit- inquiry "into the nature of art" is "the
ory tradition though with redeeming preliminary and therefore indispensa-
features. Part one of this book (pp. 3 ble preparation for the becoming of
68) again insists on situating Heideg- art" (Heidegger, 1971, p. 78) and how
ger's analysis of art against the back- this is brought into question by the con-
ground of traditional aesthetics. More tinuing predominance of modern tech-
thorough than previous discussions, nology. Kockelmans rightly notes
Kockelmans does have the merit of ad- Heidegger's own explicit doubts in an
verting to Heidegger's various criti- untranslated lecture on art delivered at
cisms of this tradition. It would have Athens in 1967 (Heidegger, 1983). But
been useful, however, to have a discus- Kockelmans' many comments add up
sion of the failure of Heidegger's ideas to very little substantive insight.
to have much impact on subsequent Kathleen Wright's (1984) "The
aesthetics and art criticism, except in- Place of the Work of Art in the Age of
sofar as deconstructionism can be read Technology" has the distinction of ad-
as an airy and often aimless offspring dressing directly the topic that was
of Heideggerian radicalism. found to be neglected so regularly. It
In part two of his monograph (pp. has been followed by Friedrich-
71-210), Kockelmans provides a de- Wilhelm von Herrmann's (1985) "Kunst
tailed analysis of "The Origin of the und Technik," another of the punctih-
Work of Art" along lines laid down ear- ous and antiseptic expositions one has
lier in German by Friedrich-Wilhelm come to expect from this author.
von Herrmann (1980). Here Heideg- Wright's is clearly the superior piece.
ger's essay is carefully dissected, and It is distinguished by superior scholar-
not just into its three major sections ship, viz., by a subtle grasp of the origi-
with "Epilogue" and "Addendum." nal German texts, by clarity of reason-
"The Thing and the Work," "Art Work ing and the readiness to confront
and Truth," and "Truth and Art" are Heidegger's reflections with eminent
each subdivided, sub-subdivided, and predecessors (Descartes and Kant) and
paraphrased, with a generous commen- contemporaries (Valery and Benja-
tary that makes abundant references to min). Finally, her thesis is intriguing
related essays by Heidegger, particu- and profoundly hopeful. "I shall
larly on poetry and the poets. But one argue," she says,
cannot help but wonder whether all this
scholarship is put to noble ends when that for Heidegger it is within and
all it yields is the conclusion that what out of the displacement of the
Heidegger has to say about art "is cer- work of art in the age of technol-
ogy that an alternative to place as
tainly provisional, incomplete, and in
cult site or exhibition setting
many respects still ambiguous" (p. emerges, an alternative which
210). exemplifies what is for Heidegger
Kockelmans, as if in response to the saving power of art (1984, p.
the implicit challenge from Heidegger 566).
to address the art-technology differ-
ence, drops into his analysis of the art More specifically, Wright en-
essay numerous scattered references to deavors to show that works of art,
technology (or, as he prefers, "technic- sculpture in "Art and Space" (1969b),
ity"). He also calls attention, in the and the peasant's shoes and the temple
end, to Heidegger's final claim that his in "The Origin of the Work of Art,"

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

145
open up a dwelling place that differs tence, and Heidegger's looking forward
fundamentally from scientific and tech- to a Jiew simplicity. But Harries goes
nological space. Yet the result is in the beyond Heidegger in his larger appreci-
end disappointing. ation of modern philosophy, of people
Wright's and Heidegger's three ex- like Schopenhauer, Freud, Lukacs and
amples are essentially pretechnologi- Sartre, and in his acquaintance with
cal; and in a pretechnological setting, the varieties of modern art. Much the
to be sure, they did or would establish a same can be said of Fandozzi's essays
nontechnological dwelling place. But (1979 and 1982) which in addition show
nothing in Wright's account would indi- a keen eye for the corrupting force of
cate how these art works could assert the consumer culture and boldness of
their orienting power within, against, conjecture in contemplating the future
or after technology. For the saving of technological art. David Hallibur-
power to grow in our time, the relation ton's (1981) "From Poetic Thinking to
between art and technology must go Concrete Interpretation" directs
beyond mere otherness toward some Heidegger's reflections on technology,
sort of affirmative interplay. Wright the fourfold, and on the equipment
has failed to answer convincingly structure in Being and Time toward a
Heidegger's fearful question (1971, p. poem of Wordsworth's and discloses
80), "is art still an essential and neces- how in the poem the centering force of
sary way in which that truth happens rural life is threatened by the emerging
which is decisive for our historical exis- technological framework and yet af-
tence, or is art no longer of this charac- firmed and entrusted to the future.
ter?" Like Heidegger, she is unable to Halliburton quotes (p. 76) among
show that art may again be of this others from Heidegger's essay, "Build-
character, and so her essay remains at ing, Dwelling, Thinking" (1971, pp. 143
the level of higher exposition. 61). It contains an important and
What most of the expository work largely neglected link between Heideg-
on art in Heidegger shows is that the ger's thought on technology and on art
framework of technology has a close and between the diagnosis of technol-
analogue in the framework of scholar- ogy and the healing power of things.
ship which like its technological ar- The fruitfulness of those connections
chetype is largely concealed, well en- appears in the possibility of finding
trenched, and threatens to occlude the one's way from the terse and recondite
saving power of things that might be proposals of Heidegger to the rich, de-
the occasion for a turn of affairs. More tailed and hopeful work of Kent C.
particularly, that expository work Bloomer and Charles W. Moore in
shows once more how the fertility of Body, Memory, and Architecture and
Heidegger's thought requires, as of David P. Billington in The Tower and
Heidegger himself recognized (1971, p. the Bridge: The New Art of Structural
5), adversaries, thinkers who challenge Engineering.^'' Here too the despair of
Heidegger's insight from a position of Schwan and Harries as regards the
their own. centering force of art for the common
Beginnings of such a challenge can welfare, mentioned in section A, 7 of
be found in Harries (1968) whose this review, is answered in a quietly
critique of modern art reflects Heideg- constructive manner. And here, finally,
ger's critique of modern subjectivity, of one may glimpse the outlines of the
the shallowness of technological exis- new dwelling place for which Kathleen

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

14
Wright has been searching. These discussion of Heidegger and mysticism.
hopes for a turn of technology will oc- First, it shows that the chief critics of
cupy us once more at the conclusion of Heidegger's mysticism, Paul Hhner-
this review. feld, Karl Lwith, and Laszlo Versenyi,
rely on a very tentative or even mista-
3. Mysticism and the East ken notion of mysticism. Caputo fur-
Heidegger has not only thought nishes constructive proof of this claim
about the question of what may consti- by giving a careful exposition of Eck-
tute a genuine counterforce to technol- hart's mysticism (pp. 97-139). That ex-
ogy and bring about a turn of our des- position further allows for a detailed
tiny. He has also practiced a kind of distinction between mysticism proper
thinking which may be taken as a radi- and Heidegger's thinking which,
cal alternative to technology, a kind of Caputo says, is not truly mystical but
thinking that Heidegger himself has does contain a mystical element (pp.
called meditative thinking (1966, p. 46). 222-40). Like mysticism, Heidegger's
It has a certain kinship with mysticism, thinking is the experience of a power
and the latter term has served as a that we cannot and do not want to con-
nodal point for critical and supportive trol and capture through conceptual
views of Heidegger's thought. These systems. Yet Heidegger's thinking has
contentions bear on our review inas- a much higher and more explicit re-
much as mysticism is counterposed to gard for language than does mysticism.
technology. The complexity of the issue It is more radically historical and
is heightened by Heidegger who, on the therefore more critical of metaphysics.
one hand, rejects the term mysticism And it moves at so fundamental a level
for his thinking (1969a, p. 53). In an un- that, unlike mysticism, it neither
published letter to Reinhart Maurer he nourishes nor seems to depend on the
says pointedly: "Only those deal in the moral conduct at the surface of every-
'mysticism of Being' who are not able day life.
to enact the thinking of Being, of its dis- Caputo is keenly aware that the
closing essence according to the on- mystical element in Heidegger in its re-
tological difference of Being and be- flective and receptive calmness is an-
ings." On the other hand, he acknowl- tipodal to the aggressive busyness of
edges that "to genuine and great mysti- that technology and that technology is
cism there belongs the utmost acute- always the implicit theme of medita-
ness and profoundness of thinking as tive thinking. He is, moreover, critical
well" (1957a, German edition, p. 71). of the austerity and reserve of Heideg-
Moreover there is Heidegger's well- ger's thought which seems to drive us
known affection for the great Meister into the unhappy dilemma of the practi-
Eckhart and his deep respect for East- cally ineffective piety of thought vs. the
ern thought. barren and suppressive practice of
Regarding mysticism particularly, cybernetics (1978, p. 257). As
the writers who use this term to charge documented earlier, Caputo's criticism
Heidegger with obscurantism and eva- can be supported by explicit remarks of
siveness more or less had the field to Heidegger's. But it overlooks many
themselves until the publication of John other, more constructive and helpful,
D. Caputo's The Mystical Element in suggestions that Heidegger has made.
Heidegger's Thought in 1978. His book Caputo throughout his book calls
does much to clarify and advance the for a fruitfully adversarial relationship

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

147
with Heidegger's thought and rightly Heidegger and one particular Asian
rejects the epigones who dismiss every culture, namely the Japanese, stressing
criticism of Heidegger as a misun- more specifically one aspect of that cul-
derstanding. But Caputo's own counter- ture, namely Zen Buddhism. Japanese
position to Heidegger is not rich and ar- culture did not participate in the long
ticulate enough to nurture the seeds of development of metaphysics that has
reform that lie concealed in Heideg- culminated in technology as Heidegger
ger's mystical element. Yet one should has it. Rather, it has been strongly in-
not blame Caputo for doing first things formed by Zen Buddhism which, as ap-
first. In regards to mysticism too, pears from remarks above, is opposed
Heidegger scholarship has been in a to technology. And the Japanese did in
primitive and deplorable state. Caputo fact provide one of the very few in-
has brought clarity and order into this stances where a community rejected a
neglected area. He has done so with technological innovation, in this case
fairness toward his opponents, critical firearms, for reasons that are conso-
sympathy toward Heidegger, with care- nant with Heidegger's critique of tech-
ful scholarship, and in an engaging, nology."' But this was at the very begin-
though occasionally expansive, style. ning of the modern era, and by now
Western mysticism has a well- Japan is perhaps the technologically
known kinship with Eastern thought, most accomplished country in the
particularly with Zen Buddhism, and so world.
provides a link between Heidegger and
the East. Caputo considers this tie suc- The limitation of what follows to
cinctly (1978, pp. 203-27) and illustrates Zen Buddhism is justified on a number
and elaborates relations that have pre- of counts. From the side of Heidegger,
viously emerged in a conference on the most obvious is the importance of
"Heidegger and Eastern Thought," or- Shuzo Kuki in the dialogue of On the
ganized in 1969 by Borgmann, Eliot Way to Language (1971, pp. 1-54). (As it
Deutsch, and others at the University happens, Kuki was also the man who
of Hawaii. (The proceedings were pub- introduced Sartre to Heidegger. As a
lished in Philosophy East and West 20, student, after studying with Heidegger
no. 3 [July 1970].) The outcome of this in Freiburg, Kuki went to Paris. Sartre,
symposium was to document both also a student, answered Kuki's adver-
Heidegger's explicit interest in Oriental tisement for a French tutor.) Kuki's in-
thinking and various parallels between fluential The Structure of "IkV' (1930,
Heideggerian and East Asian themes. followed by numerous reprints) is a
But the symposium also highlighted im- phenomenological description of iki, of
portant differences, among them the that aesthetic way of life peculiar to the
following. First, Buddhism'^ stress is Japanese. Based on stumi (taste or ele-
ethical, grounded in dealing with the gance), it cannot easily be discussed,
problem of suffering, whereas Heideg- but must be lived, an argument evi-
ger's is ontological, concerned with the dently influenced by Heidegger's analy-
theme of Being. Second, for Buddhism sis of the primordial character of Da-
Being is not essentially historical, as it sein ' s practical being-in-the-world.
is for Heidegger. Then there is the fact that Zen Bud-
These considerations suggest that it dhism, like Heidegger's later thought,
is perhaps instructive to examine in seems to involve some kind of uniting
more detail the relation between of art and mysticism. Finally, there is

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

148
William Barrett's unsubstantiated gos- bued with Buddhism, one who in fact
sip about Heidegger and Zen.'' retired from teaching at the University
From the side of Japan the justifi- of Kyoto to die in a Zen monastery.
cation is even stronger. Not only has Robert Schinzinger, in an introduction
Being and Time been translated into to his translation of Nishida's Intelligi-
Japanese more times (five) than into hility and the Philosophy of Nothing-
any other language, Japanese commen- ness, remarks on a number of compari-
tators have done a number of impor- sons between Nishida and Heidegger
tant studies and adaptations of Heideg- and, indeed, more could have been ob-
ger, work that has been summarized by served.'' Yet all such comparisons fade
Hoshihiro Nitta, Hirotaka Tatematsu beside Nishida's own criticisms of
and Eiichi Shimomisse in Heidegger, which can be summarized
"Phenomenology and Philosophy in as two: (1) Heidegger has not gotten
Japan.'"' More recently Akira Ishida hold of the concrete practical world in
(1975) and Aritsune Yonezawa (1975) his phenomenological description of
have dealt directly with Heidegger's Dasein. His history is still a concept;
philosophy of art and Shoichi Omori his "world" is not a real world which
(1972) has examined the relation be- determines human action but remains
tween art and technology. Finally, at a world of understanding.^ (2) Con-
the popular level, the Neo-Shintoist sciousness in Husserl and Heidegger
Chikao Fijisawa appeals to Heidegger has not been truly purged of individual-
in his critique of contemporary culture ity and subjectivity. The transcendence
and goes so far as to identify Das Sein and objectivity of consciousness has not
with the Kami (gods or divine forces in been recognized. (This second argu-
Shinto).'^ This last example reminds us, ment, while not specifically applied
too, that the World War H alliance of against Heidegger, occurs again and
Germany and Japan should not be dis- again throughout Fundamental Prob-
counted. lems and other works.)
Despite such mutual and well-es- There remain of course two strong
tablished influences, however, parallels between Zen Buddhism and
Japanese culture poses a number of Heidegger, one from the later Heideg-
critical questions for Heidegger. At an ger and one from the early. Both
implicit level there is the sociological Buddhism and the later Heidegger
fact that it was Japan, a country evi- teach that the highest human possibil-
dently under the sway of decidedly non- ity is reached in a spirit of detachment
Western ways of thinking, that has and receptivity, the counter-position to
nevertheless, as mentioned above, been self-love or subjectivism. It was
the most adroit at adopting Western reached by Eugen Herrigel, as his ac-
technology. Surely this raises problems count in Zen in the Art of Archery tells
for Heidegger's reading of modern us, when he ceased in his endeavors to
technology as dependent on Western master his shot and let "It" shoot
metaphysics. (Caputo, 1978, pp. 208-9).'^ The other
At a more explicit level is the ex- parallel comes from Heidegger's 1929
ample of Kitaro Nishida (1870-1945), the lecture What is Metaphysics? where he,
greatest of Japanese philosophers. much like the Buddhist tradition,
Nishida was well acquainted with and speaks about the Nothing as the
respectful of the work of Husserl and groundless ground of all there is
Heidegger, besides being a man im- (Caputo, 1978, pp. 212-13). But on this

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

149
point there is not only a parallel but a metaphysics and as technology is too
divergence of views as well, i.e., a con- well entrenched to yield to a quick and
troversy on whether Heidegger had determined move. Hence he proposes
grasped the Nothing with sufficient that we read ber as "concerning" and
radicality (Nakaoka, 1985). engage in a reflection "Concerning the
Before we turn to concluding re- Line" of nihilism, a suggestion that
marks on the light that the relation of Fandozzi has taken up in his essay
Heidegger and the East sheds on tech- Nihilism and Technology (1982).
nology, an aside on Heidegger and the Heidegger in The Question of Being
Nothing is required. Critics of Heideg- (1956) is less than sanguine about the
ger have pounced on his reflection on prospect of a deeper understanding of
the Nothing to accuse him of nihilism. nihilism. In fact the facile concept and
That Heidegger should be stigmatized charge of nihilism at times enters into
as a nihilist especially by someone such an unholy alliance with a shallow no-
as Stanley Rosen (1969) is passing tion of myticism. Their putative eva-
strange. Rosen is a student of Leo siveness and obscurantism are seen by
Strauss, a proponent of two principles Rosen as the reason for Heidegger's
which should guard against such a pre- political imprudence. In a similar
cipitous and rhetorical judgment: the spirit, Strauss says of Heidegger's
idea that one must be very careful thought: "There is no room for political
about claiming to understand a philoso- philosophy in Heidegger's work, and
pher better than he understands him- this may well be due to the fact that the
self; and a careful distinction between room in question is occupied by gods or
opinion and knowledge, exoteric and the gods" (1971, p. 2).
esoteric teachings. Heidegger perhaps Yet however misdirected these ob-
_more than any other contemporary jections, they do raise an important
philsopher has claimed to be trying to question of long standing, the question,
overcome that nihilism which he sees i.e., of whether personal mysticism
as the culmination of the Western does not have a fatal inclination toward
philosophical tradition. With regard to practical imprudence and political
the alleged nihilistic character of nihilism. In the present context we can
Heidegger's teaching, the refutation by formulate the question more cautiously
David A. White (1975) is persuasive. and ask, in conclusion, whether the
Heidegger's own defense against mystical element in Heidegger and the
the charge of nihilism is readily avail- kindred movements in Eastern thought
able in The Question of Being (1956). In have helped us to see technology more
its original form the essay was ad- clearly and hopefully.
dressed to Ernst Jnger in a To begin with the East, the com-
Festschrift for his sixtieth birthday in plex of issues involving technology, its
response to one from Jnger com- reform, and the Japanese experience is
memorating Heidegger's own sixtieth of great philosophical and current in-
anniversary six years previously. terest. Its present prominence in this
Jnger's contribution was entitled country is due to the fact that the con-
"ber die Linie," understood by Jnger ception that Americans have of their
as "across" or "over the line" (of place in the world and in history is
nihilism), i.e., as an attempt at moving strongly informed by the technological
beyond nihilism. In reply, Heidegger power and prowess of the United
urges that nihilism as the end phase of States. But this claim to world histori-

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

150
cal significance is now being chal- culture as the world's sole salvation
lenged by Japan which in productivity and have met regularly with Prime
and increasingly in research is overtak- Minister Nakasone to discuss Japan's
ing the United States. This has led, as national identity.
Murray Sayle and Ian Buruma have At the Honolulu conference, Umeh-
shown in different ways, to anger and ara (1970) read a paper acknowledging
incomprehension on the American side his debt to Heidegger (p. 273), denounc-
and to searching and troubling debates ing the technological culture of "mate-
among the Japanese.'' rial goods and sex" (p. 272; cf p. 278),
The philosophically challenging and calling for a "continuing dialogue
issue unhappily falls between the horns between thinkers of the East and the
of the dilemma that Caputo has de- West" about the global destiny of
plored (1978, p. 257). The American humankind (p. 281). Whether Umehara
reaction and the Japanese responses has in fact moved on to an intolerant
that Sayle considers are firmly within and repressive position is impossible to
the framework of the calculating think- establish from the direct quotations,
ing of technology. At the same time or- but his account is a warning to those
thodox Eastern and comparative phi- who would criticize the technologically
losophy as well as the usual Heidegger specified liberal state that they make
scholarship timidly cling to the high themselves clear on the indispensable
and highest ground of philosophical value of tolerance and civil liberty.
abstraction and tradition. At a confer- Is there any hope of drawing from
ence on "The Critique of the Times the sources of mysticism and Eastern
after Heidegger" which was held at the thought to irrigate in a liberal and to-
University of Augsburg (West Ger- lerant way the barren ground that lies
many), scholars from West Germany, between the technological enterprise
France, Italy, the United States, and and philosophical meditation? As re-
Japan were in attendance.'' Though it gards the East, there may be such cul-
was in many ways a stimulating and tivation going on now, and we are ig-
rewarding affair and proceeded under norant of it due to the fact, remarked
an appropriately ambiguous and pro- by Heidegger in his letter to the Hon-
vocative title, there was little consid- olulu conference, "that with few excep-
eration of the concrete circumstances tions there is no command of the East-
under which technology is taking its ern languages either in Europe or in
course around the globe. If there was the United States" (1970, p. 221). As re-
an undercurrent of vital interest, it was gards myticism and the mystical ele-
furnished by the playfulness of recent ment in Heidegger, it will be a matter
French philosophy. of first recovering that tradition in the
Buruma, however, believes to have fuller and perhaps more vital setting of
discovered a philosophical force in religion and Christianity.
Japanese politics that is critical of
technology and has practical though 4. Relgion and Christianity
limited significance. He names Takeshi In the Spiegel interview Heidegger
Umehara as the leader of a racist and was asked whether the individual or
chauvinist school of philosophy philosophy could influence the constric-
(Heidegger's name comes up in this tive network of the absolute technologi-
context) whose members, so Buruma cal state. Heidegger denied that possi-
says, proclaim traditional Japanese bility and gave his by now celebrated

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

151
answer: "Only a god can save us" time of Catholic education without re-
(1976a, p. 277). The significance of this sentment; in fact, he singles out two of
answer is underlined not only by the his clerical mentors with obvious affec-
fact that Heidegger once more brought tion (1958, pp. 3-4). Similarly, he wrote
up "the arrival or the absence of the about the religious life of his boyhood
god" when the question of reform arose with unreserved warmth.'^ And when
again a little later in the interview; the he felt his death approaching, he asked
answer also hearkens back to the close a Catholic priest, Bernhard Welte, that
of Heidegger's major essay on technol- he "say a few words in his memory at
ogy where, taking guidance from Hl- the burial" (Welte, 1982, p. 86).
derlin, he asserts that at the height of And yet Caputo, surely a well-in-
the danger of technology the saving formed and sensible reader of Heideg-
power would grow as well (1977, p. 28). ger, says of his thought that it is "radi-
Is God then the one to whom cally worldly and secular" (1978,
Heidegger instructs us to turn for sal- p. 252). The standard argument in sup-
vation in the face of the danger of tech- port of this view has been assembled by
nology? Not really, for Heidegger James L. Perotti in Heidegger on the
speaks of a god or the god; "god" is not Divine (1974). Perotti follows Heideg-
a proper name for him. This seemingly ger's development to show how his
fine point of linguistic usage is a clue to questions became increasingly radical
the complex relation Heidegger had and broke through the established ways
throughout his life to religion and of thinking and speaking, including
Christianity. And the broader context those that one follows to reflect and
in which this point has its place also talk about God. These are now seen to
contains a complex relation between be restricted and superficial. Tradi-
-technology and Christianity in Heideg- tional theology is discredited. But this
ger's thought. These complexities must is not to deny God. At the deeper level
be outlined and if possible clarified to of thought that Heidegger attains a new
provide a fuller context for the review experience of God becomes possible.
of work on Heidegger and technology. Perotti is concerned to present
The point is to round out this context Heidegger's views of the divine and
rather than furnish a review of the lit- God within the over-all movement of
erature on Heidegger, religion, Christ- Heidegger's thought, and much of his
ianity, and theology, a literature that is book is devoted to tracing this move-
extensive and requires a survey in its ment. What mars this laudable inten-
own right. tion is the triumphalist tone of Perotti's
Heidegger grew up in simple, account in which the power and tren-
rural, and intensely Roman Catholic chancy of Heidegger effortlessly pre-
circumstances. For a gifted boy4xi such vail over all traditions and objections.
a setting an academic career meant Perotti's ambitious preoccupation
studying for the priesthood. People like moreover disburdens him from a more
Heidegger's parents would otherwise modest but desirable achievement, viz.,
neither have had the courage to aim so a careful historical-doxographical ac-
high for their son nor would they have count of the periodic emergence and
mustered the resolve to take on the nec- submersion of the religious theme in
essary economic burdens.'^ In the brief Heidegger's work. Finally Perotti
autobiographical sketch that Heidegger seems unsure of his conclusion, both of
has left us he appears to remember his its substance and of its radicality. As

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

152
regards his substantive finding, he first tentative indication of a goal" (1982,
asserts: "The word about god will p. 88; our translation from the origi-
come forth from Heidegger only as a nal). And toward the end of Heideg-
response to the presence or absence of ger's career, the word "Being" re-
god" (p. 118). But then he has Heideg- mains behind and no longer needs to be
ger disavow any experience of God and mentioned (1982, pp.95, 97, and 98).
defer to the "unique prerogative of the Caputo would so far agree with Welte.
poet" on this point. "Heidegger," But Welte sees the early Heidegger's
Perotti says, "has selected and com- reflections on the oblivion of Being and
mitted his thinking to the poet Hlder- on the simultaneous disclosure and con-
lin" (p. 119). cealment of Being as stages on the way
Concerning the radicality of toward Heidegger's experience of the
Heidegger's position Perotti seems una- absence of God. And Heidegger, so
ware of the crucial question, what bear- Welte continues, not only gives expres-
ing the thinking of Being will finally sion to this absence but takes steps to-
have on God and the divine. The tenor ward a positive appreciation of this ab-
of Perotti's book suggests that the sence so that in that absence first hints
superior and in fact supreme radicality of the presence of the All-High begin to
of Heidegger's thinking and of its appear.
theme. Being, will provide a radically Welte presents his case with sub-
new ground or space for the appear- tlety and insight. And its seems sub-
ance of God. In this case, God would no stantially right. But it is also narrow,
longer be the supreme power but both systematically and in point of
merely a moment within the history of Heidegger's intellectual biography. To
Being. At the same time, Perotti's begin with the latter, here as in many
explicit conclusions, considered just other respects, scholars have allowed
now, both intimate a more limited role the old Heidegger to set the tone for the
for Being and its thinking, one that interpretation of the younger Heideg-
would finally be in the service of God's ger's work. In this way, a harmony and
epiphany. On this question one might consistency appear in the development
not agree with Caputo; but one must of Heidegger's relation to God and reli-
certainly acknowledge the forthright- gion that did not in fact obtain. It is not
ness and clarity of his answer which the case that Heidegger began from a
embraces the former of the alterna- religious position and then moved on to
tives above. "I do not mean that there a searching examination of Being
is no place for God in the later Heideg- which led him beyond a vital faith in
ger," he says, "but that Heidegger's God (Caputo) or to a profound experi-
God is not the Lord of history. He does ence of the absence of God (Perotti)
not govern the missions of Being with and of intimation of a new ephiphany
loving care. Rather His own appear- (Welte). It is apparent from the scat-
ance in history is subject to the move- tered references to God, Christianity,
ments of the world-play" (1978, p. 254). and faith in Being and Time that
The religious view of Heidegger's Heidegger at the height of his first
thought is taken by Heidegger's great great accomplishment did not just re-
fellow townsman, Bernhard Welte. flect more deeply and dispassionately
Being, Welte points out, is never a de- on his religious position but was con-
finitive theme or power in Heidegger's cerned to put a great critical distance
thought. It is at first "only a formal and between his work and religion.''

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

153
In the year of the pubUcation of our question, but he cannot really
Being and Time, he gave a lecture on question without ceasing to be a
"Phenomenology and Theology" believer and taking all the conse-
(1976b, pp. 3-21), a document which has quences of such a step. He will
only be able to act 'as i f . . . (1953,
been available in German since 1970
p. 6).
and which both Perotti and Welte have
ignored. There he tried to work out, in As he often does, Heidegger goes on to
light of Being and Time, a principled soften and qualify this categorical
relationship between philosophy and statement on a crucial issue and re-
theology, one that would give each dis- marks that such unquestioning faith is
cipline its due. Roughly, philosophy is really no faith at all but rather conveni-
taken by Heidegger as the reflection on ence and indifference.
the basic modes of Being that can be Still, Heidegger comes at least very
undertaken without envisaging the spe- close to saying that the Christian can-
cific Christian mode of being in the not be a philosopher. Both in 1927 and
world. Theology by contrast, is based in 1935 he dismisses Christian philoso-
on the philosophically unsurpassable gi- phy as "a wooden iron" (1976b, p. 21,
venness of faith. Theology, therefore, where the translator has "square cir-
cannot take its direction from philoso- cle"; 1953, p. 6; the translator has
phy. As a scholarly enterprise, how- "round square"). One might suppose
ever, it must draw in a complementary that the venturesome resoluteness that
and preliminary way on the philosophi- Heidegger thinks to be closed off to the
cal illumination of the basic modes of believer is of a piece with the subjec-
human existence. Heidegger tries to tive and voluntaristic authenticity of
capture this result by saying that, al- the early Heidegger that, in the later
though philosophy cannot give direction Heidegger, as Zimmerman has shown
to theology, it does provide correction. (1981), yields to detachment and open-
Philosophy could well exist without act- ness as the authentic mode of human
ing as a theological corrective. Simi- being. And the latter attitude is much
larly faith, though not the scholarly dis- closer to faith as is evident from the
cipline of theology, can exist without proximity of Heidegger and Meister
philosophy. Eckhart, considered in the previous
But just when Heidegger has ar- section. Yet as late as 1954, in a conver-
rived at this adjudication of the various sation with Protestant philosophers and
claims and territories, he goes on to theologians, Heidegger if anything saw
say that faith as a mode of existence is an even deeper chasm dividing theol-
the mortal enemy of the mode of exis- ogy and philosophy (1976b, pp. 59-71).
tence that belongs to philosophy (1976b, It is this dualistic and sometimes
p. 20). The reason is only hinted at. angry view of the relationship of the
Faith is contrasted with the philoso- philosopher to the believer that is omit-
phers' free appropriation of their own ted by Perotti and Welte. We should
total existence. Eight years later, in In- spell out at this point what is implicit in
troduction to Metaphysics, Heidegger the preceding sections. Even at his
spells out what is at issue in this con- most critical, Heidegger would never
trast: join in the criticism of Christianity that
has gained currency under the name of
One who holds to such faith can in the "Lynn White Thesis," according to
a way participate in the asking of which Christianity, by despiritualizing

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

154
nature, provides a tabula rasa for tech- divine God" (1957b, p. 72). Closer than
nology and abettes the ecological the mainstream believers and theolo-
crisis.'' For Heidegger, the metaphysi- gians? This is what Heidegger in his
cal origins of technology arise much rustic sort of cunning implies but then
earlier, viz., with Plato. And they come explicitly denies when he continues:
to a tangible fruition much later, "Here this means only: god-less think-
namely toward the middle and end of ing is more open to Him than onto-theo-
the modern period. It should also be logic would like to admit" (ibid.).'''
noted that one who grew up in a setting What are we to make of the fact
that was shaped in the Middle Ages and that in Heidegger's thought a dismis-
where many a medieval practice was sive and dualistic and a concernful and
still alive would be immune to the preparatory view of faith and theology
seductive simplicity of White's thesis. are vying with one another? Setting
Side by side with the critical and aside narrowly biographical considera-
separatist view of Christianity, faith, tions and returning to the question of
and theology we do find the other view technology, we can see that what the
which is very nearly the received one two views have in common is a deep
and from which the philosopher's work concern for the difficulty and signifi-
is seen as the replacement of theology cance of the task of thought. In the
or at least as a new preparation for dualistic position, which is essentially
theology and perhaps even faith. The the earlier one, we can see a concern to
preparatory view is first given pro- face up to the difficulty of philosophical
grammatically in the Letter on reflection and to keep premature and
Humanism, written in 1946, where pat answers at bay. The difficulty at
Heidegger says: first occupies Heidegger more than the
significance of thought since the early
Only from the truth of Being can radical resolve of his work was still
the essence of the holy be thought. ambiguous and without firm guidance,
Only from the essence of the holy as suggested many times in the forego-
is the essence of divinity to be
ing pages. But as Heidegger settled
thought. Only in the light of the es-
sence of divinity can it be thought more and more clearly on the destiny
or said what the word "God" is to of technology as the crucially signifi-
signify (1947, p. 230; see also cant issue of thought, his attitude to-
p. 218). ward faith and theology became more
conciliatory and congenial.
In "The Onto-Theo-Logical Consititu- Yet Heidegger remained worried
tion of Metaphysics" of 1957, Heidegger that the clearing he was trying to open
not only proposes such a program but up for a new advent of divinity would
appears to claim it as his own. He be overgrown by the facile and ineffec-
suggests that his refusal to talk about tive pronouncements of the established
God is due to the fact that he has ex- ways of thinking. This is especially evi-
perienced theology in its genuine dent in Heidegger's epistolary reply to
rootedness, "both the theology of Chris- Welte's article (Welte, 1975, p. 85). He
tian faith and that of philosophy" gently reminds Welte of two things:
(1957b, pp. 54-55). And he submits that first, that his concern with the question
his "god-less thinking which must of God cannot be separated from his re-
abandon the god of philosophy, god as flections on the modern history of
causa sui, is thus perhaps closer to the Being, i.e., on technology and science;

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

155
and second, that he has come to no con- throughout his life accepted the cul-
clusions, that he is still "on the path of tural embodiment of Catholic Christian-
inquiry." ity in his native environment is evident
Heidegger's assertion that only a from scattered remarks in his formal
god can save us from the danger of essays and from various addresses he
technology is not just a flourish or gave in his hometown of Messkirch
rhetoric of despair. His thought on tech- (Mller, 1986, p. 30).
nology cannot be fully grasped without There are, to be sure, many other
attention to his reflections on divinity theological currents that may fruitfully
and God. But neither should one as- converge with Heidegger's thought,
sume that there is a theological answer notably process theology which shares
to Heidegger's philosophical question. important parts of Heidegger's critique
The radically new epoch of Being in of metaphysics and of a metaphysically
which we are implicated requires us to structured theology. The problem of the
rethink from the ground up what we relationship between technology and
mean by faith and how we experience theology in Heidegger is only beginning
the divine. More specifically we must to receive attention, and this is true of
clarify the religious and theological sig- the general field of technology and
nificance of our practical and reflective theology. A beginning has been made in
experience of science and technology. Carl Mitcham and Jim Crete's anthol-
Such a proposal, of course, would be ogy. Theology and Technology.'^^ It
anathema to Protestant theologians, shows how inadequate are our tradi-
such as Karl Barth, who reject as an tional categories of history and philoso-
expression of human arrogance any re- phy, of cause and effect, of power and
flection that is even tentatively inde- grace, of failure and wholeness, of the
pendent of and antecendent to faith. sacred and the profane, and how diffi-
Catholic theologians, such as Welte and cult it is to rethink these matters in
Karl Rahner, nevertheless work in a light of the challenge of Heidegger's
tradition that has long practiced such thought and of our experience of tech-
procursive reflection under the heading nology and faith.
of fundamental theology.
Heidegger's thought is consensual 5. The Overcoming of Technology
with Catholicism not only along this We have clustered the works under
traditional theological line but also review around thematic points. But
through Heidegger's sacramental con- running through those clusters is a pro-
ception of reality that is so evident in gressive movement of scholarship with
his reflections on the fourfold. The Ger- three discernible stages. The first is the
man word for fourfold, Vierung, is in stage of translation and exposition. The
fact the technical term for the crossing translations clearly were necessary to
of nave and transept in a medieval acquaint a larger audience with
church. The cathedral in Freiburg Heidegger's thought: the larger the au-
where Heidegger lived for most of his dience to be reached, the more formi-
life has a powerful Romanesque cross- dable the obstacle of linguistic compla-
ing, concealed under the roof of the cency. The expositions were intended to
nave, as a point of balance between the help Anglo-American readers over-
austere Gothic nave, the magnificient come the idiosyncrasies of Heidegger's
late Gothic choir, and the late style and to spell out those assumptions
Romanesque transept. That Heidegger of Heidegger's that could not be taken

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

156
for granted in these parts. Whether the books of Edward G. Ballard and Wil-
expository work has in fact made a sig- liam Barrett. Such work surely repre-
nificant contribution to the Heidegger sents the most important stage and
reception in the EngUsh speaking world fruit of Heidegger scholarship. As re-
is uncertain. At any rate, it is time for marked at the beginning of this review,
this phase to come to an end. if Heidegger's thought finally matters,
The next stage is that of a dialogue it will be through work of this kind, as-
where Heidegger's thought on technol- suming that such work in turn will at
ogy is drawn into a serious conversa- long last inform our social and cultural
tion with the best minds of modern and practices.
contemporary thought. This has been Work of this kind, as admitted at
done for the philosophy of science by the beginning, exceeds the limits of the
Patrick A. Heelan and for environmen- present review. An example is Hubert
talism by Michael Zimmerman. The Dreyfus' powerful critique of the pre-
task is yet to be accomplished in a sub- tensions of artificial intelligence and
stantial way for social and political phi- his endeavor to work out a conception
losophy, for the philosophy of art, and of human practice and intelligence
for theology. One can expect that in this which would be a fruitful and more ap-
country important contributions to this propriate alternative to the one that
stage of development will be forthcom- guides workers in computer science.''
ing. There is, so one may hope, a happy The Heideggerian inspiration of What
convergence of two currents that will Computers Can't Do and the later Mind
advance this enterprise. One is the over Machine is obvious and acknowl-
growing realization in social and politi- edged. But one would not call this a
cal philosophy that a less formalistic book on Heidegger and technology.
and pedantic, a more substantive and Is it possible to say something
lively approach is needed, that philoso- more about the tasks and prospects of
phy must join again the conversation of work on technology that departs from
humanity and respond to the concrete Heidegger? Dreyfus has provided a
apprehensions and aspirations of the helpful sketch for a program. He calls
human family. The other current is the for "a two-stage strategy," the first
growing interest in Heidegger's con- stage of which is the deconstruction of
cerns on the part of Anglo-American theoretical holism (1980, p. 22). This, as
philosophers who command profes- suggested above, should not take the
sional attention and some attention in form envisaged by Dreyfus of refuting
the culture at large. (some of) the explanatory claims of
The third stage is one of explora- (scientific) theories, but of showing
tion and development. It consists of at- their limits and of disentangling the
tempts to build on Heidegger's work or problem of modern science from that of
to work under Heidegger's inspiration modern technology.
in exploring issues that have been neg- The second stage in turn has two
lected or mistaken by Heidegger and in parts. First "one must give an interpre-
articulating a vision of our world which tation of our current cultural situation
is different from Heidegger's, perhaps by finding a cultural paradigm, . . .
less ambiguous or more hopeful than which focuses our dominant practices
his. This stage is exemplified in its ex- . . . " (1980, p. 22). Such a paradigm
ploratory side by Don Ihde's work and would have to incorporate what Heideg-
in its developmental aspect by the ger has to say about the framework, re-

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

157
sources, and procuring, and it would cludes our linguistic practices that
allow a testing of his insights against an alternative understanding of human
the phenomena and the literature of so- beings once existed and still continues,
cial reality. It might allow a sharper although drowned out by our everyday
delimitation of technology. We could busy concerns" (1980, pp. 22-23).
then see more clearly what measures Heidegger points to things and hardly
of reform would be mere variants and to the practices in which they exist. But
promotions of technology and which once we can recognize the simple
would be genuine and fruitful counter- things, we can see the micropractices
forces. as well: the celebration of meals,
As regards the latter, Dreyfus de- games, plays, and prayers, thoughtful
parts from Heidegger's remark that we and communal reading, hiking in the
should seek the saving power "here and wilderness, work that engages us, and
now and in little things." Dreyfus takes more. Such practices will seem
this as a call to attend to pretechnologi- hopelessly idyllic and impotent unless
cal micropractices. The latter term, we see them in the balance that Heideg-
taken from Foucault, may at first seem ger and Dreyfus emphasize, counter-
out of place. What does Heidegger's weighted by an incisive critique of tech-
cryptic remark mean? "In little nology which exposes the pointlessness
things" is "im Geringen" in German. of its present reign.
Gering means poor, inconspicuous, I think We can take still further
simple. In Heidegger's essay, the term steps. The world will remain largely
surely hearkens back to the passage in and permanently technological. But we
"The Thing" where he says: can and must make it generous to
things and to the practices in which
Nestling, malleable, pliant, com- they prevail. We must, moreover, re-
pliant, nimble in Old German flect on the fact that focal ("thinging")
these are called ring and gering. things will have a new character in the
The mirror-play of the worlding
world, as the ringing of the ring, widely technological universe. Corres-
wrests free the united four into pondingly the surrounding practices
their own compliancy, the circling cannot in the long run just be revivals
compliancy of their presence. Out or continuations of pretechnological
of the ringing mirror-play the customs.
thinging of the thing takes place As both Heidegger and Dreyfus in-
(1971, p. 180).
dicate, final success lies beyond our
willing. To acknowledge this and to act
In the second essay on technology, the on that acknowledgment is anything
counter-position of the thing in which a but passive. Yet while the strategy just
world appears to the framework of outlined seems to us radical and conse-
technology is made explicit (1977a, quential, it provides only a start. Most
pp. 433 and 446). philosophy either drifts along with
Dreyfus only mentions literary and something that has become deeply
historical examples of micropractices questionable, or it exhausts itself in
(1980, p. 22). But he insists that we perplexity. What is needed is the cour-
must assemble "all the evidence in our age of a simple and insightful begin-
micropractices and this of course in- ning.

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

158
ENDNOTES
1. Gerald Holton, "On Being Caught Between Heidegger-influenced approaches to understand-
Dionysians and Apollonians," Daedalus 103, no. ing the historically conditioned conceptions of na-
3, (Summer 1974): 65-81. ture which are nevertheless quite compatible
2. A minor monument to the violence of this clash with a critical-realistic stance, see Wolfgang
can be found in John R. Searle's review of Schadewaldt's "The Concepts of Nature and
Jonathan Culler's book on deconstruction, 'The Technique According to the Greeks" and Jacob
World Turned Upside Down," New York Review Klein's "The Nature of Nature," both in Research
of Books 30, no. 16 (October 27, 1983): 74-79 in Philosophy and Technology, vol. 2 (1979), pp.
and in a subsequent exchange of letters between 159-171 and 173-188, respectively.
Louis H. Mackey and Searle, ibid 31, no. 1 10. John Caputo, "The Thought of Being and the
(February 2, 1984): 47-48. A balanced account of Conversation of Mankind: The Case of Heidegger
the general controversy has been given by Gary and Rorty," Review of Metaphysics 36, no. 3,
Gutting, "Paradigms and Hermeneutics: A whole no. 143 (March 1983): 661-685.
Dialogue on Kuhn, Rorty and the Social Sci- 11. William J. Richardson, Heidegger: Through
ences," American Philosophical Quarteriy 21, no. Phenomenology to Thought (The Hague: Nijhoff,
1 Qanuary 1984): 1-15. 1967); and J.L. Mehta, Martin Heidegger: The
3. Robert Pirsig, Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Way and the Vision, revised edition (Honolulu:
Maintenance (New York: Morrow, 1974), p. 40. University of Hawaii Press, 1976).
4. See, e.g., Jerome Ravetz, Scientific Knowledge 12. Otto Pggeler, ed., Heidegger: Perspektiven zur
and Its Social Consequences (New York: Oxford Deutung seines Werks (Cologne: Kiepenheuer
University Press, 1971). and Witsch, 1969).
5. For more on this history of Being within which 13. It is worth noting that according to Karl Jaspers,
Heidegger situates the issue of technology, see Heidegger was quite critical of Jaspers' own style
Bernd Magnus, Heidegger's Metahistory of Phi- with its overlong sentences. See the section of
losophy: Amor Fati, Being and Truth (The Jaspers' philosophical autobiography on "Heideg-
Hague: Nijhoff, 1970); Werner Marx (1971); ger," in Paul Arthur Schilpp, ed.. The Philosophy
Sandra Lee Bartky (1979, in section B, 2 of the of Karl Jaspers: Augmented Edition (LaSalle, IL:
bibliography); the "Heidegger and the History of Open Court, 1981), pp. 75/1-75/16. Although
Philosophy" theme issue of The Monist 64, no. 4 written in the 1950s, Jaspers would not allow
(October 1981), with articles by Hans-Georg these pages to be published until after both his
Gadamer, Bernd Magnus, David Farrell Krell, and Heidegger's deaths. It is thus spliced in be-
David A. Kolb, Mark B. Okrent, David A. White tween pages 75 and 76 in this new edition of the
and Thomas Sheehan; and Michael Allen Gilles- Schilpp volume. For good commentary on the
pie, Hegel Heidegger, and the Ground of His- Heidegger-Jaspers relationship see two articles
tory (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, by David Farrell Krell: "Toward Sein und Zeit:
1984). The last volume is the best. Heidegger's Early Review (1919-1920) of Jas-
6. Albert Hofstadter, Truth and Art (New York: pers' Psychologie der Weltanschaungen, " Journal
Columbia University Press, 1965), p. 157. of the British Society for Phenomenology 6, no. 3
Hofstadter's position is actually more influenced (October 1975): 147-156; and "The Heidegger-
by Heidegger than the few explicit references Jaspers Relationship," ibid. 9, no. 2 (May 1978):
would indicate. After all, Hofstadter takes as his 126-129.
own the title of the last section of Heidegger's art 14. As an aside, it should also be noted that Egbert
essay. Schuurman's argument for Heidegger's depen-
7. Bernd Magnus, Heidegger's Metahistory of Phi- dence on Friedrich Georg Jnger, Ernst's
losophy, op. cit note 5, p. 91. younger brother, has no substantive basis
8. For a provocative appreciation of the relationship (Schuurman, 1980, pp. 100-102). To suggest that
between practical engagements and science con- Heidegger adopted the term "total mobilization"
tained in the work of two other philosophers who from Friedrich Jnger's Die Perfection der Tech-
can help throw light on what is at issue here, see nik (written in 1939, but not published in full until
Edith Wyschograd, "The Logic of Artifactual 1946), when this phrase occurs as the title of a
Existents: John Dewey and Claude Levi- volume by Ernst Jnger in 1931, betrays an un-
Strauss," Man and World 14, no. 3 (1981): 235 fortunate lapse of scholarship. Strangely enough,
250. even Joseph Kockelmans (1984, pp. 228-229) ac-
9. Charles Hartshome, Beyond Humanism: Essays cepts Schuurman's unsubstantiated claim.
in the Philosophy of Nature (Lincoln: University 15. For Krell's articles, see note 13. Hermann Mr-
of Nebraska Press, 1968), p. 305. For two chen's studies can be found in the relatively brief

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

159
(2 pages) Macht und Herrschaft in Denken von 24. The other commentary, Michael Gelven's A
Adorno und Heidegger (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, Commentary on Heidegger's "Being and Time"
1980) and the much longer (over 700 pages) (New York: Harper Torchbook, 1970) is, how-
Adorno und Heidegger: Versuch zu einer philoso- ever, a better general study.
phischen Kommunika tions Verweigerung 25. See, e.g., Theodor Adorno, The Jargon of Au-
(Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 1981). thenticity (Evanston, IL: Northwestern Univer-
16. See, e.g., Richard Rorty, "Overcoming the Trad- sity Press, 1973; German publication, 1964);
ition: Heidegger and Dewey," in Michael Murray, Marcuse (1977b); and the studies by Hermann
ed. (1978), as well as his (1979); and P. F. Straw- Mrchen cited in note 15.
son's review of George Steiner (1979), "Take the 26. See Georg Lukacs. Existentialisme ou Mar-
B Train," New York Review of Books 26, no. 6 xismen trans. E. Keleman (Paris: Nagel, 1948);
(April 19, 1979): 35-37. and "Existentialism," in R.W. Sellars, V.J.
17. Arne Naess, "The Shallow and the Deep, Long McGill, and M . Frber, eds.. Philosophy for the
Range Ecology: A Summary," Inquiry 16, no. 1 Future (New York: Macmillan, 1949), pp. 571
(Spring 1973): 95-100; and Christopher Stone, 590.
Should Trees Have Standing? (Los Altos, CA: 27. William Leiss, "Technological Rationality: Mar-
Kaufmann, 1974). cuse and His Critics," in his The Domination of
18. Stone, Trees, op. cit. note 17, pp. 42-54. Nature (New York: Braziller, 1972), pp. 199-212.
19. See, e.g., Gary Snyder, "Re-inhabitation," in his 28. See especially Max Horkheimer, Eclipse of
The Old Ways (San Francisco: City Lights Reason (New York: Seabury, 1974; first pub-
Books, 1977), pp. 57-66, based on a talk given at lished, 1947); and Max Horkheimer and Theodor
the "Reinhabitation Conference" supported by Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment, trans. John
the California Council on the Humanities and held Cumming (New York: Seabury, 1972; German
at the North San Juan School in August 1976. original, 1947).
20. Hendrik van Riessen, Filosophie en Techniek 29. See note 15 for both books.
(Kampen: Kok, 1949). This huge (over 700 30. Hans-Dieter Bahr, Kritik der ''Politischen Tech-
pages) historico-philosophical study of the precur- nologie" (Frankfurt: Europische Verlagsanstalt,
sors of the philosophy of technology remains de- 1970).
finitive to this date. 31. For some references see, e.g., William H. Shaw,
"The Handmill Gives You the Feudal Lord:'
21. A spectrum of reviews: The lead-offs were James
Marx's Technological Determinism," History and
Atlas, "Pursuit of the Really Real," Tinie (Sep-
Theory 18, no. 1 (1979): 155-176.
tember 4, 1978): 76 and 79; and Richard Boeth,
32. Jean-Paul Sartre, Critique of Dialectical Reason,
"The End of Reason," Newsweek (October 2,
trans. Alan Sheridan-Smith (New York: Schoc-
1978): 98; followed by Marjorie Grene, untitled
ken, 1976; French publication, 1960).
review. New Republic 179, no. 16 (October 14,
33. See, e.g., Jacques Ellul, Metamorphose du
1978) : 28-30; and John Murray Cuddihy, "Philos-
bourgeois (Paris: Calmann-Levy, 1967); and The
opher Home Free," New York Times Book Re-
Technological System, trans. Joachim Neugros-
view (December 24, 1978): 5. Eventually came
chel (New York: Seabury, 1980).
Jane Larkin Grain, "A Leap of Faith," National
34. For the initial unfolding of the discussion, see:
Review 31, no. 1 (March 2, 1979): 304 and 306;
Maurice de Gandillac and Alfred de Towamicki,
Peter Singer, "Human Prospecting," New York
"Deux documents sur Heidegger," Les Temps
Review of Books 26, no. 4 (March 22, 1979): 30
Modernes 1, whole no. 4 (1946): 713-724 (the
32; and Louis Dupre, "Being and tllt^ Will to
first document, "Entretien avec Martin Heideg-
Prayer," Commonweal 106, no. 11 Oune 8,
ger," is by Gandillac; the second, "Visite Mar-
1979) : 343-344. See also Borgmann, 1980b.
tin Heidegger," is by Towamicki); Karl Lwith,
22. See, along these same lines, some suggestions "Les implications politiques de la philosophie de
regarding the phenomenological differences be- I'existence chez Heidegger," Les Temps Mod-
tween tool and machine interactions with the ernes 2, whole no. 14 (November 1946): 343
human world and the need for a more thorough 360; and Eric Weil, "Le cas Heidegger," Les
delineation of Heidegger's Zeug phenomenology, Temps Modernes 3, whole no. 22 Quly 1947):
in Carl Mitcham, "Types of Technology," Re- 128-138.
sarch in Philosophy and Technology, vol. 1 35. See Hugo Ott, "Martin Heidegger und die Uni-
(1978), pp. 238-239. versitt Freiburg nach 1945," Historisches
23. Stuart F. Spicker, ed., Organism, Medicine, and Jahrbuch 105, no. 1 (1985): 95-128.
Metaphysics: Essays in Honor of Hans Jonas on 36. See, e.g., Frangois Fedier, "Trois attaques con-
his 75th Birthday (Boston: Reidel, 1978). tre Heidegger," Critique 22, whole no. 234

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

160
(November 1966): 883-904 a defense of 42. Carl Friedrich von Weizscker, "Begegnungen in
Heidegger by way of a review of Guido vier Jahrzehnten," Erinnerung an Martin Heideg-
Schneeberger's Nachlese zu Heidegger (privately ger, in Gnther Neske, ed., (Pfullingen: Neske,
published: Hochfeldstrasse 88, Bern, Switzer- 1977), p. 245; Mller (1986), p. 19; Ute Guzzoni,
land, 1962), Theodor Adomo's Jargon der "Bemerkungen zu Heidegger 1933," Ereiburger
Eigentlichkeit (Frankfurt, Suhrkamp, 1964), and Universittsbltter 25, whole no. 92 Gune 1986):
Paul Hhnerfeld's In Sachen Heidegger (Munich: 77.
List-Bcher, 1961). Three responses attacking 43. Albert Speer, Spandau: The Secret Diaries (New
Fedier's defense are contained in "A propos de York: Macmillan, 1976), entries for March 11 and
Heidegger," Critique 23, whole no. 237 (Feb- December 1, 1963; and for August 9, 1964.
ruary 1967): 284-297. These responses are 44. It is worth noting that no major study of the
"Language et Nazisme" by Robert Minder, "La holocaust considers the influence of technology
lecture et I'enonce" by Jean Pierre Faye, and and yet it was precisely trains, telecommuni-
"Serait-ce une querelle d'Allemand?" by Aime cations, and synthetic chemicals which allowed
Patri. Fedier's reply, "Une lecture denoncee" is the destruction of Jews and others to be pursued
published under the same general heading ("A on such a massive scale.
propos de Heidegger") in Critique 24, whole no. 45. Hannah Arendt, "Martin Heidegger at Eighty," in
242 Ouly 1967): 672-686. See also Jean-Michel Michael Murray (1978), pp. 293-303, actually ar-
Palmier (1968). gues that "Heidegger himself corrected his own
37. See, e.g., Roberto Mangabeira Unger, Knowl- 'error' more quickly and more radically than many
edge and Politics (New York: Free Press, 1975); of those who later sat in judgment over him" and
and Alasdair Maclntyre, After Virtue (Notre that "he took considerably greater risks than
Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, were usual in German literary and university life
1981). during that period" (p. 302, note 3). In this re-
gard, see Mildred Bakan, "Hannah Arendt's Ap-
38. See Jaspers, "Heidegger," op. cit. note 13.
propriation of Heidegger's Thought as Political
39. See Hugo Ott, "Martin Heidegger als Rektor der Philosophy," in Don Ihde and Hugh J. Silverman,
Universitt Freiburg i. Br. 1933/34," Zeitschrift eds., Descriptions (Albany: State University of
des Breisgau-Geschichtsvereins 102 (1983): 121 New York Press, 1985).
136; and 103 (1984): 107-130. The second part,
46. As formulated, e.g., by Ronald Dworkin in
with some brief but important additions, has been
"Liberalism," in Stuart Hampshire ed., Public and
published once more in "Martin Heidegger als
Private Morality (New York: Cambridge Univer-
Rektor der Universitt Freiburg 1933/34,"
sity Press, 1978), pp. 114-143.
Zeitschrift fr die Geschichte des Oberrheins 132
47. See, e.g., John Kenneth Galbraith, The New In-
(1984): 343-358. Otto Pggeler, "Den Fhrer
dustrial State, 2nd edition (Boston: Houghton
fhren? Heidegger und kein Ende," Philoso-
Mifflin, 1972); Staffan B. Under, The Harried
phische Rundschau 32, nos. 1-2 (1985): 26-67.
Leisure Class (New York: Columbia University
Ott announced his book in "Der Habilitand Martin
Press, 1970); Daniel J. Boorstin, Democracy and
Heidegger und das von Schaezler'sche Stipen-
Its Discontents (New York: Random House,
dium," Freiburger Dizesan-Archiv 106 (1986):
1975); Tiber Scitovsky, The Joyless Economy
note to the subtitle.
(New York: Oxford Unviersity Press, 1976); and
40. See Bernd Martin, "Heidegger und die Reform Fred Hirsch, Social Limits to Growth (Cam-
der deutschen Universitt 1933," Freiburger Uni- bridge, M A : Harvard University Press, 1976).
versittsbltter 25, whole no. 92 Qune 1986): 49 48. See note 10.
69. 49. See Ronald Dworkin, "To Each His Own" a
41. See Martin in the preceding note and Mller review of Michael Walzer's Spheres of Justice: A
(1986) in the bibliography; further: Gerhart Defense of Pluralism and Equality, New York
Schmitt, "Heideggers philosophische Politik," Review of Books 30, no. 6 (April 14, 1983): 4-6;
Freiburger Universittsbltter 25, whole no. 92 Dworkin and Michael Walzer, "'Spheres of Jus-
Gune 1986): 83-90; Pggeler (note 39 above); tice:' An Exchange," ibid. 30, no. 12 Guly 21,
and finally Rudolf Ringguth, "Fhrer der Fhrer," 1983): 43-46.
Der Spiegel 40, no. 34 (August 18, 1986): 164 50. A partial copy in the authors' possession is due to
169. The outdated standard view of the Heideg- Wolfgang Schirmacher.
ger supporters is once more presented by How- 51. C f Albert Borgmann, "Mind, Body, and World,"
ard Eiland in "Heidegger's Political Engagement," Philosophical Forum 8, no. 1 (Fall, 1976): 68-86.
Salmagundi, whole nos. 70-71 (Spring-Summer 52. Albert Hofstadter and Richard Kuhns, eds., Phi-
1986): 267-284. losophies of Art and Beauty (New York: Random

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

161
House, 1964); Albert Hofstadter, Truth and Art Dizesan-Archiv 104 (1984): 315-325 and "Der
(New York: Columbia University Press, 1965). Habilitand Martin Heidegger and das von
53. Karsten Harries, The Meaning of Modem Art Schaezler'sche Stipendium," ibid. 106 (1986):
(Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 141-160; Bernhard Casper, "Martin Heidegger
1968). See also Harries, The Bavarian Rococo und die Theologische Fakultt Freiburg, 1909
Church: Between Faith and Aestheticism, (New 1923," ibid. 100 (1980): 534-541.
Haven: Yale University Press, 1981). 65. Martin Heidegger zum 80. Geburtstag von seiner
54. Kent C. Bloomer and Charles W. Moore, Body, Heimatstadt Messkirch (Frankfurt: Klostermann,
Memory, and Architecture (New Haven: Yale 1969), pp. 1-15.
University Press, 1977); David P. Billington, The 66. For references to God, Christianity and faith, see
Tower and the Bridge: The New Art of Struc- Hildegard Feick, Index zu Heideggers Sein und
tural Engineering (New York: Basic Books, Zeit, " 2nd edition (Tbingen: Niemeyer, 1968),
1984). or Rainer A. Bast and Heinrich P. Delfosse,
55. See Noel Perrin, Giving Up the Gun: Japan's Re- Handbuch zum Textstudium von Martin Heideg-
version to the Sword (Boston: Godine, 1979). gers "Sein und Zeit" (Stuttgart-Bad Cannstadt:
56. See Zen Buddhism: Selected Writings of D.T. Holzboog, 1979). For some of the biographical
Suzuki, ed. W. Barrett (Garden City, NY: circumstances that shed light on Heidegger's un-
Doubleday Anchor Books, 1956), p. xi. derstandably troubled relation to the Catholic
57. Yoshihiro Nitta and Hirotaka Tatematsu, Church, see note 64 above and also Mller,
Japanese Phenomenology. Analecta Husserliana 1986, pp. 16 and 30.
vol. VIII (Boston: Reidel, 1979). 67., See Cari Mitcham, "Questions of Christianity and
58. Chikao Fijisawa, Zen and Shinto (New York: Technology: A Bibliographic Introduction," Sci-
Philosophical Library, 1959; reprint Westport, ence, Technology and Society, whole no. 14
CT: Greenwood Press, 1971). (November 1979): 1-17.
59. Kitaro Nishida, Intelligibility and the Philosophy 68. On Heidegger's combination of timidity and coun-
of Nothingness, trans. Robert Schinzinger (Hon- try smarts, see Mller, 1986, pp. 22-26 and 28;
olulu: East-West Center Press, 1958). Schmitt (see note 41 above), p. 85; and a remark
60. Kitaro Nishida, Fundamental Problems of Philos- of Gerhart Ritter quoted by Ott in "Martin
ophy, trans. David A. Dilwork (Tokyo: Sophia Heidegger als Rektor der Universitt Freiburg i.
University, 1970), pp. 40 and 94-95. Br. 1933/34," Zeitschrift des Breisgau-
61. Eugen Herrigel, Zen in the Art of Archery, trans. Geschichtesvereins 103 (1984): 127, n. 6.
R.F.C. Hull (New York: Random House, 1971), 69. For references see note 65 above.
p. 77. 70. Cari Mitcham and Jim Grote, eds.. Theology and
62. Murray Sayle, "Japan Victorious," New York Re- Technology (Lanham, M D : University Press of
view of Books 32, no. 5 (March 28, 1985): 33 America, 1984).
40; Ian Buruma, "A New Japanese Nationalism," 71. Hubert L. Dreyfus, What Computers Can't Do: A
New York Times Magazine (April 12, 1987): 22 Critique of Artificial Reason, rev. edition (New
29, 38. York: Harper & Row, 1979). first edition,
63. Some of the proceedings have been published in 1972); and Hubert L. Dreyfus and Stuart E.
Philosophisches Jahrbuch 102, no. 1 (1985): 110 Dreyfus, with Tom Athanasiou, Mind Over
148. Machine: The Power of Human Intuition and Ex-
64. On the religious circumstances and influences of pertise in the Era of the Computer (New York:
Heidegger's youth and education, see Hugo Ott, Free Press, 1986).
"Der junge Martin Heidegger," Ereiburger

Part Two
BIBLIOGRAPHY
The most extensive index to both primary and secondary materials is Hans-
Martin Sass, Martin Heidegger: Bibliography and Glossary (Bowling Green, OH:
Philosopohy Documentation Center, 1982) a volume with over 6000 unannotated
entries, which extends and updates Sass' earlier Heidegger-Bibliographie
(Meisenheim: Hain, 1968) and Materialien zur Heidegger-Bibliographie 1917-1971

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

162
physics" (Moser, 1971, p. 149) or the science. This is what Marcuse did at
more tentative point that the later least at one point though, as Habermas
Heidegger eliminates the possibility "of points out 1970, pp. 85-89), uncertainly
any purely contemplative science" even then. Indeed, when one con-
(Ihde, 1979, p. 128). More important, it templates the task of reconstituting
frees us from the fatalistic interpreta- philosophically the sciences in their
tion of the destiny of technology which central sense, one may well yield to
is apparent in Jonas' earlier work fatalism. But on the realist view of sci-
where he essentially, if not doxographi- ence sketched above one is relieved of
cally, accepts the view that modern sci- this impossible burden and can turn
ence and technology both issue from one's attention either to delimiting sci-
the Gestell. Modern science is in the entific practice on political grounds be-
end cogent not as a social institution or cause it is demanding too much capital
in its technological application but in investment or is politically destabiliz-
its central sense as a body of laws and ing (nuclear weapons), or to the pos-
theories, where it not only commands sibilities of reforming technology or
devotion and gratitude (both of which both (since they may well be related).
could be withdrawn), but makes truth The more profound of these pos-
claims which exact assent and to which sibilities lies in the vicinity of that axis
instrumentalism is a futile protest. which connects Heidegger's reflections
If one takes science as an essen- on art with the problem of religion in
tially destructive and dominating force, his thinking. And so we come to the sec-
then the critical implication of this ond division of this review.
view should lead one to propose a new

B. Technology Between Art and Religion

Heidegger's thought on technology nings of a reform of technology which


as it extends between science and poli- would consistently and fruitfully cor-
tics is radically critical. But scattered respond to Heidegger's examination of
throughout his writings there are sug- technology. And the brevity and
gestions that a salutary turn from, or lacunae of this part will be forgivable if
perhaps through, technology to a new the systematic end of this review is
epoch of Being may come about. Art properly served, the concern, i.e., to il-
and divinity are the powers Heidegger luminate our time and to make room in
most often mentions as guides or cen- it for a more graceful life.
ters for another kind of thought and
life. A well-rounded review of the 1. The Turn from Technology to
Heidegger literature on technology re- Art and Divinity
quires therefore a consideration of When in interviews Heidegger was
what work has been done on Heideg- asked whether from his thought con-
ger's thought where it deals with art structive proposals could be derived,
and borders on religious concerns. It is his answers were emphatically nega-
not our intention to provide an exhaus- tive (Wisser, 1970, pp. 68-69; Heidegger,
tive or even comprehensive survey but 1976a, pp. 276-84). But in less guarded
to give a sense of the extent to which moments he has been more venture-
work in this area has uncovered begin- some. At one point he thought of the

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

140
poet as one who might reach through cal analysis of the situation as it is
the destitution of our time and make created by world civilization" (1972, pp.
room for the advent of divinity (1971, 35-36). Schwan himself at one time
pp. 91-142). Heidegger put this point agreed with Heidegger that the fourfold
more generally in the concluding part of earth and sky, of mortals and di-
of his first essay on technology where vinities might provide the dimensions
he suggests that in art another revela- of a political renewal (1965, pp. 172-75).
tion of Being might come about that Later he found the fourfold too arbi-
could save us from the danger of tech- trary and abstract to be helpful (1974,
nology (1977a, pp. 34-35), a suggestion pp. 166-71). "For a sufficiently con-
that Ihde takes up in urging artistic crete, complex and problem-conscious
practice as a counterforce to technol- practical philosophy" one that he
ogy (1979, p. 129). says includes "a fundamental clarifica-
At another time Heidegger sur- tion of the relation, viz., of the correla-
mised that in rural, traditional areas tion and difference, of thinking and act-
the powers of home and history may be ing, i.e., a philosophy of praxis
reawakened, a suggestion later re- Heidegger's thought provides no basis
tracted, as Pggeler points out (1972, p. (nor a 'concrete Utopia')" (1974, p. 171).
35). Then there is the proposal, em- Harries, again, sees in the fourfold a
phasized by Hood (1972, p. 362) and more hopeful opening for political re-
Grange (1977, p. 147), that we take an form than in Heidegger's view of tech-
attitude of detachment toward the nology which provides a "one-dimen-
things of technology, that we use them sional interpretation of the modern
as far as appropriate, but refuse them world," and is "only a caricature of our
in their exclusive claim, a proposal that world" (1978, p. 328). Pggeler, in spite
Marcuse raised to the gesture of the of the scepticism quoted above, holds
Great Refusal (Piccone and Delfini, out the possibility that concrete
1970, p. 44; Ahlers, 1971, p. 588). Finally analyses, which orient themselves by
there is the brief remark in the first the constellation of Being as it even-
essay on technology, elaborated by tuates in the framework and in the
Dreyfus (1980), that we can foster the fourfold can yield "obligations which
saving power "here and now and in lit- are not to be ignored" (1972, p. 49; cf.
tle things" (1977a, p. 33), a point more pp. 50 and 64).
often and forcefully made in the second It is clear from Heidegger's re-
essay on technology (1977a, pp. 43, 45 marks and from those of his critics that
and 49) where Heidegger explains that the concern with art and divinity is a
in those simple focal things the fourfold crucial if poorly articulated counter-
of earth and sky, mortals and divinities part to the analysis of technology.
and thus a richer and deeper world is Heidegger scholarship on art and reli-
gathered and disclosed. gion has done little to clarify and elabo-
How helpful are these proposals in rate the relation between these counter-
light of our perplexity and complex parts.
technological situation? Even
Pggeler, whom Schwan (1974), pp. 153 2. Art and Technology
and 159) accuses of being all too solici- Heidegger's concern with art and
tous of Heidegger's thought, feels his essays on art originate, as William
moved to admit that Heidegger "lacks Bossart (1968) and Christopher Nwodo
even the beginnings of an explicit politi- (1977) have pointed out, in that decisive

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

141
period 1935-1937 in which a turn in In the "Addendum" to the art essay
Heidegger's thought took place and the Heidegger likewise directs attention to
reflections on technology were ini- this sameness and difference when he
tiated. The failure of the Heidegger lit- notes that his use of Gestell,
erature to consider the art-technology framework, in the discussion of art and
relation emphatically and trenchantly truth (Heidegger, 1971, p. 64) is the
may in part be due to Heidegger's deci- foundation for that which "we used in
sion to publish the art and the technol- later writings as the explicit key ex-
ogy essays in different collections in pression for the nature of modern tech-
Holzwege (1950) for the former, Vor^ nology" (p. 84).
trge und Aufstze (1961) for the latter, If Heidegger's thought on art has
a pattern repeated with slightly differ- done little to inspire the literature on
ent combinations in the English Poetry, Heidegger and technology, neither has
Language, Thought (1971) and The it, taken by itself, had much impact on
Question Concerning Technology and aesthetics and art criticism. Excep-
Other Essays (1977), respectively. It is tions are Albert Hofstadter and
also true that the major art essay Richard Kuhns' anthology Philosophies
achieved something like final form of Art and Beauty that contains the
more than a decade before the basic first (and later much revised) transla-
technology essay. Nevertheless, as tion of Heidegger's seminal essay on
Heidegger has often said, difference "The Origin of the Work of Art" and
and sameness go together so that in Hofstadter's later treatise on Truth and
this case too there are connections to be Art where Heidegger's thought pro-
noticed and considered. vides a crucial impetus if not the finally
decisive position.'' Though Heidegger's
Heidegger himself, as pointed out
thought strongly informed Karsten
above, indicates the significance of
Harries' The Meaning of Modern Art,
these connections. In fact, the structure
the explicit discussion of Heidegger is
of the two primary essays is remark-
very limited.'' Heidegger's conception
ably similar. The art essay begins by
of art, along with the hermeneutics of
considering art-work as a thing in
Being and Time, was also one of the
terms of the four causes (Heidegger,
guiding insights of Hans-Georg
1971, pp. 26 ff.) but moves on to de-
Gadamer's Truth and Method (1975).
scribe art as a disclosure of truth. The
Though Gadamer's book has been
technology essay begins by referring to
widely influential of late, it is its her-
technology as a kind of means and
meneutic message, the linguistic and
again considers this in terms of the four
social constitution of truth, that was so
causes (Heidegger, 1977a, p. 6 ff) but
eagerly accepted, and much at the ex-
proceeds to describe it as challenging
pense of the thesis that Gadamer had
and revealing. At the conclusion of the
taken from Heidegger's thought on art,
technology essay, Heidegger says that
i.e., the recognition that there is some-
thing like substantive epochal truth
the decisive confrontation with that is disclosed to us in unforethinka-
[technology] must happen in a ble ways. It is precisely the ignoring of
realm that is, on the one hand, this latter point that gives deconstruc-
akin to the essence of technology tionism its peculiarly vapid and fash-
and, on the other, fundamentally
different from it. Such a realm is ionable playfulness. Henry Sen-
art (Heidegger, 1977a, p. 35). daydiego (1976) makes a direct attempt

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

1/19
to use Heidegger to reform public policy for those free creative acts which give
about funding for the arts. And Walter a work a self-sufficiency apart from
Biemel, while on the American univer- "the world of a particular historical
sity lecture circuit in 1978, developed people" (p. 65).
the Heideggerian notion that "painting If nothing else, Calvin 0. Schrg
is not only a pure representation but a (1973) and Christopher Nwodo (1977)
representation which presents itself" are correct on this point (as was
(Biemel, 1979, p. 278), referring to Hofstadter in his introduction to
works by Velazquez and Picasso. Heidegger, 1971, pp. xv-xvi), pointing
As in the case of technology, out emphatically that Heidegger's in-
Heidegger's philosophy of art has had terpretation of art is fundamentally in
its expositors and for the most part has service to his thinking of Being. In
been poorly served by them. Hans Schrag's words, Heidegger's project for
Jaeger (1958) is an early, competent "overcoming the inquiry standpoint of
paraphrase of "The Origin of the Work traditional aesthetics" is "of the same
of Art." E . F . Kaelin (1967) presents a cloth as . . . his 'destruction' of the his-
more lively and helpful exposition tory of Western metaphysics" (pp. 109
which is remarkable to this day for the 110). Schrg plays down, however,
way it sets off Heidegger's essay Heidegger's positive intentions and ig-
against Merleau-Ponty's work. Yet nores the unique status he grants to art.
Kaelin can be faulted for unquestion- For Nwodo, equally dramatically,
ingly placing Heidegger's essay in the Heidegger's analysis is not meant to
narrow and traditional framework of "produce any new theory of art" (1977,
aesthetics when it is clear not only p. 294). In an analysis which superfi-
from the thrust of Heidegger's reflec- cially parallels Theodore Kisiel's (1973)
tions but from explicit remarks (1971, distinction between Heidegger's logi-
pp. 79-81; 1977a, pp. 34 and 35; all avail- cal, existential, and epochal concep-
able in German at the time of Kaolin's tions of science, Nwodo names "three
writing) that Heidegger rejected and phases in Heidegger's thought-path to-
sought to break through the aesthetic wards Being" (p. 295) as stages for his
categories. reflections on art: (l)the existential
The same charge must be brought analytic of Dasein, (2)the revelation of
against William H. Bossart (1968). He the ontological difference, (3)the Ereig-
begins by outlining as a backdrop those nis or the event of appropriation.
passages in Being and Time that ex- The problem with this analysis (as
plain how humans take up with the with Bossart's) is that the distinction
world and then turns to one of the Hl- between the first two stages is unhelp-
derlin interpretations as the transition ful for a discussion of art in Heidegger.
piece to "The Origin of the Work of Art (Kunst) is conspicuous by its ab-
Art." The exposition of the latter essay sence in Being and Time, and poetry
is followed by an inquiry which at- (Dichtung) is only referred to once in
tempts to determine whether Heideg- passing as a kind of communication
ger's aesthetics covers all important which can be "a disclosing of exis-
views of art. Here Bossart finds tence" because the communication . . .
Heidegger limited by "metaphysical of one's state-of-mind [has] become an
prejudices" (p. 63), unable to account aim in itself" (p. 205 [162]). Nwodo has
for the art of the great eccentrics and to conscript "The Origin of the Work of
for those free creative acts which give Art" for service in the first phase of

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

143
Heidegger's thought, ignoring the fact One wonders what is more regret-
that the Introduction to Metaphysics, table, such outright lapses of scholar-
which stands for the second phase, was ship or the general failure of cir-
composed at the same time as the cumspection and incisiveness that
essay on art and makes essentially the speaks from Nwodo's remark: "We
same points as that essay. In particu- have tended to avoid controversies and
lar, the art essay explicitly formulates have concentrated upon portraying
what Nwodo calls the later ontological Heidegger's thinking as we understand
difference conception of art (1971, p. it" (1971, p. 303). At the same time, a
39). meticulous and critical approach can
The weakness of Nwodo's first two just as surely lead to unhappy and un-
distinctions is highlighted by Edward helpful results, as is evident in Sandra
Lawry (1978), who points out that as Lee Bartky's "Heidegger's Philosophy
discussed in "The Origin of the Work of of Art" (1981). The critical basis of her
Art" the work of art fits into none of the examination is the mainstream analy-
types of beings distinguished in Being tic philosophy of the late 1950s and
and Time. Art is neither something early 1960s and the metaphysical tradi-
ready to hand nor present at hand, and tion generally. Hence as a matter of
it is certainly not Dasein. "A work of course she employs concepts and as-
art is neither thing nor equipment." It cribes to Heidegger views that he has
is "in some mysterious way between radically criticized and vigorously re-
them." It is "like equipment because it jected. Like Kaelin and Bossart, she
has a function;" but unlike equipment unhesitatingly puts Heidegger in the
"art works flaunt their material" (p. framework of traditional aesthetics
190). The art work, as Harold Alder- (pp. 257 and 273) and invokes among
man (1973) earlier notes in a perceptive others the notion of the Romantic and
analysis that moves from thing to art to modern artist (pp. 272-73) to, of all
poetry, is "the most thingly of things" things, commend Heidegger for "an ac-
(p. 157). count of the artwork which grants
At the same time, it does make legitimacy to the conception of the art-
sense to attend expressly, as Nwodo ist as seer and prophet," totally una-
does, to Heidegger's consideration of ware of how such praise clashes with
Being as the event of appropriation. Heidegger's critique of modern subjec-
This consideration constitutes the tivism and his misgivings about art
thought of the later and last Heidegger since at least Hegel's time (1971, pp. 79
where he speaks with the greatest clar- 81). In the same unquestioning spirit
ity and force about our historical situa- Bartky attributes to Heidegger a
tion. Nwodo sketches this period in the search for the (metaphysical) essence
narrowly Heideggerian discourse that of art (pp. 257 and 267) and the employ-
ment of a naive phenomenology to-
characterizes both this and his earlier
gether with blindness to the hermeneu-
(1976) essay. When he finally places art
tic circle of interpretation (p. 272 and p.
in this third stage of Heidegger's
274 note 12). This is like taking Einstein
thought, he does so by quoting a re-
to task for failing to recognize the rela-
mark of Heidegger's (1971, p. 86) that
tivity of motion.
Heidegger had intended as a clarifica-
tion of the essay that Nwodo had used In the first English monograph to
to illustrate the status of art in the first address Heidegger's philosophy of art,
phase. Joseph Kockelmans (1985) continues to

PHILOSOPHY TODAY
exhibit the weaknesses of the exposit- inquiry "into the nature of art" is "the
ory tradition though with redeeming preliminary and therefore indispensa-
features. Part one of this book (pp. 3 ble preparation for the becoming of
68) again insists on situating Heideg- art" (Heidegger, 1971, p. 78) and how
ger's analysis of art against the back- this is brought into question by the con-
ground of traditional aesthetics. More tinuing predominance of modern tech-
thorough than previous discussions, nology. Kockelmans rightly notes
Kockelmans does have the merit of ad- Heidegger's own explicit doubts in an
verting to Heidegger's various criti- untranslated lecture on art delivered at
cisms of this tradition. It would have Athens in 1967 (Heidegger, 1983). But
been useful, however, to have a discus- Kockelmans' many comments add up
sion of the failure of Heidegger's ideas to very little substantive insight.
to have much impact on subsequent Kathleen Wright's (1984) "The
aesthetics and art criticism, except in- Place of the Work of Art in the Age of
sofar as deconstructionism can be read Technology" has the distinction of ad-
as an airy and often aimless offspring dressing directly the topic that was
of Heideggerian radicalism. found to be neglected so regularly. It
In part two of his monograph (pp. has been followed by Friedrich-
71-210), Kockelmans provides a de- Wilhelm von Herrmann's (1985) "Kunst
tailed analysis of "The Origin of the und Technik," another of the punctih-
Work of Art" along lines laid down ear- ous and antiseptic expositions one has
lier in German by Friedrich-Wilhelm come to expect from this author.
von Herrmann (1980). Here Heideg- Wright's is clearly the superior piece.
ger's essay is carefully dissected, and It is distinguished by superior scholar-
not just into its three major sections ship, viz., by a subtle grasp of the origi-
with "Epilogue" and "Addendum." nal German texts, by clarity of reason-
"The Thing and the Work," "Art Work ing and the readiness to confront
and Truth," and "Truth and Art" are Heidegger's reflections with eminent
each subdivided, sub-subdivided, and predecessors (Descartes and Kant) and
paraphrased, with a generous commen- contemporaries (Valery and Benja-
tary that makes abundant references to min). Finally, her thesis is intriguing
related essays by Heidegger, particu- and profoundly hopeful. "I shall
larly on poetry and the poets. But one argue," she says,
cannot help but wonder whether all this
scholarship is put to noble ends when that for Heidegger it is within and
all it yields is the conclusion that what out of the displacement of the
Heidegger has to say about art "is cer- work of art in the age of technol-
ogy that an alternative to place as
tainly provisional, incomplete, and in
cult site or exhibition setting
many respects still ambiguous" (p. emerges, an alternative which
210). exemplifies what is for Heidegger
Kockelmans, as if in response to the saving power of art (1984, p.
the implicit challenge from Heidegger 566).
to address the art-technology differ-
ence, drops into his analysis of the art More specifically, Wright en-
essay numerous scattered references to deavors to show that works of art,
technology (or, as he prefers, "technic- sculpture in "Art and Space" (1969b),
ity"). He also calls attention, in the and the peasant's shoes and the temple
end, to Heidegger's final claim that his in "The Origin of the Work of Art,"

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

145
open up a dwelling place that differs tence, and Heidegger's looking forward
fundamentally from scientific and tech- to a Jiew simplicity. But Harries goes
nological space. Yet the result is in the beyond Heidegger in his larger appreci-
end disappointing. ation of modern philosophy, of people
Wright's and Heidegger's three ex- like Schopenhauer, Freud, Lukacs and
amples are essentially pretechnologi- Sartre, and in his acquaintance with
cal; and in a pretechnological setting, the varieties of modern art. Much the
to be sure, they did or would establish a same can be said of Fandozzi's essays
nontechnological dwelling place. But (1979 and 1982) which in addition show
nothing in Wright's account would indi- a keen eye for the corrupting force of
cate how these art works could assert the consumer culture and boldness of
their orienting power within, against, conjecture in contemplating the future
or after technology. For the saving of technological art. David Hallibur-
power to grow in our time, the relation ton's (1981) "From Poetic Thinking to
between art and technology must go Concrete Interpretation" directs
beyond mere otherness toward some Heidegger's reflections on technology,
sort of affirmative interplay. Wright the fourfold, and on the equipment
has failed to answer convincingly structure in Being and Time toward a
Heidegger's fearful question (1971, p. poem of Wordsworth's and discloses
80), "is art still an essential and neces- how in the poem the centering force of
sary way in which that truth happens rural life is threatened by the emerging
which is decisive for our historical exis- technological framework and yet af-
tence, or is art no longer of this charac- firmed and entrusted to the future.
ter?" Like Heidegger, she is unable to Halliburton quotes (p. 76) among
show that art may again be of this others from Heidegger's essay, "Build-
character, and so her essay remains at ing, Dwelling, Thinking" (1971, pp. 143
the level of higher exposition. 61). It contains an important and
What most of the expository work largely neglected link between Heideg-
on art in Heidegger shows is that the ger's thought on technology and on art
framework of technology has a close and between the diagnosis of technol-
analogue in the framework of scholar- ogy and the healing power of things.
ship which like its technological ar- The fruitfulness of those connections
chetype is largely concealed, well en- appears in the possibility of finding
trenched, and threatens to occlude the one's way from the terse and recondite
saving power of things that might be proposals of Heidegger to the rich, de-
the occasion for a turn of affairs. More tailed and hopeful work of Kent C.
particularly, that expository work Bloomer and Charles W. Moore in
shows once more how the fertility of Body, Memory, and Architecture and
Heidegger's thought requires, as of David P. Billington in The Tower and
Heidegger himself recognized (1971, p. the Bridge: The New Art of Structural
5), adversaries, thinkers who challenge Engineering.^'' Here too the despair of
Heidegger's insight from a position of Schwan and Harries as regards the
their own. centering force of art for the common
Beginnings of such a challenge can welfare, mentioned in section A, 7 of
be found in Harries (1968) whose this review, is answered in a quietly
critique of modern art reflects Heideg- constructive manner. And here, finally,
ger's critique of modern subjectivity, of one may glimpse the outlines of the
the shallowness of technological exis- new dwelling place for which Kathleen

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

14
Wright has been searching. These discussion of Heidegger and mysticism.
hopes for a turn of technology will oc- First, it shows that the chief critics of
cupy us once more at the conclusion of Heidegger's mysticism, Paul Hhner-
this review. feld, Karl Lwith, and Laszlo Versenyi,
rely on a very tentative or even mista-
3. Mysticism and the East ken notion of mysticism. Caputo fur-
Heidegger has not only thought nishes constructive proof of this claim
about the question of what may consti- by giving a careful exposition of Eck-
tute a genuine counterforce to technol- hart's mysticism (pp. 97-139). That ex-
ogy and bring about a turn of our des- position further allows for a detailed
tiny. He has also practiced a kind of distinction between mysticism proper
thinking which may be taken as a radi- and Heidegger's thinking which,
cal alternative to technology, a kind of Caputo says, is not truly mystical but
thinking that Heidegger himself has does contain a mystical element (pp.
called meditative thinking (1966, p. 46). 222-40). Like mysticism, Heidegger's
It has a certain kinship with mysticism, thinking is the experience of a power
and the latter term has served as a that we cannot and do not want to con-
nodal point for critical and supportive trol and capture through conceptual
views of Heidegger's thought. These systems. Yet Heidegger's thinking has
contentions bear on our review inas- a much higher and more explicit re-
much as mysticism is counterposed to gard for language than does mysticism.
technology. The complexity of the issue It is more radically historical and
is heightened by Heidegger who, on the therefore more critical of metaphysics.
one hand, rejects the term mysticism And it moves at so fundamental a level
for his thinking (1969a, p. 53). In an un- that, unlike mysticism, it neither
published letter to Reinhart Maurer he nourishes nor seems to depend on the
says pointedly: "Only those deal in the moral conduct at the surface of every-
'mysticism of Being' who are not able day life.
to enact the thinking of Being, of its dis- Caputo is keenly aware that the
closing essence according to the on- mystical element in Heidegger in its re-
tological difference of Being and be- flective and receptive calmness is an-
ings." On the other hand, he acknowl- tipodal to the aggressive busyness of
edges that "to genuine and great mysti- that technology and that technology is
cism there belongs the utmost acute- always the implicit theme of medita-
ness and profoundness of thinking as tive thinking. He is, moreover, critical
well" (1957a, German edition, p. 71). of the austerity and reserve of Heideg-
Moreover there is Heidegger's well- ger's thought which seems to drive us
known affection for the great Meister into the unhappy dilemma of the practi-
Eckhart and his deep respect for East- cally ineffective piety of thought vs. the
ern thought. barren and suppressive practice of
Regarding mysticism particularly, cybernetics (1978, p. 257). As
the writers who use this term to charge documented earlier, Caputo's criticism
Heidegger with obscurantism and eva- can be supported by explicit remarks of
siveness more or less had the field to Heidegger's. But it overlooks many
themselves until the publication of John other, more constructive and helpful,
D. Caputo's The Mystical Element in suggestions that Heidegger has made.
Heidegger's Thought in 1978. His book Caputo throughout his book calls
does much to clarify and advance the for a fruitfully adversarial relationship

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

147
with Heidegger's thought and rightly Heidegger and one particular Asian
rejects the epigones who dismiss every culture, namely the Japanese, stressing
criticism of Heidegger as a misun- more specifically one aspect of that cul-
derstanding. But Caputo's own counter- ture, namely Zen Buddhism. Japanese
position to Heidegger is not rich and ar- culture did not participate in the long
ticulate enough to nurture the seeds of development of metaphysics that has
reform that lie concealed in Heideg- culminated in technology as Heidegger
ger's mystical element. Yet one should has it. Rather, it has been strongly in-
not blame Caputo for doing first things formed by Zen Buddhism which, as ap-
first. In regards to mysticism too, pears from remarks above, is opposed
Heidegger scholarship has been in a to technology. And the Japanese did in
primitive and deplorable state. Caputo fact provide one of the very few in-
has brought clarity and order into this stances where a community rejected a
neglected area. He has done so with technological innovation, in this case
fairness toward his opponents, critical firearms, for reasons that are conso-
sympathy toward Heidegger, with care- nant with Heidegger's critique of tech-
ful scholarship, and in an engaging, nology."' But this was at the very begin-
though occasionally expansive, style. ning of the modern era, and by now
Western mysticism has a well- Japan is perhaps the technologically
known kinship with Eastern thought, most accomplished country in the
particularly with Zen Buddhism, and so world.
provides a link between Heidegger and
the East. Caputo considers this tie suc- The limitation of what follows to
cinctly (1978, pp. 203-27) and illustrates Zen Buddhism is justified on a number
and elaborates relations that have pre- of counts. From the side of Heidegger,
viously emerged in a conference on the most obvious is the importance of
"Heidegger and Eastern Thought," or- Shuzo Kuki in the dialogue of On the
ganized in 1969 by Borgmann, Eliot Way to Language (1971, pp. 1-54). (As it
Deutsch, and others at the University happens, Kuki was also the man who
of Hawaii. (The proceedings were pub- introduced Sartre to Heidegger. As a
lished in Philosophy East and West 20, student, after studying with Heidegger
no. 3 [July 1970].) The outcome of this in Freiburg, Kuki went to Paris. Sartre,
symposium was to document both also a student, answered Kuki's adver-
Heidegger's explicit interest in Oriental tisement for a French tutor.) Kuki's in-
thinking and various parallels between fluential The Structure of "IkV' (1930,
Heideggerian and East Asian themes. followed by numerous reprints) is a
But the symposium also highlighted im- phenomenological description of iki, of
portant differences, among them the that aesthetic way of life peculiar to the
following. First, Buddhism'^ stress is Japanese. Based on stumi (taste or ele-
ethical, grounded in dealing with the gance), it cannot easily be discussed,
problem of suffering, whereas Heideg- but must be lived, an argument evi-
ger's is ontological, concerned with the dently influenced by Heidegger's analy-
theme of Being. Second, for Buddhism sis of the primordial character of Da-
Being is not essentially historical, as it sein ' s practical being-in-the-world.
is for Heidegger. Then there is the fact that Zen Bud-
These considerations suggest that it dhism, like Heidegger's later thought,
is perhaps instructive to examine in seems to involve some kind of uniting
more detail the relation between of art and mysticism. Finally, there is

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

148
William Barrett's unsubstantiated gos- bued with Buddhism, one who in fact
sip about Heidegger and Zen.'' retired from teaching at the University
From the side of Japan the justifi- of Kyoto to die in a Zen monastery.
cation is even stronger. Not only has Robert Schinzinger, in an introduction
Being and Time been translated into to his translation of Nishida's Intelligi-
Japanese more times (five) than into hility and the Philosophy of Nothing-
any other language, Japanese commen- ness, remarks on a number of compari-
tators have done a number of impor- sons between Nishida and Heidegger
tant studies and adaptations of Heideg- and, indeed, more could have been ob-
ger, work that has been summarized by served.'' Yet all such comparisons fade
Hoshihiro Nitta, Hirotaka Tatematsu beside Nishida's own criticisms of
and Eiichi Shimomisse in Heidegger, which can be summarized
"Phenomenology and Philosophy in as two: (1) Heidegger has not gotten
Japan.'"' More recently Akira Ishida hold of the concrete practical world in
(1975) and Aritsune Yonezawa (1975) his phenomenological description of
have dealt directly with Heidegger's Dasein. His history is still a concept;
philosophy of art and Shoichi Omori his "world" is not a real world which
(1972) has examined the relation be- determines human action but remains
tween art and technology. Finally, at a world of understanding.^ (2) Con-
the popular level, the Neo-Shintoist sciousness in Husserl and Heidegger
Chikao Fijisawa appeals to Heidegger has not been truly purged of individual-
in his critique of contemporary culture ity and subjectivity. The transcendence
and goes so far as to identify Das Sein and objectivity of consciousness has not
with the Kami (gods or divine forces in been recognized. (This second argu-
Shinto).'^ This last example reminds us, ment, while not specifically applied
too, that the World War H alliance of against Heidegger, occurs again and
Germany and Japan should not be dis- again throughout Fundamental Prob-
counted. lems and other works.)
Despite such mutual and well-es- There remain of course two strong
tablished influences, however, parallels between Zen Buddhism and
Japanese culture poses a number of Heidegger, one from the later Heideg-
critical questions for Heidegger. At an ger and one from the early. Both
implicit level there is the sociological Buddhism and the later Heidegger
fact that it was Japan, a country evi- teach that the highest human possibil-
dently under the sway of decidedly non- ity is reached in a spirit of detachment
Western ways of thinking, that has and receptivity, the counter-position to
nevertheless, as mentioned above, been self-love or subjectivism. It was
the most adroit at adopting Western reached by Eugen Herrigel, as his ac-
technology. Surely this raises problems count in Zen in the Art of Archery tells
for Heidegger's reading of modern us, when he ceased in his endeavors to
technology as dependent on Western master his shot and let "It" shoot
metaphysics. (Caputo, 1978, pp. 208-9).'^ The other
At a more explicit level is the ex- parallel comes from Heidegger's 1929
ample of Kitaro Nishida (1870-1945), the lecture What is Metaphysics? where he,
greatest of Japanese philosophers. much like the Buddhist tradition,
Nishida was well acquainted with and speaks about the Nothing as the
respectful of the work of Husserl and groundless ground of all there is
Heidegger, besides being a man im- (Caputo, 1978, pp. 212-13). But on this

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

149
point there is not only a parallel but a metaphysics and as technology is too
divergence of views as well, i.e., a con- well entrenched to yield to a quick and
troversy on whether Heidegger had determined move. Hence he proposes
grasped the Nothing with sufficient that we read ber as "concerning" and
radicality (Nakaoka, 1985). engage in a reflection "Concerning the
Before we turn to concluding re- Line" of nihilism, a suggestion that
marks on the light that the relation of Fandozzi has taken up in his essay
Heidegger and the East sheds on tech- Nihilism and Technology (1982).
nology, an aside on Heidegger and the Heidegger in The Question of Being
Nothing is required. Critics of Heideg- (1956) is less than sanguine about the
ger have pounced on his reflection on prospect of a deeper understanding of
the Nothing to accuse him of nihilism. nihilism. In fact the facile concept and
That Heidegger should be stigmatized charge of nihilism at times enters into
as a nihilist especially by someone such an unholy alliance with a shallow no-
as Stanley Rosen (1969) is passing tion of myticism. Their putative eva-
strange. Rosen is a student of Leo siveness and obscurantism are seen by
Strauss, a proponent of two principles Rosen as the reason for Heidegger's
which should guard against such a pre- political imprudence. In a similar
cipitous and rhetorical judgment: the spirit, Strauss says of Heidegger's
idea that one must be very careful thought: "There is no room for political
about claiming to understand a philoso- philosophy in Heidegger's work, and
pher better than he understands him- this may well be due to the fact that the
self; and a careful distinction between room in question is occupied by gods or
opinion and knowledge, exoteric and the gods" (1971, p. 2).
esoteric teachings. Heidegger perhaps Yet however misdirected these ob-
_more than any other contemporary jections, they do raise an important
philsopher has claimed to be trying to question of long standing, the question,
overcome that nihilism which he sees i.e., of whether personal mysticism
as the culmination of the Western does not have a fatal inclination toward
philosophical tradition. With regard to practical imprudence and political
the alleged nihilistic character of nihilism. In the present context we can
Heidegger's teaching, the refutation by formulate the question more cautiously
David A. White (1975) is persuasive. and ask, in conclusion, whether the
Heidegger's own defense against mystical element in Heidegger and the
the charge of nihilism is readily avail- kindred movements in Eastern thought
able in The Question of Being (1956). In have helped us to see technology more
its original form the essay was ad- clearly and hopefully.
dressed to Ernst Jnger in a To begin with the East, the com-
Festschrift for his sixtieth birthday in plex of issues involving technology, its
response to one from Jnger com- reform, and the Japanese experience is
memorating Heidegger's own sixtieth of great philosophical and current in-
anniversary six years previously. terest. Its present prominence in this
Jnger's contribution was entitled country is due to the fact that the con-
"ber die Linie," understood by Jnger ception that Americans have of their
as "across" or "over the line" (of place in the world and in history is
nihilism), i.e., as an attempt at moving strongly informed by the technological
beyond nihilism. In reply, Heidegger power and prowess of the United
urges that nihilism as the end phase of States. But this claim to world histori-

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

150
cal significance is now being chal- culture as the world's sole salvation
lenged by Japan which in productivity and have met regularly with Prime
and increasingly in research is overtak- Minister Nakasone to discuss Japan's
ing the United States. This has led, as national identity.
Murray Sayle and Ian Buruma have At the Honolulu conference, Umeh-
shown in different ways, to anger and ara (1970) read a paper acknowledging
incomprehension on the American side his debt to Heidegger (p. 273), denounc-
and to searching and troubling debates ing the technological culture of "mate-
among the Japanese.'' rial goods and sex" (p. 272; cf p. 278),
The philosophically challenging and calling for a "continuing dialogue
issue unhappily falls between the horns between thinkers of the East and the
of the dilemma that Caputo has de- West" about the global destiny of
plored (1978, p. 257). The American humankind (p. 281). Whether Umehara
reaction and the Japanese responses has in fact moved on to an intolerant
that Sayle considers are firmly within and repressive position is impossible to
the framework of the calculating think- establish from the direct quotations,
ing of technology. At the same time or- but his account is a warning to those
thodox Eastern and comparative phi- who would criticize the technologically
losophy as well as the usual Heidegger specified liberal state that they make
scholarship timidly cling to the high themselves clear on the indispensable
and highest ground of philosophical value of tolerance and civil liberty.
abstraction and tradition. At a confer- Is there any hope of drawing from
ence on "The Critique of the Times the sources of mysticism and Eastern
after Heidegger" which was held at the thought to irrigate in a liberal and to-
University of Augsburg (West Ger- lerant way the barren ground that lies
many), scholars from West Germany, between the technological enterprise
France, Italy, the United States, and and philosophical meditation? As re-
Japan were in attendance.'' Though it gards the East, there may be such cul-
was in many ways a stimulating and tivation going on now, and we are ig-
rewarding affair and proceeded under norant of it due to the fact, remarked
an appropriately ambiguous and pro- by Heidegger in his letter to the Hon-
vocative title, there was little consid- olulu conference, "that with few excep-
eration of the concrete circumstances tions there is no command of the East-
under which technology is taking its ern languages either in Europe or in
course around the globe. If there was the United States" (1970, p. 221). As re-
an undercurrent of vital interest, it was gards myticism and the mystical ele-
furnished by the playfulness of recent ment in Heidegger, it will be a matter
French philosophy. of first recovering that tradition in the
Buruma, however, believes to have fuller and perhaps more vital setting of
discovered a philosophical force in religion and Christianity.
Japanese politics that is critical of
technology and has practical though 4. Relgion and Christianity
limited significance. He names Takeshi In the Spiegel interview Heidegger
Umehara as the leader of a racist and was asked whether the individual or
chauvinist school of philosophy philosophy could influence the constric-
(Heidegger's name comes up in this tive network of the absolute technologi-
context) whose members, so Buruma cal state. Heidegger denied that possi-
says, proclaim traditional Japanese bility and gave his by now celebrated

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

151
answer: "Only a god can save us" time of Catholic education without re-
(1976a, p. 277). The significance of this sentment; in fact, he singles out two of
answer is underlined not only by the his clerical mentors with obvious affec-
fact that Heidegger once more brought tion (1958, pp. 3-4). Similarly, he wrote
up "the arrival or the absence of the about the religious life of his boyhood
god" when the question of reform arose with unreserved warmth.'^ And when
again a little later in the interview; the he felt his death approaching, he asked
answer also hearkens back to the close a Catholic priest, Bernhard Welte, that
of Heidegger's major essay on technol- he "say a few words in his memory at
ogy where, taking guidance from Hl- the burial" (Welte, 1982, p. 86).
derlin, he asserts that at the height of And yet Caputo, surely a well-in-
the danger of technology the saving formed and sensible reader of Heideg-
power would grow as well (1977, p. 28). ger, says of his thought that it is "radi-
Is God then the one to whom cally worldly and secular" (1978,
Heidegger instructs us to turn for sal- p. 252). The standard argument in sup-
vation in the face of the danger of tech- port of this view has been assembled by
nology? Not really, for Heidegger James L. Perotti in Heidegger on the
speaks of a god or the god; "god" is not Divine (1974). Perotti follows Heideg-
a proper name for him. This seemingly ger's development to show how his
fine point of linguistic usage is a clue to questions became increasingly radical
the complex relation Heidegger had and broke through the established ways
throughout his life to religion and of thinking and speaking, including
Christianity. And the broader context those that one follows to reflect and
in which this point has its place also talk about God. These are now seen to
contains a complex relation between be restricted and superficial. Tradi-
-technology and Christianity in Heideg- tional theology is discredited. But this
ger's thought. These complexities must is not to deny God. At the deeper level
be outlined and if possible clarified to of thought that Heidegger attains a new
provide a fuller context for the review experience of God becomes possible.
of work on Heidegger and technology. Perotti is concerned to present
The point is to round out this context Heidegger's views of the divine and
rather than furnish a review of the lit- God within the over-all movement of
erature on Heidegger, religion, Christ- Heidegger's thought, and much of his
ianity, and theology, a literature that is book is devoted to tracing this move-
extensive and requires a survey in its ment. What mars this laudable inten-
own right. tion is the triumphalist tone of Perotti's
Heidegger grew up in simple, account in which the power and tren-
rural, and intensely Roman Catholic chancy of Heidegger effortlessly pre-
circumstances. For a gifted boy4xi such vail over all traditions and objections.
a setting an academic career meant Perotti's ambitious preoccupation
studying for the priesthood. People like moreover disburdens him from a more
Heidegger's parents would otherwise modest but desirable achievement, viz.,
neither have had the courage to aim so a careful historical-doxographical ac-
high for their son nor would they have count of the periodic emergence and
mustered the resolve to take on the nec- submersion of the religious theme in
essary economic burdens.'^ In the brief Heidegger's work. Finally Perotti
autobiographical sketch that Heidegger seems unsure of his conclusion, both of
has left us he appears to remember his its substance and of its radicality. As

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

152
regards his substantive finding, he first tentative indication of a goal" (1982,
asserts: "The word about god will p. 88; our translation from the origi-
come forth from Heidegger only as a nal). And toward the end of Heideg-
response to the presence or absence of ger's career, the word "Being" re-
god" (p. 118). But then he has Heideg- mains behind and no longer needs to be
ger disavow any experience of God and mentioned (1982, pp.95, 97, and 98).
defer to the "unique prerogative of the Caputo would so far agree with Welte.
poet" on this point. "Heidegger," But Welte sees the early Heidegger's
Perotti says, "has selected and com- reflections on the oblivion of Being and
mitted his thinking to the poet Hlder- on the simultaneous disclosure and con-
lin" (p. 119). cealment of Being as stages on the way
Concerning the radicality of toward Heidegger's experience of the
Heidegger's position Perotti seems una- absence of God. And Heidegger, so
ware of the crucial question, what bear- Welte continues, not only gives expres-
ing the thinking of Being will finally sion to this absence but takes steps to-
have on God and the divine. The tenor ward a positive appreciation of this ab-
of Perotti's book suggests that the sence so that in that absence first hints
superior and in fact supreme radicality of the presence of the All-High begin to
of Heidegger's thinking and of its appear.
theme. Being, will provide a radically Welte presents his case with sub-
new ground or space for the appear- tlety and insight. And its seems sub-
ance of God. In this case, God would no stantially right. But it is also narrow,
longer be the supreme power but both systematically and in point of
merely a moment within the history of Heidegger's intellectual biography. To
Being. At the same time, Perotti's begin with the latter, here as in many
explicit conclusions, considered just other respects, scholars have allowed
now, both intimate a more limited role the old Heidegger to set the tone for the
for Being and its thinking, one that interpretation of the younger Heideg-
would finally be in the service of God's ger's work. In this way, a harmony and
epiphany. On this question one might consistency appear in the development
not agree with Caputo; but one must of Heidegger's relation to God and reli-
certainly acknowledge the forthright- gion that did not in fact obtain. It is not
ness and clarity of his answer which the case that Heidegger began from a
embraces the former of the alterna- religious position and then moved on to
tives above. "I do not mean that there a searching examination of Being
is no place for God in the later Heideg- which led him beyond a vital faith in
ger," he says, "but that Heidegger's God (Caputo) or to a profound experi-
God is not the Lord of history. He does ence of the absence of God (Perotti)
not govern the missions of Being with and of intimation of a new ephiphany
loving care. Rather His own appear- (Welte). It is apparent from the scat-
ance in history is subject to the move- tered references to God, Christianity,
ments of the world-play" (1978, p. 254). and faith in Being and Time that
The religious view of Heidegger's Heidegger at the height of his first
thought is taken by Heidegger's great great accomplishment did not just re-
fellow townsman, Bernhard Welte. flect more deeply and dispassionately
Being, Welte points out, is never a de- on his religious position but was con-
finitive theme or power in Heidegger's cerned to put a great critical distance
thought. It is at first "only a formal and between his work and religion.''

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

153
In the year of the pubUcation of our question, but he cannot really
Being and Time, he gave a lecture on question without ceasing to be a
"Phenomenology and Theology" believer and taking all the conse-
(1976b, pp. 3-21), a document which has quences of such a step. He will
only be able to act 'as i f . . . (1953,
been available in German since 1970
p. 6).
and which both Perotti and Welte have
ignored. There he tried to work out, in As he often does, Heidegger goes on to
light of Being and Time, a principled soften and qualify this categorical
relationship between philosophy and statement on a crucial issue and re-
theology, one that would give each dis- marks that such unquestioning faith is
cipline its due. Roughly, philosophy is really no faith at all but rather conveni-
taken by Heidegger as the reflection on ence and indifference.
the basic modes of Being that can be Still, Heidegger comes at least very
undertaken without envisaging the spe- close to saying that the Christian can-
cific Christian mode of being in the not be a philosopher. Both in 1927 and
world. Theology by contrast, is based in 1935 he dismisses Christian philoso-
on the philosophically unsurpassable gi- phy as "a wooden iron" (1976b, p. 21,
venness of faith. Theology, therefore, where the translator has "square cir-
cannot take its direction from philoso- cle"; 1953, p. 6; the translator has
phy. As a scholarly enterprise, how- "round square"). One might suppose
ever, it must draw in a complementary that the venturesome resoluteness that
and preliminary way on the philosophi- Heidegger thinks to be closed off to the
cal illumination of the basic modes of believer is of a piece with the subjec-
human existence. Heidegger tries to tive and voluntaristic authenticity of
capture this result by saying that, al- the early Heidegger that, in the later
though philosophy cannot give direction Heidegger, as Zimmerman has shown
to theology, it does provide correction. (1981), yields to detachment and open-
Philosophy could well exist without act- ness as the authentic mode of human
ing as a theological corrective. Simi- being. And the latter attitude is much
larly faith, though not the scholarly dis- closer to faith as is evident from the
cipline of theology, can exist without proximity of Heidegger and Meister
philosophy. Eckhart, considered in the previous
But just when Heidegger has ar- section. Yet as late as 1954, in a conver-
rived at this adjudication of the various sation with Protestant philosophers and
claims and territories, he goes on to theologians, Heidegger if anything saw
say that faith as a mode of existence is an even deeper chasm dividing theol-
the mortal enemy of the mode of exis- ogy and philosophy (1976b, pp. 59-71).
tence that belongs to philosophy (1976b, It is this dualistic and sometimes
p. 20). The reason is only hinted at. angry view of the relationship of the
Faith is contrasted with the philoso- philosopher to the believer that is omit-
phers' free appropriation of their own ted by Perotti and Welte. We should
total existence. Eight years later, in In- spell out at this point what is implicit in
troduction to Metaphysics, Heidegger the preceding sections. Even at his
spells out what is at issue in this con- most critical, Heidegger would never
trast: join in the criticism of Christianity that
has gained currency under the name of
One who holds to such faith can in the "Lynn White Thesis," according to
a way participate in the asking of which Christianity, by despiritualizing

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

154
nature, provides a tabula rasa for tech- divine God" (1957b, p. 72). Closer than
nology and abettes the ecological the mainstream believers and theolo-
crisis.'' For Heidegger, the metaphysi- gians? This is what Heidegger in his
cal origins of technology arise much rustic sort of cunning implies but then
earlier, viz., with Plato. And they come explicitly denies when he continues:
to a tangible fruition much later, "Here this means only: god-less think-
namely toward the middle and end of ing is more open to Him than onto-theo-
the modern period. It should also be logic would like to admit" (ibid.).'''
noted that one who grew up in a setting What are we to make of the fact
that was shaped in the Middle Ages and that in Heidegger's thought a dismis-
where many a medieval practice was sive and dualistic and a concernful and
still alive would be immune to the preparatory view of faith and theology
seductive simplicity of White's thesis. are vying with one another? Setting
Side by side with the critical and aside narrowly biographical considera-
separatist view of Christianity, faith, tions and returning to the question of
and theology we do find the other view technology, we can see that what the
which is very nearly the received one two views have in common is a deep
and from which the philosopher's work concern for the difficulty and signifi-
is seen as the replacement of theology cance of the task of thought. In the
or at least as a new preparation for dualistic position, which is essentially
theology and perhaps even faith. The the earlier one, we can see a concern to
preparatory view is first given pro- face up to the difficulty of philosophical
grammatically in the Letter on reflection and to keep premature and
Humanism, written in 1946, where pat answers at bay. The difficulty at
Heidegger says: first occupies Heidegger more than the
significance of thought since the early
Only from the truth of Being can radical resolve of his work was still
the essence of the holy be thought. ambiguous and without firm guidance,
Only from the essence of the holy as suggested many times in the forego-
is the essence of divinity to be
ing pages. But as Heidegger settled
thought. Only in the light of the es-
sence of divinity can it be thought more and more clearly on the destiny
or said what the word "God" is to of technology as the crucially signifi-
signify (1947, p. 230; see also cant issue of thought, his attitude to-
p. 218). ward faith and theology became more
conciliatory and congenial.
In "The Onto-Theo-Logical Consititu- Yet Heidegger remained worried
tion of Metaphysics" of 1957, Heidegger that the clearing he was trying to open
not only proposes such a program but up for a new advent of divinity would
appears to claim it as his own. He be overgrown by the facile and ineffec-
suggests that his refusal to talk about tive pronouncements of the established
God is due to the fact that he has ex- ways of thinking. This is especially evi-
perienced theology in its genuine dent in Heidegger's epistolary reply to
rootedness, "both the theology of Chris- Welte's article (Welte, 1975, p. 85). He
tian faith and that of philosophy" gently reminds Welte of two things:
(1957b, pp. 54-55). And he submits that first, that his concern with the question
his "god-less thinking which must of God cannot be separated from his re-
abandon the god of philosophy, god as flections on the modern history of
causa sui, is thus perhaps closer to the Being, i.e., on technology and science;

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

155
and second, that he has come to no con- throughout his life accepted the cul-
clusions, that he is still "on the path of tural embodiment of Catholic Christian-
inquiry." ity in his native environment is evident
Heidegger's assertion that only a from scattered remarks in his formal
god can save us from the danger of essays and from various addresses he
technology is not just a flourish or gave in his hometown of Messkirch
rhetoric of despair. His thought on tech- (Mller, 1986, p. 30).
nology cannot be fully grasped without There are, to be sure, many other
attention to his reflections on divinity theological currents that may fruitfully
and God. But neither should one as- converge with Heidegger's thought,
sume that there is a theological answer notably process theology which shares
to Heidegger's philosophical question. important parts of Heidegger's critique
The radically new epoch of Being in of metaphysics and of a metaphysically
which we are implicated requires us to structured theology. The problem of the
rethink from the ground up what we relationship between technology and
mean by faith and how we experience theology in Heidegger is only beginning
the divine. More specifically we must to receive attention, and this is true of
clarify the religious and theological sig- the general field of technology and
nificance of our practical and reflective theology. A beginning has been made in
experience of science and technology. Carl Mitcham and Jim Crete's anthol-
Such a proposal, of course, would be ogy. Theology and Technology.'^^ It
anathema to Protestant theologians, shows how inadequate are our tradi-
such as Karl Barth, who reject as an tional categories of history and philoso-
expression of human arrogance any re- phy, of cause and effect, of power and
flection that is even tentatively inde- grace, of failure and wholeness, of the
pendent of and antecendent to faith. sacred and the profane, and how diffi-
Catholic theologians, such as Welte and cult it is to rethink these matters in
Karl Rahner, nevertheless work in a light of the challenge of Heidegger's
tradition that has long practiced such thought and of our experience of tech-
procursive reflection under the heading nology and faith.
of fundamental theology.
Heidegger's thought is consensual 5. The Overcoming of Technology
with Catholicism not only along this We have clustered the works under
traditional theological line but also review around thematic points. But
through Heidegger's sacramental con- running through those clusters is a pro-
ception of reality that is so evident in gressive movement of scholarship with
his reflections on the fourfold. The Ger- three discernible stages. The first is the
man word for fourfold, Vierung, is in stage of translation and exposition. The
fact the technical term for the crossing translations clearly were necessary to
of nave and transept in a medieval acquaint a larger audience with
church. The cathedral in Freiburg Heidegger's thought: the larger the au-
where Heidegger lived for most of his dience to be reached, the more formi-
life has a powerful Romanesque cross- dable the obstacle of linguistic compla-
ing, concealed under the roof of the cency. The expositions were intended to
nave, as a point of balance between the help Anglo-American readers over-
austere Gothic nave, the magnificient come the idiosyncrasies of Heidegger's
late Gothic choir, and the late style and to spell out those assumptions
Romanesque transept. That Heidegger of Heidegger's that could not be taken

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

156
for granted in these parts. Whether the books of Edward G. Ballard and Wil-
expository work has in fact made a sig- liam Barrett. Such work surely repre-
nificant contribution to the Heidegger sents the most important stage and
reception in the EngUsh speaking world fruit of Heidegger scholarship. As re-
is uncertain. At any rate, it is time for marked at the beginning of this review,
this phase to come to an end. if Heidegger's thought finally matters,
The next stage is that of a dialogue it will be through work of this kind, as-
where Heidegger's thought on technol- suming that such work in turn will at
ogy is drawn into a serious conversa- long last inform our social and cultural
tion with the best minds of modern and practices.
contemporary thought. This has been Work of this kind, as admitted at
done for the philosophy of science by the beginning, exceeds the limits of the
Patrick A. Heelan and for environmen- present review. An example is Hubert
talism by Michael Zimmerman. The Dreyfus' powerful critique of the pre-
task is yet to be accomplished in a sub- tensions of artificial intelligence and
stantial way for social and political phi- his endeavor to work out a conception
losophy, for the philosophy of art, and of human practice and intelligence
for theology. One can expect that in this which would be a fruitful and more ap-
country important contributions to this propriate alternative to the one that
stage of development will be forthcom- guides workers in computer science.''
ing. There is, so one may hope, a happy The Heideggerian inspiration of What
convergence of two currents that will Computers Can't Do and the later Mind
advance this enterprise. One is the over Machine is obvious and acknowl-
growing realization in social and politi- edged. But one would not call this a
cal philosophy that a less formalistic book on Heidegger and technology.
and pedantic, a more substantive and Is it possible to say something
lively approach is needed, that philoso- more about the tasks and prospects of
phy must join again the conversation of work on technology that departs from
humanity and respond to the concrete Heidegger? Dreyfus has provided a
apprehensions and aspirations of the helpful sketch for a program. He calls
human family. The other current is the for "a two-stage strategy," the first
growing interest in Heidegger's con- stage of which is the deconstruction of
cerns on the part of Anglo-American theoretical holism (1980, p. 22). This, as
philosophers who command profes- suggested above, should not take the
sional attention and some attention in form envisaged by Dreyfus of refuting
the culture at large. (some of) the explanatory claims of
The third stage is one of explora- (scientific) theories, but of showing
tion and development. It consists of at- their limits and of disentangling the
tempts to build on Heidegger's work or problem of modern science from that of
to work under Heidegger's inspiration modern technology.
in exploring issues that have been neg- The second stage in turn has two
lected or mistaken by Heidegger and in parts. First "one must give an interpre-
articulating a vision of our world which tation of our current cultural situation
is different from Heidegger's, perhaps by finding a cultural paradigm, . . .
less ambiguous or more hopeful than which focuses our dominant practices
his. This stage is exemplified in its ex- . . . " (1980, p. 22). Such a paradigm
ploratory side by Don Ihde's work and would have to incorporate what Heideg-
in its developmental aspect by the ger has to say about the framework, re-

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

157
sources, and procuring, and it would cludes our linguistic practices that
allow a testing of his insights against an alternative understanding of human
the phenomena and the literature of so- beings once existed and still continues,
cial reality. It might allow a sharper although drowned out by our everyday
delimitation of technology. We could busy concerns" (1980, pp. 22-23).
then see more clearly what measures Heidegger points to things and hardly
of reform would be mere variants and to the practices in which they exist. But
promotions of technology and which once we can recognize the simple
would be genuine and fruitful counter- things, we can see the micropractices
forces. as well: the celebration of meals,
As regards the latter, Dreyfus de- games, plays, and prayers, thoughtful
parts from Heidegger's remark that we and communal reading, hiking in the
should seek the saving power "here and wilderness, work that engages us, and
now and in little things." Dreyfus takes more. Such practices will seem
this as a call to attend to pretechnologi- hopelessly idyllic and impotent unless
cal micropractices. The latter term, we see them in the balance that Heideg-
taken from Foucault, may at first seem ger and Dreyfus emphasize, counter-
out of place. What does Heidegger's weighted by an incisive critique of tech-
cryptic remark mean? "In little nology which exposes the pointlessness
things" is "im Geringen" in German. of its present reign.
Gering means poor, inconspicuous, I think We can take still further
simple. In Heidegger's essay, the term steps. The world will remain largely
surely hearkens back to the passage in and permanently technological. But we
"The Thing" where he says: can and must make it generous to
things and to the practices in which
Nestling, malleable, pliant, com- they prevail. We must, moreover, re-
pliant, nimble in Old German flect on the fact that focal ("thinging")
these are called ring and gering. things will have a new character in the
The mirror-play of the worlding
world, as the ringing of the ring, widely technological universe. Corres-
wrests free the united four into pondingly the surrounding practices
their own compliancy, the circling cannot in the long run just be revivals
compliancy of their presence. Out or continuations of pretechnological
of the ringing mirror-play the customs.
thinging of the thing takes place As both Heidegger and Dreyfus in-
(1971, p. 180).
dicate, final success lies beyond our
willing. To acknowledge this and to act
In the second essay on technology, the on that acknowledgment is anything
counter-position of the thing in which a but passive. Yet while the strategy just
world appears to the framework of outlined seems to us radical and conse-
technology is made explicit (1977a, quential, it provides only a start. Most
pp. 433 and 446). philosophy either drifts along with
Dreyfus only mentions literary and something that has become deeply
historical examples of micropractices questionable, or it exhausts itself in
(1980, p. 22). But he insists that we perplexity. What is needed is the cour-
must assemble "all the evidence in our age of a simple and insightful begin-
micropractices and this of course in- ning.

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

158
ENDNOTES
1. Gerald Holton, "On Being Caught Between Heidegger-influenced approaches to understand-
Dionysians and Apollonians," Daedalus 103, no. ing the historically conditioned conceptions of na-
3, (Summer 1974): 65-81. ture which are nevertheless quite compatible
2. A minor monument to the violence of this clash with a critical-realistic stance, see Wolfgang
can be found in John R. Searle's review of Schadewaldt's "The Concepts of Nature and
Jonathan Culler's book on deconstruction, 'The Technique According to the Greeks" and Jacob
World Turned Upside Down," New York Review Klein's "The Nature of Nature," both in Research
of Books 30, no. 16 (October 27, 1983): 74-79 in Philosophy and Technology, vol. 2 (1979), pp.
and in a subsequent exchange of letters between 159-171 and 173-188, respectively.
Louis H. Mackey and Searle, ibid 31, no. 1 10. John Caputo, "The Thought of Being and the
(February 2, 1984): 47-48. A balanced account of Conversation of Mankind: The Case of Heidegger
the general controversy has been given by Gary and Rorty," Review of Metaphysics 36, no. 3,
Gutting, "Paradigms and Hermeneutics: A whole no. 143 (March 1983): 661-685.
Dialogue on Kuhn, Rorty and the Social Sci- 11. William J. Richardson, Heidegger: Through
ences," American Philosophical Quarteriy 21, no. Phenomenology to Thought (The Hague: Nijhoff,
1 Qanuary 1984): 1-15. 1967); and J.L. Mehta, Martin Heidegger: The
3. Robert Pirsig, Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Way and the Vision, revised edition (Honolulu:
Maintenance (New York: Morrow, 1974), p. 40. University of Hawaii Press, 1976).
4. See, e.g., Jerome Ravetz, Scientific Knowledge 12. Otto Pggeler, ed., Heidegger: Perspektiven zur
and Its Social Consequences (New York: Oxford Deutung seines Werks (Cologne: Kiepenheuer
University Press, 1971). and Witsch, 1969).
5. For more on this history of Being within which 13. It is worth noting that according to Karl Jaspers,
Heidegger situates the issue of technology, see Heidegger was quite critical of Jaspers' own style
Bernd Magnus, Heidegger's Metahistory of Phi- with its overlong sentences. See the section of
losophy: Amor Fati, Being and Truth (The Jaspers' philosophical autobiography on "Heideg-
Hague: Nijhoff, 1970); Werner Marx (1971); ger," in Paul Arthur Schilpp, ed.. The Philosophy
Sandra Lee Bartky (1979, in section B, 2 of the of Karl Jaspers: Augmented Edition (LaSalle, IL:
bibliography); the "Heidegger and the History of Open Court, 1981), pp. 75/1-75/16. Although
Philosophy" theme issue of The Monist 64, no. 4 written in the 1950s, Jaspers would not allow
(October 1981), with articles by Hans-Georg these pages to be published until after both his
Gadamer, Bernd Magnus, David Farrell Krell, and Heidegger's deaths. It is thus spliced in be-
David A. Kolb, Mark B. Okrent, David A. White tween pages 75 and 76 in this new edition of the
and Thomas Sheehan; and Michael Allen Gilles- Schilpp volume. For good commentary on the
pie, Hegel Heidegger, and the Ground of His- Heidegger-Jaspers relationship see two articles
tory (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, by David Farrell Krell: "Toward Sein und Zeit:
1984). The last volume is the best. Heidegger's Early Review (1919-1920) of Jas-
6. Albert Hofstadter, Truth and Art (New York: pers' Psychologie der Weltanschaungen, " Journal
Columbia University Press, 1965), p. 157. of the British Society for Phenomenology 6, no. 3
Hofstadter's position is actually more influenced (October 1975): 147-156; and "The Heidegger-
by Heidegger than the few explicit references Jaspers Relationship," ibid. 9, no. 2 (May 1978):
would indicate. After all, Hofstadter takes as his 126-129.
own the title of the last section of Heidegger's art 14. As an aside, it should also be noted that Egbert
essay. Schuurman's argument for Heidegger's depen-
7. Bernd Magnus, Heidegger's Metahistory of Phi- dence on Friedrich Georg Jnger, Ernst's
losophy, op. cit note 5, p. 91. younger brother, has no substantive basis
8. For a provocative appreciation of the relationship (Schuurman, 1980, pp. 100-102). To suggest that
between practical engagements and science con- Heidegger adopted the term "total mobilization"
tained in the work of two other philosophers who from Friedrich Jnger's Die Perfection der Tech-
can help throw light on what is at issue here, see nik (written in 1939, but not published in full until
Edith Wyschograd, "The Logic of Artifactual 1946), when this phrase occurs as the title of a
Existents: John Dewey and Claude Levi- volume by Ernst Jnger in 1931, betrays an un-
Strauss," Man and World 14, no. 3 (1981): 235 fortunate lapse of scholarship. Strangely enough,
250. even Joseph Kockelmans (1984, pp. 228-229) ac-
9. Charles Hartshome, Beyond Humanism: Essays cepts Schuurman's unsubstantiated claim.
in the Philosophy of Nature (Lincoln: University 15. For Krell's articles, see note 13. Hermann Mr-
of Nebraska Press, 1968), p. 305. For two chen's studies can be found in the relatively brief

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

159
(2 pages) Macht und Herrschaft in Denken von 24. The other commentary, Michael Gelven's A
Adorno und Heidegger (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, Commentary on Heidegger's "Being and Time"
1980) and the much longer (over 700 pages) (New York: Harper Torchbook, 1970) is, how-
Adorno und Heidegger: Versuch zu einer philoso- ever, a better general study.
phischen Kommunika tions Verweigerung 25. See, e.g., Theodor Adorno, The Jargon of Au-
(Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 1981). thenticity (Evanston, IL: Northwestern Univer-
16. See, e.g., Richard Rorty, "Overcoming the Trad- sity Press, 1973; German publication, 1964);
ition: Heidegger and Dewey," in Michael Murray, Marcuse (1977b); and the studies by Hermann
ed. (1978), as well as his (1979); and P. F. Straw- Mrchen cited in note 15.
son's review of George Steiner (1979), "Take the 26. See Georg Lukacs. Existentialisme ou Mar-
B Train," New York Review of Books 26, no. 6 xismen trans. E. Keleman (Paris: Nagel, 1948);
(April 19, 1979): 35-37. and "Existentialism," in R.W. Sellars, V.J.
17. Arne Naess, "The Shallow and the Deep, Long McGill, and M . Frber, eds.. Philosophy for the
Range Ecology: A Summary," Inquiry 16, no. 1 Future (New York: Macmillan, 1949), pp. 571
(Spring 1973): 95-100; and Christopher Stone, 590.
Should Trees Have Standing? (Los Altos, CA: 27. William Leiss, "Technological Rationality: Mar-
Kaufmann, 1974). cuse and His Critics," in his The Domination of
18. Stone, Trees, op. cit. note 17, pp. 42-54. Nature (New York: Braziller, 1972), pp. 199-212.
19. See, e.g., Gary Snyder, "Re-inhabitation," in his 28. See especially Max Horkheimer, Eclipse of
The Old Ways (San Francisco: City Lights Reason (New York: Seabury, 1974; first pub-
Books, 1977), pp. 57-66, based on a talk given at lished, 1947); and Max Horkheimer and Theodor
the "Reinhabitation Conference" supported by Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment, trans. John
the California Council on the Humanities and held Cumming (New York: Seabury, 1972; German
at the North San Juan School in August 1976. original, 1947).
20. Hendrik van Riessen, Filosophie en Techniek 29. See note 15 for both books.
(Kampen: Kok, 1949). This huge (over 700 30. Hans-Dieter Bahr, Kritik der ''Politischen Tech-
pages) historico-philosophical study of the precur- nologie" (Frankfurt: Europische Verlagsanstalt,
sors of the philosophy of technology remains de- 1970).
finitive to this date. 31. For some references see, e.g., William H. Shaw,
"The Handmill Gives You the Feudal Lord:'
21. A spectrum of reviews: The lead-offs were James
Marx's Technological Determinism," History and
Atlas, "Pursuit of the Really Real," Tinie (Sep-
Theory 18, no. 1 (1979): 155-176.
tember 4, 1978): 76 and 79; and Richard Boeth,
32. Jean-Paul Sartre, Critique of Dialectical Reason,
"The End of Reason," Newsweek (October 2,
trans. Alan Sheridan-Smith (New York: Schoc-
1978): 98; followed by Marjorie Grene, untitled
ken, 1976; French publication, 1960).
review. New Republic 179, no. 16 (October 14,
33. See, e.g., Jacques Ellul, Metamorphose du
1978) : 28-30; and John Murray Cuddihy, "Philos-
bourgeois (Paris: Calmann-Levy, 1967); and The
opher Home Free," New York Times Book Re-
Technological System, trans. Joachim Neugros-
view (December 24, 1978): 5. Eventually came
chel (New York: Seabury, 1980).
Jane Larkin Grain, "A Leap of Faith," National
34. For the initial unfolding of the discussion, see:
Review 31, no. 1 (March 2, 1979): 304 and 306;
Maurice de Gandillac and Alfred de Towamicki,
Peter Singer, "Human Prospecting," New York
"Deux documents sur Heidegger," Les Temps
Review of Books 26, no. 4 (March 22, 1979): 30
Modernes 1, whole no. 4 (1946): 713-724 (the
32; and Louis Dupre, "Being and tllt^ Will to
first document, "Entretien avec Martin Heideg-
Prayer," Commonweal 106, no. 11 Oune 8,
ger," is by Gandillac; the second, "Visite Mar-
1979) : 343-344. See also Borgmann, 1980b.
tin Heidegger," is by Towamicki); Karl Lwith,
22. See, along these same lines, some suggestions "Les implications politiques de la philosophie de
regarding the phenomenological differences be- I'existence chez Heidegger," Les Temps Mod-
tween tool and machine interactions with the ernes 2, whole no. 14 (November 1946): 343
human world and the need for a more thorough 360; and Eric Weil, "Le cas Heidegger," Les
delineation of Heidegger's Zeug phenomenology, Temps Modernes 3, whole no. 22 Quly 1947):
in Carl Mitcham, "Types of Technology," Re- 128-138.
sarch in Philosophy and Technology, vol. 1 35. See Hugo Ott, "Martin Heidegger und die Uni-
(1978), pp. 238-239. versitt Freiburg nach 1945," Historisches
23. Stuart F. Spicker, ed., Organism, Medicine, and Jahrbuch 105, no. 1 (1985): 95-128.
Metaphysics: Essays in Honor of Hans Jonas on 36. See, e.g., Frangois Fedier, "Trois attaques con-
his 75th Birthday (Boston: Reidel, 1978). tre Heidegger," Critique 22, whole no. 234

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

160
(November 1966): 883-904 a defense of 42. Carl Friedrich von Weizscker, "Begegnungen in
Heidegger by way of a review of Guido vier Jahrzehnten," Erinnerung an Martin Heideg-
Schneeberger's Nachlese zu Heidegger (privately ger, in Gnther Neske, ed., (Pfullingen: Neske,
published: Hochfeldstrasse 88, Bern, Switzer- 1977), p. 245; Mller (1986), p. 19; Ute Guzzoni,
land, 1962), Theodor Adomo's Jargon der "Bemerkungen zu Heidegger 1933," Ereiburger
Eigentlichkeit (Frankfurt, Suhrkamp, 1964), and Universittsbltter 25, whole no. 92 Gune 1986):
Paul Hhnerfeld's In Sachen Heidegger (Munich: 77.
List-Bcher, 1961). Three responses attacking 43. Albert Speer, Spandau: The Secret Diaries (New
Fedier's defense are contained in "A propos de York: Macmillan, 1976), entries for March 11 and
Heidegger," Critique 23, whole no. 237 (Feb- December 1, 1963; and for August 9, 1964.
ruary 1967): 284-297. These responses are 44. It is worth noting that no major study of the
"Language et Nazisme" by Robert Minder, "La holocaust considers the influence of technology
lecture et I'enonce" by Jean Pierre Faye, and and yet it was precisely trains, telecommuni-
"Serait-ce une querelle d'Allemand?" by Aime cations, and synthetic chemicals which allowed
Patri. Fedier's reply, "Une lecture denoncee" is the destruction of Jews and others to be pursued
published under the same general heading ("A on such a massive scale.
propos de Heidegger") in Critique 24, whole no. 45. Hannah Arendt, "Martin Heidegger at Eighty," in
242 Ouly 1967): 672-686. See also Jean-Michel Michael Murray (1978), pp. 293-303, actually ar-
Palmier (1968). gues that "Heidegger himself corrected his own
37. See, e.g., Roberto Mangabeira Unger, Knowl- 'error' more quickly and more radically than many
edge and Politics (New York: Free Press, 1975); of those who later sat in judgment over him" and
and Alasdair Maclntyre, After Virtue (Notre that "he took considerably greater risks than
Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, were usual in German literary and university life
1981). during that period" (p. 302, note 3). In this re-
gard, see Mildred Bakan, "Hannah Arendt's Ap-
38. See Jaspers, "Heidegger," op. cit. note 13.
propriation of Heidegger's Thought as Political
39. See Hugo Ott, "Martin Heidegger als Rektor der Philosophy," in Don Ihde and Hugh J. Silverman,
Universitt Freiburg i. Br. 1933/34," Zeitschrift eds., Descriptions (Albany: State University of
des Breisgau-Geschichtsvereins 102 (1983): 121 New York Press, 1985).
136; and 103 (1984): 107-130. The second part,
46. As formulated, e.g., by Ronald Dworkin in
with some brief but important additions, has been
"Liberalism," in Stuart Hampshire ed., Public and
published once more in "Martin Heidegger als
Private Morality (New York: Cambridge Univer-
Rektor der Universitt Freiburg 1933/34,"
sity Press, 1978), pp. 114-143.
Zeitschrift fr die Geschichte des Oberrheins 132
47. See, e.g., John Kenneth Galbraith, The New In-
(1984): 343-358. Otto Pggeler, "Den Fhrer
dustrial State, 2nd edition (Boston: Houghton
fhren? Heidegger und kein Ende," Philoso-
Mifflin, 1972); Staffan B. Under, The Harried
phische Rundschau 32, nos. 1-2 (1985): 26-67.
Leisure Class (New York: Columbia University
Ott announced his book in "Der Habilitand Martin
Press, 1970); Daniel J. Boorstin, Democracy and
Heidegger und das von Schaezler'sche Stipen-
Its Discontents (New York: Random House,
dium," Freiburger Dizesan-Archiv 106 (1986):
1975); Tiber Scitovsky, The Joyless Economy
note to the subtitle.
(New York: Oxford Unviersity Press, 1976); and
40. See Bernd Martin, "Heidegger und die Reform Fred Hirsch, Social Limits to Growth (Cam-
der deutschen Universitt 1933," Freiburger Uni- bridge, M A : Harvard University Press, 1976).
versittsbltter 25, whole no. 92 Qune 1986): 49 48. See note 10.
69. 49. See Ronald Dworkin, "To Each His Own" a
41. See Martin in the preceding note and Mller review of Michael Walzer's Spheres of Justice: A
(1986) in the bibliography; further: Gerhart Defense of Pluralism and Equality, New York
Schmitt, "Heideggers philosophische Politik," Review of Books 30, no. 6 (April 14, 1983): 4-6;
Freiburger Universittsbltter 25, whole no. 92 Dworkin and Michael Walzer, "'Spheres of Jus-
Gune 1986): 83-90; Pggeler (note 39 above); tice:' An Exchange," ibid. 30, no. 12 Guly 21,
and finally Rudolf Ringguth, "Fhrer der Fhrer," 1983): 43-46.
Der Spiegel 40, no. 34 (August 18, 1986): 164 50. A partial copy in the authors' possession is due to
169. The outdated standard view of the Heideg- Wolfgang Schirmacher.
ger supporters is once more presented by How- 51. C f Albert Borgmann, "Mind, Body, and World,"
ard Eiland in "Heidegger's Political Engagement," Philosophical Forum 8, no. 1 (Fall, 1976): 68-86.
Salmagundi, whole nos. 70-71 (Spring-Summer 52. Albert Hofstadter and Richard Kuhns, eds., Phi-
1986): 267-284. losophies of Art and Beauty (New York: Random

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

161
House, 1964); Albert Hofstadter, Truth and Art Dizesan-Archiv 104 (1984): 315-325 and "Der
(New York: Columbia University Press, 1965). Habilitand Martin Heidegger and das von
53. Karsten Harries, The Meaning of Modem Art Schaezler'sche Stipendium," ibid. 106 (1986):
(Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 141-160; Bernhard Casper, "Martin Heidegger
1968). See also Harries, The Bavarian Rococo und die Theologische Fakultt Freiburg, 1909
Church: Between Faith and Aestheticism, (New 1923," ibid. 100 (1980): 534-541.
Haven: Yale University Press, 1981). 65. Martin Heidegger zum 80. Geburtstag von seiner
54. Kent C. Bloomer and Charles W. Moore, Body, Heimatstadt Messkirch (Frankfurt: Klostermann,
Memory, and Architecture (New Haven: Yale 1969), pp. 1-15.
University Press, 1977); David P. Billington, The 66. For references to God, Christianity and faith, see
Tower and the Bridge: The New Art of Struc- Hildegard Feick, Index zu Heideggers Sein und
tural Engineering (New York: Basic Books, Zeit, " 2nd edition (Tbingen: Niemeyer, 1968),
1984). or Rainer A. Bast and Heinrich P. Delfosse,
55. See Noel Perrin, Giving Up the Gun: Japan's Re- Handbuch zum Textstudium von Martin Heideg-
version to the Sword (Boston: Godine, 1979). gers "Sein und Zeit" (Stuttgart-Bad Cannstadt:
56. See Zen Buddhism: Selected Writings of D.T. Holzboog, 1979). For some of the biographical
Suzuki, ed. W. Barrett (Garden City, NY: circumstances that shed light on Heidegger's un-
Doubleday Anchor Books, 1956), p. xi. derstandably troubled relation to the Catholic
57. Yoshihiro Nitta and Hirotaka Tatematsu, Church, see note 64 above and also Mller,
Japanese Phenomenology. Analecta Husserliana 1986, pp. 16 and 30.
vol. VIII (Boston: Reidel, 1979). 67., See Cari Mitcham, "Questions of Christianity and
58. Chikao Fijisawa, Zen and Shinto (New York: Technology: A Bibliographic Introduction," Sci-
Philosophical Library, 1959; reprint Westport, ence, Technology and Society, whole no. 14
CT: Greenwood Press, 1971). (November 1979): 1-17.
59. Kitaro Nishida, Intelligibility and the Philosophy 68. On Heidegger's combination of timidity and coun-
of Nothingness, trans. Robert Schinzinger (Hon- try smarts, see Mller, 1986, pp. 22-26 and 28;
olulu: East-West Center Press, 1958). Schmitt (see note 41 above), p. 85; and a remark
60. Kitaro Nishida, Fundamental Problems of Philos- of Gerhart Ritter quoted by Ott in "Martin
ophy, trans. David A. Dilwork (Tokyo: Sophia Heidegger als Rektor der Universitt Freiburg i.
University, 1970), pp. 40 and 94-95. Br. 1933/34," Zeitschrift des Breisgau-
61. Eugen Herrigel, Zen in the Art of Archery, trans. Geschichtesvereins 103 (1984): 127, n. 6.
R.F.C. Hull (New York: Random House, 1971), 69. For references see note 65 above.
p. 77. 70. Cari Mitcham and Jim Grote, eds.. Theology and
62. Murray Sayle, "Japan Victorious," New York Re- Technology (Lanham, M D : University Press of
view of Books 32, no. 5 (March 28, 1985): 33 America, 1984).
40; Ian Buruma, "A New Japanese Nationalism," 71. Hubert L. Dreyfus, What Computers Can't Do: A
New York Times Magazine (April 12, 1987): 22 Critique of Artificial Reason, rev. edition (New
29, 38. York: Harper & Row, 1979). first edition,
63. Some of the proceedings have been published in 1972); and Hubert L. Dreyfus and Stuart E.
Philosophisches Jahrbuch 102, no. 1 (1985): 110 Dreyfus, with Tom Athanasiou, Mind Over
148. Machine: The Power of Human Intuition and Ex-
64. On the religious circumstances and influences of pertise in the Era of the Computer (New York:
Heidegger's youth and education, see Hugo Ott, Free Press, 1986).
"Der junge Martin Heidegger," Ereiburger

Part Two
BIBLIOGRAPHY
The most extensive index to both primary and secondary materials is Hans-
Martin Sass, Martin Heidegger: Bibliography and Glossary (Bowling Green, OH:
Philosopohy Documentation Center, 1982) a volume with over 6000 unannotated
entries, which extends and updates Sass' earlier Heidegger-Bibliographie
(Meisenheim: Hain, 1968) and Materialien zur Heidegger-Bibliographie 1917-1971

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

162
(Meisenheim: Hain, 1975). Winfried Krnzen, Martin Heidegger (Stuttgart: Metz-
ler, 1976) is another compact bibliographic introduction which has been helpful in
preparing the present survey. The present bibliography, however, in the re-
stricted area of recent Heideggerian studies of technology and related issues, is
more complete than either Sass or Krnzen.
In order to preserve some focus, this bibliography does not include those non-
Heideggerian works for which notes have been provided. It does contain supple-
mental references and, particularly for minor articles and undiscussed entries,
annotations. Kor major works, it is generally assumed that discussions in the text,
to which reference is often made, already provides sufficient analysis. The index
provides a ready means for locating all authors in both bibliography and text.
The bibliography has two major divisions, the second of which is further sub-
divided.
A. Works by Heidegger
B. Works about Heidegger
1. Works on Science, Technology, and Politics
2. Works on Art and Religion
Sections B , l and B,2 correspond to Divisions A and B of the text, respectively.
Each includes (except for minor exceptions as indicated) all works referred to
therein, even when this requires some separation of works by a single author, or
some potential confusion because of duplicate dates. The aim is to preserve a
focus and facilitate selective use.
Because of the character of Division A of the text, bibliography B , l naturally
contains the more general works and collections. Without contraindication, non-
Heideggerian references are to bibliography B , l .

A. Works by Heidegger
N.B. Because translation dates would be confusing in the text, whenever possible
Heidegger's works are listed by date of original German publication. When En-
glish collections include works from more than one German source, the date is
unavoidably that of the translation.

Heidegger, Martin (1912). "The Problem of Reality in Modern Philosophy," trans.


Philip J . Bessert, Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 4, no. 1 (Janu-
ary 1973): 64-71.

(1916). "The Concept of Time in the Science of History," trans.


Harry S. Taylor and Hans W. Uffelmann, Journal of the British Society for
Phenomenology 9, no. 1 (January 1978): 3-10.

(1927). Being and Time. Trans. John Macquarrie and Edward


Robinson. New York: Harper & Row, 1962. Pp. 589. All English references in the
text are followed by bracketed page numbers which refer to the 7th German edi-
tion. Another translation by Joan Stambaugh and J . Glenn Gray of the "Introduc-
tion" (pp. 1-40) is included in David Karrell Krell, ed. (1977), pp. 41-89.

(1929). "What Is Metaphysics?" trans. David Karrell Krell and in-


cluded in David Karrell Krell, ed. (1977), pp. 95-112. An earlier R.K.C. Hull and

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

163
Alan Crick trans, is in Werner Brock, ed.. Existence and Being (Chicago: Reg-
nery, 1949), pp. 325-361, along with Heidegger's nine-page 1943 "Postscript" criti-
cal of calculative thinking. A fifteen-page 1949 introduction entitled "The Way
Back into the Ground of Metaphysics," trans. Walter Kaufmann, is included
(along with the Hull-Crick trans, of "What Is Metaphysics?") in Walter Kauf-
mann, ed.. Existentialism: From Dostoevsky to Sartre (Cleveland: World, 1956),
pp. 207-221; revised and expanded edition (New York: New American Library,
1975), pp. 265-279.

(1933). "The Self-Assertion of the German University," trans.


Karsten Harries, Review of Metaphysics 38, no. 3, whole no. 151 (March 1985):
470-480. This includes a complete translation, with notes and introduction, of Die
Selbstbehauptung der deutschen Universitt: Rede, gehalten bei der feierlichen
bernahme des Rektorats der Universitt Freiburg i. Br. am 27.5.1933 and Das
Rektorat 1933/34: Tatsachen und Gedanken the first of which was originally
published, Breslau: Korn, 1933; and subsequently reprinted with Heidegger's
later remarks, Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1983. It corrects the scurrilous version
attributed to Heidegger by Dagobert Runes in German Existentialism (New
York: Philosophical Library, 1965), pp. 18-20.

(1947). "Letter on Humanism," trans. David Farrell Krell and in-


cluded in David Farrell Krell, ed. (1977), pp. 193-242. Another version, trans.
Edgar Lohner, can be found in William Barrett and Henry David Aiken, eds.. Phi-
losophy in the Twentieth Century, vol. 3 (New York: Random, 1962), pp. 270-302.

(1950). "The Age of the World View," trans. Marjorie Grene, Meas-
ure 2 (1951): 269-284. Later trans. William Lovitt as "The Age of the World Pic-
ture" and included in Heidegger (1977a), pp. 115-154. For explication see Joseph
Kockelmans (1970b).

(1953). An Introduction to Metaphysics. Trans. Ralph Manheim.


Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1961. Pp. 182. Trans, first published. New Haven,
CT: Yale University Press, 1959. This text actually dates from 1935.

(1954). What Is Called Thinking? Trans. J . Glenn Gray. New York:


Harper & Row, 1968. Pp. xvi, 244. Lectures from the summer terms of 1951 and
1952 the first Heidegger was permitted to give after 1944, and the last before his
formal retirement from the University of Freiburg. Early sections relate science
and technology and contrast them to thinking, which is described as a craft.
Selections included in David Farrell Krell, ed. (1977), pp. 345-367.

(1955). The Question of Being. Trans. Jean T. Wilde and WilUam


Kluback. New Haven, CT: College & University Press, 1958. Pp. 109. Originally an
essay contributed to an Ernst Jnger Festschrift.

(1957a). "The Principle of Ground," trans. Keith Hoeller, Man and


World 7, no. 3 (August 1974): 207-222. The concluding and summarizing essay

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

164
from Der Satz vom Grund (Pfullingen: Neske, 1957), Heidegger's book on Leibniz.
Technology is the ultimate manifestation of the principle of sufficient reason.

(1957b). Identity and Difference. Trans. Joan Stambaugh. New


York: Harper & Row, 1969. First trans. Kurt F . Leidecker as Essays in
Metaphysics: Identity and Difference (New York: Philosophical Library, 1960), a
less literal version which nevertheless renders Gestell as "framework."

(1958). "A Recollection," trans. Hans Seigfried, Man and World 3,


no. 1 (February 1970): 3-4. Brief inaugural address at the Heidelberg Academy of
Science, first published in the Jahreshefte der Heidelberger Akademie der Wis-
senschaften (1957-1958).

(1959a). Discourse on Thinking [= Gelassenheit]. Trans. John M.


Anderson and E . Hans Freund. New York: Harper & Row, 1966. Pp. 90.

(1959b). On the Way to Language. Trans. Peter D. Hertz. New


York: Harper & Row, 1971. Pp. 200.

(1961a). Nietzsche I: The Will to Power as Art. Trans. David Farrell


Krell. San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1979. Pp. xvi, 263.

(1961b). Nietzsche II: The Eternal Recurrence of the Same. Trans.


David Farrell Krell. San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1984. Pp. xii, 290.

(1961c). Nietzsche III: The Will to Power as Knowledge and as


Metaphysics. Trans. David Farrell Krell. San Francisco: Harper & Row.

(1961d). Nietzsche IV: Nihilism. Trans. Frank A. Capuzzi. San


Francisco: Harper & Row, 1982. Pp. x, 301.

(1962). What Is a Thing? Trans. W.B. Barton Jr. and Vera Deutsch.
Chicago: Regnery, 1967. Pp. vii, 310. Eugene T. Gendlin's appended 50 page
"Analysis" of this book concludes with a discussion of technology, pp. 287-296. A
selection entitled "Modern Science, Metaphysics, and Mathematics" is included
in David Farrell Krell, ed. (1977), pp. 247-282.

(1969a). On Time and Being. Trans. Joan Stambaugh. New York:


Harper & Row, 1972. Pp. xi, 84. English translation of Zur Sache des Denkes
(Tbingen: Niemeyer, 1969).

(1969b). "Art and Space," trans. Charles H. Seibert, Man and World
6, no. 1 (February 1973): 3-8. Translation of Die Kunst und der Raum (St. Gallen:
Erker, 1969).

(1970). [Letter to a symposium on "Heidegger and Eastern


Thought"], trans. Albert Borgmann, Philosophy East and West 20, no. 3 (July
1970): 221.

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

165
(1971). Poetry, Language, Thought. Trans. Albert Hofstadter. New
York: Harper & Row, 1971. Pp. xxv, 229. Essays from Holzwege (Frankfurt: Klo-
stermann, 1950), Vortrge und Aufstze (Pfullingen: Neske, 1954), and Unterwegs
zur Sprache (Pfullingen: Neske, 1959). An earlier translation of one essay in this
collection, "The Origin of the Work of Art" (from 1936), first appeared, minus
Heidegger's 1956 "Addendum," in Albert Hofstadter and Richard Kuhns, eds..
Philosophies of Art and Beauty (New York: Modern Library, 1964). An ab-
breviated version of this essay plus another from this collection, viz., "Building
Dwelling Thinking," are included in David Farrell Krell, ed. (1977), pp. 149-187
and 323-339, respectively.

(1973). The End of Philosophy. Trans. Joan Stambaugh. New York:


Harper & Row, 1973. Pp. xiv, 110. Includes one chapter from Vortrge und Auf-
stze (1954) and three from Nietzsche II (1961).

(1976a). "Only a God Can Save Us: Der Spiegel's Interview with
Martin Heidegger," trans. Maria P. Alter and John D. Caputo, Philosophy Today
20, no. 4 (Winter 1976): 267-284. This is an interview granted ten years earlier, on
the condition that it not be published until after his death. Appeared originally in
Der Spiegel, vol. 30, no. 23 (May 31, 1976): 193-219 (which includes about 15 pages
of advertising). Der Spiegel editorial comment, p. 3, provides a photograph of the
typescript indicating the extent of Heidegger's reworking of the interview. A
slightly freer version, trans. David Schendler, can be found in Graduate Faculty
Philosophy Journal 6, no. 1 (Winter 1977): 5-27. A more literal version, with notes,
trans. WiUiam J . Richardson, is included in Thomas Sheehan, ed. (1981), pp. 45
67. Two other occasional pieces in which Heidegger speaks about technology are
"The Pathway" and "Messkirch's Seventh Centennial," trans. Thomas F.
O'Meara and Thomas J . Sheehan, Listening 8, nos. 1-3 (1973): 32-57. Earlier ren-
derings of both these public lectures delivered in Heidegger's home town of
Messkirch appeared in Listening 2, no. 2 (Spring 1967) and 6, no. 3 (Autumn 1971),
respectively. Along the same line see also the interview in Richard Wisser, ed.
(1970), in bibliography B,2.

(1976b). The Piety of Thinking. Trans. James G. Hart and John C.


Maraldo. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1976. Pp. x, 212. Works
dealing with religion from 1927 to 1964.

(1977a). The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays.


Trans. William Lovitt. New York: Harper & Row, 1977. Pp. xxxix, 182. Contains
translations of Heidegger's two major essays on technology, "Die Frage nach der
Technik" and "Die Kehre." These essays grew out of four lectures given in late
1949 and early 1950. "Die Frage . . . " was initially published as the first essay in
Vortrge und Aufstze (Pfullingen: Neske, 1954), and then along with "Die
Kehre" as a separate volume entitled Die Technik und die Kehre (Pfullingen:
Neske, 1962). Another (slavishly literal) translation of "Die Frage . . . " has been
done by Edwin M . Alexander as an MA thesis under George Grant, "Martin
Heidegger's The Question about Technic' A Translation and Commentary"
(Hamilton, Ontario: McMaster University, 1973). "Die Kehre" first trans. Ken-

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

166
neth R. Maly as "The Turning/' Research in Phenomenology 1 (1971): 3-16. Also
included in the Lovitt collection are the important "The Word of Nietzsche: 'God
Is Dead'," "The Age of the World Picture," and "Science and Reflection." This is
the crucial volume for understanding Heidegger's philosophy of technology. The
title essay is reprinted in David Farrell Krell, ed. (1977), pp. 287-317.

(1977b). "Modern Natural Science and Technology," Research in


Phenomenology 7 (1977): 3-4. German original, pp. 1-2. This is a letter of greeting
to a Heidegger conference held in Chicago two weeks before Heidegger's death. It
is reportedly his last composition. The volume is republished in John Sallis, ed..
Radical Phenomenology (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1978).

(1983). "Die Herkunft der Kunst und die Bestimmung des Den-
kens," in P. Jaeger and R. Lthe, eds., Distanz und Nhe: Reflexionen und Analy-
sen zur Kunst der Gegenwart (Wrzburg: Knigshausen & Neumann, 1983), pp.
11-22. This volume is a Festschrift for Walter Biemel.

Heidegger, Martin, and Eugen Fink (1979). Heraclitus Seminar 1966167. Trans.
Charles H. Seibert. University, AL: University of Alabama Press, 1979. Pp. xii,
169. See also John Sallis and Kenneth Maly, eds., Heraclitean Fragments: A Com-
panion Volume to the Heidegger/Fink Seminar on Heraclitus (University, A L :
University of Alabama Press, 1980).

B. Works about Heidegger

1. Works on Science, Technology, and Politics

Ahlers, Rolf (1971). "Technologie und Wissenschaft bei Heidegger und Marcuse,"
Zeitschrift fr philosophische Forschung 25, no. 4 (October-December 1971): 575
590. See also Ahlers, "Is Technology Intrinsically Repressive?" Continuum 8, no. 1
(Spring-Summer 1970): 111-122, which rejects both Marcuse's and Heidegger's
critiques of technology as romantic flights from Hegelian acceptance.

Alderman, Harold (1978). "Heidegger's Critique of Science and Technology," in


Michael Murray, ed. (1978), pp. 35-50. This combines and revises the author's
"Heidegger's Critique of Science," Personalist 50, no. 4 (Autumn 1969): 549-558;
and "Heidegger: Technology as Phenomenon," Personalist 51, no. 4 (Autumn
1970): 535-545. Alderman did a dissertation on "Heidegger and the Overthrow of
Philosophy" under Edward G. Ballard at Tulane University (1967). Pp. 148-163 of
this dissertation are on "Technicity."

AUemann, Beda (1969). "Martin Heidegger und die Politik," in Otto Pggeler, ed.,
Heidegger: Perspektiven zur Deutung seines Werks (Cologne: Kiepenheuer and
Witsch, 1969), pp. 246-260. First published in Merkur 21, no. 10 (1967): 962-976.

Axelos, Kostas (1966). Einfhrung in ein knftiges Denken: ber Marx und
Heidegger. Tbingen: Niemeyer, 1966. Pp. 104. See also Axelos, Alienation,

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

167
Praxis, and Techne in the Thought of Karl Marx, trans. Ronald Bruzina (Austin:
University of Texas Press, 1976), which exhibits a Heidegger influenced interpre-
tation of Marx; and Axelos, "Le 'Dialogue avec le Marxisme' et la 'Question de la
technique'," in Jean Beaufret, ed.. Dialogue avec Heidegger 11: Philosophie Mod-
erne (Paris: Editions de Minuit, 1973).

Ballard, Edward G. (1970). "Heidegger's View and Evaluation of Nature and Nat-
ural Science," in John Sallis, ed., Heidegger and the Path of Thinking
(Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1970), pp. 37-64.

(1978). Man and Technology: Toward the Measurement of a Cul-


ture. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1978. Pp. x, 251. See also Ballard,
"Man or Technology: Which Is to Rule?" in Stephen Skousgaard, ed. (1981, in sec-
tion B,2 of the bibliography), pp. 3-19. For discussion, see section A,4 of text. For
more detailed review, see Albert Borgmann, untitled review of Ballard and
Donald M. Borchert and David Stewart, eds.. Being Human in a Technological
Age (Athens: Ohio University Press, 1979), Man and World 15, vol. 1 (1982): 107
115.

Baker, Evelyn M . (1983). "Heidegger's Existential Conception of Science" in


Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka and Calvin 0. Schrg, eds.. Foundations of Morality,
Human Rights, and the Human Sciences: Phenomenology in a Foundational
Dialogue with the Human Sciences, Analecta Husserliana 15 (Boston: D. Reidel,
1983), pp. 431-440. Heidegger's existential interpretation of science (see the discus-
sion in section A , l of the text) shows that science cannot be a basis for morality.

Barrett, William (1978). The Illusion of Technique: A Search for Meaning in a


Technological Civilization. Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1978. Pp. xx, 359. Chap-
ter 8, "Homeless in the World," an apology for Heidegger's collusion with Nazism,
first appeared, interestingly enough, in the Jewish magazine Commentary 61, no.
3 (March 1976): 34-43.

(1986). Death of the Soul: from Descartes to the Computer. Garden


City, NY: Doubleday, 1986. Pp. xvi, 173. Criticizes Heidegger's philosophical an-
thropology of Being and Time as of a piece with the idealistic desubstantialization
of the self that allows technology to put forward the computer as a replacement
for the human, pp. 137-140.

Baruzzi, Arno (1985). Alternative Lebensform? Freiburg: Karl Alber, 1985. Pp.
179. "Die Frage nach der Technik" discussed pp. 33-50 as a preliminary to E . F .
Schumacher and intermediate technology.

Beausoleil, Jocelyn R. (1983). "Heidegger ou le defi de penser la technique,"


Dialogue (Canada) 22, no. 4 (December 1983): 647-660. Sympathetic overview.

Becker, Oskar (1969). "Para-Existenz; Menschliches Dasein und Dawesen," in


Otto Pggeler, ed., Heidegger: Perspektiven zur Deutung seines Werks (Cologne:
Kiepenheuer und Witsch, 1969), pp. 261-285.

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

168
Berciano, Modesto (1980). "Herbert Marcuse: E l Primer Marxista
Heideggeriano," Pensamiento 36 (April-June 1980): 131-164.

Biemel, Walter (1976). Heidegger. Trans. J.L. Mehta. New York: Harcourt Brace
Jovanovich, 1976. Chapter 8 (pp. 133-148) of this illustrated biographical introduc-
tion is on "Aletheia and the Nature of Technology."

Blitz, Mark (1981). Heidegger's ''Being and Time'' and the Possibility of Political
Philosophy. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1981. Pp. 260. For discussion,
see section A,7 of text.

Borgmann, Albert (1971). "Technology and Reality," Man and World 4, no. 1
(February 1971): 59-69.

(1972). "Orientation in Technology," Philosophy Today 16, no. 2


(Summer 1972): 135-147.

(1975). "Functionalism in Science and Technology," in Proceedings


of the XVth World Congress of Philosophy, vol. 6 (Sofia: Sofia Press Production
Center, 1975), pp. 31-36.

(1978a). "The Explanation of Technology," Research in Philosophy


and Technology, vol. 1 (1978): 99-118.

(1978b). "Heidegger and Symbolic Logic," in Michael Murray, ed.


(1978), pp. 3-22.

(1979). "Freedom and Determinism in a Technological Setting," Re-


search in Philosophy and Technology, vol. 2 (1979): 79-90.

(1980a). "Should Montana Share Its Coal? Technology and Public


Policy," Research in Philosophy and Technology, vol. 3 (1980): 287-311. An earlier
version appeared in Montana Trails, whole no. 2 (1977): 27-33.

(1980b). Untitled review of WiUiam Barrett, The Illusion of Tech-


nique (1978), Man and World 13, nos. 3-4 (1980): 458-465.

(1982a). Untitled review of Edward G. Ballard, Man and Technol-


ogy (1978); and Donald M. Borchert and David L. Stewart, eds.. Being Human in
a Technological Age (Athens: Ohio University Press, 1979), Man and World 15, no.
1 (1982): 107-115.

(1982b). "Technology and Nature in Europe and America," in


Richard N. Barrett, ed.. International Dimensions of the Environmental Crisis
(Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1982), pp. 3-20.

(1984). Technology and the Character of Contemporary Life: A

Philosophical Inquiry. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984. Pp. 306. An ex

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY


169
tended study of the influence of modern technology on society and culture, with
suggestions for reform. The influence of Heidegger is strong but indirect. Two
other studies relevant to these themes are "The Good Life and Appropriate Tech-
nology," Research in Philosophy and Technology, vol. 6 (1983): 11-19; and "Tech-
nology and Democracy," Research in Philosophy and Technology, vol. 7 (1984):
211-228.

Bronner, Stephen Eric (1977). "Martin Heidegger: The Consequences of Political


Mystification," Salmagundi, whole nos. 38-39 (Summer-Fall 1977): 153-174.

(1979). "The Poverty of Scholasticism/A Pedant's Delight: A Re-


sponse to Thomas Sheehan," Salmagundi, whole no. 43 (Winter, 1979): 185-199.

Caputo, John D. (1971). "Heidegger's Original Ethics," New Scholasticism 45, no.
1 (Winter 1971): 127-138. Connects technology and ecology.

Colaizzi, Paul F . (1978). Technology and Dwelling: The Secrets of Life and Death.
Privately published: 5552 Beacon Street, Apt. 1, Pittsburgh, PA 15217. Pp. 187. For
discussion, see section A,4 of text.

Dallmayr, Fred R. (1984). "Ontology of Freedom: Heidegger and Political Philos-


ophy," Political Theory 12, no. 2 (May 1984): 204-234.

.Dauenhauer, Bernard P. (1976). "Renovating the Problem of Politics," Review of


Metaphysics 29, no. 4, whole no. 116 (June 1976): 626-641. See also Dauenhauer,
"Heidegger, the Spokesman for the Dweller," Southern Journal of Philosophy 15,
no. 2 (Summer 1977): 189-199. What substantive contribution does Heidegger
make to political thought? Answer: The idea of the human being as dweller, one
who can save the earth.

De Carolis, Massimo (1978). "Metafisica e tecnica in Heidegger," Sapienza 31


(July-September 1978): 330-346.

DeGeorge, Richard T. (1965). "Heidegger and the Marxists," Studies in Soviet


Thought 5, no. 4 (December 1965): 289-298.

Dessauer, Friedrich (1956). Strait um die Technik. Frankfurt: Knecht, 1956. Pp.
471. See especially pp. 348-368. Some commentary on Dessauer's failure to under-
stand Heidegger on technology can be found in Klaus Tuchel, "Friedrich Des-
sauer as Philosopher of Technology: Notes on his Dialogue with Jaspers and
Heidegger," Research in Philosophy and Technology, vol. 5 (1982): 269-280
which is a partial translation of Tuchel's Die Philosophie der Technik hei Fried-
rich Dessauer (Frankfurt: Knecht, 1964).

Dreyfus, Hubert L . (1980). "Holism and Hermeneutics," Review of Metaphysics


34, no. 1, whole no. 133 (September 1980): 3-23. See also Dreyfus' use of Heidegger
in "Cybernetics as the Last Stage of Metaphysics," in Proceedings of the XlVth
World Congress of Philosophy, vol. 2 (Vienna: Herder, 1968), pp. 493-499, and in

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

170
What Computers Can't Do: A Critique of Artificial Reason (New York: Harper &
Row, 1972; revised edition, 1979).

(1984). "Between Techne and Technology: The Ambiguous Place of


Technology in Being and Time," in Michael E . Zimmerman, ed.. The Thought of
Martin Heidegger, "Tulane Studies in Philosophy," vol. 32 (New Orleans: Tulane
University, 1984), pp. 23-35. A French version of this essay first appeared in
Michel Haar, ed., Martin Heidegger (Paris: L'Herne, 1983).

Emad, Parvis (1981). "Technology as Presence: Heidegger's View," Listening 16,


no. 2 (Spring 1981): 133-144.

Fandozzi, Phillip R. (1982). Nihilism and Technology: A Heideggerian Investiga-


tion. Washington, DC: University Press of America, 1982. Pp. ix, 147. For discus-
sion, see both sections A,4 and A,5 of text.

Fay, Thomas A. (1977). Heidegger: The Critique of Logic. The Hague: Nijhoff,
1977.

Fell, Joseph P. (1979). Heidegger and Sartre: An Essay on Being and Place. New
York: Columbia University Press, 1979. Pp. 517. Some brief discussion of technol-
ogy in chapter 9, "Heidegger's Notion of Two Beginnings."

Franks, Dean (1971). "An Interpretation of Technology Through the Assertorical-


Problematical Distinction," Kinesis 4, no. 1 (Fall 1971): 22-30.

Gadamer, Hans-Georg (1975). Truth and Method. New York: Continuum, 1975.
Pp. xxvi, 551. First published as Wahrheit und Methode (Tbingen: Mohr, 1960).
Second, expanded edition, 1965.

(1977). "Theory, Technology, Practice: The Task of the Science of


Man," Social Research 44, no. 3 (Autumn 1977): 529-561. This is a poorly trans-
lated and slightly modified version of "Theorie, Technik, Praxis: Die Aufgabe
einer neuen Anthropologie," the introduction to H.G. Gadamer and Paul Vogler,
eds.. Neue Anthropologie (Stuttgart: Thieme, 1972-1975). The essay "What Is
Practice? The Conditions of Social Reason," in Gadamer, Reason in the Age of
Science, trans. Frederick G. Lawrence (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983), pp.
69-87, also contains some comments on technology.

Gerratana, Valentino (1977). "Heidegger and Marx," New Left Review, whole no.
106 (November-December 1977): 51-58.

Globus, Gordon G. (1986). "The Machine Basis for the Dasein: On the Prospects
for an Existential Functionalism," Man and World 19, no. 1 (1986): 55-72. Heideg-
ger's Dasein cannot have a Turing machine as its physical base.

Goff, Robert Allen (1968). "Wittgenstein's Tools and Heidegger's Implements,"


Man and World 1, no. 3 (August 1968): 447-462.

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

171
Goldmann, Lucien (1977). Lukacs and Heidegger. Trans. William Q. Boelhower.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1977. Pp. xxii, 112. This is an expanded ver-
sion of a posthumous work first published in French in 1973.

Grange, Joseph (1974). "Magic, Technology and Being," Religious Humanism 8,


no. 2 (Spring 1974): 88-91.

(1977). "On the Way Toward Foundational Ecology," Soundings 60,


no. 2 (Summer 1977): 135-149.

Grant, George Parkin (1974). English-speaking Justice. Sackville, New


Brunswick, Canada: Mount Allison University, 1974. Pp. 112. Reprinted, Notre
Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1984. Pp. 104. In one of the interviews
in Larry Schmidt, ed., George Grant in Process: Essays and Conversations (To-
ronto: House of Anansi, 1978), Grant also indicates his indebtedness to Heidegger
(see p. 141). But in his earlier Technology and Empire (Toronto: House of Anansi,
1969), Grant relies on Jacques ElluFs definition of technology instead of Heideg-
ger's.

Grnder, Karlfried (1962). "M. Heideggers Wissenschaftskritik in ihren ge-


schichtlichen Zusammenhngen," Archiv fr Philosophie 11, nos. 3-4 (1962): 312
335. English trans, as "Heidegger's Critique of Science in its Historical Back-
ground," Philosophy Today 7, no. 1 (Spring 1963): 15-32.

Habermas, Jrgen (1970). "Technology and Science as Ideology'," in Toward a


Rational Society, trans. Jeremy J . Shapiro (Boston: Beacon Press, 1970), pp. 81
122. For an essay explicitly on Heidegger, see "Martin Heidegger: The Great In-
fluence" (from 1959), in Habermas, Philosophical-Political Profiles, trans. Fre-
derick G. Lawrence (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1983), pp. 53-60. Brief mention
of technology, p. 59. "The story of Heidegger's influence is great, and most would
call his work itself great. Perhaps this very case makes understandable why our
relationship to greatness is a broken one" (p. 60).

Harries, Karsten (1978). "Heidegger as a Political Thinker," in Michael Murray,


ed. (1978), pp. 304-328. First published in Review of Metaphysics 29, no. 4, whole
no. 116 (June 1976): 642-669.

Heelan, Patrick A. (1972a). "Nature and Its Transformations," Theological


Studies 33, no. 3 (September 1972): 486-502. "[T]he manifest image of nature as
the [historically] pregiven arena for human action . . . includes horizons that are
the product of science and technology" (p. 501). See also Heelan, "Purpose in the
Universe," Encyclopedia of Bioethics, vol. 3 (New York: Free Press, 1978), pp.
1399-1404.

(1972b). "Hermeneutics of Experimental Science in the Context of


the Life-World," Philosophia Mathematica 9, no. 2 (Winter 1972): 101-144. The con-
cluding summary of the paper (pp. 133-135) is reprinted as an English abstract in
Zeitschrift fr allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 5, no. 1 (1974): 123-124, followed

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

172
by Theodore Kisiel's "Commentary on . . . " (pp. 124-135) and Heelan's "Com-
ments on . . ." (pp. 135-137). Original paper reprinted in Don Ihde and Richard
Zaner, eds., Interdisciplinary Phenomenology (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1975). As
Heelan observes in a footnote, this paper can be read as taking off from John J .
Compton, "Natural Science and the Experience of Nature," in James Edie, ed..
Phenomenology in America (Chicago: Quadrangle, 1969), pp. 80-95.

(1972c). "Toward a Hermeneutic of Natural Science," Journal of


the British Society for Phenomenology 3, no. 3 (October 1972): 252-260. This is fol-
lowed by Wolf Mays' "Toward a Hermeneutic of Natural Science: A Reply to Pat-
rick Heelan" (pp. 261-276), and Heelan's "Toward a Hermeneutic of Natural Sci-
ence: A Reply to Wolf Mays" (pp. 277-283).

(1983a). Space Perception and the Philosophy of Science. Berkeley:


University of California Press, 1983. Pp. xiv, 383. Heelan's "hermeneutical
realism" contains few explicit references to, yet is strongly influenced by,
Heidegger. For discussion, see section A , l of text, near the end.

(1983b). "Natural Science as a Hermeneutic of Instrumentation,"


Philosophy of Science 50, no. 2 (June 1983): 181-204. All perception, including sci-
entific observation, is hermeneutical as well as causal. For more on this, see
Heelan's "Perception as a Hermeneutical Act," Review of Metaphysics 37, no. 1,
whole no. 145 (September 1983): 61-75; and "Natural Science and Being-in-the-
World," Man and World 16, no. 3 (1983): 207-219. For a much earlier Heelan arti-
cle moving in this direction see "Horizon, Objectivity and Reality in the Physical
Sciences," International Philosophical Quarterly 7, no. 3 (September 1967): 375
412.

Hood, Webster F . (1972). "The Aristotelian Versus the Heideggerian Approach to


the Problem of Technology," in Carl Mitcham and Robert Mackey, eds. (1972),
pp. 347-363. Adapted from Hood's dissertation, "A Heideggerian Approach to the
Problem of Technology" (University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University,
1968). For discussion, see section A,4 of text. See also Hood, "The Latent Dimen-
sion of Experience," Main Currents in Modern Thought 27, no. 3 (January-Feb-
ruary 1971): 84-88, which essays a broader sketch of Heidegger's thought, includ-
ing his philosophy of technology.

Ihde, Don (1979). Technics and Praxis. Boston: Reidel, 1979. Pp. xxviii, 151. For
discussion, see section 4. Paul Durbin in an untitled review. Humanities Perspec-
tives on Technology, whole no. 11 (April 1979): 14-16, calls this "the first full-scale
philosophical analysis of technology by an American to appear in English." There
is also an untitled review by Albert Borgmann, Philosophical Topics 12 (1982):
190-194. A closely related paper which is not included in this collection of essays
on technology is "A Phenomenology of Man-Machine Relations," in Walter Fein-
burg and Henry Rosemont Jr., eds.. Work, Technology, and Education (Urbana:
University of Illinois Press, 1975), pp. 186-202.

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

173
(1983). Existential Technics. Albany, NY: State University of New
York Press, 1983. Pp. ix, 190. For discussion, see section A,4 of text. For further
analysis, see the untitled review by Carl Mitcham, Science, Technology & Society,
whole no. 37 (September 1983): 15-16. One essay, "The Historical-Ontological
Priority of Technology," is not properly credited as appearing first in German in
Paul Durbin and Friedrich Rapp, eds., Technikphilosophie in der Diskussion
(Braunschweig: Vieweg, 1982), pp. 205-217; and in the English version of this vol-
ume, Durbin and Rapp, eds.. Philosophy and Technoogy (Boston: Reidel, 1983),
pp. 235-252.

Jobin, Jean-Frangois (1975). "Heidegger et la technique," Studia Philosophica,


vol. 35 (1975): 81-127. Good, extended overview of technology in texts from Being
and Time on.

Jonas, Hans (1959). "The Practical Uses of Theory," in Carl Mitcham and Robert
Mackey, eds. (1972), pp. 335-346. First published in Social Research 26, no. 2
(1959): 151-166. Included in Jonas' The Phenomenon of Life (New York: Harper &
Row, 1966), pp. 188-210.

(1974). Philosophical Essays: From Ancient Creed to Technological


Man. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1974. Pp. xviii, 349. An introduction
provides an intellectual autobiography, and part one contains eight essays on
"Science, Technology, and Ethics." The first and third of these are "Technology
and Responsibility: Reflections on the New Task of Ethics" (from Social Re-
search [1973]) and "Seventeenth Century and After: The Meaning of the Scientific
and Technological Revolution" (from Philosophy Today [1971]).

(1976). "Responsibility Today: The Ethics of an Endangered Fu-


ture," Social Reserach 43, no. 1 (Spring 1976): 77-97. An earlier version of this
paper was presented at a conference at the Technical University in Israel in De-
cember, 1974, and published under the title "The Heuristics of Fear," in Melvin
Kranzberg, ed.. Ethics in an Age of Pervasive Technology (Boulder, CO:
Westview Press, 1980), pp. 213-221.

(1979). "Toward a Philosophy of Technology," Hastings Center Re-


port 9, no. 1 (February 1979): 34-43. Also appears in The Connecticut Scholar,
whole no. 3 (1980), in a symposium devoted to "Science, Technology, & Ethics."

(1984). The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for


the Technological Age. Trans. Hans Jonas with David Herr. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1984. Pp. xii, 255. For discussion, see section A,4 of text, near
the end. Originally published as Das Prinzip Verantwortung: Versuch einer Ethik
fr die technologische Zivilisation (Frankfurt: Insel, 1979) and Macht oder
Ohnmacht der Subjectivitt? Das Leib-Seele-Problem im Vorfeld des Prinzips
Vorantwortung (Frankfurt: Insel, 1981). Incorporates reworked versions of the
following earlier essays in roughly the following order: "Technology and Respon-
sibility: Reflections on the New Tasks of Ethics," Social Research 40, no. 1
(Spring 1973): 31-54, reprinted in Jonas (1974), pp. 3-20; "Responsibility Today:

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

174
The Ethics of an Endangered Future," Social Research 43, no. 1 (Spring 1976): 77
97; "The Concept of Responsibility: An Inquiry into the Foundations of an Ethics
for Our Age," in H.T. Engelhardt and D. Callahan, ed., Knowledge, Value, and
Belief (Hastings-on-Hudson, NY: The Hastings Center, 1977), pp. 169-198; "Reflec-
tions on Technology, Progress, and Utopia," Social Research 48, no. 3 (Autumn
1981): 411-455; "Parallelism and Complementarity: The Psycho-Physical Prob-
lem in Spinoza and in the Succession of Niels Bohr," in R. Kennington, ed.. The
Philosophy of Baruch Spinoza (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America
Press, 1980), pp. 126-128; and "On the Power or Impotence of Subjectivity," in
S.F. Spicker and H.T. Englehardt, eds.. Philosophical Dimensions of the Neuro-
Medical Sciences (Boston: Reidel, 1976), pp. 143-160. Two subsequent, related ar-
ticles: "Yesterday's Values for Tomorrow's World?" (with German version), in
Folkert Precht, ed., Wandlung von Verantwortung und Werten in unserer Zeit/
Evolution of Responsibilities and Values Today (Munich: Saur, 1983), pp. 182-194;
and "Ontological Grounding of a Political Ethics: On the Metaphysics of Commit-
ment to the Future of Man," Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 10, no. 1
(1984): 47-61.

Jung, Hwa Yol (1972). "The Ecological Crisis: A Philosophical Perspective,"


Bucknell Review 20 (Winter 1972): 25-44.

(1974). "The Paradox of Man and Nature: Reflections on Man's


Ecological Predicament," Centennial Review 18, no. 1 (Winter 1974): 1-28.

Jung, Hwa Yol, and Pettee Jung (1975). "To Save the Earth," Philosophy Today
19, no. 2 (Summer 1975): 108-117.

(1976). "Humanism: The Politics of Civility in a 'No-Growth' Soci-


ety," Man and World 9, no. 3 (August 1976): 283-306.

Kimball, Roger (1985). "Heidegger at Freiburg, 1933," New Criterion 3, no. 10


(June 1985): 9-18.

King, Magda (1973). "Truth and Technology," Human Context 5, no. 1 (1973): 1
34. This supplements King's earlier Heidegger's Philosophy: A Guide to His Basic
Thought (New York: Macmillan, 1964), which does not consider technology.

Kisiel, Theodore J . (1970a). "Science, Phenomenology, and the Thinking of


Being," in Joseph J . Kockelmans and Theodore J . Kisiel, eds. (1970), pp. 167-183.
Good commentary on Heidegger's "Science and Reflection."

(1970b). "Ideology Critique and Phenomenology: The Current De-


bate in German Philosophy," Philosophy Today 14, no. 3 (Fall 1970): 151-160. Out-
lines distinctions between hermeneutic philosophy (Husserl, Heidegger,
Gadamer) and critical social theory (Marx, Marcuse, Habermas, Apel). For dis-
cussion, see section A,6 of text.

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

175
(1973). "On the Dimensions of a Phenomenology of Science in Hus-
serl and the Young Dr. Heidegger," Journal of the British Society for
Phenomenology 4, no. 3 (October 1973): 217-234.
(1977). "Heidegger and the New Images of Science." Research in
Phenomenology 7 (1977): 162-181. Reprinted in John Sallis, ed. (1978). For related
articles see Kisiel, "Zu einer Hermeneutik naturwissenschaftlicher Entdeckung,"
Zeitschrift fr allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 2 (1971): 195-221; "The
Mathematical and the Hermeneutical: On Heidegger's Notion of the A priori," in
Edward G. Ballard and Charles E . Scott, eds., Martin Heidegger: In Europe and
America (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1973), pp. 109-120; "Scientific Discovery: Logical,
Psychological or Hermeneutical?" in David Carr and Edward S. Casey, ed.. Ex-
plorations in Phenomenology (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1973), pp. 263-284 a paper
which is actually an earlier and shorter English version of "Zu einer Hermeneutik
naturwissenschaftlicher Entdeckung," op. cit. first in this list; "Commentary on
Patrick Heelan's 'Hermeneutics of Experimental Science in the Context of the
Life-World'," Zeitschrift fr allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 5 (1974): 124-135;
"New Philosophies of Science in the USA: A Selective Survey," co-authored with
Galen Johnson, ihid., pp. 138-191; and "Hermeneutic Models for Natural Science,"
in E.W. Orth, ed.. Die Phnomenologie und die Wissenschaften, no. 2 in the
"Phnomenologische Forschungen" series (Freiburg: Alber, 1976), pp. 180-191.

Kockelmans, Joseph J . (1966). Phenomenology and Physical Science. Pittsburgh:


Duquesne University Press, 1966. The relation between science and technology is
described in Heideggerian terms, pp. 170-175. See also Kockelmans, The World in
Science and Philosophy (Milwaukee: Bruce, 1969).
(1970a). "Heidegger on the Essential Difference and Necessary Re-
lationship Between Philosophy and Science," in Joseph J . Kockelmans and Theo-
dore J . Kisiel, ed., (1970), pp. 147-166.

(1970b). "The Era of the World-as-Picture," in Joseph J . Kockel-


mans and Theodore J . Kisiel, eds. (1970), pp. 184-201. Excellent commentary on
Heidegger (1951).

(1984). On the Truth of Being: Reflections on Heidegger's Later Phi-


losophy. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1984.

(1985). Heidegger and Science. Washington, DC: Center for Ad-


vanced Research in Phenomenology and University Press of America, 1985. Pp.
xiii, 309.

Kockelmans, Joseph J . , and Theodore J . Kisiel, eds. (1970). Phenomenology and


the Natural Sciences: Essays and Translations. Evanston, IL: Northwestern Uni-
versity Press, 1970. Pp. xxi, 520. An important volume which includes, in a section
on Heidegger, Kockelmans' "Heidegger on the Essential Difference and Neces-
sary Relationship Between Philosophy and Science" (pp. 147-166), Kisiel's "Sci-
ence, Phenomenology, and the Thinking of Being" (pp. 167-183), and Kockelmans'
"The Era of the World-as-Picture" (pp. 184-201).

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

176
Kolb, David A. (1983). "Heidegger on the Limits of Science," Journal of the
British Society for Phenomenology 14, no. 2 (January 1983): 50-64.

Krell, David Farrell, ed. (1977). Martin Heidegger: Basic Writings. New York:
Random, 1977. Pp. xvi, 397. Contains a substantial introduction and a judicious
selection of ten texts from the introduction to Being and Time to "The End of Phi-
losophy and the Task of Thinking." Each selection is also preceded by a succinct
note. This is undoubtedly the best introduction to the Heidegger corpus.

Langan, Thomas (1967). The Meaning of Heidegger: A Critical Study of an Exis-


tentialist Phenomenology. New York: Columbia University Press, 1967. Chapter
11 (pp. 191-200) is on "The Notion of Technique."

Leach, Dirk (1987). Technik. Montpellier: Oris Banal, 1987. A French and English
version of a memoir of a period spent working in the Benz Daimler plant in which
the author uses Heidegger to interpret his experience.

Leder, Drew (1985). "Modes of Totalization: Heidegger on Modern Technology


and Science," Philosophy Today 29, no. 3 (Fall 1985): 245-256. Argues the unity of
Heidegger's (early) analyses of science and (later) analyses of technology.

Lingis, Alfonso F. (1968). "On the Essence of Technique," in Manfred S. Frings,


ed., Heidegger and the Quest for Truth (Chicago: Quadrangle, 1968), pp. 126-138.
See also Lingis, "The Production of Productive Man," Contemporary Philosophy
8, no. 2 (Late Spring 1980): 15-16. "Technological production is not simply a more
vast and more efficient expansion of pretechnological production; with technology
productive man enters into an entirely new history, in which not only his relations
with the productive means, but also with the products and with himself, are al-
tered essentially" (p. 15).

Loscerbo, John (1977). "Martin Heidegger: Remarks Concerning Some Early


Texts on Modern Technology," Tijdschrift voor Filosofie 39 (March 1977): 104-129.
Comments based on the last half of "Die ewige Wiederkehr des Gleichen und der
Wille zur Macht," which derives from lectures in 1939-1940 and is included in
Nietzsche II (Pfullingen: Neske, 1961), pp. 7-29; and section XXVI (first published
separately in 1951) of "Overcoming Metaphysics" in Heidegger (1973).

(1981). Being and Technology: A Study in the Philosophy of Martin


Heidegger. The Hague: Nijhoff, 1981. Pp. xii, 283. So far, the only book in English
focusing on the theme of technology in Heidegger. For discussion, see section A,2
of text.

Lovitt, William (1973). "A 'Gespraech' with Heidegger on Technology," Man and
World 6, no. 1 (February 1973): 44-59.

(1980). "Techne and Technology: Heidegger's Perspective on What


Is Happening Today," Philosophy Today 24, no. 1 (Spring 1980): 62-72.

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

177
Macomber, W.B. (1967). The Anatomy of Disillusion: Martin Heidegger's Notion
of Truth. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1967. Pp. 198-208 contain
a section entitled "Science and Technology: Mathematics and Manipulation."

Macquarrie, John (1975). "The Idea of a Theology of Nature," Union Seminary


Quarterly Review 30, nos. 2-4 (Winter-Summer 1975): 69-75. Nature can be inter-
preted from below, in terms of experiments, or from above, in terms of human
experience. Uses Heidegger's ontology to consider the second alternative. "[T]he
strength of Heidegger's contribution will ensure that, in this reflection on Nature,
the human existent, rather than the hydrogen atom, will be the point of depar-
ture" (p. 75).

Marcuse, Herbert (1964). One-Dimensional Man: Studies in the Ideology of Ad-


vanced Industrial Society. Boston: Beacon Press, 1964. Pp. xvii, 260.

(1977a). "Enttuschung," in Gnther Neske, ed., Erinnerung an


Martin Heidegger (Pfullingen: Neske, 1977), pp. 162-163.

(1977b). "Heidegger's Politics: An Interview with Herbert Marcuse


by Frederick Olafson," Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 6, no. 1 (Winter
1977): 28-40. Taken from the transcript of a film presented at a conference on the
philosophy of Martin Heidegger sponsored by the Department of Philosophy at
the University of California, San Diego, in May, 1974.

Marx, Werner (1971). Heidegger and the Tradition. Trans. Theodore Kisiel and
Murray Greene. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1971. Pp. xxxiii,
275. Contains a short chapter on "The Essence of Technology at the 'Turn'" (pp.
173-179).

Maurer, Reinhart (1970). "Der angewandte Heidegger: Herbert Marcuse und das
akademische Proletariat," Philosophisches Jahrbuch 77, no. 2 (1970): 238-259.

(1972). "Von Heidegger zur praktischen Philosophie," in Manfred


Riedel, ed., Rehabilitierung der praktischen Philosophie (Freiburg: Rombach,
1972), pp. 415-454. English translation minus footnotes by Walter E . Wright as
"From Heidegger to Practical Knlosophy," Idealistic Studies 3, no. 2 (May 1973):
133-162.

Mitcham, Carl (1980). "Philosophy of Technology," in Paul Durbin, ed.. Guide to


the Culture of Science, Technology and Medicine (New York: Free Press, 1980),
pp. 282-363. Heidegger discussed under the subheading "Technology as Volition,"
pp. 317-322.

(1985). "What is the Philosophy of Technology?" International


Philosophical Quarterly 25, no. 1, whole no. 97 (March 1985): 73-88. For the
explicit discussion of Heidegger, see pp. 80-83. Mitcham, Carl and Robert Mac-
key, eds. (1972). Philosophy and Technology: Readings in the Philosophical Prob-

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

178
lems of Technology. New York: Free Press, 1972. Pp. ix, 339. Paperback reprint,
1983. Pp. xii, 403.

Moehling, Karl A. (1972). "Martin Heidegger and the Nazi Party: An Examina-
tion." DeKalb: Northern Illinois University, 1972. Pp. 298. Ann Arbor Microfilms,
No. 72-29, 319. Contains Heidegger's letters of explanation from 1945 to the rector
of Freiburg University and the de-Nazification committee. See also Moehling's
summary and restatement of his finding in view of Heidegger's Spiegel interview
in "Heidegger and the Nazis," Listening 12, no. 3 (Fall 1977): 92-105, reprinted in
Thomas Sheehan, ed. (1981), pp. 31-43.

Moser, Simon (1971). "Toward a Metaphysics of Technology," trans. William Car-


roll, Carl Mitcham, and Robert Mackey, Philosophy Today 15, no. 2 (Summer
1971): 129-156. Heidegger is discussed at length, pp. 144-156. Translated from "Zur
Metaphysik der Technik," in Metaphysik einst und jetzt (Berlin: De Gruyten,
1958). For a revised version of this essay, see Moser, "Kritik der traditionellen
Technikphilosophie," in Hans Lenk and Simon Moser, eds., Technik, Techne,
Technologie (Pullach: Verlag Dokumentation, 1973), pp. 11-81.

Mller, Max (1986). "Ein Gesprch mit Max Mller," Freiburger Univer-
sittsbltter whole no. 92 (June 1986): 13-31.

Murray, Michael, ed. (1978). Heidegger and Modern Philosophy. New Haven, CT:
Yale University Press, 1978. Pp. xxiii, 374. Includes Albert Borgmann's "Heideg-
ger and Symbolic Logic" (pp. 3-22), Harold Alderman's "Heidegger's Critique of
Science and Technology" (pp. 35-50), Richard Rorty's "Overcoming the Tradi-
tion: Heidegger and Dewey" (pp. 239-258), and Karsten Harries' "Heidegger as
Political Thinker" (pp. 304-328).

Murray, Patrick (1982). "The Frankfurt School Critique of Technology," Re-


search in Philosophy and Technology, vol. 5 (1982): 223-248.

Naess, Arne (1979). "Martin Heidegger," in International Encyclopedia of the So-


cial Sciences, vol. 18: Biographical Supplement (New York: Free Press and Mac-
millan, 1979), pp. 286-287.

Nicholson, Graeme (1971). "The Commune of Being and Time," Dialogue


(Canada) 10, no. 4 (1971): 708-726. See also Nicholson, "Camus and Heidegger:
Anarchists," University of Toronto Quarterly 41 (1971): 14-23.

Orr, John (1974). "German Social Theory and the Hidden Face of Technology,"
Archives Europeennes de Sociologie 15, no. 2 (1974): 312-336.

Ottmann, Henning (1980). "Praktische Philosophie und technische Welt: Pro-


legomena zu einer unfertigen Philosophie der Praxis," Zeitschrift fr philoso-
phische Forschung 34, no. 2 (April-June 1980): 157-178.

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

179
Pachter, Henry (1976). "Heidegger and Hitler; The Incompatibility [sic] of Geist
and Politics," Boston University Journal 24, no. 3 (1976): 47-55. For discussion,
see section A,7 of text.

Palmier, Jean-lVIichel (1968). Les Ecrits politiques de Heidegger. Paris: L'Herne,


1968.

Piccone, Paul, and Alexander Delfini (1970). "Herbert Marcuse's Heideggerian


Marxism," Telos, whole no. 6 (Fall 1970): 36-47. For discussion, see section A,6 of
text.

Pggeler, Otto (1972). Philosophie und Politik bei Heidegger. Freiburg: Alber,
1972. Pp. 151.

(1982). "Neue Wege mit Heidegger?" Philosophische Rundschau,


29, nos. 1-3 (1982): 39-71. A review of six books three about and three by Heideg-
ger: Ute Guzzoni, ed., Nachdenken ber Heidegger (Hildesheim: Gerstenberg,
1980); Friedrich-Wilhelm von Herrmann, Heideggers Philosophie der Kunst
(Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1980); Jochen Schlter, Heidegger und Parmenides
(Bonn: Bouvier-Grundmann, 1979); and Heidegger's Gesamtausgabe, vols. 20, 39
and 55.

Rapp, Friedrich (1984). "Kosmische Technik als Zuspruch des Seins: Bemer-
kungen zu W. Schirmachers Weiterdenken nach Heidegger," Zeitschrift fr phi-
losophische Forschung 37, no. 3 (1984): 445-449.

Richardson, William J . (1968). "Heidegger's Critique of Science," New Scholasti-


cism 42, no. 4 (Autumn 1968): 511-536.

Robinet, Andre (1976). "Leibniz und Heidegger: Atomzeitalter oder Informatik-


zeitalter?" Studia Leibnitiana 8, no. 2 (1976): 241-256. Whereas Heidegger con-
trasts calculative and meditative thinking, number and being, Robinet argues
that Leibniz actually offers a synthesis of number and being. Heidegger is a
dualistic gnostic.

Rohrmoser, Gnter (1969). "Humanitt und Technologie," Studium Generale 22,


no. 8 (August 1969): 771-782. In a subsequent article, "Revolution, Philosophy, and
Psychoanalysis" in Universitas: A German Review of the Arts and Sciences 16,
no. 1 (1974): 37-42, the argument is that Marcuse develops a "Freud-Marxism."

Romano, Bruno. Tecnica e giustizia nel pensiero di Martin Heidegger. Milan: A.


Giuffre, 1969. Pp. xiv, 233.

Rouse, Joseph (1981). "Kuhn, Heidegger, and Scientific Realism," Man and World
14, no. 3 (1981): 269-290. Uses Heidegger to defend Kuhn and criticize realism. For
discussion, see section A , l of text.

Rorty, Richard (1978). "Overcoming the Tradition: Heidegger and Dewey," in


Michael Murray, ed. (1978), pp. 239-258.

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

180
(1979). Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1979. Pp. xv, 401. Views Wittgenstein, Heidegger, and Dewey as
leading a challenge to the idea that the mind mirrors nature. For discussion, see
section A , l of text, near the end.

Sachsse, Hans (1973). "Die Technik in der Sicht Herbert Marcuses und Martin
Heideggers," Proceedings of the XVth World Congress of Philosophy, vol. 1
(Sofia: Sofia Press Production Center, 1973), pp. 371-375.

Sallis, John (1970). "Toward the Movement of Reversal: Science, Technology,


and the Language of Homecoming," in John Sallis, ed., Heidegger and the Path of
Thinking (Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1970), pp. 138-168.

Sallis, John, ed. (1978). Radical Phenomenology. Atlantic Highlands, NJ:


Humanities Press, 1978. Pp. 318. This reprints the Heidegger Memorial Issue of
Research in Phenomenology 7 (1977), and contains papers from a Heidegger con-
ference held at DePaul University in Chicago, May 14-16, 1976.

Schirmacher, Wolfgang (1973). "Heidegger's Radikalkritik der Technik als


gesellschaftlicher Handlungsentwurf," Proceedings of the XVth World Congress
of Philosophy, vol. 1 (Sofia: Sofia Press Production Center, 1973), pp. 383-387.

(1982a). "Heideggers Einfluss auf das gegenwrtige Denken," Phi-


losophischer Literaturanzeiger 35, no. 4 (October-December 1982): 383-398. A re-
view of nine books: Ute Guzzoni, ed., Nachdenken ber Heidegger (Hildesheim:
Gerstenberg, 1980); Hermann Mrchen, Macht und Herrschaft im Denken von
Adorno und Heidegger (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 1980); Mrchen, Adorno und
Heidegger (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 1981); Assen Ignatow, Heidegger und die phi-
losophische Anthropologie (Meisenheim: Hain, 1979); Helga Kuschbert-Tlle,
Martin Heidegger: Der letzte Metaphysiker? (Meisenheim: Hain, 1979); Friedrich
Seven, Die Ewigkeit Gottes und die Zeitlichkeit des Menschen (Gttingen: Van-
denhoeck & Ruprecht, 1979); John Sallis, ed.. Radical Phenomenology (Atlantic
Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1978); Mervyn Sprung, ed., The Question of
Being (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1978); and David
A. White, Heidegger and the Language of Poetry (Lincoln: University of Neb-
raska Press, 1978).

(1982b). "Bauen, Wohnen, Denken: Ethische Konsequenzen der


Naturphilosophie Martin Heidegger," Philosophisches Jahrbuch 89, no. 2 (1982):
405-410.

(1983a). Technik und Gelassenheit: Zeitkritik nach Heidegger.


Freiburg: Alber, 1983. Pp. 274. This is the second half of Schirmacher's disserta-
tion, Ereignis Technik: Heidegger und die Frage nach der Technik (University of
Hamburg, 1980), with a new introduction and conclusion. For discussion, see sec-
tion A,4 of text.

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

181
(1983b). "From the Phenomenon to the Event of Technology: a
Dialectical Approach to Heidegger's Phenomenology," in Paul T. Durbin and
Friedrich Rapp, eds.. Philosophy and Technology (Boston: Reidel, 1983), pp. 275
289. A German version of this paper is available in P. Durbin and F . Rapp, eds.,
Technikphilosophie in der Diskussion (Braunschweig: Vieweg, 1982), pp. 245-257.

Schmitt, Richard (1969). Martin Heidegger on Being Human. New York: Ran-
dom, 1969. Pp. 274. Most of chapter 2, "Things," appeared earlier as "Heidegger's
Analysis of 'Tool'," Monist 49, no. 1 (January 1965): 70-86.

Schufreider, Gregory (1981). "Heidegger on Community," Man and World 14, no.
1 (1981): 25-54.

Schrmann, Reiner (1978). "Political Thinking in Heidegger," Social Research 45,


no. 1 (Spring 1978): 191-221. See also the author's "Questioning the Foundations of
Practical Philosophy," Human Studies 1, no. 4 (October 1978): 357-368; "The On-
tological Difference and Political Philosophy," Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research 40, no. 1 (Septembr 1979): 99-122.

(1981). "Principles Precarious: The Origin of the Political in


Heidegger," in Thomas Sheehan, ed. (1981), pp. 245-256.

(1986). Heidegger on Being and Acting: From Principles to Anar-


chy, trans. Christine-Marie Gros. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press,
1986. Translation of Le Principe d^anarchie: Heidegger et la question de Vagir
(Paris: Seuil, 1982).

Schuurman, Egbert (1980). Technology and the Future: A Philosophical Chal-


lenge. Trans. Donald Morton. Toronto: Wedge Publishing Foundation, 1980. Pp.
xxiii, 434. See especially pp. 80-122. Originally published as Technik en tekomst:
Confrontatie met wijsgerige beschouwingen (Assen, The Netherlands: Van Gor-
cum, 1972). For sympathetic analysis, see Donald Morton, "Continuing the Neo-
Calvinist Critique of Technology: Review of Egbert Schuurman's Technology and
Deliverance," Research in Philosophy and Technology, vol. 2 (1979): 329-340.
("Technology and Deliverance" was the preliminary title for the translation on
which Morton was working at the time.)

Schwan, Alexander (1965). Politische Philosophie im Denken Heideggers. Col-


ogne: Westdeutscher Verlag, 1965. Pp. 206.

(1974). "Martin Heidegger, Politik und praktische Philosophie: Zur


Problematik neuerer Heidegger-Literatur," Philosophisches Jahrbuch 81, no. 1
(1974): 148-171.

Seeburger, Francis F . (1976). "The Conversion of Nature and Technology," in


Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka, ed., Analecta Husserliana, vol. 5: The Crisis of Cul-
ture: Steps to Reopen the Phenomenological Investigation of Man (Boston:
Reidel, 1976), pp. 281-290. "Nature, which, in the mythico-religious attitude, was

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

182
manifest as the dimension of the sustaining, overwhelming, and ineluctable . . .
under the technological attitude . . . becomes manifest as a field open to human
organization and control" (pp. 286-287).

Seidel, George J . (1971). "Heidegger: Philosopher for Ecologists?" Man and


World 4, no. 1 (February 1971): 93-99.

Seigfried, Hans (1978). "Heidegger's Longest Day: Being and Time and the Sci-
ences," Philosophy Today 22, no. 4 (Winter 1978): 319-331.

(1980). "Scientific Realism and Phenomenology" Zeitschrift fr phi-


losophische Forschung 34, no. 3 (July-September 1980): 395-404.

Sheehan, Thomas (1979). "Philosophy and Propaganda: Response to Professor


Bronner," Salmagundi whole no. 43 (Winter 1979): 173-184.

Sheehan, Thomas, ed. (1981). Heidegger: The Man and the Thinker. Chicago: Pre-
cedent, 1981. Pp. XX, 347. The best single collection of essays on Heidegger in En-
glish. Divided into six parts. Part I, "Glimpses of the Philosopher's Life," con-
tains Sheehan's philosophical biography of the years leading up to Being and
Time, two brief auto-biographical reflections by Heidegger, as well as the Spiegel
interview, a letter from Husserl to Rudolph Otto about Heidegger, Karl Moehl-
ing's "Heidegger and the Nazis," and Fr. Bernhard Welte's funeral eulogy. Part
H, "Being, Dasein, and Subjectivity," contains essays by William J . Richardson,
Theodore Kisiel, John Sallis, and Robert E . Innis. Part HI deals with the Scheler-
Heidegger relationship and contains Max Scheler's critique of Being and Time,
section 43, a study by Parvis Emad, and Heidegger's "In Memory of Max
Scheler." Part IV, "Overcoming Metaphysics," contains essays by Walter
Biemel, Otto Pggeler, Jacques Taminiaux, and John D. Caputo. Part V is com-
posed of essays on "Technology, Politics, and Art" by Michael E . Zimmerman,
David Schweickart, Reiner Schrmann, and Sandra Lee Bartky. Part VI is an
exhaustive (but unannotated) bibliography of Heidegger translations and "Secon-
dary Literature in English, 1929-1977" by H. Miles Groth. The contributions by
Sheehan, Richardson, Kisiel, Biemel, Scheler, Zimmerman, Caputo, Moehling,
and Welte, along with three translations from Heidegger, only one of which is in-
cluded in the book, appeared earlier in Listening 12, no. 3 (Fall 1977), under the
same thematic title, "Heidegger: The Man and the Thinker."

Shmueli, Efraim (1975). "Contemporary Philosophical Theories and Their Rela-


tion to Science and Technology," Philosophy in Context vol. 4 (1975): 37-60.

Steiner, George (1979). Martin Heidegger. New York: Viking, 1979. Pp. 173.

Stewart, Roderick M. (1983). "Heidegger's Transcendental-Phenomenological


'Justification' of Science" in Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka and Calvin 0. Schrg,
eds.. Foundations of Morality, Human Rights, and the Human Sciences:
Phenomenology in a Foundational Dialogue with the Human Sciences, Analecta
Husserliana 15 (Boston: D. Reidel, 1983), pp. 189-207. An examination of Heideg-

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

183
ger's "existential conception of science" in Being and Time and how this provides
only historical not a universal or transcendental justification of science.

Strauss, Leo (1971). "Philosophy as a Rigorous Science and Political Philosophy,"


Interpretation 2, no. 1 (Summer 1971): 1-9. Included in Strauss, Studies in Platonic
Political Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984). See also
Strauss' essay on "Kurt Riezler" in What Is Political Philosophy? and Other
Studies (Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1959), especially pp. 246-248; the "Preface to
Spinoza's Critique of Religion," in Liberalism: Ancient and Modern (New York:
Basic Books, 1968), especially pp. 233-235; and Leo Strauss and Jacob Klein, "A
Giving of Accounts," The College [St. John's, Annapolis, MD] (April 1970), pp. 1
5.

Strawson, P.F. (1979). "Take the B Train," New York Review of Books 26, no. 6
(April 19, 1979): 35-37. A review of two books by George Steiner: Martin Heideg-
ger (1979) and On Difficulty and Other Essays (New York: Oxford University
Press, 1978).

Tribe, Laurence H. (1974). "Ways Not to Think about Plastic Trees," Yale Law
Journal 83, no. 7 (June 1974): 1315-1348. Limited use of Heidegger.

Van Meisen, Andrew G. (1961). Science and Technology. Pittsburgh: Duquesne


University Press, 1961. Pp. ix, 373. See especially chapters 9-13, where Heideg-
ger's analysis of technology is explicitly utilized.

Volpi, Franco (1980). "Nochmals Heidegger? Eine Bilanz der neuen internationa-
len Heidegger-Forschung," Philosophischer Literaturanzeiger 33, no. 4 (October-
December 1980): 366-386. A review of Alfred Jger, Gott: Nochmals Martin
Heidegger (Tbingen: Mohr, 1978); Manfred Thiel, Martin Heidegger: Sein Werk
Aufbau und Durchblick (Heidelberg: Elpis, 1977); Gerhard Schmitt, The Con-
cept of Being in Hegel and Heidegger (Bonn: Bouvier-Grundman, 1977); John D.
Caputo (1978); J.L. Mehta, Martin Heidegger: The Way and the Vision (Honolulu:
University of Hawaii Press, 1976); Jean Beaufret, Dialogue avec Heidegger, vols.
I-III (Paris: Editions de Minuit, 1973-1974); Henri Birault, Heidegger et Vexperi-
ence de la pensee (Paris: Gallimard, 1978); Vincenzo Vitiello, Heidegger: il nulla
e la fondazione della storicit <Urbino: Argalia, 1976); Vincenzo Vitiello, Dialet-
tica ed ermeneutica: Hegel e Heidegger (Naples: Guida, 1979); and Mario Rugge-
nini, II soggetto e la tecnica: Heidegger interprete ''inattuale'' delVepoca moderna
(Rome: Bulzoni, 1977).

Waterhouse, Roger (1981). A Heidegger Critique: A Critical Examination of the


Existential Phenomenology of Martin Heidegger. Atlantic Highlands, NJ:
Humanities Press, 1981. Pp. xi, 239.

Weizscker, Carl Friedrich von (1982). "Heidegger and Natural Science," in


Werner Marx, ed., Heidegger Memorial Lectures (Pittsburgh: Duquesne Univer-
sity Press, 1982), pp. 75-99.

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

184
Winner, Langdon (1977). Autonomous Technology: Technics out of Control as a
Theme in Political Thought. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1977. Pp. x, 386.

Zimmerman, Michael (1974). "Heidegger, Ethics, and National Socialism,"


Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 5, no. 1 (Spring 1974): 97-106.

(1975). "Heidegger on Nihilism and Technique," Man and World 8,


no. 4 (November 1975): 394-414.

(1977a). "Beyond 'Humanism': Heidegger's Understanding of Tech-


nology," Listening 12, no. 3 (Fall 1977): 74-83. Reprinted in Thomas Sheehan, ed.
(1981), pp. 219-227.

(1977b). "A Brief Introduction to Heidegger's Concept of Technol-


ogy," Humanities Perspectives on Technology Newsletter, whole no. 2 (October
1977): 10-13.

(1979a). "Heidegger and Marcuse: Technology as Ideology," Re-


search in Philosophy and Technology, vol. 2 (1979): 245-261.

(1979b). "Marx and Heidegger on the Technological Domination of


Nature," Philosophy Today 23, no. 2 (Summer 1979): 99-111.

(1981). Eclipse of the Self: The Development of Heidegger's Concept


of Authenticity. Athens: Ohio University Press,TL981. Pp. xxx, 331. For discussion,
see section A,5 of text.

(1983a). "Humanism, Ontology, and the Nuclear Arms Race," Re-


search in Philosophy and Technology, vol. 6 (1983): 157-172.

(1983b). "Toward a Heideggerean Ethos for Radical Environmen-


talism," Environmental Ethics 5, no. 2 (Summer 1983): 99-131. For discussion, see
section A,3 of text.

(1984). "Karel Kosik's Heideggerian Marxism," Philosophical


Forum 15, no. 3 (Spring 1984): 209-233.

2. Works on Art and Religion

Alderman, Harold G. (1973). "The Work of Art and Other Things," in Edward G.
Ballard and Charles E . Scott, eds., Martin Heidegger: In Europe and America
(The Hague: Nijhoff, 1973), pp. 157-170. From thing to art to poetry, a good basic
statement of the relationships.

Bartky, Sandra Lee (1979). "Heidegger and the Modes of World Disclosure," Phi-
losophy and Phenomenological Research 40, no. 2 (December 1979): 212-236.

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

185
(1981). "Heidegger's Philosophy of Art," in Thomas Sheehan, ed.
(1981), pp. 257-274. This is a revised version of an article with the same title,
British Journal of Aesthetics 9 (1969): 353-371. For discussion, see section B,2 of
text.

Biemel, Walter (1979). "Philosophy and Art," trans. Parvis Emad, Man and
World 12, no. 3 (1979): 267-283. Historical review from Plato to Heidegger, fol-
lowed by a Heideggerian attempt at "rendering intelligible what is articulated in
Art" (p. 275) in the case of one painting by Velazquez and another by Picasso.

Borgmann, Albert (1968). "The Place of Theology in a Technological World,"


NCEA [National Catholic Educational Association] Bulletin 64, no. 3 (February
1968): 28-33.

Bossart, William H. (1968). "Heidegger's Theory of Art," Journal of Aesthetics


and Art Criticism 27, no. 1 (Fall 1968): 57-66. For discussion, see section B,2 of
text.

Caputo, John D. (1978). The Mystical Element in Heidegger's Thought. Athens:


Ohio University Press, 1978. Pp. xvi, 292.

Cohen, Richard A. (1983). "Dasein's Responsibility for Being," Philosophy Today


27, no. 4 (Winter 1983): 317-325. Argues "an ethic of hermeneutic responsibility is
the very being of Dasein." Suggests an ethics in art.

Danner, Helmut (1971). Das Gttliche und der Gott bei Heidegger. Meisenheim:
Hain, 1971. Pp. 187.

DriscoU, Giles (1967). "Heidegger: A Response to Nihilism," Philosophy Today


11, no. 1 (Spring 1967): 17-37. Contains a brief discussion of technology in Heideg-
ger's via negativa response to nihilism.

Fandozzi, Phillip (1979). "Art in a Technological Society," Research in Philoso-


phy and Technology, vol. 2 (1979): 111-118. Commentary on the aesthetic theories
of Karsten Harries, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and Stanley Cavell. For further
reflection, see Fandozzi, "Art in a Technological Setting," Research in Philosophy
and Technology, vol. 5 (1982): 3-13, which (with only implicit reference to Heideg-
ger) argues that modern art "becomes a business rather than a fundamental
mode of knowledge; it becomes a recreation rather than genuine creation" (p. 8).

Foti, Veronique M. (1986). "Heidegger's and Merleau-Ponty's Turn from Technic-


ity to Art," Philosophy Today 30, No. 4 (Winter 1986): 306-16. Good comparison of
two different attempts to break out of technology by appealing to art.

Gethmann-Siefert, Annemarie (1974). Das Verhltnis von Philosophie und


Theologie im Denken Martin Heideggers. Freiburg: Alber, 1974. Pp. 340.

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

186
Halliburton, David (1981a). "From Poetic Thinking to Concrete Interpretation/'
Papers on Language and Literature 17, no. 1 (Winter 1981): 71-79. A Heideggerian
analysis of Wordsworth's poem "Michael."

(1981b). Poetic Thinking: An Approach to Heidegger. Chicago: Uni-


versity of Chicago Press, 1981. Pp. xii, 235.

Harries, Karsten (1966). "Heidegger's Conception of the Holy," Personalist 47, no.
2 (Spring, April 1966): 169-184.

(1983). "Thoughts on a Non-Arbitrary Architecture," Perspecta 20,


no. 1 1983): 9-20.

Heine, Steven (1985). Existentialism and Ontological Dimensions of time in


Heidegger and Dogen. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1985. Pp. 202.

Herrmann, Friedrich-Wilhelm von (1980). Heideggers Philosophie der Kunst:


Eine systematische Interpretation der Holzwege-Abhandlung ''Der Ursprung des
Kunstwerkes.'' Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1980. Pp. 379.

(1985). "Kunst und Technik," Heidegger Studies 1 (1985): 25-62.

Hsiao, Paul Shih-Yi (1977). "Wir trafen uns am Holzmarktplatz," in Gnther


Neske, ed., Erinnerung an Martin Heidegger (Pfullingen: Neske, 1977), pp. 119-29.

Hyland, Drew A. (1971). "Art and the Happening of Truth: Reflections on the End
of Philosophy," Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 30, no. 2 (Winter 1971):
177-187.

Ishida, Akira (1975). "Between Art and the Work of Art: On the Ontological Dif-
ference of Art" (in Japanese), Bigaku 26 (1975): 27-39.

Jaeger, Hans (1958). "Heidegger and the Work of Art," Journal of Aesthetics and
Art Criticism 17, no. 1 (September 1958): 58-71.

Jonas, Hans (1964). "Heidegger and Theology," Review of Metaphysics 18, no. 2,
whole no. 70 (December 1964): 207-233. Reprinted in Jonas' The Phenomenon of
Life (New York: Harper & Row, 1966), pp. 235-261.

Kaelin, E . F . (1967). "Notes Toward an Understanding of Heidegger's Aesthe-


tics," in E.N. Lee and M. Mandelbaum, eds.. Phenomenology and Existentialism
(Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Press, 1967), pp. 59-92.

Kelley, Derek A. (1977). "The Earth as Home," Religious Humanism 11, no. 4
(Autumn 1977): 216-218. Pop Heidegger.

Kockelmans, Joseph (1973). "Heidegger on Theology," Southwestern Journal of


Philosophy 4, no. 3 (Fall 1973): 85-108.

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

187
(1985). Heidegger on Art and Art Works. Dordrecht: Nijhoff, 1985.
Pp. xiv, 249. Two earlier studies related to this book: "Alcune Riflessioni sull
Coincezione della Terra in Heidegger," Humanitas 33 (1978): 445-468; and "On Art
and Language," in Jacques Sojcher and Gilbert Hottois, eds., Philosophie et Lan-
gage (Brussels: Editions de I'Universite de Bruxelles, 1982), pp. 125-146.

Kohak, Erazim (1984). The Embers and the Stars: A Philosophical Inquiry into
the Moral Sense of Nature. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984. Pp. xiii,
269. For review see Gale A. Johnson, "A Philosophical Inquiry into the Moral
Sense of Nature and Artifacts," Man and World 19 (1986): 103-118.

Kreeft, Peter (1971). "Zen in Heidegger's Gelassenheit," International Philosophi-


cal Quarterly 11, no. 4 (December 1971): 521-545.

Krell, David Farrell (1976). "Art and Truth in Raging Discord: Heidegger and
Nietzsche on the Will to Power," Boundary 2, vol. 4 (1976): 379-392. Good descrip-
tion of how Heidegger builds on and transforms Nietzsche's theory of art.

Langan, Thomas (1972). "Heidegger and the Possibility of Authentic Christian-


ity," Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association, vol. 46
(1972): 101-112.

(1980). Untitled review of John D. Caputo's The Mystical Element


in Heidegger's Thought (1978), New Scholasticism 54, no. 4 (Autumn 1980): 519
522.

Lawry, Edward G. (1978). "The Work-Being of the Work of Art in Heidegger,"


Man and World 11, nos. 1-2 (1978): 186-198. The art work in "The Origin of the
Work of Art" fits none of the types of being found in Being and Time (i.e., ready-
to-hand equipment, present-at-hand things, Dasein). Heidegger thus adds a new
type of being.

Leonard, Linda (1972). "Toward an Ontological Analysis of Detachment," Philos-


ophy Today 15, no. 4 (Winter 1972): 268-280.

Luther, Arthur R. (1982). "Original Emergence in Heidegger and Nishida," Phi-


losophy Today 26, no. 4 (Winter 1982): 345-356.

Magnus, Bernd (1971). "Nihilism, Reason, and The Good'," Review of


Metaphysics 25, no. 2, whole no. 98 (December 1971): 292-310.

Malik, Charles Habib (1977). "A Christian Reflection on Martin Heidegger,"


Thomist 41, no. 1 (January 1977): 1-61.

Malet, Andre (1983). "The Believer in the Presence of Technique," trans. Jim
Grote, in Carl Mitcham and Jim Grote, eds., Theology and Technology: Essays in
Christian Analysis and Exegesis (Lanham, MD: University Press of America,

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

188
1983), pp. 91-106. Originally published as "Le Croyant en face de la technique,"
Revue d'histoire et de philosophie religieuses 55, no. 3 (1975): 417-430.

Marx, Werner (1972). "The World in Another Beginning: Poetic Dwelling and the
Role of the Poet," in Joseph J . Kockelmans, ed. and trans.. On Heidegger and
Language (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1972), pp. 235-250.
From a conference. Discussion follows, pp. 250-259.

MiceU, Vincent P., SJ (1972). "Heidegger and Bultmann: Keepers of the Cosmic
Cage," UOsservatore Romano 25, no. 221 (June 22, 1972): 4 and 11.

Murray, Edward L. (1982). "Be-ing . . . Think-ing . . . Thank-ing: Reflections on


Technology in the Spirit of Martin Heidegger," Studies in Formative Spirituality
3, no. 2 (May 1982): 225-243.

Nakaoka, Narifumi (1985). "Zur Differenz-Frage: H. Tanabes Philosophie des Ab-


soluten Nichts," Philosophisches Jahrbuch 92, no. 1 (1985): 124-125.

Nwodo, Christopher (1976). "The Work of Art in Heidegger: A World Disclosure,"


Cultural Hermeneutics 4, no. 1 (November 1976): 61-74). Art is not only an object
of aesthetic experience but also a revelation of the world of a people at a particu-
lar time and place, and through this the epochal manifestation of a people's open-
ness to Being.

(1977). "The Role of Art in Heidegger's Philosophy," Philosophy


Today 21, no. 3 (Fall 1977): 294-304. For discussion, see section B,2 of text.

Olivier, G. (1984). "Heidegger and Architecture: Preliminary Remarks," South


African Journal of Philosophy 3, no. 1 (February 1984): 22-30.

Olson, Carl (1981). "The Leap of Thinking: A Comparison of Heidegger and the
Zen Master Dgen," Philosophy Today 25, no. 1 (Spring 1981): 55-62.

Omori, Shoichi (1972). "Art and Technology," Bigaku 23, no. 3, whole no. 91 (De-
cember 1972): 42 and 81. Japanese and German abstracts of a paper read at the
23rd National Congress of the Japanese Society for Aesthetics.

Perotti, James L. (1974). Heidegger on the Divine: The Thinker, the Poet, and
God. Athens: Ohio University Press, 1974. Pp. x, 134.

Richardson, Herbert W. (1965). "Heidegger and God and Professor Jonas,"


Thought 40, whole no. 156 (Spring 1965): 13-40.

Robinson, James M., and John B. Cobb, eds. (1963). The Later Heidegger and
Theology. New York: Harper & Row, 1963. Pp. xii, 212.

Rosen, Stanley (1969). Nihilism: A Philosophical Essay. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press, 1969. Pp. xx, 241.

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

189
Schaeffler, Richard (1978). Frmmigkeit des Denkens? Martin Heidegger und die
katholische Theologie. Darmstadt: Wissenschafthche Buchgesellshaft, 1978. Pp.
xiii, 160.

Schrg, Calvin 0. (1973). "The Transvaluation of Aesthetics and the Work of Art,"
Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 4, no. 3 (Fall 1973): 109-124.

Schrmann, Reiner (1973). "Heidegger and Meister Eckart on Releasement," Re-


search in Phenomenology 3 (1973): 95-119.

(1974) and (1975). "Trois penseurs de delaissement: Maitre Eck


hart, Heidegger, Suzuki," Part I, Journal of the History of Philosophy 12, no. 4
(October 1974): 455-477; and Part H , ibid. 13, no. 1 (January 1975): 43-60.

(1978). "The Loss of the Origin in Soto Zen and in Meister Eckhart,"
Thomist 42, no. 2 (April 1978): 281-312.

Seigfried, Hans (1978). "Art and the Origin of Truth," Man and World 11, nos. 1-2
(1978): 45-58. Philosophy can benefit from studying works of art la Heidegger.

Sendaydiego, Henry B. (1976). "Heidegger's Thoughts on Aesthetics," Journal of


the West Virginia Philosophical Society, vol. 10 (1976): 14-16. Attempts to use
Heidegger's theory of art as a basis for expanding public funding of artists. Vigor-
ous and largely accurate statement which nonetheless misuses the term "aesthe-
tics" in relation to Heidegger.

Skousgaard, Stephen, ed. (1981). Phenomenology and the Understanding of


Human Destiny. Washington, DC: University Press of America, 1981. Pp. viii, 384.
A collection of twenty-three papers, two of which deal with Heidegger and reli-
gion: Michael E . Zimmerman's "The Religious Element of the 'Destiny of
Being'" (pp. 303-324), and David McKenzie's "Seinsdenken and the Paradox of
Grace" (pp. 325-334).

Smith, P. Christopher (1977). "A Poem of Rilke: Evidence for the Later Heideg-
ger," Philosophy Today 21, no. 3 (Fall 1977): 250-262. In a 1922 poem Rilke distin-
guishes "authentic and inauthentic levels of the creative process [and] gives us
the outlines of a theory of techne which breaks radically with the modern princi-
ple of subjectivity, indeed with any understanding of self and world which sees
the world in terms of acts of objectification originating in the self." Uses this
poem to explicate the understandings of techne in Heidegger and Gadamer. Writ-
ing a poem, Rilke says, is like a woman giving birth to a child; she does not ex-
perience herself as efficient cause but merely as the instrument of an event which
transcends her.

Stahl, Gerry (1979). "Attuned to Being: Heideggerian Music in a Technological


Society," in William V. Spanos, ed., Martin Heidegger and the Question of Litera-
ture: Toward a Post-Modern Literary Hermeneutics (Bloomington, IN: Indiana
University Press, 1979), pp. 297-324.

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

190
Steffney, John (1981). "Man and Being in Heidegger and Zen Buddhism," Philoso-
phy Today 25, no. 1 (Spring 1981): 46-54.

Sun, P. Hans (1985). "Martin Heidegger, Leo Strauss, and Ellul," Cross Currents
35, no. 1 (Spring 1985) : 84-87. A comparison to Heidegger's detriment.

Tyman, Stephen (1984). "Mysticism and Gnosticism in Heidegger," Philosophy


Today 28, no. 4 (Winter 1984): 358-371.

Umehara, Takeshi (1970). "Heidegger and Buddhism," Philosophy East and West
20, no. 3 (July 1970): 271-81.

Watson, James R. (1975). "Being . . . There: The Neighborhood of Being," Philos-


ophy Today 19, no. 2 (Summer 1975): 118-130.

Weber, Ludwig, OP (1980). Heidegger und die Theologie. Knigstein: Forum


Academicum of the Athenum-Hain-Scriptor-Hanstein Publishing Group, 1980.
Pp. 100.

Welte, Bernhard (1965). "Die Gottesfrage im Denken Heideggers," in Welte's Auf


der Spur des Ewigen (Freiburg: Herder, 1965), pp. 262-276.

(1975). "God in Heidegger's Thought," trans. William J . Kramer,


Philosophy Today 20, no. 1 (Spring 1982): 85-100.

(1977). "Seeking and Finding: The Speech at Heidegger's Burial,"


trans. Thomas Sheehan, Listening 12, no. 3 (Fall 1977): 106-109. Reprinted in
Thomas Sheehan, ed. (1981), pp. 73-75. Another English trans., under the title
"Search and Find," Universitas: A German Review of the Arts and Sciences 19,
no. 4 (1977): 301-305, appends Psalm 130 and a passage from St. Matthew which
were apparently read at the funeral.

White, David A. (1975). "A Refutation of Heidegger as Nihilist," Personalist 56,


no. 3 (Summer 1975): 276-288.

(1978). Heidegger and the Language of Poetry. Lincoln: University


of Nebraska Press, 1978. Pp. xv, 245.

Wisser, Richard, ed. (1970). Martin Heidegger im Gesprch. Freiburg: Alber,


1970. Pp. 77. An English translation by Vincent Guagliardo and Robert Pambrun
of Wisser's interview with Heidegger under the title "Martin Heidegger: An Inter-
view," in Listening 6, no. 1 (Winter 1971): 34-40.

Wright, Kathleen (1984). "The Place of the Work of Art in the Age of Technology,"
Southern Journal of Philosophy 22, no. 4 (Winter 1984): 565-582.

Yonezawa, Aritsune (1975). "The Art-Philosophy of Heidegger" (in Japanese),


Bigaku 26, no. 3, whole no. 103 (December 1975): 16-26.

Zimmerman, Michael (1983). "Heidegger and Heraclitus on Spiritual Practice,"


Philosophy Today 27, no. 2 (Summer 1983): 87-103.

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

191
Part Three
INDEX OF NAMES
Name Page Eckhart, Meister 147, 154
Adorno, Theodor 111, 124, 125 Einstein, Albert 144
Ahlers, Rolf 125, 141 Ellul, Jacques 114, 115, 133
Alderman, Harold 102, 109, 144 Emad, Parvis 110
Allemann, Beda 129
Apel, Otto 123 Fandozzi, Phillip 117, 122, 123, 146, 150
Aristotle 136 Fay, Thomas 114
Fell, Joseph 109
Bahr, Hans-Dieter 125 Fijisawa, Chikao 149
Ballard, Edward 102, 116, 120, 157 Fink, Eugen 126, 127
Barth, Karl 156 Foucault, Michel 135
Bartky, Sandra Lee 144 Franks, Dean 113
Barrett, William 157 Freud, Sigmund 146
Becker, Oskar 139
Benjamin, Walter 145 Gadamer, Hans-Georg 104, 142
Berciano, Modesto 123 Galbraith, John Kenneth 134
Biemel, Walter 108, 138, 142, 143 Gerratana, Valentino 124
Billington, David P. 146 Goff, Robert 113
Blitz, Mark 135, 136, 137 Goldmann, Lucien 125, 126
Bloch, Ernst 119 Grange, Joseph 112, 120, 141
Bloomer, Kent C. 146 Grant, George 111
Boorstin, Daniel 134 Grene, Marjorie 108
Borgmann, Albert 99, 111, 114, 148 Grote, Jim 109, 156
Bossart, William 141, 143, 144 Grnder, Karlfried 102, 125
Brand, Stewart 113 Guzzoni, Ute 129
Bronner, Stephen Eric 127, 128
Buruma, Ian 151 Habermas, Jrgen 123, 124, 140
Halliburton, David 146
Caputo, John 106, 112, 134, 147, 149 Harries, Karsten 133, 134, 141, 142, 146
150, 151, 152, 153 Hartshorne, Charles 104
Colaizzi, Paul 112, 115, 120 Heelan, Patrick 102, 106, 107, 138, 157
Hegel, G.W.F. 144
Dallmayr, Fred 137, 138 Hermann, Friedrich-Wilhelm von 108,
Dauenhauer, Bernard 134, 135, 137 145
DeCarolis, Massimo 102 Hirsch, Fred 134
DeGeorge, Richard T. 126 Hofstadter, Albert 103, 109, 142
Delfini, Alexander 123, 124, 141 Hlderlin, Friedrich 153
Descartes, Rene 145 Holton, Gerald 100
Dessauer, Friedrich 110, 115 Hood, Webster 115, 116, 141
Deutsch, Eliot 148 Horkheimer, Max 124
Dewey, John 105 Hhnerfeld, Paul 147
Dooyeweerd, Herman 114 Husserl, Edmund 101, 123, 127, 149
Dreyfus, Hubert 118, 121, 122, 132, 136,
139, 141, 157, 158 Ihde, Don 118, 120, 121, 122, 139, 157
Dworkin, Ronald 136, 137 Ishida, Akika 149

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

192
Jaeger, Hans 143 Mitcham, Carl 99, 109, 113, 114,
Jaspers, Karl 129 115, 119, 156
Jonas, Hans 118, 119, 120, 139 Moehling, Karl A 129
Jung, Hwa Yol 112 Moore, Charles W. 146
Jung, Pette 112 Mrchen, Hermann 111, 124, 125
Jnger, Ernst 111, 127, 150 Moser, Simon 109, 115, 138, 139
Jnger, Friedrich Georg 114 Mller, Max 128, 129
Murray, Michael 108
Murray, Patrick 124
Kaelin, E . F . 143, 144
Kant, Immanuel 113, 126, 145
Kimball, Roger 127, 129 Naess, Arne 108, 112
King, Magda 102, 109 Nakaoka, Narifumi 149
Kisiel, Theodore 101, 102, 104, 105, Nicholson, Graeme 134
11, 123, 143 Nietzsche, Friedrich 122, 130
Klaus, Georg 114 Nishida, Kitaro 149
Kockelmans, Joseph 101, 102, 144, 145 Nitta, Hoshihiro 149
Kolb, David A. 107 Nwodo, Christopher 141, 143, 144
Krell, David Farrell 110, 111
Kuhn, Richard 142 Omori, Shoichi 149
Kuhn, Thomas 103 Orr, John 111
Kuki, Shuzo 148 Ott, Hugo 129
Ottmann, Henning 114
Laertius, Diogenes 110 Pachter, Henry 127, 128
Langan, Thomas 108 Palmier, Jean-Michel 111
Lawry, Edward 144 Perotti, James L. 152, 153, 154
Leiss, William 124 Picasso, Pablo 143
Linder, Staffan 134 Piccone, Paul 123, 124, 141
Lingis, A . F . 113 Pirsig, Robert 100
Loscerbo, John 108, 110, 114 Plato 136, 155
Lovitt, William 108, 109 Pggeler, Otto 108, 129, 130, 132,
Lowith, Karl 138, 147 133, 137, 141
Lukacs, Georg 124, 125, 146
Quine, Willard Van Or man 100
Maclntyre, Alasdair 128
Mackey, Robert 109, 119 Rapp, Friedrich 117
Macomber, W.B. 108 Richardson, WiUiam J . 101, 108
Macquarrie, John 102 Rohrmoser, Gunter 123
Magnus, Bernd 103, 108 Rorty, Richard 105, 106, 107, 128
Malet, Andre 109 Rosen, Stanley 127, 150
Marcuse, Herbert 123, 124, 125, Rouse, Joseph 103
127, 137, 140, 141
Marx, Werner 108, 119, 123, 124, Sachsse, Hans 125
125, 126, 127, 137 Sallis, John 102
Maurer, Reinhart 123, 124, 125, 137, Sayle, Murray 151
138, 147 Schinzinger, Robert 149
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice 135, 143 Schirmacher, Wolfgang 108, 113, 117,
Meyer, Hermann 114 121, 124, 125, 132

HEIDEGGER AND TECHNOLOGY

193
Schmitt, Richard 120, 131, 132, 133 Umehara, Takeshi 151
Schopenhauer, Arthur 117, 146 Unger, Roberto Mangabeira 128
Schrg, Calvin 0. 143
Schufreider, Gregory 133 Valery, Paul 145
Schrmann, Reiner 127, 134, 135, 137 Van Meisen, Andrew G. 102
Schuurman, Egbert 114 Velazquez 143
Schwan, Alexander 125, 127, 130, Versenyi, Laszlo 147
132, 133, 137, 141, 146
Scitovsky, Tiber 134 Walzer, Michael 136, 137
Seeburger, Francis F. 102 Waterhouse, Roger 104, III, 123, 126
Seidel, George 112 Weizscker, Carl Friedrich von 105,
Seigfried, Hans 101 129, 138
Sendaydiego, Henry 142 Welte, Bernhard 152, 153, 154, 155, 156
Sheehan, Thomas 108, 128, 129 White, David A. 150, 155
Shmueli, Efraim 125 Wiener, Norbert 114
Sophocles 119 Winner, Langdon 133
Speer, Albert 129 Wittgenstein, Ludwig 105, 113
Spinoza, Baruch 117 Wright Kathleen 145, 146
Stambaugh, Joan 109
Steinbuch, Karl 114 Zimmerman, Michael 102, 110, 111, 113,
Steiner, George 108, 109, 129 122, 123, 124, 125, 127, 131, 154, 157
Stone, Christopher 112
Strauss, Leo 127, 150

Tatematsu, Hirotaka 149


Tribe, Laurence 112

PHILOSOPHY TODAY

194

Anda mungkin juga menyukai