Anda di halaman 1dari 13

See

discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at:


https://www.researchgate.net/publication/7385988

On Evidence and Evidence-Based


Medicine: Lessons from the Philosophy of
Science

Article in Social Science & Medicine July 2006


Impact Factor: 2.89 DOI: 10.1016/j.socscimed.2005.11.031 Source: PubMed

CITATIONS READS

143 142

1 author:

Maya J. Goldenberg
University of Guelph
40 PUBLICATIONS 395 CITATIONS

SEE PROFILE

All in-text references underlined in blue are linked to publications on ResearchGate, Available from: Maya J. Goldenberg
letting you access and read them immediately. Retrieved on: 25 May 2016
ARTICLE IN PRESS

Social Science & Medicine 62 (2006) 26212632


www.elsevier.com/locate/socscimed

On evidence and evidence-based medicine: Lessons from the


philosophy of science
Maya J. Goldenberg
Michigan State University, East Lansing, Mich., USA
Available online 27 December 2005

Abstract

The evidence-based medicine (EBM) movement is touted as a new paradigm in medical education and practice, a
description that carries with it an enthusiasm for science that has not been seen since logical positivism ourished (circa
19201950). At the same time, the term evidence-based medicine has a ring of obviousness to it, as few physicians, one
suspects, would claim that they do not attempt to base their clinical decision-making on available evidence. However, the
apparent obviousness of EBM can and should be challenged on the grounds of how evidence has been problematised in
the philosophy of science. EBM enthusiasm, it follows, ought to be tempered.
The post-positivist, feminist, and phenomenological philosophies of science that are examined in this paper contest the
seemingly unproblematic nature of evidence that underlies EBM by emphasizing different features of the social nature of
science. The appeal to the authority of evidence that characterizes evidence-based practices does not increase objectivity
but rather obscures the subjective elements that inescapably enter all forms of human inquiry. The seeming common sense
of EBM only occurs because of its assumed removal from the social context of medical practice. In the current age where
the institutional power of medicine is suspect, a model that represents biomedicine as politically disinterested or merely
scientic should give pause.
r 2005 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

Keywords: Evidence; Evidence-based medicine; Philosophy of science; Positivism; Feminist epistemology; Phenomenology

Introduction This rigour is achieved through methodological


clinical decision-making based on examination of
To have evidence is to have some conceptual evidence derived from the latest clinical research.
warrant for belief or action (Goodman 2003, p. 2), Evidence as accumulated data has been made widely
and it is the practice of basing all beliefs and and easily available to clinicians and educators by
practices strictly on evidence that allegedly sepa- evolving information technologies, and EBM a-
rates science from other activities (Husserl, 1982; cionados, such as those found in the Cochrane
Kuhn, 1996). The evidence-based medicine (EBM) Collaboration (Grimshaw, 2004) and on the editor-
movement purports to eschew unsystematic and ial boards of various evidence-based practice
intuitive methods of individual clinical practice in journals, describe the movement as a new paradigm
favour of a more scientically rigorous approach. in medical education and practice, a description that
carries with it a science enthusiasm that has not
E-mail address: golden11@msu.edu. been seen since the days of positivism.

0277-9536/$ - see front matter r 2005 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.socscimed.2005.11.031
ARTICLE IN PRESS
2622 M.J. Goldenberg / Social Science & Medicine 62 (2006) 26212632

The term evidence-based medicine, and its the second half of the 20th century by such
standard denition as the conscientious, explicit, historically oriented philosophers as Thomas Kuhn,
and judicious use of current best evidence in making Norwood Hanson, and Paul Feyerabend. Their
decisions about the care of individual patients historical analyses of scientic change and progress
(Sackett, Rosenberg, Gray, Haynes, & Richardson, undermined the positivistempiricist endorsement
1996, p. 71), has a ring of obviousness to it which of the claims of science to provide a value-free
makes it difcult to argue against. Few doctors, one understanding of the natural world. Their examina-
suspects, would be willing to assert that they do not tion of the relationship between science and values
attempt to base their clinical decision-making on (and the denial of their possible or even preferable
available evidence.1 However, the apparent ob- separation) has been enriched by the insights of
viousness of EBM can and should be challenged feminist epistemologies of science and phenomen-
on the grounds of how evidence has been ological investigations. Feminist epistemologists
problematised in the philosophy of science. In this have exposed the political stakes in knowledge
paper, I argue that evidence-based practices main- production by demonstrating the androcentric
tain an antiquated understanding of evidence as assumptions underlying conventional understand-
facts about the world in the assumption that ings of scientic thought and practice, while
scientic beliefs stand or fall in light of the evidence. phenomenologists have questioned the goals and
This understanding of evidence is explicitly positi- methods of scientic medicine through examination
vist, and such a picture of science has been seriously of the patients lived experience of illness and dis-
undermined by post-positive philosophies of ease. In this paper, I take the lessons learned from
science. EBMs ability to guide healthcare deci- post-positivist, feminist, and phenomenological
sion-making by appealing to the evidence as the epistemologies of sciences critiques of the presumed
bottom line is attractive to many because it self-apparentness of evidence and consider their
proposes to rationalise this complex social process. implications for EBM.
Yet it does so through the positivistic elimination of
culture, contexts, and the subjects of knowledge Evidence and evidence-based medicine
production from consideration, a move that permits
the use of evidence as a political instrument where The popular histories of science recount scientic
power interests can be obscured by seemingly progress as having been motivated by the evidence-
neutral technical resolve. based practices of innovative scientists. Rejecting
Logical positivism is a philosophical system that the dogma and superstition that pervaded their
recognises only scientically veriable propositions historical moment, these innovators let the evidence,
as meaningful. This school of thought originated in as gathered through unbiased and careful experi-
Vienna in the 1920s by a group of philosophers and mentation, dictate their scientic practices, beliefs,
scientists concerned with the philosophy of formal and theories (Harding, 1986; Kuhn, 1996). Thus
and physical science. However, it was their attitude science purports to be a democratic enterprise
toward science and its relationship to philosophy insofar as the beliefs of the Church, accomplished
that denes the Vienna Circle. Because the Circle colleagues, or department chairs are subject to the
rejected the possibility of justifying knowledge same critical inquiry as lay beliefs.
claims that were beyond the scope of science, The EBM movement centres around ve linked
they dismissed metaphysics and many of the claims ideas: rst, clinical decisions should be based on the
made in theology and ethics as nonsensical (or best available scientic evidence; second, the clinical
unveriable). Emigration by many of the Circles problem, and not the habits or protocols, should
members to Britain and the United States during the determine the type of evidence to be sought; third,
early war years led to the strong inuence of logical identifying the best evidence means using epidemio-
positivism on Anglo-American analytic philosophy. logical and biostatistical ways of thinking; fourth,
The post-positive turn in the philosophy of conclusions derived from identifying and critically
science refers to the critical examinations of appraising evidence are useful only if put into action
scientic thought and practice that originated in in managing patients or making health care
decisions; nally, performance should be constantly
1
This has led some critics to suggest that there is nothing new evaluated (Davidoff, Haynes, Sackett, & Smith,
about EBM (Sackett et al., 1996, p. 71). 1995, p. 1085). Evidence-based medical practice
ARTICLE IN PRESS
M.J. Goldenberg / Social Science & Medicine 62 (2006) 26212632 2623

purports to achieve these goals by enlisting numer- evidence-based practice. This paper draws on major
ous techniques for the management, evaluation, and lines of thinking in the philosophy of science over
application of clinical data into medical practice. Its the past half century to question the evidence
hallmark is the hierarchy of evidence that consis- base of EBM.
tently places the evidence derived from randomised
controlled clinical trials on top (Sackett et al., 1996, Post-positivist philosophy of science
p. 72). The synthesis of large amounts of clinical
trial data into manageable clinical summaries or Much of the philosophy of science over the last
meta-analyses by the hardworking volunteers at half century has been preoccupied with challenging
the Cochrane Collaboration and other institutional the positivist picture of scientic methodology on
afliates and the proliferation of this information two grounds. In the rst, Hanson (1958), Kuhn
via EBM journals and electronic databases are (1970, 1996) and Feyerabend (1978) have claimed
supposed to revolutionise medical practice and offer that observation is theory-laden; that is, our
objective and politically transparent criteria for observations are coloured by our background
funding decisions at the policy level. beliefs and assumptions (and therefore can never be,
Evidence-based is typically read in medicine even under the most ideal circumstances or con-
and other life and social sciences as the empirically trolled experimental settings, the unmitigated per-
adequate standard of reasonable practice and a ception of the nature of things). In the second,
means for increasing certainty. Evidence-based Duhem (1982) and Quine (1960) have argued that
practices are therefore enormously appealing in theories are underdetermined by data. In other
the age of moral pluralism; rather than relying on words, our theory choices are never determined
explicit values that are likely not shared by all, the exclusively by the evidence.
evidence is proposed to adjudicate between com- The rst claim is damaging (if not devastating) to
peting claims. (Goldenberg, 2005). However, the the positivist empiricist picture because the princi-
notion that any claim (including scientic beliefs) ples of empiricism are tendered against the back-
can stand or fall in light of the evidence assumes a ground presupposition that ones perceptions are
givenness of evidence as facts about the world. unaffected by the beliefs one has and by the
Positivistic empiricists have regarded evidence in assumptions one makes about the objects that one
this way: any bias that enters scientic inquiry in the is observing. These observations are supposed to
context of discovery is eradicated in the purifying provide a maximally certain and conceptually
process of the context of justification. The evidence unrevisable foundation of empirical knowledge, a
left standing after scientic inquiry is assumed to be foundation that supplies the basic premises of all
facts about the world and therefore warrants the our reasoning and without which there would not
title scientific evidence. even be any probable knowledge. Empiricist episte-
EBM promotes such a scientic conception of mology, from Humes (1977, 2000) 18th century
evidence in its endorsement of evidence derived congurations onward, seems to rest on the
from systematic and methodologically rigorous assumption that there is an absolutely stable and
clinical research and maligning the use of intuition, invariant correspondence between perceptions and
unsystematic clinical experience, patient and profes- the stimuli which produce them. The critics men-
sional values, and pathophysiologic rationale (Bue- tioned above object that observations are not
tow & Keneally, 2000; Guyatt, Cairns, Churchill et givens or data, but are always the product of
al., 1992). This preference has prompted critics to interpretation (in light of our background assump-
detail other sources of evidence that enter into tions). The idea of unambiguous objects of percep-
clinical decision-making (Buetow, 2002; Buetow & tion is a myth, as multistable images (such as
Keneally, 2000; Upshur, VanDenKerkhof, & Goel, Wittgensteins duck/rabbit and the popular old
2001) and to defend the unsystematic intuitions and lady/young lady image) aptly demonstrate. This
expertise that arise from clinical experience as exercise in gestalt psychology suggests that what
epistemically signicant and indispensable to clin- someone perceives is not independent of ones
ical decision-making (Tanenbaum, 1993). Yet even beliefs and expectations.
before we consider the complex nature of clinical The charge that theories are underdetermined by
decision-making, we can question the very tenability datacommonly referred to as the DuhemQuine
of the conception of evidence being assumed in thesis in the philosophy of scienceconcerns the
ARTICLE IN PRESS
2624 M.J. Goldenberg / Social Science & Medicine 62 (2006) 26212632

claim that any given body of evidence may support functioned equipment, poor design, or bias, and
numerous, even contradicting, theories. The charge there are no predetermined rules for the statistical
once again undermines empirical sciences self- interpretation of the results of a test (Shahar, 1997).
understanding as an objective enterprise that The highly prized meta-analysis provides a further
progresses (i.e., accepts, renes, or rejects scientic level of interpretation, one that is notably high
theories) in light of how theories stand up to impact insofar as it carries the institutional brand
empirical evidence. Since scientic theories are evidence-based medicine and because individual
deductively underdetermined by the data, scientists practitioners who rely on these summaries for
must adopt extraempirical criteria for what counts evidence-based decision-making are no longer
as a good theory when deciding to accept one theory critically reading the trial data. Finally, the practi-
in preference over its empirically adequate rivals. tioner must apply one more layer of interpretation
This extraempirical criteria is subject to the in her application of trial results to a specic
whims, preferences, biases, and social agendas of patient. The formal methods promoted by EBM to
the researching scientists, and not the rigour of replace so-called traditional medicines over-
evidenced-based adjudication. reliance on intuition, habits, and unsystematic
While the theory ladenness objection chal- clinical experience (Guyatt et al., 1992) appear to
lenges the stability of observations themselves, the repeat the misplaced effort to separate science from
underdetermination thesis undermines the stabi- values.
lity of evidential relations. Both accounts have
seemed to permit the unrestrained expression of Feminist epistemologies of science
scientists subjective preferences in the content of
science. If observation is theory-laden, then it Feminist philosophers endorse the post-positivis-
cannot serve as an independent constraint on tic conclusions derived from analyses of the
theories, thus permitting subjective elements to relations between observation, evidence, and theory
constrain theory choice. Similarly, if observations and have taken the critique of empiricist epistemol-
acquire evidential relevance only in the context of a ogy further to challenge empiricisms silent part-
set of assumptions, a relevance that changes with a ner: the theory of the unconditioned subject. This
suitable change in assumptions, then it is not clear unbiased observer is argued in feminist thought to
what protects theory choice from subjective ele- be the necessary companion to empiricist epistemol-
ments hidden in ones background assumptions. ogy, and reection on this subjects unusual and
Although empirical adequacy serves as a constraint implausible ontology reveals further difculties with
on theory acceptance, it is not sufcient to pick out positivist thought. Positivism, therefore, not only
one theory from all contenders as the true theory errs in holding sensory observation in ideal ob-
regarding a domain of the natural world. servation conditions as the privileged source of
knowledge, but also inappropriately attaches a
Post-positive implications for EBM dubious theory of epistemic agency in which
knowers are detached and neutral spectators sepa-
A 1995 publication in The Lancet documented the rate from the objects of knowledge. Positivist
disagreement among members of a research team empiricism does not, in fact, yield neutral and
regarding the interpretation of their trial results for universally valid conceptions of knowledge. Instead,
streptokinase treatment for acute ischemic stroke knowledge is indelibly shaped by its creators and
(Horton, 1995). Upon agreeing to disagree, the attests to the specicities of their epistemic loca-
team presented two views (see Candelise, Aritzu, tions. Indeed, it is because subjects are irrelevant to
Ciccone, Ricci, & Warlaw, 1995; Tognoni & the knowledge claims that the latter appear to be
Roncaglioni, 1995). No one position was seen to veriable by appeals to the evidence (Code, 1993,
be wrong at least insofar as both sides appeared to p. 17).
be supported by the clinical data (Horton, 1995). Notions of evidence and theories of epistemic
Even within the connes of strictly evidence-based agency are, therefore, closely related. Haraway
practice, empirical evidence undergoes numerous (1996) argues that the notion of matters of fact
subjective interpretations. There is room for dispute depends on many kinds of transparencies in the
regarding the design of a study on the grounds of grand narratives of the experimental way of life. The
measurement error, contaminated solution, mal- modest witness, the protagonist of the dramas of
ARTICLE IN PRESS
M.J. Goldenberg / Social Science & Medicine 62 (2006) 26212632 2625

the Scientic Revolution who testies without atisation (Nelson, 1993a, p. 131). It is only by
prejudice to new facts, had to be constructed in positing this framework of a shared reality experi-
sufciently detached and abstracted terms to make entially accessible to all sentient beings that any-
plausible the unusual situation where his experiences body (or everybody) can discover, observe, or
could somehow represent everyones and no-one-in- witness truths about the world. While ones faith
particulars experiences. Notions of evidence as in such universality might be partly underwritten by
self-appearing similarly rely on such a knower similarities in sense organs, it also requires that
(Nelson, 1993a). there is a unique and true theory of nature and that
Feminist epistemologies of science have demon- our sense organs are sufciently rened to discover
strated that the ideals of the autonomous knower it and discriminate it from possible alternatives
the dislocated, disinterested observerand the (Nelson, 1993a, p. 132). Experience alone, however,
epistemologies they inform are the artefacts of a does not warrant the assumption that only one
small, privileged group of educated and prosperous system could organise the world or that the world is
white men. Their material circumstances allow them of a determinate nature, speciable in categories
to believe that they are autonomous individuals that our sense organs will lead us to discover. There
without specic locations (i.e., gendered or raced) is nothing in our experience to rule out the
even in their positions of privilege.2 Haraways possibility of a future theory that is commensurate
postulation of such a modest man, whose with all of our experiences to date but incompatible
narratives mirror reality, requires invisibility, such with the current theory. There is also nothing in our
that such a man must inhabit the space perceived experience or in our current knowledge about our
by its inhabitants to be the culture of no-culture sense organs to warrant the inference that they are
(1996, p. 429). able to discriminate a best theory of nature (if,
In this culture, the inhabitants contingencies can indeed, there is such a thing) from multiple
be established with all of the authority, but none of candidates.
the considerable problems, of transcendental truth. Feminist epistemologists are particularly resistant
His modesty is of a specically modern, profes- to the notion of shared experience that supports
sional, European, masculine and scientic form orthodox empiricism because feminist investigations
(and is therefore very different from the virtue into the lives of women reveal great diversity of
typically attributed to women), and it imbues him experiences, many of which are distinctly gendered,
with a disguised epistemological and social power raced, classed, or mediated by numerous other
concealed by modernist ideals of rationality, social stratications. For orthodox empiricists (in-
objectivity, and value-neutrality. His modesty cluding positivists, who apply radical empiricist
guarantees his legitimacy as an authorised ventri- epistemology to science) historical, gendered, and
loquist for the object world, adding nothing from locational differences between and among knowers
his mere opinions, from his biasing embodiment. reduce to bias or aberration and should be
And so he is endowed with the remarkable power to discounted in formal justication procedures. Fem-
establish the facts. He bears witness (Haraway, inists object that such reductions exclude and even
1996, p. 429). harm women, as the so-called universals that are
Underlying the orthodox account of scientic thought to underlie the social context (and serve as
investigation and justication is a presumed uni- the foundation of scientic knowledge) are dis-
versality of experience (or at least the potential for tinctly androcentric. This claim has been illustrated
such universality through the rened abilities of the by numerous documentations of gender bias in the
modest witness), which presumes, in turn, both a natural and biological sciences (for example, see
view of evidence and a view of knowers, where Fausto-Sterling, 1989, 1992; Haraway, 1989, 1991;
individuals have unmediated or unltered access to Hubbard & Lowe, 1979; Keller, 1985). For all of its
a reality that itself admits of only one system- alleged experiential grounding, the experience with
which empiricism works is an abstraction in which
2
Feminist psychologists have argued that afuent white boys cognitive specicities are homogenised under one
are nurtured to embody the psychosocial characteristics needed
dominant conception of what counts as knowledge
for detached and objective knowledge seeking, deliberation, and
work. For example, see Keller (1985) and Bordo (1987). It should and of who qualies as a knower. In practice, those
therefore be no surprise that they can come to see themselves as conceptions mirror and replicate the experiences
disembodied rational beings. that their (usually white, male, prosperous, and
ARTICLE IN PRESS
2626 M.J. Goldenberg / Social Science & Medicine 62 (2006) 26212632

educated) creators are positioned to regard as notions of subjects, origins, and cause. Instead
exemplary (Code, 1991). experience reproduces its terms: it does not allow
The inexactness of the term experience seems to us to see that it is not the individuals who have
allow it to resonate in many ways, to function as a experience, but subjects who are constituted through
universally understood category, and to create a experience (1991, p. 777). By taking experience to be
sense of consensus by attributing to it an assumed a given, and ignoring how discourse and history
stable and shared meaning (Scott, 1991, p. 782). structure ones experiences, the status quothe
Through its assumption as a foundational concept same social order that maintains the privilege of the
in empiricist epistemology, experience is protected modest witnessis left unexamined.
from different meanings and relativisms, and there- Because knowers are understood to be collabora-
fore establishes the possibility for objective knowl- tive agents, whose epistemic projects are shaped by,
edge (Scott, 1991, p. 785). This move effectively and evaluated within, the communities where their
removes subjects from critical scrutiny as active knowledge-producing practices occur, standards of
producers of knowledge, and it is this insistence of evidence are by no means self-announcing, but
separation of meaning and experience that is rather historically relative, dynamic, and of our own
crucial. Epistemology constructs truth on the making (Nelson, 1993a). While experience can
foundation of the speakers irrelevance (Scott, 1991, remain central to our evidential claims, it must be
p. 785). understood to be inherently social, for we experi-
That speaker is, of course, the modest witness. It ence the world through the lens of our projects,
has already been discussed how he bears witness in categories, theories, and standards. Therefore, what
his unbiased accounts of the world. His modesty constitutes evidence for specic claims or theories
authorises him to do so. His subjectivity, therefore, includes not only experience, but also the knowl-
is his objectivity. Lorraine Code has argued that edge and standards constructed and adopted by
objectivity is a generalization from the sub- epistemological communities (Nelson, 1993a, p.
jectivity of quite a small group (1993, p. 22). 142). Against the insistence of radical empiricists,
However, this group has the power, security, and feminists contend that science is not a value-free
prestige toygeneralise its experiences and norma- enterprise. Even the notion of empirical adequacy is
tive ideals across the social order thus producing a conditioned by a set of beliefs which cannot be
group of like minded practitioners (we) and disentangled into factual and evaluative cate-
dismissing others as deviant and aberrant (they) gories (Nelson, 1993b). The benet of unmasking
(Code 1993, p. 22). Within the privileged culture of the assumptions, norms, and values at play in
no culture, the witnesss narratives lose all trace scientic inquiry is that we can now address the
of their history as stories, as products of partisan important socio-political question of which values
projects, as contestable representations, or as ought to enter the scientic arena.
constructed documents in their potent capacity to In sum, feminist insights tell us that rather than
dene the facts (Haraway 1996, p. 429). The empirical evidence increasing certainty by factoring
evidence of experience is therefore called into out the subjective features of everydayness that bias
question. our understanding of things, the constructs of
For positivist epistemologies, of which medicine objectivity, universality, and value-free in-
retains its residue, sensory observation and experi- stead obscure the subjective elements that inescap-
ence in ideal conditions is a privileged source of ably enter all forms of human inquiry. Since the
knowledge offering the best promise of certainty. evidence is by no means objective or neutral, but
When experience is taken as the origin of knowl- rather part of a social system of knowledge
edge, the individual subjects perception becomes production, many feminist epistemologists recom-
the bedrock of evidence on which explanation is mend social models of scientic practice. This model
built at the expense of inquiry into subject forma- entails recognising our background assumptions as
tion. Joan Scott argues that reliance on experience playing a constitutive (and not a biasing) role in
precludes critical examination of the workings of knowledge acquisition and evaluation (Longino,
the ideological system itself, its categories of 1990). Scientic inquiry cannot be value-free, as
representation (such as man, woman, homosexual, traditional empiricists required, for cultural and
heterosexual), its premises about what these cate- social values make knowledge possible. These values
gories mean and how they operate, and of its must, of course, be subject to examination and
ARTICLE IN PRESS
M.J. Goldenberg / Social Science & Medicine 62 (2006) 26212632 2627

critique, ideally by those from outside the commu- current medical practice, repeating and reinforcing
nity who do not share those cultural assumptions. existing biases against women, both in research and
Thus the evaluation of scientic beliefs becomes in treatment (Rogers, 2004b, p. 54). The short-
more rigorous: in addition to demonstrating em- comings of biomedicine for properly addressing
pirical adequacy, scientic beliefs must be subject to womens health needs, as articulated by feminist
public scientic inquiry, where the background scholars and allies of the womens health movement
assumptions motivating the investigation are ex- over the past few decades, are not corrected by
plicitly recognized and therefore subject to the same evidence-based medical practice.
critical scrutiny to which good empiricists (Feyer- Because evidence-based clinical decision-making,
abend, 1998) subject their knowledge claims. This policy determinations, and the formulation of
public activity not only raises the standards of clinical guidelines rely upon existing clinical re-
theoretical adequacy, but also better mediates the search, the movement reects any gaps or biases
knowledge/power interplay in scientic investiga- that currently exist in medical research. Womens
tion. Once we recognise that an uninterrogated health research has been marked by a sexist research
conception of empirical adequacy is not sufcient to agenda that over-focuses on womens reproductive-
act as a criterion of theory choice, we can turn to the related issues (fertility, menstruation, menopause,
question of what epistemological virtues we want and breast and gynecological cancers) while failing
our theories to additionally display. A feminist to properly investigate gender dimensions of other
philosophy of science is explicitly political, as health problems that appear to have sex-differen-
science is recognised to be a vehicle for feminisms tiated causes, incidences, responses to treatment,
emancipatory programme. and prognoses due to a combination of biological
factors, social conditions, and social processes
Feminist implications for EBM (Rogers, 2004b). Some examples include HIV/
AIDS, coronary heart disease, depression, and
Against feminist misgivings about so-called ob- tuberculosis.
jectivity, rationality, and value-neutrality, EBM Gender bias also arises in the performance of
proposes to introduce rational order into the research, where women have been grossly under-
deliberative processes of healthcare decision-mak- represented as subjects in clinical trials (Dresser,
ing. The epistemic concerns of feminist scientists 1992; Merton, 1993).3 This exclusion has been
and philosophers are accompanied by a feminist justied on the grounds of the need for homogenous
commitment to improving the lives of women. subject populations, the fear of harms to pregnant
Feminist critiques of science are driven by a deep women and offspring, the alleged difculties ac-
concern that the abstractions made in the names of counting for womens hormonal uctuations in data
scientic objectivity, generalisability, and predict- analysis, and the purported difculties recruiting
ability harm women. These tendencies appear to women (Dresser, 1992). Critics insist, however, that
resurface in the practice of EBM. biological differences between men and women are
EBM offers the promise of consistent and signicant enough that research evidence is often
impartial evidence about the benets and harms of not relevant to women and therefore the use of
treatments due to the transparent use of high- medical technologies on and by female patients is
quality primary research in systematic reviews and dangerous. Despite robust criticism, the bias to-
meta-analyses. These results are then applied in wards male participants in research trials remains.
equally transparent processes to make clinical In the US, 85% of research participants are male;
decisions (Rogers, 2004a). Feminist insight reveals this rises to 95% in Canada (Sherr, 2000).
that the practices of EBM are marked by potential The fact that certain areas of womens health are
or actual gender bias, which has led at least one underresearched, others are overresearched, and
critic to argue that EBM is bad for womens health other areas of health research lack evidence relevant
(Rogers, 2004b). Despite the idealistic suggestion to women suggests that the evidence that serves as
that evidence-based methods can improve womens the basis for EBM may not be helpful for women.
health by making available more high-quality data EBM is implicated for the past mistakes of medicine
regarding the efcacy of different treatments, thus
leading to more informed treatment choices by and 3
This is especially the case for women of colour and elderly
for women, EBM is in fact superimposed upon women.
ARTICLE IN PRESS
2628 M.J. Goldenberg / Social Science & Medicine 62 (2006) 26212632

because it presents much of this evidence as Cartesian dualism, which split the world into minds
authoritative and even arguably reies much of and bodies, the spiritual and the physical, was
the thinking and methods that allowed for these erroneous and created a truncated body of science
egregious gaps in research to occur in the rst place. that exhibited impressive technological ability to
Feminist researchers have found bias against control nature, but could not address questions of
women not only in the production of the research human self-understanding. This led to a crisis of
that informs EBM, but also in the purportedly fair meaning, which Husserl (1970) attributes to the
methods used to analyse and synthesise the evidence failure of positivist natural science.
(Rogers, 2000b). A common critique of EBMs pre- The biomedical model is charged with suffering
graded evidence hierarchies is that they do not from similar problems, as the technological abilities
acknowledge that research methods must be tai- of modern medicine fail to address the existentiality
lored to the question at hand, and that different of illness. Self-proclaimed medical humanists like
questions gather best evidence from different Reiser (1978), Reiser and Rosen (1984), who lament
research designs. Leaving aside the gendering of the lost art of medicine, regard the well-docu-
the quantitative vs. qualitative debates in the social mented increase in patient dissatisfaction (despite
scienceswith the former being regarded as mas- the amazing technological advances) as a similar
culine and the latter as feminine (Oakley, crisis. The rising popularity of alternative medicine
2000)qualitative methods have been favoured by can be understood to be part of that backlash, as
many feminist researchers for allowing the voices of patients increasingly seek out unorthodox practices
women to be heard in describing problems and in despite the impressive technological success of the
nding solutions. The endorsement of an evidence orthodoxy. The biomedical model is grounded in
hierarchy that discounts evidence from qualitative the natural sciences, and medical practice consists of
research has implications for womens health the practical application of these sciences to human
insofar as health interventions that recognise the illness and health (Schwartz & Wiggins, 1985, p.
social and political context contributing to womens 333). However, with the unity, predictive power,
poor health have consistently proven to be more and exactitude of scientic medicine comes the
effective in improving health outcomes. EBM neglect of those components of human distress that
methodology in fact supports a reductionist model elude description in natural scientic nomenclature
of health and disease that is not amenable to the (Schwartz & Wiggins, 1985, p. 332). It is demon-
crucial social and political determinants of womens strated in the illness narratives of Toombs (1993)
health. and Sacks (1984) that these nonsomatic components
of human life that are typically disregarded as
Phenomenology of science and medicine subjective features of illness stubbornly remain
crucial to the experience of illness and to recovery.
Phenomenological approaches to science and By taking seriously questions about the world as
medicine further challenge notions of evidence in experienced rather than scientically described,
EBM by questioning why relevant evidence is phenomenologists seek to reunite science with life
assumed to come primarily from clinical trials and experience and to explore the relationship between
other objective measures. They argue instead that the abstract world of the sciences and the concrete
the patients self-understanding and experience of world of human consciousness. Toombs (1993)
illness4 also offers a legitimate source of relevant argues that as embodied beings, we experience life
medical knowledge. This theoretical approach is in and through the body both before and after we
grounded in the philosophy of Edmund Husserl and develop cognitive and symbolic structures for
his followers who questioned the philosophical mapping experience and meaning. Phenomenolo-
completeness of natural sciences. They argued that gists typically speak of embodiment instead of
the body to deemphasise the physical body and
4
The emphasis on the patients experience of illness in medical the assumed subjectobject split that comes with
phenomenology may seem, at rst, to be at odds with feminist anatomical description. They instead aim to create
epistemology, where the evidence of experience is suspect.
an understanding of our bodies in their experiential
Feminists speak to supposedly universal sensory experience,
which is shared by ideal observers and grounds empiricist givenness.
knowledge claims, however, while phenomenologists focus on From this emphasis on the lifeworld rather
the very subjective experience of illness (or the illness narrative). than the scientic organisation of the world, a
ARTICLE IN PRESS
M.J. Goldenberg / Social Science & Medicine 62 (2006) 26212632 2629

different account of illness ensues. When the body is Phenomenological implications for evidence-based
no longer thought of as an anatomical entity, but medicine
rather as the source of our experiences, illness
becomes a way of being-in-the-world that is best Reecting on how the popular idea of patient-
described as a sense of disorder, a loss of control, of centred care remains largely unrealized in clinical
things not being right in the world. This practice, Van Weel and Knottneurus (1999) note
embodied understanding of illness resists medical that while physicians are encouraged to make
classication as these categories lack its existential diagnoses in physical, psychological, and social
qualities. In fact, illness may not even be localised to terms, the EBM that is currently promoted either
any one place. Scarry (1985) has forcefully described restricts itself to physical evidence alone, or casts
in The Body in Pain: The Making and Unmaking of such evidence at the top of a hierarchy that tends to
the World (1985) that pain obliges a loss of the devalue any evidence lower down. The hierarchy
taken-for-grantedness of our bodies, and illness can of evidence promotes a certain scientistic accounting
be understood as, similarly, the loss of the at- of the goals of medicine, which, the worry goes, is
handedness or everydayness (Heidegger, 1996) incommensurable with the proposed reorientation
of things. Toombs (1993) philosophical reections of medical practice toward the patients search for
on living with MS lead her to conclude that health is meaning in the illness experience. The bridging of
not experienced as the absence of disease, but rather scientistic measure and existential meaning has
as a state of unselfconscious being that illness received some attention in the critical EBM
shatters. Illness is a problem of embodiment, as the literature (see, for example, Buetow, 2002; Djulbe-
usual effortless and unselfconscious unity of the govic, Morris, & Lyman, 2000; Upshur et al., 2001)
body and the self is disrupted, making one pay with the general consensus that we need an
explicit attention to the body as suddenly proble- integrated model of evidence that properly
matic (and separate or alien from the self). reects modern health cares constitution by diverse
Toombs (1993) examines the different ways that academic traditionsincluding the humanities, so-
physicians and patients approach and understand cial sciences, and the pure and applied sciences
illness and encourages physicians to try to under- that rely on equally diverse notions of evidence
stand what illness means to the patient. She advises (Upshur et al., 2001, p. 91).
that rather than trying to understand disease as a While EBM values evidence that is statistical in
breakdown of the objectied body-machine, the nature and general in its application, and therefore
physician must try to approach illness as a places quantitative data derived through the appli-
disturbance in the patients ability to relate to and cation of recognised study designs at the top of its
function in the world, as it is ones embodiment, pre-graded hierarchies of evidence, the phenomen-
ones capability of interacting with the world, that is ological approaches rooted in hermeneutics, ethno-
damaged in the event of illness. graphy, sociology, and anthropology, regard
Such an approach to medical practice would evidence as primarily narrative, subjective, and
entail a radically different understanding of evi- historical in nature. Unlike the impersonal and
dence, and probably lead to a new scientic method. generalisable measures undertaken in EBM, this
Once the patient and not the disease exemplar conception of evidence is illustrated in case
becomes the subject of examination and treatment, histories, clinical encounters, and qualitative studies
the personal anecdotes, life circumstances, and such as in-depth interviews and focus groups
other subjective features of the patients circum- (Upshur et al., 2001, p. 94).
stances become crucial parts of the diagnosis The features of the medical encounter and the
(Greenhalgh & Hurwitz, 1998). Diagnosis would illness experience emphasised by medical phenom-
not be tailored to medical categorisation, as the goal enologists and proponents of a more humane
of treatment would not be centred so much on the medicine suggest the need to reconsider what
elimination of disease, but rather the reintegration constitutes the goals of medicine (Cassell, 1982;
of the patient into the lifeworld.5 Toombs, 1995; 1993) and ip EBMs hierarchy of

5
This is not to say that the elimination of disease would not be (footnote continued)
an important feature of treatment, but it certainly would not be a slightly overused expression, this model emphasises care instead
regarded as more important than, say, rehabilitation. To borrow of cure.
ARTICLE IN PRESS
2630 M.J. Goldenberg / Social Science & Medicine 62 (2006) 26212632

evidence on its head. The quantitative measures and demonstrate the biases implicit in the modern
generalisations that come out of controlled trials scientic worldview and offer ways of conceiving
and biostatistical analysis are not conducive to the evidence differently.
questions of meaning that medical phenomenology While the assertions of EBM may seem common
wants to address and make central to medicine. sense, we must remember that they have been
stripped of the social context of medical practice.
The politics of evidence Just as feminist epistemologists have demonstrated
how this alleged value-neutrality distorts scientic
Because EBM is largely an effort to manage the practice, the same concerns arise in medicine. In an
unruly social world in which medicine is practiced age where the institutional power of medicine is
via objective scientic procedure, the movement suspect (for all the reasons offered by Foucault
appears to be the latest expression of scientism, (1990)), a model that represents biomedicines power
modernitys rationalist dream that science can as disinterested (or merely scientic) should give
produce the knowledge required to emancipate us pause for thought. Denny (1999) reads EBM as a
from scarcity, ignorance, and error. However, such discourse that problematically resists contemporary
efforts tend to disguise political interests in the challenges to established medical authority. While
authority of so-called scientic evidence. The EBM may appear to question the authority of
conguration of policy considerations and clinical individual physicians, it actually reinforces it
standards into questions of evidence conveniently through the regulation of doctors authority/ knowl-
transform normative questions into technical ones. edge. Furthermore, it does not question the institu-
Political issues are not resolved, however, but tional authority of medicine itself to the rest of
merely disguised in technocratic consideration and society, the way healthcare dollars are allocated for
language. Thus the goals of medicine and other the necessary clinical research, and what role the
normative considerations lie just below the surface pharmaceutical industry plays in setting the research
of these evidentiary questions, and evidence be- agenda. It has been argued that the separation of the
comes an instrument of, rather than a substitute for, technical and the political is an instructive mark of
politics (Belkin, 1997; Rodwin, 2001). modernity (Haraway, 1996; Habermas, 1989). This
removal of normative content from the ideological
In conclusion apparatuses has the dangerous effect of depoliticis-
ing the organisation of social life and therefore
The basic tenets of EBM, it seems, rest on the justifying the institutions by rendering them func-
unquestioned authority of scientic evidence, a tional within a system of supposedly technically
position that is now out of step with current post- necessary activity. By framing the problems of
positivistic thinking. Nelson (1993a) has argued that biomedicine as problems of (lack of) evidence
any call for evidence (or a claim to lack it) relies on exclusively, the assumptions, methods, and practices
a specic conception of evidence. The conception of of scientic medicine go unquestioned. While
evidence used in EBM has been demonstrated to be evidenced-based approaches can improve de rigueur
problematic by post-positivists, feminist epistemol- medical practice, evidence-based should not be
ogists and medical phenomenologists. understood to be synonymous with best practice
Relying on the facts or the evidence to in all relevant respects.
adjudicate between competing clinical practices or A lesson learned from the philosophy of science is
scientic beliefs assumes that the evaluative stan- that evidence is not self-apparent or given when
dards of EBM are transparent, neutral, objective, gathered from even the most idealised and con-
and universal. The numerous accounts of scientic trolled observational setting. The critiques launched
knowledge as situated knowledges (Haraway, against positivist philosophy by feminist and
1988) offered by post-positivist, feminist, and phenomenological epistemologies of science contest
phenomenological thinkers suggest that this under- the seemingly unproblematic nature of evidence
standing of evidence is far too simple and no longer that underlies EBM by emphasising different
a tenable position in science studies. Furthermore, features of the social nature of science. The appeal
against the position that modern science stands out to the authority of evidence that characterises
as the only objective method of knowledge-gather- evidence-based practices does not increase objectiv-
ing, feminist epistemologists and phenomenologists ity but rather obscures the subjective elements that
ARTICLE IN PRESS
M.J. Goldenberg / Social Science & Medicine 62 (2006) 26212632 2631

inescapably enter all forms of human inquiry. Fausto-Sterling, A. (1989). Life in the XY corral. Womens
Abstracted from the social context of medicine, Studies International Forum, 12(3), 319331.
EBM seems common sense and the connections Fausto-Sterling, A. (1992). Myths of gender: Biological theories
about women and men. New York: Basic Books.
between power and knowledge are obscured. Feyerabend, P. (1978). Against method. London: Verso.
Feyerabend, P. (1998). How to be a good empiricistA plea for
tolerance in matters epistemological. In M. Curd, & J. A.
Acknowledgements Cover (Eds.), Philosophy of science: The central issues
(pp. 922949). New York: Norton.
An earlier version of this paper was written as Foucault, M. (1990). The history of sexuality: An introduction
part of my comprehensive exams in preparation for (Vol. 1). New York: Vintage Books.
Goldenberg, M. J. (2005). Evidence based ethics? On evidence
my dissertation project. Thanks to my dissertation based practice and the empirical turn from normative
committee: Jim Lindemann Nelson, Judy Andre, bioethics. BMC Medical Ethics, 6, 11.
Marilyn Frye, Fred Gifford, and Lisa Schwartz- Goodman, K. W. (2003). Ethics and evidence-based medicine:
man. Also, to my audience and co-panelists at the Fallibility and responsibility in clinical science. Cambridge:
presentation of a later draft at the 2004 meeting of Cambridge University Press.
Greenhalgh, T., & Hurwitz, B. (Eds.). (1998). Narrative based
the American Society for Bioethics and Humanities. medicine: Dialogue and discourse in clinical practice. London:
Finally, thanks to the editors of this volume for BMJ Publishing Group.
editorial suggestions, particularly on how to speak Grimshaw, J. (2004). So what has the Cochrane Collaboration
across disciplines. ever done for us? A report card on the rst 10 years. Canadian
Medical Association Journal, 171, 747.
Guyatt, G., Cairns, J., Churchill, D., et al. (1992). Evidence-
based medicine. Journal of the American Medical Association,
References 268, 24202425.
Habermas, J. (1989). Technology and science as ideology. In S.
Belkin, G. S. (1997). The technocratic wish: Making sense and Seidman (Ed.), Jurgen Habermas on society and politics: A
nding power in the managed medical marketplace. Journal reader (pp. 237265). Boston: Beacon Press.
of Health Politics, Policy and Law, 22, 509532. Hanson, N. R. (1958). Patterns of discovery. Cambridge: Cam-
Bordo, S. (1987). The flight to objectivity: Essays on cartesianism bridge University Press.
and culture. Albany: SUNY Press. Haraway, D. (1988). Situated knowledges: The science question
Buetow, S. A. (2002). Beyond evidence-based medicine: Bridge- in feminism and the privilege of partial perspective. Feminist
building a medicine of meaning. Journal of Evaluation in Studies, 14(3), 575599.
Clinical Practice, 8, 103108. Haraway, D. (1989). Primate visions: Gender, race, and nature in
Buetow, S. A., & Keneally, T. (2000). Evidence-based medicine: the world of modern science. London: Routledge.
The need for a new denition. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Haraway, D. (1991). Simians, cyborgs, and women: The reinven-
Practice, 6, 8592. tion of nature. New York: Routledge.
Candelise, L., Aritzu, E., Ciccone, A., Ricci, S., & Warlaw, J. Haraway, D. (1996). Modest witness: Feminist diffractions in
(1995). Randomised controlled trial of streptokinase, aspirin, science studies. In P. Galison, & D. Stump (Eds.), The disunity
and combination of both in treatment of acute ischemic of science: Boundaries, contexts, and power (pp. 428442).
stroke. Lancet, 346, 15091514. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Cassell, E. J. (1982). The nature of suffering and the goals of Harding, S. (1986). The science question in feminism. Ithaca, NY:
medicine. New England Journal of Medicine, 306, 639645. Cornell University Press.
Code, L. (1991). What can she know? Feminist theory and the Heidegger, M. (1996). Being and time. Albany, NY: SUNY Press
construction of knowledge. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University (translated by J. Stambaugh).
Press. Horton, R. (1995). MAST-I: Agreeing to disagree. Lancet, 346, 1504.
Code, L. (1993). Taking subjectivity into account. In L. Alcoff, & Hubbard, R., & Lowe, M. (Eds.). (1979). Genes and gender. New
E. Potter (Eds.), Feminist epistemologies (pp. 1548). New York: Gordian Press.
York: Routledge. Hume, D. (1977). In E. Steinberg (Ed.), An enquiry concerning
Davidoff, F., Haynes, B., Sackett, D., & Smith, R. (1995). human understanding. Indianapolis: Hackett.
Evidence-based medicine. British Medical Journal, 310, Hume, D. (2000). In D. F. Norton, & M. J. Norton (Eds.), A
10851086. treatise of human nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Denny, K. (1999). Evidence-based medicine and medical author- Husserl, E. (1970). The crisis of European sciences and
ity. Journal of Medical Humanities, 20(4), 247263. transcendental phenomenology. Evanston, IL: Northwestern
Djulbegovic, B., Morris, L., & Lyman, G. (2000). Evidentiary University Press (translated by D. Carr).
challenges to evidence-based medicine. Journal of Evaluation Husserl, E. (1982). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology
in Clinical Practice, 6(2), 99109. and a phenomenological philosophy: First book: General
Dresser, R. (1992). Wanted: Single, white male for medical introduction to a pure phenomenology.The Hague: Nijoff
research. Hastings Center Report, 22, 2429. (translated by F. Kersten).
Duhem, P. (1982). The aim and structure of physical theory. Keller, E. F. (1985). Reflections on gender and science. New
Princeton: Princeton University Books. Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
ARTICLE IN PRESS
2632 M.J. Goldenberg / Social Science & Medicine 62 (2006) 26212632

Kuhn, T. (1970). Reections on my critics. In I. Lakatos, & Sackett, D., Rosenberg, W., Gray, J. A. M., Haynes, B., &
A. Margraves (Eds.), Criticisms and the growth of knowledge Richardson, W. S. (1996). Evidence-based medicine: What it
(pp. 231278). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. is and what it isnt. British Medical Journal, 312, 7172.
Kuhn, T. (1996) (3rd ed). The structure of scientific revolutions. Sacks, O. (1984). A leg to stand on. New York: Summit Books.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Scarry, E. (1985). The body in pain: The making and unmaking of
Longino, H. (1990). Science as social knowledge: Values and the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Scott, J. (1991). The evidence of experience. Critical Inquiry,
Press. 178(3), 773797.
Merton, V. (1993). The exclusion of pregnant, pregnable, and Schwartz, M., & Wiggins, O. (1985). Science, humanism, and the
once-pregnable people (AKA women) from biomedical nature of medical practice: A phenomenological view.
research. American Journal of Law and Medicine, 19, 369451. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 28(3), 331361.
Nelson, L. H. (1993a). Epistemological communities. In Shahar, E. (1997). A Popperian perspective of the terms
L. Alcoff, & E. Potter (Eds.), Feminist epistemologies evidence-based medicine. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical
(pp. 121160). New York: Routledge. Practice, 3, 109116.
Nelson, L. H. (1993b). A question of evidence. Hypatia, 8(2), Sherr, L. (2000). Women and clinical trials. In L. Sherr, & J. St.
172190. Laurence (Eds.), Women, health, and the mind (pp. 7790).
Oakley, A. (2000). Experiments in knowing: Gender and method in Chichester: Wiley.
the social sciences. Oxford: Polity Press. Tanenbaum, S. J. (1993). What physicians know. New England
Quine, W. V. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Journal of Medicine, 329, 12681271.
Press. Tognoni, G., & Roncaglioni, M. (1995). Dissent: An alternative
Reiser, D., & Rosen, D. (1984). Medicine as a human experience. interpretation of MAST-I. Lancet, 346, 1515.
Baltimore: University Park Press. Toombs, S. K. (1993). The meaning of illness: A phenomenological
Reiser, S. J. (1978). Medicine and the reign of technology. New account of the different perspectives of physician and patient.
York: Cambridge University Press. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Rodwin, M. (2001). The politics of evidence-based medicine. Toombs, S. K. (1995). Chronic illness and the goals of medicine.
Journal of Health Politics, Policy, and Law, 26, 439445. Second Opinion, 21, 1119.
Rogers, W. A. (2004a). Does evidence-based medicine offer fair Upshur, R. E. G., VanDenKerkhof, E. G., & Goel, V. (2001).
benets for all? Ethics Journal of the American Medical Associ- Meaning and measurement: An inclusive model of evidence in
ation, 6(12) www.ama-assn.org/ama/pub/category/14295.html. health care. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 7, 9196.
Rogers, W. A. (2004b). Evidence-based medicine and women: Do Van weel, C., & Knottneurus, J. A. (1999). Evidence-based
the principles and practice of EBM further womens health? interventions and comprehensive treatment. Lancet, 353,
Bioethics, 18(1), 5070. 916918.

Anda mungkin juga menyukai