Anda di halaman 1dari 75

Mar1in .

my

Jonqthtlll trbry

Ro!:alintf Krauss

THE jFl j Pl,l

, Horman Bryson

l TNE GA.E I,,M,

Jac.quellrte Ro~p

~e lf.1A

mOlTED BY
Dia Art Foundation
Discussions in Contemporary Culture
Humber 2

VISION AND VISUALITY

Edited by Hal Foster

BAY PRESS SEATTLE 1988


CONTENTS

1988 Dia Art Fou ndation Hal Foster


All rights reserved. No part of this book ma), be reprod uced in any
form without permission in writing from the publisher and author. PREFA C E

Printed in the United States of America


99 98 97 7 6 5 4 Martin Jay

SCOPIC REGIMES OF MODERNIT Y


Bay Press
[15 West Denny Way
Seattle, Washington 98 [ 19
Jonathan Crary

Design by Bethany Johns MODERNIZING VI SION


Typesetting by Sarabande, New York
Printed by Walsworth Publishing Company, Marceline, Missouri
Set in Perpetua Rosalind Krauss

Library of Congress CotaloginginPublicatlon Data THE 1M / PULSE TO SEE

(Rev ised for \'01. 2)

Discussions in Contemporary Culture.


GENERAL DISCUSS ION
No. 1-2 edited by Hal Foster.
Includes bibliographies.
Contents; no. 1 [without specia l titleJ-no. 2.
Vision and VislIa lity.
Horman Bryson
I. Art and society. 2. Aesthet ics, Modern-20th ce ntury.
I. Foster, Hal. II. Dia Art Foundation. THE GAZE IN THE EXP AN DED F I ELD
N72.56D57 1987 700'. 1'03 87-7 1579
ISBN 0-941920-10-0 (no. 2, pbk.)
Jacqueline Rose

SEXUALITY AND VISION : SOME OUESTIONS

GENERAL D ISCUSS I ON
A NOTE ON THE SERIES

in 1987, the Dia Art Foundation initiated its commitment to


critical discussion and debate through a series of six weekly
discussions on diverse cultural topics organized by Hal Foster.
Edited transcripts of these discussions together with prepared
texts were presented in the first volume of an ongoing series of
publications called Discussions in Contemporary Culture. The
series is intended to record aspects of the organized discussion
events held at Dia from time to time, primarily at its downtown
space at 155 Mercer Street, Ne"v York.
This volume, Number 2 in the Discussions in Contempo-
rary Culture series, includes texts prepared by the participants
in a day. . long symposium held on April 30, 1988, at Dia's
exhibition space at 548 West 22nd Street, together with edited
transcripts of discussions with the audience following the pre-
sentations of the participants. The symposium was generally an
exploration of modes of vision; the presenters explained dif-
ferent ways in which what is seen is revised, through various so-
cia l, psychological, and biological filters, before it is perceived.
Characteristics of different models of seeing are shown to evolve
historically, and recently in reaction to models specifically asso-
ciated with the principles of modernism. Most but not all of
these analyses centered around the production and perception of
visual art. Hal Foster, who organized the symposium and edited
this volume, explains in his preface something of the topicality
of new critical attention to theories of vision.
We are grateful to Hal Foster for his work on this book
and for his conception and organization of the Vision and Visu-
ality symposium, which was attended by a diverse and. as is evi-
dent in the discussion portions of this book, keenly engaged
audience. We also thank the five participants in the symposium
for their excellent presentations that day and for their helpful

v II
Hal Foster

texts. This book also reflects the careful production work o f Phil
Mariani, Bethany Johns, and Ellen Foos, and of Thatcher Bailey
at Bay Press.
We look forward to a series of events in 1988-89 centered PREFACE
around criti cal discuss io n and to additional volumes of this pub-
lication se ries.

Why vision and visuality, why these terms? Although \-ision sug-
Charles Wright gests sight as a physica l operation, and visuality sight as a socia l
Executi\'e Director fact, the two are not opposed as nature to culture: vision is so-
Dia Art Foundation cial and ru storical too, and visuality involves the body and the
psyche. Yet neither are they identical: here, the difference be-
tween the terms signa ls a difference within the visual-between
the mechanism of sight and its hi storica l techniques, between
the datum of vision and its discursive determinations-a dif-
ference, many differences, among how we see, how we are able,
allO\ved, or made to see, and how we see this seeing or the un-
seen therein. With its own rhetoric and represe ntations, each
scopic regime seeks to close out these differences: to make of its
many social visualities one essential vision, or to order them in a
natural hi erarchy of sight. It is importa nt , then , to slip these su-
perimpositions out of focus, to di sturb the gi\'en array of dsual
facts (it may be the only way to see them at all), and trus little
book suggests ways to do this fo r the modern period. Thus the
general project in whi ch it partakes: to thicken modern vision,
to insist on its phYSiological substrate (Jonathan Crary) and on its
psychic imbri cation (whether this is seen in terms of \'icissitude
(Jacqueline Rose] or sub\'ersion [Rosalind Krauss]); to socialize
this vision, to indi cate its part in the production of subjectiVity
(all the authors) and its own production as a part of intersubjec-
tivity (a dialectic of the gaze in which, according to one "para-
noid" model, the subject is menaced by its other [Norman
Bryson]); and, in general, to histori cize modern vision, to spe-
cify its dominant practices and its cr iti cal resistances (Martin Jay

v Iii ix
Hal faster I PREFACE

ex plicitly, the others implicitly). To complicate matters, there vision-from the paradigm of the camera obscura, of a veridical
emerged in the symposium a criticism of this genera l critique, ,-ision of bipo lar subject and object, to the model of the body as
and a call for an alternath'e to the sea rch fo r alternati\'c \' isual producer of a non\'er idical vision relatively indifferent to worldly
regimes. reference. Immediately this history estranges familiar others: one
But ,,-hy this topi c, or these ta kes, now? This is more diffi- is forced to revise or reject, on the one hand , any linear narra-
cult to answer, for "causes" are alwa~-s too little or too much, t ive of techni ca l progressio n (from camera obscura to photogra-
and "preconditions" too thi ck or too thin_ It is, hO\\'e\'er, no se- phy) and , on the other hand , any simple concept of historical
cret that se\'cral strong critiques of modern(ist) models of ,-ision break (as if modernist abstraction had herOically, on its own and
ha\-c de"eloped: e.g_, critiques of the "Cartesia n perspect iyalism" from above, voided perspecthalism). Moreoyer, one is left to
",hkh separates subj ect and object, renders the first transcen- wonder at the sheer perseverance of perspectivalism as an epis-
dental and the seco nd inert, and so subtends metaphysical temologica l model. However, rather than celebrate the phys-
thought, empiri cal science, and cap italist logiC all at once; or cri- iolOgical account-as, say, a precondition of the modernist
tiques of the categorica l separation of art istic expression which, autonomy of the \"isual, or abstractly as a basis for a new free-
compli cit with thi s modern rationalism nen as it is critical of it, dom or a higher truth- Crary refers it to the construction of
pri,-ileges the purely opti cal in dsua l art, to which formal prin- the modern subj ect, the reconfiguration of vision, of the senses,
ciple painting is periodi cally di sciplined. Here, in turn, Martin of the body as objects of science and agents of work. (Inciden-
Jay points to cracks within tradit ional perspecth-e-conAi cts in tal1y, this discussion implies a crucia l theoretical caution for art
practice, paradoxes in logiC (e_g., perspecth'e seen as empirica lly history: not only, on the one hand , not to presuppose an essen-
true and uni versally ,-alid versus perspecti,-e as com-entional and tial ,-iewer but also, on the other hand , not to historicize the
contingent - "a symbolic fo rm ," in the famous phrase of Pan- viewer too stri ctly in terms of cultural forms-as if the viewer
ofsky); he also poses critical ,ariants. e,'en countertraditions: an had no other site of formation, as ir these forms somehow
"ar t of describing" (the term is S,-etiana Alpers's) ,vhi ch emerges existed prior to the subject, as ir they were not also complexly
in se"enteenth-ce ntury Dutch paint ing based on cartographic produced.)
principl es; and a "madness of \-ision" (or folie du FOir) which is In her paper, Rosalind Krauss explores an optica l uncon-
de\-eloped in baroque art that Aaunts the opacity of sublime sub- scious in modernism, here as tapped by Duchamp, Ernst,
jects and underscores the rhetorical com'entionality of Sight. For Giacometti, and others. This intuition about the visual is sensi-
Jay, each practice extends beyond its own histori ca l formation: tive to its invoh-ement with corporea l desire; it thus runs coun-
not only is the first said to operate in certain modernist forms, ter to the relati ve rarefaction (or reifi cati on) of vision, ev ident
but the second is seen now to challenge Cartesian perspectiyal- elsewhere in moderni sm, as a domain "of pure release, of pure
ism for cultural primacy in the postmodern West. transparency, of pure se lf-knowledge." In effect, Krauss con-
Jonathan Crary also rejects any reading of Cartesian per- siders the ramificatio ns, for this countertraditi on, of the phys-
specti,-alism as consistent or continuous. In fact, he locates its iological concept of the visual detailed by Crary, as well as of the
theoretica l di splacement in the early nineteenth century. with psychoanalytical concept of its mises-en-scene discussed by Bryso n
the shift from geometri ca l opti cs to a phYSiological account of and Rose. In parti cular, she argues that there exists a beat, pulse,

x xi
Hal Faster I PREFACE

or rhythm , a "matrix" of the visual which, not restricted to in terms of a brea kdown in psychic life: the social as schizo-
space or time, to high culture or low, serves to confound such phrenic. Rose questions this use of psychoanalysis; specifi ca lly,
catego ries of form, to undo such distinctions o f \'ision dear to she argues, no soone r is its notion of sch izophren ia eyoked than
much art and cultural hi story. In her portrait of Picasso, this its negativities napora te: sex ual difference tends to be elided
dysmorphic aspect of vision is exposed in an oeUHe celebrated (with feminism "disenfranchised") and psychi c life to be distilled
for its formal invention. (with its "a nguish" taken as our "pleasure"). This "innocenting"
With Norman Bryso n, "ision is again regarded as corro- of the sexual and the psychical, Rose maintains, inmkes an in-
si"e-to subjectivity. In its guise as the gaze of the other, vision, nocenting of the Yisua l, as if th ere existed some immediate "i-
according to Sartre and Lacan, decenters the subject; yet in this sion before this schi zoid Sight. Theoretically problematic, the
scheme, Bryso n argues, the centered subj ect remai ns residual- schizo-trope, she concludes, may also be politically dange rous,
in protest, as it were. This threatened remainder leads Sa rtre especia lly in the face of a repressi\'e right which taps the unco n-
and Lacan variously to present the gaze in para noid terms, as an scious for its own fantasms of terror and desire.
event which persecutes, even annihilates the subj ect. In certa in No o ne set of preconditions goyerns this range of argu-
Eastern philosophi es, Bryson maintains, the decentering of the ment; there are, ho\\'ever, di scourses held in commo n. Certai nly
subject is more complete. More importantly, it is welcomed the entire discussion draws on analyses of the subject and the .
rather than resisted; thus the gaze is not regarded as a terror. image derived from poststructuralism and psychoanal ys is; in fact,
This has significa nt conseque nces for the co nstructi on of subjec- vision is inyestigated as a st ructure instrumental to the
tivity and its spaces, fo r the concept ion of art and its techniques, (dis)placement of both these terms. In thi s regard, the feminist
some of which Bryson explores. He does not, howe\'er, pose this attention to the psychic imbri cation of the sexual and the visual
other tradition as an alternati\'e open to our appropriation is especia lly important, as is the semi ologica l sensiti\'ity to the
(which was nonetheless a contested tendency of the discussion), visual as a field of signs produced in difference and ri ven by de-
but rather as a way to denature our habitual practices of the vi- sire. These inSights haye begun to produce, as is evident here, a
sual -to prepare, in short, a politics of sight, For, finall y, it is deconstruction of "pcrceptualist" art history in general and
not that th e gaze is not experienced as menace in our culture, "formalist" art theory in particular. In this respect, the disc lls-
but that this menace is a social product, determined by power, sio n is also allied with a certain "anti-foundati onal" critique,
and not a natural fact. "To think of a terror intrinsic to sight i.e., a critique of the histori ca l concepts posited by a discipli ne
makes it harder to think what makes sight terroristic, or (e.g., art hi story, for instance) as its natural epistemologica l
otherwise. " grounds. The contemporary rage to historicize is also crucia l,
Jacqueli ne Rose also finds a psychic trope operative in dis- for the sine qua non of this discussion is the recognit ion that "i-
cussions of vision, particularly in accounts of postmodern ism sion has a history, that there are different regimes of Yisuality.
that propose as its prime attr ibute a new formation of space. (The co ncern with a "politica l unconscious" of vision and an
These accounts (she menti ons Jameson, Deleuze and Guattari, "arc haeology" of its formations may suggest the co ntested inAu-
Lyotard) present postmodernism in terms of a crisis in social to- ences of Jameson and Foucault.) One hesitates to speculate on
talit),; whether celebrated or lamented, this crisis is often figured more worldly conditions; they will be speC ific to each reader.

xii xiii
Hoi Foster I

However, the virulence in the Western metropolis of sexist, het-


erosexualist, and racist gazes, deepened by a reactive patriarchy
and a divisive political eco nomy, cannot help but inAect the dis-
cussion and inform its reception. The same is true of the visual
technorama which envelops most of us with new technologies of
the image and new techniques of the subject-in-sight ,
One last comment. The critique of perspect ivalism, the
concern with corporeal vision, the analysis of the gaze -these
things are not new. Decades have passed since Panofsky pointed
to the conventionality of perspective, and Heidegger to its com-
VISION AND VISUAL I TY
plicity with a subject wi lled to mastery; years since Merleau-
Ponty stressed the bodiliness of sight, Lacan the psychic cost of
the gaze, and Fanon its colonialist import. Yet Signifi cant dif-
ferences distinguish the present discussionj one is its partial
questi oning of these prior ana lyses. Thus Rose asks what positi ve
terms are set up by such critique (e.g., do we want to seek an
alternative visua l realm in the unconscious if this is to pril'i\ege
psychic disturbance?), and Jay cautions against the celebration of
a postmodern Jolie du voir (e.g., what is lost with the distance
granted by per spective?). Such questioning is not intended to
cor rect modern analyses of vision but precisely to keep them
critical - to nOl turn partial tendencies into whole traditions,
plural differences into a few static oppositions. On thls point,
too, there emerged a critique of the search for alternati\e visu-
aliti es, whether these are to be located in the unconscious or the
body, in the past (e.g., the baroque) or in the non-West (e.g.,
Japan), and it emerged for similar reasons: not to foreclose such
differences, but to open them up, so that alternatives might not
be merely appropriated as the same or strictly distanced as
other-so that diffe rent visualities might be kept in play, and
difference in vision might remain at work.

x lv
Martin Jay

SCOPIC REGIMES OF MODERNITY

The modern era, it is often alleged,l has been dominated by the


sense of Sight in a way that set it apart from its premod ern pre-
decessors and poss ibl y its postmodern successor. Beginning with
the Renaissance and the scientifi c revolution, modernity has
been normally considered resolutely ocuJarcentri c, The im'enti on
of printing, according to th e familiar argwnent of McLuhan and
Ong,l reinforced the pri\'ileging of the \'isual abetted by such in -
ventions as the telescope and the microscope. "The perceptual
field thus constituted," co ncludes a typical account, " was funda-
mentally no nreAexive, visual and quantitati\e,"3
Although the implied characterization of different eras in
this generalization as mo re fa\'orably inclined to other se nses
should not be taken at face \a]ue,4 it is difficult to deny that the
visual has been dominant in modern Western culture in a wide
variety of \\'ays. Whethcr we focus o n "the mirror of nat ure"
metaphor in philosophy with Ri chard Rorty or emphasize the
prevalence of sun'eillan ce with Mi chel Foucault or bemoan the
society of the spectacle with Guy Debord,5 we confront again
and again the ubiquity of vis ion as the master sense of the mod-
ern era,
But what preCisely constitutes the \isual culture of thi s era
is not so readily apparent. Indeed , we might well ask, borrowing
Christian Metz's term , is thcre one unified "scopic regi me"6 of
the modern or are there se\'cral , perhaps competing o nes? For,
as Jacqueline Rose has recently reminded us, "our predous his-
Gion.nni Battista Tiepolo. Th lVarld Pap Homt1fJ 10 Sp<lin. 1762-64. Washington, D.C., tory is not the petrified block of a Single \'isual space si nce,
Na tional Gallery of Art, Samuel H. Kress Collection. (Courtesy Na tional Gallery of Art) looked at obliquely, it can always be seen to conta in its moment
Martin Jay I SCO P I C REG I MES OF" MODERNIT Y

of unease."? In fact, may there possibly be several such mo- peoples of Eu rope. "M The second is from Richard Rorty's \\"ide ly
ments, which can be discerned, if often in repressed form, in the discussed Philosop~r and che Mirror oj Noture. puhlished in 1979:
modern era? If so, the scopic regime of modernity may best be " in the Cartesian model the intellect inspects entities modeled on
understood as a contested terrain, rather than a harmoniously retinal images" " " . In Descartes' conception-the one that be-
integrated complex of visual theories and practices. It may, in came the basis for 'modern' epistemo log~- it is represencotions
fact, be characterized by a differentiation of visual subcultures, wh ich are in the 'mind_'''~ The assumpt ion expressed in these
whose separation has allowed us to understand the multiple im- citations that Ca rtesian perspecti,"alism is the reigning ,"isua l
pli cations of sight in ways that are now only beginn ing to be ap- model of modernity is often ti ed to the further contention that
preciated. That new understanding, I want to suggest, may well it succeeded in becoming so because it best ex pressed the "natu-
be the product of a radica l reversa l in the hierarchy of visual ral" expe rience of Sight ,alori zed by the scient ifi c ,,orld d ew"
subcultures in the modern scopi c regime. When the assumed equh"alence bet\\"ee n scientific obse n "ation
Before spelling out the competing ocular fi elds in the mod- and the natura l world was disputed, so too ,\as the dominati on
ern era as I understand them, I want to make clear that I am of this ,-isual subculture, a salient insta nce being Erwin Pan-
presenting only very crude ideal typical characterizations, which ofsky's celebrated critique of pcrspecti,c as merely a CQ men-
can easily be faulted for their obvious d istance from the complex tiona 1 symboliC form" [0
rea liti es they seek to approximate" I am also not suggesting that But for a ,"c ry long time Cartesian perspecti,alism was
the three main visual subcultures I si ngle out for spec ial atten- identifi ed with the modern scopi c regime roue court. With full
tion exhaust all those that might be discerned in the lengthy and awareness of the schematic nature of what folio\\"s, let me try to
loosely defined epoch we call modernity" But, as will soon be- establish its most important characterist ics. There is, of course,
come apparent, it will be challenging enough to try to do justice an immense literature on the discovery, rediscQ\e ry, or imentio n
in the limited space I have to those I do want to highlight as of perspecti ve -all three terms are used depending on the
most significant" writer's interpretation of ancient ,isual knowledge-in the ital-
Let me begin by turning to what is normally claimed to be ian Quattroce nto. Brunelleschi is traditionallv accorded the
the dominant, even totally hegemoni c, visua l model of the mod - honor of being its practical im"entor or discowrer, wh ile Alberti
ern era , that which we can identi fy with Renaissance notions of is almost unhe rsally acknowledged as it'i first theoreti ca l inter-
perspective in the visual arts and Cartesian ideas of subjective preter. From I\-ins, Panofsky, and Krautheimer to Edgerto n,
rationality in philosophy. For conve ni ence, it can be called Car- White, and Kubon,, II scholars ha,"e im"estigated ,"ir tua ll\", c'"er\",
tesian perspectivalism" That it is often assumed to be equivalent aspect of the perspecti,alist re,olution, technical, aestheti c, psy-
to the modern scopic regime per se is illustrated by two remarks chologi ca l, religiOUS, e'en economic and polit ical.
from prominent commentators" The first is the claim made by Despite many still disputed issues, a rough consensus see ms
the art historian William Ivins, Jr., in his An and Geometry of to have emerged around the fo llOWing points. GrOWing out of
1946 that "the history of art during the five hundred years that the late medic,"a l fascination with the metaphysica l impli cations
have elapsed since Alberti wrote has bee n little more than the of light - light as di,ine lux rather than pe rceh-ed lumen- linea r
story of the slow diffusion of his ideas through the artists and perspecth"e came to symbolize a harmony bet\\"een the mathe-


School of PitTO della Francesca. View rf In /dUll Cil)'. 1470(?). Urbino, Palano D\lcale.
(Co\ln es)' Art Reso\lrce, N.Y.)

matica l regularities in opticS and God's will. Even after the re- famous metaphor, could also be understood as a Rat mirror re-
ligious underpinnings of this equation were eroded , ~he favorable Aecting the geometri calized space of the scene depicted back
connotations surrounding the allegedly objecti ve optical order onto the no less geometricalized space rad iating out from t he
remained powerfully in place. These positive associations had viewing eye.
been displaced from the objects, often religious in content , de- Significa ntly, that eye was singular, rather than the two
picted in earlier painting to the spatial relations of the perspec- eyes of normal binocular vision. It was conceived in the manner
tival canvas themselves. T his new concept of space was geo- of a lone eye looking through a peephole at the scene in front of
metrically isotropic, rectilinear, abstract, and uniform. The velo it. Such an eye was, moreover, understood to be static, unblink-
or veil of threads Alberti used to depict it conventionalized that ing, and fixated, rather than dynami C, moving with what later
space in a way that anticipated the grids so characteristic of scientists would call " saccadic" jumps from one foca l point to
twent ieth-ce ntury art , although, as Rosalind Krauss has re- another. In Norman Bryson's terms, it followed the logic of the
minded us, Alberti's veil was assumed to correspond to external Gaze rather than the Glance, thus producing a visual take that
reality in a way that its modernist successor did not . i2 . was eternalized, reduced to one "point of view," and disem-
The three-dimensional, rationalized space of perspectival bodied. In what Bryson ca lls the "Founding Perception" of the
visi on could be rendered on a two-dimensional surface by fol- Cartesian perspectivalist tradition ,
lowing all of the transformational rules spelled out in Alberti's
De Pirwra and later treatises by Viator, DUrer, and others. The
the aaze '!! the painter arrests the flux if phenomena, comemplares the
visual field from a vamage-poine outside the mobility if duration, in
basic device was the idea of symmetrical visual pyram ids or
cones with one of their apexes the reced ing vanishing or centri c
an eternal momem if disclosed presence; while in the momem if view-
ina, the viewina subjea unites his aaze with the Founding Perception,
poi nt in the painting, the other the eye of the painter .or the b~~
holder. T he transparent window that was the canvas, m Alberti s
in a momene if perfect recreation if that fi rst epiphao/. 13


SCOPIC REGIMES OF MODERNITY
Norlin Joy \

A number of implications follO\ved from the adoption of this vi- from any substantive content, which is part of the cliched his-
sual order. The abstract coldness of the perspectival gaze meant tory of twentieth-century modernism, was already prepared by
the withdrawal of the painter's emotional entanglement with the the perspecti"al revolution fi ve centuri es earl ier. What Bryson in
obj ects depicted in geometricalized space. The pa~ti~i~atory .in- his book Word and Image call s the diminution of the discursive
"olvement of more absorpti"e visual modes "vas dlmlOlshed, If function of painting, its telling a story to the unlettered masses,
not entirelv suppressed, as the gap between spectator and spec- in fayor of its figura l fun ction,16 meant the increaSi ng autonomy
tacle wide~ed. The moment of erotic proj ecti on in vision -what of the image from any ex trinsic purpose, religious or otherwise.
" I d . "14
St. August ine had anxiously condemned as ocu ar eSlre - The effect of realism was conse<juently enhanced as ca nvases
. I
"as ost a.~" the bodies of the pa inter and viewer were forgottenh were filled with more and more information that seemed unre-
in the name of an allegedly disincarnated, absolute eye. Althoug lated to any narrati ve or textual fun ction. Cartesian perspectival-
such a gaze could, of course, sti ll fall on obj ects of desire- . ism was thus in league with a scientific world view that no
think , for example, of the female nude in DUrer's famous pnnt longe r hermeneutically read the world as a divine text, but
of a draftsman drawing her through a screen of perspectival rather saw it as situated in a mathematica lly regular spatio-tem-
threads IS _ it did so largely in the service of a reifying male look poral order filled 'w ith natural objects that could only be ob-
that turned its targets into stone. The marmoreal nude drained se rved from without by the dispassionate eye of the neutral
of its ca pacity to arouse desire was at least tendentially the out- researcher.
come of this development. Despite important exceptions, such as It was also compli citous, so many commentators have
Carayaggio's seductive boys or Titian's Venus cif Urbina, the ~udes claimed, with the fundamentally bourgeOiS ethi c of the modern
themsekes fail to look out at the "iewer, radiating no erotiC en- world. According to Edgerton, Florentine businessmen with
ergy in the other direction. Only much later in .the histo,r y o,f their newly im'ented technique of doubl e-entry bookkeeping may
Western art, with the brazenly shocking nudes m Ma n~t s D~ have been "more and more disposed to a visual order that would
jeuner sur l'herbe and Otl'mpia, did the crossing of the vIewer s accord wi th the tidy principles of mathematica l order that they
gaze with that of the subject finally occur. By then the ra- applied to their bank ledgers."17 John Berge r goes so far as to
tionalized "isual order of Cartesian perspectival ism was already claim that more appropriate than the Albertian metaphor of t he
coming under attack in other ways as well. . window on the world is that of "a safe let into a wall, a sa fe in
In addition to its de-eroti cizing of the visual order, It had which the visible has been deposited."IB It was, he contends, no
also fostered what might be called de-narratiyization or de-tex- accident that the invention (or rediscovery) of perspect i\'e ,'ir-
tualization. That is, as abstract, quantitatively conceptualized tuaUy coincided with the emergence of the Qil painting detached
space became more interesting to the artist than th~ qualitatively from its conte .. t and available for buying and selling. Separate
differentiated subjects painted within it, the rendermg of the from the painter and the viewer, the visual field dep icted on the
sce ne became an end in itself. Alberti, to be sure, had empha- other side of the canvas could become a portable commodity
sized the use of perspective to depict isroria, ennobling stories, able to enter the circulation of capitalist exchange. At the same
but in time they seemed less important than the visual skill time, if philosophers like Martin Heidegger are correct, the nat-
shown in depicting them . Thus the abstraction of artistic form ural world was transformed through the techno lOgical ,vorld


Martin Jay I SCOP I C REGIMES OF" MOOERNIT Y

view into a "standing reserve" for the sUT\'eillance and manip- denunciations of their failings are often directed at a straw man
ulation of a dominating subject, 19 (or at least his straw eye),
Cartesian perspectival ism has, in fact, been the target of a Equa lly problematic is the subject pOsition in the Cartesian
widespread phjlosophical critique, which has denounced its pri\'- perspecth'a list epistemol ogy, For the mo nocular eye at the apex
ileging of an ahistorical, disinterested, disembodi ed subj ect en- of beholder's py ramid could be co nstrued as transce ndental and
tirely outside of the world it claims to know only from afar, The uniye rsal - that is, exactly the same for any human viewer oc-
questio nable assumptio n of a transcendental subjectivity charac- cupying the same point in time and space-or contingent -
teristic of universalist humanism, which ignores our embedded- solely dependent on the particular, individual visio n of distinct
ness in what Maurice Merleau-Ponty liked to call the Aesh of the beholders, with their own concrete relatio ns to the scene in .
world , is thus tied to the "high altitude" thinking characteristic front of them , When the fo rmer was e.x plicitly tra nsformed into
of this scopic regime, In many accounts, this entire tradition has the lat ter, the relati vist ic impl icat ions of perspect ival ism could
thus been subjected to wholesale condemnation as both false and be eaSily drawn, Even in the nineteenth century, th is potential
pernicious, was apparent to thi nkers like Lei bniz, alth ough he generally
Looked at more closely, however, it is possible to discern sought to escape its more troubling implications. These were not
internal tensions in Ca rtesian perspectiyalism itself that suggest expliCitly stressed and than praised until the late nineteenth cen-
it was not quite as uniformly coercive as is sometimes assumed, tury by such thinkers as Nietzsc he, If (' ,'eryone had his or her
Thus, for example, John White distinguishes between what he own came ra obscura with a distinctly different peephole, he
terms "artificial perspective," in which the mirror held up to gleefully concluded, then no transcendental world ,'iew was
nature is Rat, and "syntheti c perspecti\'c," in which that mirror poss ibl e,11
is presumed to be concave, thus producing a curved rather than Finally, the Cartesia n perspecti,'alist traditio n conta ined a
planar space on the canvas, Here, according to White, Paolo potential for internal contestation in the possible uncoupling of
Uccello and Leonardo da Vinci were the major innovators, offer- the painter's \'i ew of the scene from that of the presumed be-
ing a "spherical space which is homogeneous, but by no means holder, Interestingl), Bryso n ident ifies this dc,'elopment with
simple, and which possesses some of the qualities of Einstein's Ve rmeer, who represents for. . . him a seco nd state of pcrspect iyal-
fini te infinity,"lO Although artificial perspective was the domi- ism even more di sinca rnatcd th;-il that of Alberti, "The bond
nant model, its competitor \vas never entirely forgotten, with the ,'icwe r's physique is broken and thc \'ie\\'ing subject,"
Michael Kubovy has recently added the observation that he writes, " is now proposed and assumed as a notional pOint, a
what he ca lls the "robustness of perspective"l l meant that Ren- non-empiri ca l Gaze, "13
aissance canvases could be success full y dewed from more than What makes this last obse n 'ation so sugg:es ti\'e is the open-
the imagined apex of the beholder's \' isual pyramid, He criticizes ing it proddes for a co nsideration of an alternati\'e scopic regime
those .." ho najvely identify the rules of perspect ive established by that may be understood as more than a slilwariant of Cartesian
its theoretical champions with the actual practice of the artists perspecth'a lism, Although I cannot prete nd to be a serious stu-
themse h'es, Rather than a procrustean bed, they were practically de nt of Vermeer ab le to guarrel w ith)~r'yson's interpretati on of
subordinated to the exigencies of perception, whi ch means that his wo rk, it might be lIseful to si t uate the painter in a differe nt

10
II
Martin jay ! SCOPIC FlE:GIME:S OF MO DE:RNITY

context from the one we have been discussing. That is, we might menc in a leaible space; an wiframed imaae versus one chac is clear!J

include him and the Dutch seventeenth-century art of which he framed; one wich no clear!! siwated I'iewer compared to one with such

was so great an exemplar in a dsual culture very different from a viewer. The disrincLion fo11oll's a hierarchical model if distinauishina
that we associate with Renaissance perspective, one which between phenomena commonl), r:Jerred to as primary and secondary:

S"etlana Alpers has recently called The Art if Describina. 24 objeccs and space versus the surfaces, forms I'USUS the (extures if the
According to Alpers, the hegemonic role of Italian painting world. 26

in art history has occluded an appreciation of a second tradition, If there is a philosophical correlate to Norther n art, it is
which flourished in the seventeenth-century Low Countries. not Cartesianism with its faith in a geomet rica lized, rationalized , !

'"
Borrowing Georg Lukacs's distinction between narration and de- essentially intellectual concept of space but rather the more em-
scription, which he used to contrast realist and natur.alis~ ficti~n, pirical "isual expe ri ence of observationally oriented Baconian
~e argues that Italian Renaissance art, for all its fascmatlo~ wIth empiricism. In the Dutch context Alpers identifi es it wi th Con-
the techniques of perspective, still held fast to the storytellmg stantin Huygens. The nonmathematical impulse of this traditi on
function for which they were used. In the Renaissance, the accords well with the indifference to hierarchy, proportion, and
world on the other side of Alberti's window, she writes, "was a analogical resemblances characteristic of Cartesian perspectival-
stage in which human figures performed significant actions ism. Instead, it casts its attentiye eye on the fragmentary, de-
. ms N th
based on the tex ts of the poets. It is a narratIve art. - or ern tailed, and richly articulated surface of a world it is content to
art, in contrast, suppresses narrative and textual reference in describe rather than explai n. Like the mi croscopist of the seven-
fa"or of description and visual surface. Rejecting the privileged, teenth century- Leeuwenhoeck is her prime example-Dutch
constituti" e role of the monocular subject, it emphasizes instead art savors the d iscrete particularity of yisual experience and re-
the prior existence of a world of obj ects depicted on the Rat ~an sists the temptation to allegorize or typologize what it sees, a
vas a world indifferent to the beholder's position in front of It. temptation to which she claims Southern art readily succumbs.
Th~s world , moreover, is not contained entirely within the frame In two Signi fica nt \vays, the art of describing can be said to
of the Albertian w indow, but seems instead to extend beyond it. haye anti cipated later visual models, however much it was subor-
Frames do exist around Dutch pictures, but they are arbitrary dinated to its Cartesian perspectivalist riyal. As we ha"e already
and without the totalizing function they serve in Southern art . noted, a direct fi liation between Alberti 's velo and the grids of
If there is a model for Dutch art, it is the map ''lith its un- modernist art is problematic because, as Rosalind Krauss has ar-
apologetically flat surface and its willingness to include words as gued, the former assumed a three-dimensional world out there
well as objects in its visual space. Summarizing the difference in nature, whereas the latter did not. A more likely predecessor
between the art of describing and Cartesian perspectival ism, can thus be located in the Dutch art based on the mapping im-
Alpers posits the following oppositions: pulse. As Alpers notes,

aHenrion to many small thinas versus a Jew larae ones; baht rllecred Althouah the arid thor Ptolem), proposed, and those thal Mercator larer
cfJ objecrs ~'ersus objecrs modeled by baht and shadow; the surface if imposed, share the mathematical uniformity if the Renaissance perspec-
objects, their colors and textures, deah with rather chan cheir place- tive arid, they do not shore the positioned viewer, the frame, and the

13
12
SCOP I C REG I MES OF' MODERNIT Y

defini tion cif the picwre as a lVindo lV throu8 h which an enema/I'jewel


looks. On rhese accounts the Prolemaic arid, indeed carto8raphic arids
in aeneral, mUSt be distinguished from, nor corifused with, the perspec-
rh'o f arid. Th e projecrion is, one miBhl say. viewed f rom nowhere. Nor
is it (0 be looked rhrouah . It assumes a fiOt wotkins su:Jace. 27

Secondly\ the art of describing also anticipates the visual experi-


ence produced by the ninetee nth-century im"ention of photogra-
phy. Both share a number of salient features: "fragmentariness,
arbitrary fram es, the immediacy that th e first practitioners ex-
pressed by claiming that the photograph gave Nature the power
to reproduce herself directly unaided by man." 28 The parallel
frequently drawn between photography and the anti-perspec-
tivali sm of impressionist art, made for example by Aaron Scharf
in his discllss ion of Degas,29 should thus be extended to include
the Dutch art of the se\'enteenth century. And if Peter Galassi is
correct in Brjore Photography, there was also a tradition of
topographical painting- landscape sketches of a fragment of
reality-that resisted Cartesian perspectival ism and thus pre-
pared the way both for photography and the impressionist re-
turn to two-dimensi onal canvases.30 How wides pread or se lf-
consciously oppositional such a traditi on was I will leave to
experts in art history to dec ide. What is important for our pur-
poses is simply to register the existence of an alternative scopic
regime even during the heyday of the dominant tradition.
Alpers's attempt to characterize it is, of course, open to
possible criticisms. The strong opposit ion between narrati on and
description she posits may seem less firm if we recall the de-nar-
rati vizing impulse in perspectival art itself mentioned above. And
if we can detect a certain fit between the exchange principl e of
cap ita lism and the abstract relational space of perspecti\"c, we
might also disce rn a comp lementary fit between the valorization
" I G II of Art (Courtc$)" of of material surfaces in Dutch art and the fetishism of com-
GerTh Dou. A pouJltre,5 Shop. c. 16 17. London, NaUona a cry .
the Trust ee~, T he National G31lery. Lo ndon) modities no less characteri sti c of a market economy. In this

15
Marlin Jay 1 SCOPIC REGIMES OF' MODERNITY

sense, both scopic regimes can be sa id to re\'cal different aspects sional space seen with a God's-eye-\"iew from afar. She also
of a complcx but unified phenomenon . just as Cartesian and taCitly contrasts the Dutch art of describing, with its belief in
Baconian philosophies can be said to be consonant, if in dif- legi ble surfaces and faith in the material solidity of the world its
ferent \\'ays, with the sc ientifi c world de\\". paintings map. with the baroq ue faSCination for opacity, unread-
If, however, we turn to a third model of d sion, or what ability, and the indeCipherability of the rea lity it depicts.
can be ca lled the second moment of unease in the dominant . For BUci-Glucksmann , the ba roque self-conSC iously revels
model, the possibilities for an e,'en more radical alternati\'c can III the contradicti ons between surface and depth, disparaging as
be discerned. This third model is perhaps best identified with .a result any at tempt to reduce the multipli ci ty of visual spaces
the baroque. At least as earl ~- as 1888 and Heinrich Woffiin's mto anyone coherent essence. Sign ifi cantly, the mirror that it
epochal study, Renaissance and Baroque, art historians have bee n holds up to nature is not the Rat reAecting glass that Commenta-
tempted to postulate a perennial oscillation between two styles tors li ke Edgerton and White see as "ital in the development of
in both painting and architecture. 31 In oppositi on to the lucid, rationali zed or "analyti c" perspective, but rather the anam or-
linear, so lid, fixed , planimetric, closed fo rm of the Renaissance, phosistic mirror, either Concave or com'ex, that distorts the vis ual
or as W olffiin late r ca lled it, the classica l style, the baroque was image-or, more preCisely, rnea ls the com'en tio nal rather than
painterly, recessional, soft-focused, multiple, and open. Deri\'ed, natural quality of "normal" specu larity by shOWing its depend -
at least according to one standard etymology, from the Por- ence on th e materi ality of the medium of reAection. In fact, be-
tuguese word for an irregular, oddly shaped pea rl , the baroque cause of its greater awa reness of that materiality-what a rece nt
connoted the bi za rre and peculiar, traits whi ch were normally commentator, Rodolphe Gasche, has drawn attention to as the
di sdained by champions of clarity and transparency of form. "t ' f h . "34 b
al~ 0 t e mirror - aroq ue \'isual experi ence has a strongly
Although it may be prudent to confine the baroque largely tactile or haptic quality, which prevents it from turning into the >
to the seventee nth century and link it with the Catholic Counter absolute ocularcentrism of its Ca rtesia n perspccti" alist rival.
Reformation or the manipulati on of popular culture by the In philosophi cal terms , although no one system ca n be seen
newly ascendant absolutist state-as has, for e.xampic, the Span- as its co rrelate, Leibniz's pluralism of monadic ,iewpoints.35 Pas-
ish historian Jose Antonio Mara\"all 12 - it may also be possible to c~l '~ medi~at.i ons on paradox, and the Counter Reformat ion mys-
see it as a permanent, if often repressed, \'isual poss ibility tiCS su bmlsslon to "crtiginous expe riences of rapture might all
throughout the entire modern era. In the rece nt work of the be seen as related to baroque vision. MoreO\'cr, the philosophy it
French philosopher Christine Buci-G lucksmann, La raison baroque favored se lf-conScio usly eschewed the model of intellectua l clar-
of 1984 and La folie du \"Oir of 1986,1.3 it is prec isely the explos i\'e ~ty ex pressed in a literal language puri fied of ambiguity. Instead,
power of baroque \'isio n' that is seen as the most Significant al- It recognized the inextricabil ity of rhetoric and visio n, which
ternati\'e to the hegemonic \'isual style we ha\-e called Cartes ian meant that images were signs and that concepts always contained
perspectivalism. Celebrating the dazzling, disor ienting, ecstatic an irredUCibly imagisti c component.
surplus of images in baroque visual exper ience, she emphasizes Baroque vision, Buci-Glucksma nn al so suggests, sought to
its reject ion of the monocular geometricali zation of the Carte- represe nt the un represe ntable and, necessarily f..liling, produced
sian traditio n, with its illusion of homogeneous three-dimen- the melancho ly that Walter Benjamin in particular saw as

16
11
Martin Jay I SCOPIC REGIMES OF" MODERNITY

characteristic of the baroque se nsibility. As such, it was closer to prefer, counter-art form). There are as well contemporary artists
what a long tradition of aesthetics called the sublime, in co ntrast like the German Jewish, now Israeli painter Joshua Neustein,
to the beautiful, because of its yearning for a presence that can whose fascination with the flat materiality of maps has recently
never be fulfilled. Indeed, desire, in its erotic as well as meta- earned a comparison with Alpers's seventeenth-century
physi cal forms, courses through the baroque scopic regime. The Dutchmen. 36
body returns to dethrone the disinterested gaze of the disincar- Still, if one had to Si ngle out the scopic regime that has fi-
nated Cartesian spectator. But unlike the return of the body nally come into its own in our time, it would be the "madness of
celebrated in such twentieth-century philosophies of vision as vision" Bud-Glucksmann identifi es with the baroque_ Even pho-
Merleau-Ponty's, with its dream of mea ning-laden imbrication of tography, if Rosa lind Krauss's recent work on the Surrealists is
the viewer and the viewed in the flesh of the 'Norld, here it gen- any indication,37 ca n lend itself to purposes more in line with
erates only allegories of obscurity and opacity_Thus it truly pro- this visual impulse than the art of mere describing. In the
duces one of those "moments of unease" whi ch Jacqueline Rose postmodern discourse that elevates the sublime to a position of
sees challenging the petrification of the dominant d sual order superiority over the beautiful, it is surely the "palimpsests of the
(the art of describing seeming in fact far more at ease in the unseeable,"38 as Buci-Glucksmann calls baroque vision, that seem
world). most compelling. And if we add the current imperati\-e to re-
A great deal more might be said about these three ideal store rhetoric to its rightful place and accept the irreducible lin-
typical visual cultures, but let me conclude by offering a few guistic moment in vision and the equally insistent visual moment
speculations, if I can use so visual a term, on their current sta- in language, the timeliness of the baroque alternative once again
tus. First, it seems undeniable that we have . .vitnessed in the seems obvious.
twentieth ce ntury a remarkable challenge to the hierarchical In fact, if I may conclude on a somewhat pen 'erse note, the
order of the three regim es. Although it would be foolish to claim radi ca l dethroning of Cartesian perspectival ism may ha\-e gone a
that Cartesian perspectivalism has been dri ven from the field, bit too far. In our haste to denaturalize it and debunk its claims
the extent to whi ch it has been denaturalized and Vigorously to represent vision per se, we may be tempted to forget that the
contested, in philosophy as well as in the visual arts, is truly re- other scopic regimes I have qUic kly sketched are themseh-es no
markable. The rise of hermeneutics, the return of pragmatism, more natural or closer to a "true" vision. GlanCi ng is not some-
the profusion of linguistically oriented structuralist and how innately superior to gazing. vision hostage to desire is not
poststructuralist modes of thought have all put the epistemolOgi- necessarily always better than casting a cold eyei a Sight from
cal tradition derived largely from Descartes ve ry much on the the situated context of a body in the world may not always see
defensive. And, of course, the alternative of Baconian observa- things that are d sible to a " high-altitude" or "God's-cye-\-iew."
tion, which periodically resurfaces in variants of positivistic However we may regret the excesses of scientism, the Western
thought, has been no less vulnerable to attack, although one scientific tradition may ha,-e only been made poss ibl e by Carte-
might argue that the \'isual practice with which it had an elec- sian perspecti\'alism or its complement, the Baco nian art of de-
tive affinity has shown remarkable resilience with the growing scribing_There may weII ha\-e been some link between the
status of photography as a nonperspectival art form (or, if you absence of such scopic regimes in Eastern cultures, especially the

18 19
SCOPIC REGIMES OF M OOER N ITY

Marlin Jay \

Notes
former, and their general lack of indigenous scientifiC revolu-
tions. In our scramble to scrap the rationalization of sight as a I. Sec, for example, Lucicn Febne
Tire Rtligion or R bel .
TM
, e m f! Unbch~f in rhe Si.Hunrh (cnfUfI':
Prob! { .
'2 0 01$, trans. Aeatrice Gottlieb (Ca b 'd M
pernicious reification of visual Huidity. we need to ask what the "crsit)' Press 1982) d R be m n ge. ass.: HanOlrd Un i-
J 500-1640' ~n . ~ n . 0 . rl Mandrou, JmrOOIl(fion 10 Il rooern Fto",e.
costs of too uncritical an embrace of its alternatives may be. In . &so) In HIS/Of/col PSJ<:hoIOS)" trans R E H II k(
Holmes & Meier, 1975). . . . . a mar New York:
the case of the art of describing. \ve might see another rei fica-
tion at work. that which makes a fetish of the material surface ~ ~arsh~ \~c Luhan, Und~mondiflg Mooio : The Enensions of .IIan (New York
e raw- I ,1964); Walter J. Ong, The Pwencc aflhe Hhrd' .
instead of the three-dimensional depths. Lukacs's critique of nat- [il/IUTO/ and Rdig/oUJ HisloTr (New Haren' Yale U '. _ . P ' 501J1(' PtolegomcnaIot
uralist description in literature, unmentioned by Alpers, might Elizabeth L. Eisemtcin Th p ' I p' O!H'rslty reliS, 1967); Set' al.~
, e fin! ng tess os an A8en! of (hon e' [am
II~"
' .
be applied to painting as well. In the case of baroque vision, we [IIII IITa/ Trans'ormOllons In E I .
V'
E . '8'
or I I (}(lcrn uropt 2 \"DIs (C b'd
mumCOllom and
University Press, 1979). ... , . am n gc: Camnridgc
might wonder about the celebration of ocular madness, which
may produce ecstasy in some, but bewilderment and confusion 3. Donald
"' P M 'c HiSIOty ~f Bollt8eais Percepcion (Chicago: Unin-rsitv
19'8Lo)\', or"",'
... go ress, 2 , p. 26. '. ....-
in others. As historians like Maravall have darkly warned, the
4. For an account of the POSltll'C.. attitude to\\OIrds vision in th~' mcdil'val
phantasmagoria of baroque spectacle was easily used to manipu- h h see Margaret R M' I J
[~/ru;ee;~0::~:a~::!~r:p~:=II~~~;sl~,ndin9 Illw~rn
cure,
late those who were subjected to it. The current vision of "the [litiSliofli!)' ond 5cculor in.
gument of FcblTe and Mand rou , which h" .. L~cen ,-err
' . ' ontrar~
mAuen, ',1 h toI t 1(' ar- I
culture industry," to use the term Mara,'all borrows from extent to which si ht \\ b . . - I ,S C S l OW5 t 1('
, g OIS) no mcans WIdely dC/Jl('ancd in the Middl , >\
Horkheimer and Adorno in his account of the seventeenth cen-
5. Richard Rorty, Philosoph)' OM lhe Jilirrot of ,vOlUTe Prin .' t:. gcs ..
tury, does not seem very threatened by postmodernist visual ex- "ersity Press 1979)' M' h I F l ' (ccton. Pnnceton Un!-
1979n)~ ~
, IC e oucau t, Discipline ond Pu sh Th B' h {
periments in ul a foli e du voir." In fact, the opposite may well be trans. Alan Sheridan (New Yo rk: Vintage Books . e '" ? the Prison.
lhe S i d UI Debord Socierr of
pte'OCC, reL C (Detroit: Alack and Red 1977) . ' .
the case. 6 Ch' . . . ' .
Rather than erect another hierarchy, it may therefore be I' Bns~lan Metz, lhe Imaginal')' Signifier: PI".rchoonalj"SiJ ond lhe Onemo trans
7 e la Tltton
C . et al . (8100 mmgton:
. Ind'lana University Press, 1982). '. 61. .
more useful to acknowledge the plurality of scopic regimes now
available to us. Rather than demonize one or another, it may be
. Jacquelme Rose. 5exuoJir) '
pp, 232-233.
in lhe Field rYVision (L d . V P
o n on. erso, 1986).

less dange rous to explore the implications, both positive and Mas~.'. : ' Arr an d Geomelry: A Silldy in Space Imuirions (Cambrid e
8. W illiam .M' Idns. 'Jr
negative, of each. In so doing, we won't lose entirely the sense of ~ Hanard UIlI I"Crslt)' Press 1946) , p. 8 I . g,
9. Rorty, p. 45.
unease that has so long haunted the visual culture of the West,
I~.
Blb/lorh~k Worbll19 4 ( 1924-1925): 258-331.
Erwin Panofsky, "Die Perspekti\"e als 'symbolischen Form'" c
but we may learn to see the virtues of differentiated ocular ex- ' \'orrrii8 der
periences. We may learn to wean ourselves from the fiction of a 11. William M. I nns.
M ' Jr., an rhe Ralionali7.olion if Siahl (New York Met I'
"true" vision and revel instead in the possibilities opened up by .uscum
h d of Art ' 1938)', Pa nofsky. "d.Ie Perspektil'e als 'sl'lTlbolischcn
. Foropo"'.ltan

the scopic regimes we haw already invented and the ones, now RIC ar Krautheimer, "8 rune IIesch'I and linear Perspect' il'c ". B rm .. ,

SO hard to envision, that are doubtless to come. Samu I;


PersptClirC comp Is bell H
Ed . a
' m fIllleifeschl m
e yman (Englcwood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall , 1974)'
e . gerton, Jr., The RenoilSQnu D' . . ~r .
Basic Books 1975)' J h W ho I$(OIC,) lj Lmeot PersptClil'e (Ncw York:
(Camb'd' ,on Ite, The B/rrh and Rebirrh if Picroriof Spac~. 3rd cd,
. n ge, Mass.: Belknap Press. 1987); Michael Kubo\")' The PSI'chol ,~r Po
speer/I'e and Rcnaissance An (Camb n'dge.. C ambndge
. . ' Press,
U lll\"ersit~, ;t "8.' C!J u-
1986).

21
20
Marlin Jay 1 SCO P IC REGIME S OF" MODERN ITY

12. Rosalind E. Krauss, Tht Oriaina/il}" rf 1M Arone-Garde and Orhu Modernist tlljtths Editions Galilee, 1984) and LaJo/it du 1"Olr: de J'esrhili'lue baroqut (Paris: Editions
(Cambridge, Mass.: The M IT Press, 1985), p. 10. Galilee, 1986).
13. Norman Bryson, Vision and Paimins: The Loaic rf the GalC (New Ha\"en: Yale 34. Rodolphc Gasche, The Taln rf Ihl! Mirror: Derrido and the Philosoph)' of Rif/tcfion
Uni\"ersity Press, 1983), p. 94. (Cambridge, Mass.: Har\"3rd Unh'ersity Press, 1986).
14. Augustine discusses ocular desire in C hapter 35 of the CI)f![euions. 35. As Bud-Glucksmann recognizcs, Leibnizian pluralism retains a faith in the
IS. For a discussion o f the gender implications o f this work, see S"etlana Al- harmonizing of perspectives that is absent fro m the mo re radically Nietzschean
pers, "Art History and its Exclusions," in Feminism and An H iswr)'= Questionina t~ impulse in the baroque, See La Jolie du \oir. p. 80, where she identifies that im-
Uro~l'. cd, Nonna Bro ude and Mary' D. Garrard (New Yo rk: Harper and Row, pulse with Gracian and Pasca l.
1982), p. 187. 36. Sce Irit Rogoff, "Mapping Out Strategies of Dislocation. " in thc catalogue
16. Norman Bryson, Word and fmaae: Funch POimina f?fthe Anden Resime (Cam- for Neustein's October 24-No\"embcr 26, 1987 show at the Exit Art gallery in
bridge: Cambridge Un iversity Press, 198 1), chapte r I. New York.
17. Edgerton, p. 39. 37. Krauss, "The Photographic Conditions of Surrealism," in The Or/Sina/il)' rf
18. John Berger, W'!rs rfSeeina (London: BBC, 1972), p. 109. fhe Avon/ - Gorde. See also her work with Jane lidngston, L 'omollr Jou: PhotO[Jraphy
19. Martin Heidegger, " The Question Concerning TCi:hnology," in Th~ Queslion and Surreo/ism (New York: Abbeville Press. 1985).
Concernina uchnoJos.,\, and Of her Essoys. tra ns. Will iam Lovitt (New York: Harpe r 38. Bud-Glucksmann, La folie du \oir. chapter VI.
and Row, 1977). Heidcgger's most extensh'e critique of Cartesian perspt'"ct h'al-
ism can be found in his essay " The Age of the World Picture," in the same
volume.
20. White, p. 208.
2 1. Kubo\")", chapter IV.
22 . Sarah Kofman , Camera Obscura, de I'ideo/asie ( Pari~: Editions GaiMe, 1973),
t reats this theme in Nit-tl'.sche.
23. Br:'son, I'ision and Paimina. p. 112 .
24. 5\"edana Alpers, Til< An ~[Docribina: Dlltch Art in III< St"enttenth CenulI)"
(Chicago: U n iver~it~ of C hicago Press. 1983).
25 . Ibid., p. xix.
26. Ibid . p. 44.
27 . Ibid ., p. 138.
28. Ibid. , p. 43.
29. Aaron Sl,harf. Art and Phol"9rap~r (Lofl(lon: Allen Lant" 1968; reprint , New
\ 1- "
York: Pcnguin Books, 1986), ('haptcr VII I.
30. P{'trr Ga lassi, B~[ore Phol"9ra~r: Paintirra and /he Im-cnrion t?[ Pha1oorophy (New
r York: MU~'um or Moder n .~ r t, 1981).
31. Heinrich WolflHn, Renai$SOnre and &roque. trans. Kathrin Simon (Ithaca,
N.Y.: Corncll Unin' rsity Pnss. 1966). Sn' also tht' syst{'matic dc\'e!opmcnt of
the t'ontrast in Principles f?[ Art H;5to~r: The Problem t?[ the Derdopment f?f S~rle in
La fer Art. trans. M. I) . Hottingl'r (London: G. Bcll & Sons. Ltd., 1932).
32. JOSl- Antonio Mar;I\'all, Culture t?f the Baroque: Ano~rJis f?[ a Historical Srructure.
trans. Trrry Cochran (Minm'apolis: Unhcrsit~ o f Mimwsota Prcss, 1986).
33. Christ im' Bud-Glul' bmann, La raison baroque; de Boudcloire Ii lkn;amin (Paris:

22 23
DISCUSSION

criticize its relat ion to sc ientism. But before we move too


quickly to a counterscicntihc position, we should recognize that
Western science depe nded on this practically useful hct ion of a
Jacqueline Rose I want to ask a question about your idea of " the distanciating vision. I don't want in any way to underplay the
plurality of scopic regimes." I take your poi nt that this spectacu- dangers here -gender dange rs, class dangers, and so forth .
lar plurality ca n be used as an oppressi"e device. Rut the critique Nonetheless, one ca n sometimes dise ntangle the political from
of Car tesia n perspecti\'c has always bee n tied to a specih c con- the \'isual; it is not always entailed.
ception of the political and to a particular noti on of the bour-
geois subj ect. And I wonder ",hat happens to that politi ca l Norman Bryson I have a quest ion about Dutch art, your second
critigue if one refo rm ulates it as you ha\'e. scopic regime. It's true that, unli ke Mediterranean art, Dutch art
does seem typically to get rid of the frame: t he framin g of the
Martin Jay It would be fascinati ng to map out th e politi cal im - image see ms arbitrary-a random cut-and compositi on doesn't
plicati ons of scopic regimes, but it can 't be done too reducti\'ely. appea r as the set of repercussions within the image of its frame.
The perspect i\,al ist regime is not necessa rily complicitous o nly Ne\'ertheless, one could also say that Dutch art is, so to speak,
with politically oppressive practices. Under certain ci rcum - hyperrea l compared to Mediterranean art: it is even more realist
stances it may be emancipator),; it rea lly depends on how it is precisely because it is not limited by structures of the frame.
used. And the same is arguable about any alternatives that are And although Northern painting follows another perspectival
prese nted. system -spherica l rather than Hat-its commitment to perspec-
The perspecti"alist regime may be compli citous with a ce r- ti"e is not fun damentally different from that in the south . In
tain noti on of an isolated bourgeo is subject, a subj ect that fai ls to short, I wonder whether there rea lly is such a difference be-
recogn ize its corporeality, its intersubj ecti\'ity, its embedded ness tween Dutch art and Mediterranean art, and whether a rea l
in the flesh of the world . Of course, this subject is now "ery point of d ifference between Cartesian perspectinlism and other
much under attack, and I don't want to reconstitute it naively. modes has to do instead with the per formati,'e- the idea of per-
Ne"ertheless, Ca rtesian perspecti\,alism also functions in the se r- formance and the insertion of embod iment into the optical field.
\'i ce of types of political self-understanding that depend on di s- I am thinking here of baroque art, but also of nineteenth-cen-
tanciation- explanatory social-scientific models, for example, tury art forms in which there is a considerable inten 'entio n of
,~jch argue aga inst the hermeneutic immersion o~he self in the bod ily into the frame-in the dsibility of pigment and ges-
the world and create.. at least the fiction of an objecti\'e dista nce ture, in the rise of the sketch, and in bra\'u ra styles such as that
from it. Here I think of the com bination that JUrgen Habermas of Delacroix or of Daum ier. The significant break with Cartesia n
has introduced in his discussion of the logiC of the socia l sci- perspecti\'alism might he found in this fracturing of "isual space
ences-a combination of explanatory and hermeneuti c under- upon the entry of the body.
standing based largely o n a perspecti"alist hction of being
outside the object of inquiry. This hction is easy to debunk be- Jay In a way I was trying to make the same point: that Dutch
cause we are always embedded in the world; it is also casy to art is not as radi ca l a break with perspecti valism as baroque art.

24 25
O ISCUSSIO N

But here I should clarify what I mean by realism. One might, as betwee n the disincarnated eye and the depicted sce ne that the
Svetlana Alpexs does, draw on the familiar Lukacsian distinction painting lacks the immediacy associated with desire. But this is
between ~~and na~ism (which should be taken with a often ca lled into questio n by various aesthetic practices; I men-
grain of salt). As Lukacs descr ibes it, realism deals with typo- tioned Caravaggio as an example, One crucial thing here is the
logica l, esse ntial depths-not with surfaces. Narration produces crossing of gazes; in most nudes the figure does not look back at
a typological se nse of mean ingfulness which goes beyond the us, but rather is objectified in such a way that ou r gaze meets no
scattered and untotalizable facts of a literary tex t (or perhaps a intersubjective return look. In Manet, howe\'er, there is such a
painting). With its stress on the three-dimensional space rather Jrisson of reciprocity. wh ich was lost in the Cartesian p erspec-
than the two-dimensional surface of the canvas, Cartesian per- tivalist construction, and the result was de-eroticization.
spectivalism is reali st in this sense. Naturalism, on the other
hand. is interested solely in surface-in descr ibing its varieties Foster In your model, then, de-eroticization is somehow opposed
of forms without redUCing them to any symboli cally meaningful to fetishization?
visua l depth. It rests content with the visual experience of light
on our eyes. Jay That's an interesting issue. A fetish can be seen as erotic. or
Now these modes of realism and natura lism might well be as producing a kind of closed entity which lacks erotic reciproc-
seen as complementary. Both create a reality-effect, the one by ity. Maybe there are two types of erotic relationship, the one
our belief that rea lity is depth . the other by simply show ing sur- fetishistic, the other not. Certa inly fetishism occurs more in
faces. Both modes are also complicitous with a cer tain kind of Dutch art in te rms of the objects on the canvas. If there is a
scientific thought; indeed, science has gone back and forth be- fetishism in Cartesian perspectivalism, it is a fetishism of the
twee n such Cartesian and Baconian notions of where rea lity lies. space itself. But it would be interesting to pursue an idea of dif-
But I think you are right: the third alte rnative calls both of them ferent modes of erotic interaction rather than the simple opposi-
into question through a performati ve critique of the reality-ef- tion of the erotic versus the de-eroti cized.
fect itself, In painting I suppose this is produced by the painter
or the beholder entering the pi cture in some metaphorical way;
this makes it impossible to see the painting as a scene out there
vi ewed with either the realist or the naturalist eye. It would be
interesting to see what the history of that more radical alterna-
Itive might be. Ce rtainly, as I argued at the end of my paper, it
see ms to entrance many of us now.

Hal Foster Could you say a little more about how, in your way of
thinking, Ca rtesian perspecti\"alism de-eroticizes?

Jay The argument is that perspecti\'al ism creates such a distance

26 21
Jonathan Crary

MODERNIZING VISION

My starting point is the various ways in which vision and the


techniques and discourses surrounding it have been periodized
historically. It is interesting that 50 many attempts to theorize
vision and visuality are wedded to models that emphasize a con-
tinuous and overarching Western visual tradition. Obviously at
times it is strategically necessary to map out and pose the out-
lines of a dominant Western speculative or scopic tradition of
vision that is continuous or in some sense effective, for instance,
from Plato to the present, or from the Quattrocento into the
twentieth century, or to whenever. My concern is not so much
to argue against these models, which have their own usefulness ,
but rather to insist there are some important discontinuities that
such hegemoniC constructions have prevented from coming into
view. The speCific account that interests me here, one that has
become almost ubiquitous and continues to be developed in a
variety of form s, is that the emergence of photography and cin-
ema in the nineteenth century is a fulfillment of a long unfolding
of technolOgi ca l and/or ideolOgica l development in the West in
which the camera obscura evolves into the photographic camera.
Implied is that at each step in this evolution the same essential
presuppositions about an observer's relation to the world are in
place. One could name a dozen or more books on the history of
film or photography in whose first chapter appears the obliga-
tory seventeenth-century engraving depicting a camera obsc\.l.ra,
as a kind of inaugural or incipient form on a long evolutionary
ladder.
These models of continuity are used in the service of both,

"
JODalhan Crary I MOOERN I Z I NG V ISION

for lack of better terms, the right and the left. On the one hand or a set of techn ical premises to be tinkered upon and improved
are those who pose an account of ever-increasing progress to- over the years; rather, it was embedded in a much larger and
ward verisimilitude in representation, in which Renai ssance per- denser orga nization of knowledge and of the obserVing subject.
spective and photography are part of the same quest for a full y If we want to be historical about it, we must recognize how for
objective equivalent of " natural vision." On the other are those nearly t wo hundred yea rs, from the late 1SODs to the end of the
who see, for example, the camera obscura and ci nema as bound 1700s, the structural and optical principles of the camera
up in a single enduring apparatus of pO\ver, elaborated over sev- obscura coa lesced into a dominant paradigm through which was
eral centuries, that continues to define and regulate the status of described the status and possibilities of an obsener.
an observer. It became a model, obViously elaborated in a variety of
What I want to do are essentially two related things: ( I) to ways, for how observation leads to truthful inferences about an
briefly and very generally articulate the camera obscura model of external world. It was an era when the camera obscura was
vision in terms of its historical specificity, and (2) to suggest Simultaneous ly and inseparably a ce ntral epistemo logical figure
how that model collapsed in the early nineteenth century-in witmn a discursive order, as in Descartes's DiOptriCS, Locke's
the 1820s and 1830s-when it was displaced by radically dif- Essay on Human Underscandins> and Leibniz's critique of Locke,
ferent notions of what an observer was and of what constituted and occupied a major position within an arrangement of techni-
vision. So if later in the nineteenth century cinema or photogra- cal and cultural practices, for example in the work of Kepler and
phy seem to invite formal comparisons 'w ith the camera obscura, Newton. As a complex technique of power, it was a means of
or if Marx, Freud, Bergson, and others refer to it, it is within a legislating for an observer what constituted perceptual "truth,"
social, cultural, and scientific milieu in which there had already and it delineated a fixed set of relati ons to which an observer
been a profound rupture with the conditions of vision pres up- was made subject.
posed by this device. What I wi ll argue is that very early on in the ninetee nth
century the camera obscura co llapses as a model for an observer
For at least two thousand years it has been known that, when and for the fun ctioning of hwnan vision. There is a profou nd
light passes through a small hole into a dark, enclosed interior, shift in the way in wh ich an observer is described, figured, and
an inverted image will appear on the wall opposite the hole. posited in science, philosophy, and in new techniques and prac-
Thinkers as remote fr om each other as Euclid, Aristotle, Roger tices of visio n. Here I want brieRy and very sketchily to indi cate
Bacon, and Leonardo noted this phenomenon and speculated in a few important features of this shift.
various ways how it might or might not be analogous to the First, a bit more about the camera obscura in the seven-
functioning of human vision. teenth and eighteenth centuries. Above all, whether in the work
But it is crucial to make a distinction between the empiri- of scientists or artists, empiricists or rationalists, it was an appa-
cal fact that an image can be produced in this way (something ratus that guaranteed access to an objective truth about the
that continues to be as true now as it was in antiquity) and the world. It assumed importa nce as a model both for the observa-
camera obscura as a SOC ially constructed artifact. For the camera tion of empiri ca l phenomenon and for reAective introspect ion
ohscura was not simply an inert and neutral piece of equipment and self-obse rvation. In Locke, for example, the camera is a

30
"
Jonathon Crary \ MOOE:RN1Z1NG VISION

means of spatially visualizing the position of an observ ing sub- slightly different image with each eye, was never seriously ad-
ject. I The image of the room in Locke takes on a special signifi- dressed as a central issue. It was igno red or minimized as a
cance, referring to what it meant in the seventeenth century to problem, for it impli ed the inadmissible physio~ogical and ana-
be in camera, that is, within the chambers of a judge or person of tomical operation of human vision. A monocular model , on the
title.2' Thus he adds onto the observer's passive role a more au- other hand, precluded the difficult problem of haV ing to recon-
thoritative and juridical function to guarantee and to police the ci le th e dissimilar and therefore prmTisional and tentative images
correspondence between exterior world and interior representa- presented to each eye. Monocularity, like perspective and geo-
tion and to exclude anything disorderly or unruly. metrical optics, was one of the Renaissance codes through which
Richard Rorty has pointed to Locke and Descartes as key a visua l world is constructed according to systematized con-
figures ill establishing this conception of the human mind as "an stants, and from which any inconsistencies and irregularities are
inner space in which clear and distinct ideas passed in review banished to insure the formati.on of a homogeneous , unified, and
before an inner Eye ... an inner space in which perceptual sen- fully legible space.
sations were themselves the objects of quasi-observation. "] For Finally to wind up this extremely compressed outline, it
Descartes, the camera obscura was a demonstration of how an should also be suggested how closely the camera obscura is
observer can know the world "uniquely by perception of the bound up with a metaphysic of interiority. It is a figure for the
mind." The secure positioning of the self with this empty inte- observer who is nominally a free sovereign individual but who is
rior space was a precondition for knowing the outer world . Its also a privatized isolated subject enclosed in a quasi-domestic
enclosedness, its darkness, its categorical separation from an ex- space separated from a public exterior world . It defined an ob-
terior incarnates Descartes's announcement in the Third Medita- server who was subjected to an inAexi ble set of positions and di-
tion, ~' I will now shut my eyes, I shall stop my ears, I shall visions. The visual world could be appropriated by an autono-
disregard my senses."4 If part of Descartes's method implied a mous subj ect but only as a private unitary consciousness de-
need to escape the uncertainties of mere human vision, the cam- tached fro m any active relation with an exterior. The monadic
era obscura is compatible with his quest to found knowledge on vie\vpoi nt of the individual is legitimi zed by the camera obscura,
a purely objective view of the world. The aperture of the camera but his or her sensory experience is subordinated to an external
corresponds to a Single mathematically definable point from and pre-given world of objective truth.
which the world could be logically deduced and re-presented.
Founded on laws of nature-that is, geometrica l optics-the What is striking is the suddenness and thoroughness with whi ch
camera prOVided an infallible vantage point on the world. Sen- this paradigm collapses in the early nineteenth century and gives
sory ev idence that depended in any way on the body was re- way to a diverse set of fundamentally different models of human
jected in favor of the representations of this mechanical and vision. I want to discuss one crucial dimension of this shift, the
monocular apparatus, whose authenticity was placed beyond insertion of a new term into discourses and pract ices of vision:
doubt. the human body, a term whose exclusion was one of the founda-
Monocular, not binocular. A Si ngle eye, not two. Until the tions of classical theories of vision and optics as I have just sug-
nineteenth century, binocular disparity, the fact that we see a gested. One of the most telling signs of the new centrality of the

" 33
Jonothon Crory I MOOERNIZING VISION

body in vision is Goethe's Theory if Colours, published in 1810, eye and sun, paintings in which the strictures that pre\'iously
which I have disc ussed at length elsewhere. 5 This is a work cru- had mediated and regulated vision are abandoned. Nothing now
cial not for its polemic with Newton over the composition of protects or distances the observer from the seductive and sen-
light but for its articulation of a model of subj ective vision in sual brilliance of the sun. The symbolic confines of the camera
which the body is introduced in all its physiological density as obscura have crumbled.
the ground on which vision is possible. In Goethe we find an ObViously afterimages have been noted and recorded since
image of a newly productive observer whose body has a range of antiquity, but they had always been outside or on the margins of
capacities to generate \'isual experiencej it is a question of visual the domain of optics. They were considered illusions-decep-
experience that does not refer or correspond to anything exter- tive, spectral, and unreal. In the early nineteenth century such
nal to the observing subject. Goethe is concerned mainly with experiences that preViously had been an exp ression of the frailty
the exper iences associated with the retinal afterimage and its and the unreliability of the body now constituted the positivity
chromatic transformations. But he is only the first of many re- of vision. But perhaps more importantly, the prh'ileging of the
searchers \-vho become preoccupied with the afterimage in the body as a visua l producer began to collapse the distinction be-
1820s and 1830s throughout Europe. Their collective study de- tween inner and outer upon which the camera obscura de-
fined how vision was an irreducible amalgam of phys iological pended . Once the objects of "ision are coextensh'e with o ne's
processes and external stimulation, and dramatized the produc- own body, vision becomes dislocated and depositioned onto a
tive role played by the body in vision. single immanent plane. The bipolar setup vanishes. Thirdly, sub-
Although we are talking about scientists, what is in ques- jective vision is fou nd to be distinctly temporal , an unfolding of
tion here is the discovery of the "visionary" capaci ties of the processes within the body, thus undOing notions of a direct cor-
body, and we miss the Significance of this research if we don't respondence between perception and object. By the 1820s, then,
recall some of its stra nge intensity and exhilaration. For what we efTecti" ely ha"e a model of autonomous ,isio n.
was often involved was the experience of staring directly into
the sun, of sunl ight searing itself onto the body, palpably dis- The subj ecti"e vision that endowed th e obser\'er with a new per-
turbing it into a proli feratio n of incandescent color. Three of the ceptual autonomy and product i\,ity was Simultaneously the result
most celebrated students of vision of this period went blind or of the observe r having been made into a subject of new kno\\'I-
permanently damaged their eyesight by repeatedly staring at the edge, of new techniques of power. And the terrain on which
sun: David Brewster, who im'ented the kaleidoscope and stereo- these two interrelated obsen'ers emerged in the ninetee nth ce n-
scope; Joseph Plateau, who studied the so-ca lled persistence of tury was the science of phYSiology. From 1820 through the
vision; and Gustav Fechner, one of the founders of modern 1840s it was "e ry unlike the specia li z~d science that it later be-
quantitative psychology. Fechner's biography prOVides an account camej it had then no formal instit utional identity and came into
of the almost addictive fasci nation with which he persisted in being as the accumulated work of disconnected indi\' iduals from
this activity. At the same time in the late 1830s and early 1840s diverse branches of learning. In common was the exci tement
we have the visual expression of these attempts in the late paint- and wonderment at the hod)', which no\\' appeared like a new
ings of Turner, in whi ch there is that piercing confrontation of continent to be mapped, ex plored, and mastered , with new re-

" 35
Jonathan Crary I M ODERNIZI N G VISIO N

cesses and mechanisms uncovered for the first time. But the real a mapping of the human eye as an opaque territory \\" ith "a rying
importance of physiology lay in the fact that it became the arena zones of effiCiency and aptitude and specific parameters of nor-
for new types of epistemologi ca l reSection that depended on mal and pathological vis ion. Some of the most celebrated of
new knowledge about the eye and processes of vision. Physiology these exper iments were Josep h Plateau's calcu lat ion, in the
at this moment of the nineteenth century is one of those sci- 1830s, of the a,erage duration of an afterimage. or persistence of
ences that stand for the rupture that Foucault poses between the vision, which was about one-third of a seco nd, and later,
eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, in which man emerges as a Helmholtz's measurement of the speed of ncn'C transmission,
6
being in whom the transcendent is mapped onto the empirical. whi ch astounded people by how slow it was, about ninety feet
It was the di scovery that knowledge was conditioned by the pe r second. Both statistics heightened the sense of a temporal
physical and anatomical structure and functi oning of the body, disjunct ion between perception and its object and suggested new
and in particular of the eyes. At the same time, as Georges Ca n- possi bilities of intervening externally in the process of \ ision.
gUi lhem has noted , for the new sciences in the nineteenth cen- Clearly this study of the eye in terms of reaction time and
tury the body was a priori a productive body: it existed to be set thresholds of fatigue and stimulation was not unrelated to in-
to work. 7 creasing demand for knowledge abou t the adaptat ion of a human
Even in the early 1820s the study of afterimages quickly subject to producthe tasks in which optimum attention span was
became the object of a more rigorous and quamitative scientific indispensable for the rationalization of human labor. The eco-
research throughout Europe. Studi ed was the persistence and nomi c need for rapid coordination of hand and eye in perform-
modulation of after images: how long they lasted, what changes ing repetit ive actions required accurate knowledge of human
they went through, and under what conditions. But instead of optical and sensory capac ities. In the contex t of new industria l
recording afterimages in terms of the lived time of the body as models of factory production the problem of visual inattenti on
Goethe had gene rally done, they were studied as part of a com- was a ser ious one. But what de\eloped was a notion of \'ision
prehensive quantification of the irr itability of the eye. Re- that was funda mentally quantitati\'e, in which the terms con-
searchers timed how long it took the eye to become fatigued, stituting the relatio n bet\veen percepti on and obj ect became ab-
how long dilation and contraction of the pupil took, and mea- stract, interchangeable. and nonvisual. One of the most
sured the strength of eye movements. They e.xamined con- paradoxica l fig ures of the nineteenth century is Gusta,' Fechner,
vergence and accommodation in binocular vision and the whose delirious and e,'cn mystical experiences with solar after-
relati on of image to retinal curvature. images led to his mathematizatio n of perceptio n, in which he es-
The physical surface of the eye itself became a field of sta- tablished a funct ional relation between stimulus and sensatio n.8
tistical information: the retina was demarcated in terms of how Sensory perception was given a measurable magnitude solely in
color changes hue depending on where it st rikes the eye. Also terms of the known and controll able magnitudes of external
measured were the extent of the area of visibility, of peripheral stimulatio n. Vision became studied in terms of abstract measur-
vision, the distinction between direct and indirect vision, and able regular it ies, and Fechner's famous equations were to be one
the location of the blind spot. Classical opticS, which had stud- of the foundations of modern stimulus-response psychology.
ied the transparency of mechanical optical systems, gave way to Another dimension of the collective achievement of phys-

" "
JonolhDn Crory I MODERNIZING VISION

iology in the first half of the nineteenth century was the gradual Helmholtz's OptiCS, which dominated the second half of the
parcelization and division of the body into increasingly separate 18005; in science, philosophy, and psychology it was Widely pro-
and specific systems and functions. Especially important were pounded, debated, and denounced even into the early twentieth
the loca lization of brain and nerve functions, and the distinction century. (A lso, I believe Marx was paraphrasing this work when
between sensory nerves and motor nerves. Finally, by 1826 it he discussed the separation of the senses in his 1844 Manu-
was determined that sensory nerves were of five distinct types, scripts. ll ) In short, this is a major way in which an observer was
correspondi ng to the five senses. All of this produced a new figured in the nineteenth century. a way in which a ce rtain
"truth" about the body which some have linked to the so-called "truth" about Sight was depicted,
"separation of the senses" in the nineteenth century, and to the The theory was based on the discovery that the nerves of
idea that the specializati on of labor was homologous to a special- the different senses were phYSiologically distinct. It asserted
ization of sight and of a heightened autonomous vision, some- quite Simply-and this is what marks its epistemolOgical scan-
thing that Fredric Jameson develops briefly but provocatively in dal-that a uniform cause (e.g., electricity) would generate
The Political Unconscious. 9 I beli e,'e, however, that such a homol- utterly different sensations from one kind of nerve to another,
ogy doesn't take account of how thoroughly vision was recon- Electricity applied to the optic nerve produces the experience of
ceived in the earli er njneteenth century, It sti ll seems to pose light, applied to the skin the sensation of touch. Conversely,
obsen'ation as the act of a unified subject looking out onto a Muller shows that a var iety of different causes will produce the
world that is the object of his or her Sight, only that, because the same sensation in a given sensory nerve; in other words, he de-
objects of the world haye become reified and commodified, vi- scribes a fundam entally arbitrary relation between stimulus and
sion in a sense becomes conscious of itself as sheer looking. sensation. It is a description of a body with an innate capacity,
But in the first major scientific theorization of the separa- one might even say a transcendental faculty, to misperceive, of an
tion of the senses, there is a much more decisive break with the eye that renders differences equivalent.
classical obseryer; and what is at stake is not simply the height- His most exhaustive demonstration concerns the sense of
ening or iso lating of the optical but rather a notion of an ob- Sight, and he concludes that the observer's e.xperi ence of light
sen'er for whom vision is concei,'ed ,"vithout any necessary has no necessary connection with any actual light. Miiller enu-
connection to the act of looking at all. The work in question is merates the agencies capable of prodUcing the se nsation of light.
the research of the German physiologist Johannes Muller, the "The sensati ons of light and co lor are produced wherever parts
Single most important theorist of ,'ision in the first half of the of the retina are excited 1) by mechanical influences, such as
nineteenth century. 10 In his study of the physiology of the pressure, a blow or concussion 2) by electricity 3) by chemi cal
senses, Muller makes a comprehensi,'e statement on the subdivi- agents, such as narcotics, digitalis 4) by the stimulus of the blood
sion and specialization of the human sensory apparatus; his fame in a state of congestion. "12 Then last on his li st, almost be-
was due to his theorization of that specialization: the so-called grudgingly, he adds that luminous images also can be produced
"doctri ne of specific nenc energies." It was a theory in many by "the undulations and emanation which by their action on the
ways as important to the nineteenth century as the Molyneux eye are called light."
problem was to the eighteenth century. It was the foundation of Aga in the camera ohscura model is made irrelevant. The

38
"
Jonothon Crory I MOOANIZING VISION

experience of light becomes snered from any stable point of ref~ for the model of the camera obscura_ in his supposedly empirical
erence or from any source or origin around which a world could description of the human se nsory apparatus, Muller presents the
be constituted and apprehended_ And of course the ,-ery inde- subject not as a unitary "tabula rasa ," but as a composite struc-
pendent identity of light had already been undermined as a new ture on which a wide range of techniques and forces could pro-
wa,-e theory of light became part of a sc ience of electro-mag- duce a manifold of experiences that are all equally "reality_" If
netic phenomena _ John Ruskin proposed reclaiming the "innocence of the eye,"
Sight here has been separated and specialized certainly. but this was about as innoce nt as one could get_ The observer is
it no longer resembles any classical models_ T he them")' of spe- Simultaneously the object of knowledge and the object of pro-
cifi c nen -e energies prese nts the outlines of a Yistlai modernity cedures of stimulati on and normalization, which have the essen-
in which the "referential illusion" is unsparingly laid bare. The tial ca paCity co produce experience for the subject. ironi cally the
,-ery absence of referentiality is the ground on whi ch new in- notions of the reflex arc and reflex action, which in the se,-en-
strumental techniques will construct for an obsen-er a ne"- teenth century referred to vision and the optics of reflection,
"real" world_ It is a question of a perceh-er whose ,-ery empiri - begin to become the centerpi ece of an emerging technology of
cal nature renders identities unstable and mobile, and for whom the subject, culminating in the work of PadO\_
sensations are interchangeable_ And remember, this is roughly In his account of the relatio n bet,veen stimulus and sensa-
1830_ In effect, the doctrine of specific nerve energies redefines tion, Muller suggests not an orderly and legislative function ing of
vi sion as a capacity for being affected by se nsati ons that ha,-c no the se nses, but rather their receptivity to calculated management
necessary link to a referent, thus threatening any coherent sys- and dera ngement_ Emile Dubois-Reymond, a colleague of
tem of meaning_ Muller's theory was potentially so nihilisti c that Helmholtz, seriously pursued the possibility of elect rica lly cross-
it is no wonder that Helmholtz and others, who accepted its em- connecting nerves, enabling the eye to see sounds and the ear to
pirical premises, were impelled to im-ent theories of cogn ition hear colors, well before Rimbaud_ It must be emphaSized that
and signi fication which concealed its uncompromising cultural Muller's research and that of psychophysics in the nineteenth
impli cations_ But what was at sta ke and seemed so threatening ce ntury is inseparable from the resources made a,'a ilable by con-
was not just a new form of epistemologica l skepti Cism about the temporary work in electri city and chemistry_Some of the em-
unreliability of the senses but a positive reorganization of per- piri ca l eyidence by Muller had been avai lable since antiquity, or
ception and its objects_ The issue was not just how does one was in the domain of common-sense knowledge_ However, what
know what is real, but that new forms of the rea l ,,-ere being is new is the c-x traordinary prh-ilege giycn to a complex of elec-
fabri cated and a new truth about the capacities of a human su b- tro-physical techniques_ What constitutes "sensatio n" is dramat-
ject was being articulated in these terms_ ically expa nded and transformed, and it has little in common
with how it was discussed in the eighteenth ce ntury_ The adja-
The theory of specifi c nen -e energies eradi cated distinctions be- cency of Mtiller's doctrine of speC ific nen-e energies to the tech-
tween internal and external sensation, so that interiority was nology of nineteenth-century modernity is made particularly
drained of the mea nings it once had for a classical obse n -er, or dear by Helmholtz:

40 41
Jonathon Crary I MODERNIZIN G VISION

Ne rves in the human body have been accurately compared to telearaph vision and modernity we must look first at these ea rly decades,
wires. Such a wire conducts one sinale kind t?! elearic current and no not to modernist painting in the 18705 and 18S0s. A new type
other; it may be stronaer, it may be weaker, ie may mO~'e in either di- of obsen er was form ed then, and not one that we can see fig-
reaion; it has no other qualiweive d!fferences. Nevertheless, accordins ured in paintings or prints. We\e been trained to assume that
to the d!fforent kinds t?! apparatus wieh which \I'e provide its termina- an observer will always lea"e visible tracks, that is, will be identi-
tions, we can send relearaphic dispatches, rinS bells, explode mines, de- fiable in terms of images. But here it's a Cjuestion of an observe r
compose warer, move maaners, maanecize iron, develop liSht, and so who takes shap e in othe r, grayer practices and discourses, and
on. The same thing with our nerves. The condition of excicement whose immense legacy will be all the industries of the image and
which can be produced in them, and is conducted by chern, is . the spectacle in the twentieth century. The body which had
everywhere the same. 13 bee n a neutra l or invisible term in vision now was the thickness
Far from the spec ialization of the senses, Helmho ltz is explicit from which knowledge of vision was deri\'ed. This opacity or
about the body's indifference to the sources of its experience carnal denSity of the ohsen 'er loomed so suddenly into "iew that
and of its capacity for multiple connections with other age ncies its ful l co nsequences and effects could not be immediately real-
and machines. The percei\"er here becomes a neutral conduit, ized. But it was this ongoing articulation of vision as nom'eridi-
one kind of relay among others to allow optimum cond itions of ca l, as lodged in the body, that was a condition t?! poSSibility both
circulation and exchangeability, whether it be of commodities, for the artistic exper imentation of modernism and for new
ene rgy, capital, images, or information. forms of domination, for what Foucault calls the "techno logy of
indi\iduals."'4 Inseparable from the technolOgies of domination
The collapse of the camera obscura as a model for the status of and of the spectacle in the later nineteenth and twenti eth ce n-
an obsen er was part of a much larger process of modernization, tury were of course film and photography. Paradoxically, the in -
even as the camera obscura itself was an element of an earlier creasing hegemony of these two techniq ues helped recreate the
modernity. By the early lSQOs, however, the rigidity of the cam- myths that vision was incorporeal, verid ical, and " realistic." But
era obscura, its linear optical system, its fixed positions, its cate- if cin ema and photography seemed to reincarnate the camera
gOri cal distinction between inside and outside, its identifi cation obsc ura, it was only as a mirage of a transparent set of relations
of perception and object, were all too inAexible and unWieldy that modernity had already overthrown.
for the needs of the new century. A more mobile, usable, and
productive obse n 'er was needed in both discourse and prac-
tice-to be adequate to new uses of the body and to a vast pro- Holes

liferation of equally mobile and exchangeable signs and images. I. John Lockc, An &SO)' Concernina Human Undemondina (New York: OO\cr Pub-
Modernization entai led a decodi ng and deterritor ialization of lications. 1959), \'0 1. 2, xi, 17.
vision. 2. Ibid., \'01. 2, ii i, I.
3. Richard Rort~'. Philosophy and fhe Mirror '?f ,vature (Princ<'Ion : Princeton Uni-
What I\'e been trying to do is gi\"e some sense of how rad-
versity Press, 1979), pp. 4950.
ical was the reconfiguration of vision by l S40. If our problem is 4. Rene Descartes. The Philosophical Writings '?f ~scarm, trans. John Cottingham

" 43
DISCUSSION

et al. (Cambridge: Cambridge University p~ss, 1984), "01. 2, p. 24.


5. Johann Wolfgang \'on Goethe, Thear;' rf Colours. trans. Charles Lock Eastlake
(Cambridge, Mass.: The M IT Press, 1970). See my " Techniques of the Ob-
sen'er," OcIQ~r. no. 45 (Summer 1988).
6. Michel Foucault, Tht Orotr rf Thi"85 (New York: Pantheon Books, 1971), Nartln Jav I found your paper "ery rich, but I want to pus h one
pp.3 18-320. aspect of it - the binary opposition between "er idi ca l and noo-
7. Georges Canguilhem, "Qu'est-ce que Ie psychologie," in his Erudts d'hisIQlu et
veridi ca l Sight - more than you did. It might be argued that the
de philruophit des scitncts. 5th ed. (Paris: 1- Vrin, 1983), pp. 377-378.
Cartesian perspectival tradition- your tradition of the camera
8. See Gusta,' Fechner, Elemems rf P.>ychophpics, trans. Helmut E. Adler (New
York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1966). obscura-,vas aware to some extent of the constituti\'e, rather
9. Fredric Jameson, Tht Political Unconscious: Norraril'c as 0 SoCially S)'mbolic Act than the merely reAecti\'c, nature of visual expe ri ence. For ex-
(Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 198 1), pp. 62-64. ample, John Yolton, in hi s book Perceptual Acquaintance from
10. See Jo hannes Miiller, Handbuch dCl Physiologic des Mcnschcn (Coblenz:
Descartes to Reid, deals with the semantic element in Descartes's
Holscher, 1838); Elements rf Physiologic, trans. William Haly (London: Taylor and
Walton, 1848). Oplics; and here he argues (against Richard Rorty) that even in
II . See Ka rl Marx, The Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts oj 1844, ed. Dirk J. this "mirror of nature" tradition there is a constitutive moment
Struik, trans. Martin Milligan (New York: International Publishers, 1964), that has to do with a natural geometry of the mind which is not
pp. 140-141. simply "out there" - that e,'en in this most "eridical tradition of
12. Miiller, p. 1064.
vision there is a non\'eridica l element or at least one that is not
13. Hermann ,'o n Helmho ltz, On thc &nsarions rf To~ as a Physiological Basis for lM
Thcory of Music, 2nd ed., trans. Alexander J. Ellis (New York: Do\'er Publications, simply mimetic. Now I think you are right to say that the intro-
1954), pp. 148-149. duction of the body emphasizes this constituti" e qua lity that was
14. Michel Foucault, Di5cipline and Punish: Thc Birth tf rhc Prison. trans. Alan hitherto relatively forgotten. But I want to ask if the resu lt is
Sheridan (New York: Vintage Books, 1975), p. 225.
completely nonver id ical or rather a complex mixture of the co n-
stitutive and the reflective, so that dsion does not simply be-
come reduced to the stimulation of nerves but also has to do
with an external reality \vhich is in a complicated way re-
produced -so that there is a mimetic moment that sun'h'es even
after this revolution that you described so nicely. In short, docs
the binary oppositi on of th e veridi cal and the nom'eridi cal ho ld
up? Or are there Cjualities of each in the two epochs that you
sketched ?

Jonathan Crary My use of these two very distinct typolOgies sim-


plifies many of the complexities of the theories of dsion in ques-
tion . In the nineteenth ce ntury. vision ,vas most often desc ribed
in terms of mimetic and subjecth'e elements. Some theorists af-
ter Muller sought to rei ntroduce a dependable representational

.. "
DISCUSSION

structure onto mere se nsory data, for instance Helmholtz's no- Crary Ce rtainly not in a major way. I've been speaki ng rnainly
tion of "unconscious inference" and Hermann Lotze's "theory of about developments betwee n 1820 and 1840. We would have to
loca l signs." Nonetheless, I still insist that what is new in the talk about just what a "concept of sexua lity" would rnean at that
nineteenth century is the emergence of the body as a productive histori cal moment. Probably not what it does for us now.
physiological apparatus; and if vision in the nineteenth century is
thought of as "constitutive," this means something radically dif- Rose I'm just looking for a trace. Is thi s particular theory of
ferent from what John Yolton means. The articulation of subjec- phYSiological misapprehension with its multiplicity of registers
tive vision in the 1830s and 1840s-that is, of the subj ect's and its lack of coherent in ference-is this model of " nerves and
productive role in the process of vision-coincided with a new brains" ever a sex ualized noti on of psychic fun ctioning? In eight-
network of techniques and institutions by which visual experi- eenth - and nineteenth-century di scussions of hysteria, the dis-
ence could be produced jor a subject. So the emergence of theo- tinction behveen fu nction and organic disorder is immediately
ries of nonveridical perception should be considered in relation bound up with a theory of speC ifically feminine disorder. Does
to processes of modernization that are specific to the nineteenth anything of that kind occur in this realm as well?
century. That is, the abstraction and exchangeability of visual
experience is not unconnected to economic and social Crary No.
transformations.
NDrman Bryson You made one very suggestive reference to Turner.
Jacqueline Rose I have a question about the accusation of psychol- 1 wonder whether the legacy of the obsene r const ructed in the
ogism launched against the theories you described. As far as I nineteenth ce ntury is to be located mainly in cinema and pho-
understood it, this could be seen simply in terms of perceptual tog raphy, or whether there are traces in painting (other than
misapprehension. Did this psychologism, in either its positive or Turner) where one might find this construction at '''lork.
its negative renderings, contain a theory of sex uality or of psy-
chic life, or was it entirely confined to the realm of perception Crary I was a bit reluctant to even mention Turner because he is
accurately or inaccurately registered? so overused as an example. But in the context of the discussion
this morning, part of Turn er's work represents the triumphant
Crary It depends what you mean by "psyche." In a sense, some reemergence of a kind of cou ntertradition to geometrical optics
of what I was talking about in the nineteenth century comes un- and perspecti,e, that is, the practice born out of the ifumolo of
der the genera l label of "psychophysics," and yes, it was very Leonardo. Yet Turner's work is bound up, as Michel Se rres has
much a theory of psychi c life and functioning. This is lodged in shown , in a whole new scie ntific paradigm. In genera l, there is
a more general deve lopment of empirical theories of an uncon- no immediate homologous relation between sc ience and artistic
scious from J. F. Herbart to Fechner and Wilhelm Wundt. But practice; there is a lag, a phase in which older conventions and
aU of this is probably very different from what you mean. techniques lose their effectheness.
Your larger question - that is, whether we should look for
Rose And no concept of sexuality is present either? a nineteenth-century observer in film/ photog raphy or painting-

. 41
DISCUSSION

raises a set of other issues. I'm ,"ery deliberately tryi ng to re- though the ex tent to whi ch they "dis-embody" vision really de-
frame the whole problem of the observer by severing it from the pends on the speCifi c case in question. Van Gogh is a different
kinds of questions art history has usually asked. Rather than let problem from Pissa r ro; Theodor Lipps is different from Mauri ce
a history of an obsen-er be defined in terms of the changing Denis_ But they still depend on the models of subjecti ye vision
forms of visual representations (which gives art works a kind of and of nOlwcr idical perception that emerged earlier, and these
ontological priority), I think of an observer as an amalgam of models were bound up in massi\'e tra nsformations to the notions
many disparate events and forces_ If it could be said that there is both of su bjecti,- ity and of production.
an observer spec ific to the nineteenth century, it is only as an
eJfeCl of a heterogeneous net'work of discursiye, soc ial, tech-
nologica l, and institutiona l relations_ There is no observer prior
to this continually shifting fieldi the noti on of an observer has
mea ning only in terms of the multiple conditions under which
he or she is pOSSible.

Hal Foster Jonathan, on the one hand , you say that in the nine-
teenth century vision comes to be known as produced in the
body, that it becomes regarded as somehow autonomous, sepa-
rated from any refe rent, and you suggest that this is a precondi-
ti on of the modernist move that culminates in abstraction, On
the other hand, this modernist move is usually seen in terms of
a disembodiment of visio n_ Is there a way to clarify th is, or is it
not really a contradi ction?

Crary I wanted to sketch out in a more general way some of the


preconditions for modernism , one of which \-vas the breakdown
of the representatio nal model of the camera obscura on many
different levels in nineteenth-century culture. It is part of a
modernizing of vision which begins very early on-a kind of
clearing away, a casting off of old encumbrances that allows for
new notions of what is possible for a viewer, And va rious ideas
of autonomous vis ion and abstraction are certainly part of this.
or course, you are right that many modernist articulations of au-
tonomous vision or of pure visuality tota lly excluded the body,

. 49
Rosolind Krauss

THE 1M/PULSE TO SEE

TraMe sua quemque ro/UplOS: I'un s'identi fie au spectacle. et


I'autre donne a voir.
- Jacques Lacan

What I'd like to broach here is the issue of a rhythm , or beat, o r


pulse-a kind of throb of on/off on/ofT on/off-which, in itself,
acts against the stability of visual space in a way that is destruc-
tive and devolutio nary. For, as I hope to show, this beat has the
power to decompose and disso lve the very coherence of form o n
which " isuaBty may be thought to depend.
This rhythm turns out to have been the resource of a vari-
ety of works that appeared aga inst the background of ea rly
twentieth-century moderni sm in direct contestation of that
modernism's ambition to grou nd the visual arts on a particular
notion of the autonomy of vision. That that autonomy is not se-
cured simply in relation to matters of space, but depends as well
on vcry particular limits set on the experi ence of time, can he
demonst rated in a variety of ways. Perhaps the simplest might be
to illustrate it with an anecdote.
Drawn from the art world of the early 19605, this involves
a story that a cr itic, Michael Fried. told about an ar tist, Frank
Stella. It ope ns w ith a questio n. "Do you know who Frank.
thinks is the g reatest li ving American?" Michael asked me one
day. And then. grinning at the sheer brilliance of the answer, he
sa id it was Ted Willi ams, the g reat hitter for the Red Sox. "He
sees fas ter than any livi ng human," Michael said. " His vision is
Pablo Picasso. Le Dfjtuller sur /,htr~ d'apru MOllt!. July 10, 1961. St.latsgalerie
Stuttgart. (Copyright ARS N.Y.lSPADEM. 1988) so fast that he ca n see the stitching on the baseba ll as it comes

51
Rosalind Krauss I THE 1 M /PULSE TO SEE

o"er the plate. Ninety miles an hour, but he sees the stitches. So uncovering and displaying the conditions of vision itself, as these
he hits the ball right out of the park. That's why Frank thinks were understood, abstractly. "The heightened sensitiv ity of the
he's a genius." picture plane may no longer permit sculptural illusion, or
I remember the urgency in Michael's mice as his tone was trompe- l'oeil," Greenberg wrote, "but it does and must permit
divided by total hilarity at the image and utter se ri ousness about optical illusion. The firs t mark made on a surface destroys its
its import. But it was the early '60s and I was in the grip of a virtual Aatness, and the configuratiOns of a Mondrian still sug-
certain view of modernism and so its import did not escape me gest a kind of illusion of a kind of third dimension. O nly now it
either. I too found it a completely brilliant idea: Ted Williams, is a strictly pictor ial, st rictly optical third dimension .. . one
the spectacular home run hitter, the perfect metaphor of visual into which one can look, can travel through, only with the
moder nism. eye."l
If at this moment the image does not come across with the Lukacs, deplor ing this technologizing of the body, this need
effortless immediacy it did then, this would not be surprising, to abstract and reify each of the senses in a submission of human
since the g rip modernism has on our intuitions has begun for subjectivity to the model of positivist science, would have found
some time to slacken. But for me-then-the image performed nothing to argue with in Greenberg's analysis. He would only
the condition of an abstracted and he ightened Yisuality, one in have objected to its tone, to its position, whi ch Greenberg
which the eye and its object made contact with such amazing shared with Adorno, that in this withdrawal of each diSCipline
rapidity that neither one seemed any longer to be attached to its into that sphere of sensory experience unique to it, there was
merely carna l support-neither to the body of the hitter, nor to somethi ng pOSitive, something utopian. For this utopianist mod-
the spher ical substrate of the ball. Vision had, as it were, been ernism was insisting that this se nsory stratum newly understood
pared away into a dazzle of pure instantaneity, into an abstract as discrete, as se lf-sufficient, as autonomous-this very strati fica-
cond ition with no before and no after. But in that very motion- tion-permitted an experience of rescue and retreat, a high
less explos ion of pure presentness was contained as well vision's ground uncontaminated by the instrumentality of the world of
connecti on to its objects, also represented here in its abstract labor and of sc ience, a preserve of play and thus a model of fre e-
form-as a moment of pure release, of pure transpa rency, of dom. And perhaps the pl easure for us at that moment in the '60s
pure se lf-knowledge. in the idea of a high-cultural ambition's being allegorized
Thus in the ea rly '60s, the image of Williams's heightened through a baseball player was just this insistence on the seri ous-
,'ision conjured those "ery aspirations toward what Clement pess of thi s very sense of play.
Greenberg had, at just about the same time, out lined as modern- Now the beat, or pulse, or throb I want to focus o n works
ist painting's self-critical dimensions: its participation in a mod- not only against the formal premises of modernist opticality-
ern ist culture's ambition that each of its disciplines be ra- the premises that connect the dematerialization of the visual
tionalized by being gr ou nded in its unique and separate domain field to the dilated instantaneity or peculiar timelessness of the
of exper ience, this to be achined by using the characterist ic moment of its perception-but it works as well against a further
methods of that discipline both to narrow and "to entrench it assumptio n contained in the anecdote I've just recounted. It
more firmly in its area of competence." For painting, this meant ends up challenging the notion that low art, or mass-cultural

52
"
Max Ernst. A Lilde Girl Dreams?! Takins Ihe l'ei/, 1930. From La Natu re, 1888.

practice, ca n be made to sen e th e ambiti ons of high art as a medicine, anthropology, geology, La NalUre was particularly ob-
kind of denatured accessory, the all egory of a playfuln ess that sessed with optical de,ices - the fruit of recent psycho-
high-art pract ice will ha,e no trouble recuperating and refor- physio logical resea rch. IneV itably, in these pages, the de\'ices
mulating on its own terms. important to this resear ch were lifted from the neutral confines
Thus when, in the centra l image of his 1930 collage novel, of the laboratory, to be incorporated into the condi tions of pub-
A Linle Girl Dreams if rakillB che Veil, Max Ern st places his hero- lic spectacle, as the stereoscopic slide was visualized, for in-
ine at the center of an enclosure, whi ch she calls a doyecoat but stance, in terms of a kind of scenic projection (the static fore-
whk h we recognize as the drum of a zootrope, he not o nly runner of the 3-D movie), or the limited, intimate, personal
presents us w ith a model o f ,isuality di ffe rent from that of mod- "iewing-space of the praxinoscope was enlarged and distanced to
ernism's, but associates that model Guite directly with an opti ca l fill the screen on an opposite wall.
de\'ice which was generated from and spoke to an experience of As Jonathan Crary has pointed out in his own discussions
popular cultu re. As was the case in many of the compone nts of of the archaeology of these optical de\'ices, the obvious drive
his collage noyels- this one as well as La Femme 100 ceres- the demonstrated here towards the cond iti ons of modern ci nematic
underlying element of the zootrope structu ring this image was projection should not blind us to the particular experience these
taken from the pages of the late ~ineteenth-ce ntury magazine of illustrations still make available, an experience that not only con-
popu lar science ca lled La Nacure. jures up the effects of a given illusion but also exposes to view
Demted to bringing its audi ence news of the latest exp loits the mea ns of this illusion's proc!.ucti on.2 So that the acknowl-
of tec hnology in a whole "ariet} of fie lds including enginee ring, edgement that goes on in these pages is that the spectator will

54 55
OPPOSitl' , top: Ma:..: Ernst, La Fcmm~ 100 rb~s. 1919; botto m: {rom La !ValUre. 189 1;
abo,...: rrom La No rurc, 189 1 and !882.
Max Ernst. A Liult Girl Drw1nS t/Taiins 1M \~il. 1910. From Lo NOrlm. 1888.

occupy two places simultaneously. One is the imaginary identi- to the scene of the dream as a stage on which he himself or she
fication or closure with the illusion- as we see, as if they were herself is acting, so that the dreamer is simuJtaneously protago-
unmediated, the cow grazi ng against the hallucinatory depth of nist within and viewer outside the screen of his or her own vi-
the ste reoscop ica lly distanced stream, or the bobbing gest ures of sion, is the strangely redoubled form of dream visuality that
feeding geese. The second position is a co nnect.ion to the optical Ernst wants to exploit. And so it is to a sensati on of being both
machine in questi on, an insistent reminder of its prese nce, of its inside and ou tside the zootrope that Ernst appeals in this image.
mechanism, of its form of constituting piecem ea l the on ly From ou tside the revolving drum, peering thro ugh the slits
seemingly unifi ed spectacle. This double effect, of both having as they pass rhythmica lly before our eyes, we would be presented
the experience and watching oneself have it from outs ide, of course with a succession of stationary birds performing the
characterized the late nineteenth-century fascinatio n with the majesti c flexi ng of their wings in what would appear to be the
spectacle in which there was produced a sense of being captured unifi ed image of a Si ngle fowP From the drum's inside, howeve r,
not so much by the visual itself as by what one could ca ll the the ex perience would be broken and muJtiplied, analyz.ed into its
visua lity-effect. discrete, serial components, the result of chronophotography's
Now this double vantage, occupied by these ea rly viewers record of a mechan ica l segmentati on of the conti nuity of mo-
of protO-cinematic devices, was particuJarly interesting for tio n. But uniting the exper ience of both inside and outside is the
Ernst's purposes inasmuch as the model of vis ion he was inte nt beat or pulse that cou rses through the zootropic field, the flicker
on explor ing was the pecuJiarly mediated perceptual fie ld of the of its successive images acting as the structural equiva lent of the
dream. That ex perience of the dreamer as spectator or witness flapping wings of the interi or illusion, the beat both constructing

" 59
Rasillind Krau ss I

the gestalt and undoing it at the same time-both positioning us


within the scene as its active viewer and outside it as its passive
\-\fitness.
In a ce rtain way we could think of Ernst's image as config-
uring within the specific space of the dream many of the effects
that Duchamp had in fact put into place throughout his own fif-
teen-year-Iong devotion to the turning discs of the dev ices he
co llective ly caUed Precision OpUcs. There we find the same tap-
ping into forms of mass culture- in this case both the revolving
turntable of the phonograph player and the flickering sil ence of
early film-as we also find an expli cit refe rence to the n ine-
tee nth-century optics that underwrote these form s. Further, Pre-
cision Optics bears witness to Duchamp 's commitment to the
constitution of the image through the acti vity of a beat: here,
the slow throb of a spiral, contracting and expanding bio-
rhythmi ca lly into a projection for ward and an extension bac k-
ward. An d here as we ll the pulse is accompanied by what feels
like a structural alteration of the image as it is consolidated only
continually to dissoh"e- the ill usion of t rembling breast giving
way to that of uterin e concav ity, itself then swelling into t he
proj ecting orb of a blinking eye. Yet, to speak of metamorphosis,
here, is to miss the dysmorphic condition of this pulse, which,
committed to the constant dissoluti on of the image, is at wo rk
aga inst the interests of what we could identify as form.
I ha\e, in another context , spoken about tl1e connect ion
between the pulSing nature of the dsion Duchamp constructs
and the exp liCitly erotic theater it stages - t he sexual imp li ca-
tions of the motions of these di scs ha\ ing escaped no commenta-
tor on this aspect of Duchamp's product ion. 4 I have also
described what is clearly Duchamp's conce rn here to corporeal-
ize the \ isua l, restori ng to the eye (aga inst the disem bodied op-
ticalit)' of modernist paint ing) that eye's condition as bod ily
Marcel Duchamp. Abon': Rororeliif No. I, "(oroJ/es", 1935; below:
orga n, a\ai lable like any other phYS ica l zo ne to the force of erot-
RororeliifNo. J, "Chinese Lanum', 1935. (Copyright ARS N.Y.lADAGP,
ic izati on. Dependent on the connect ion of the eye to the whole 1988)

60
THE 1M/ P ULS E T O SEE

pli city of a child's toy. That the t wo elements in the sculpture


are ex tremely ge nital is as obvious here as it had been in the
case of Ducham p's Rorore1ieJs. But what is less easy to assert is
the ge nder identity of either form . So that the osciUation figured
in the work through the back-and -forth of its rhythmic arc op-
erates as a tempo ral analogue to the shifting undec idability of its
definiti on of male and female, the sculpture thus asserting itself
as a machine geared to the co Uapse of sexual difference. And as
thi s little guillotine of castration works once again in relation to
a beat, its pulse can be seen to be operating ill a way that is
deeply inimical to the stability and self-evidence of form , to the
permanence-we could say-of the good gesta lt.
Alberto Giacomc n i. Sus~nJ~J &//. 1930- 3 1. two "iews. Ku nstmuseum Basel. If the gestalt operates as a kind o f absolute in the held of
(Copyright ARS N.Y.lADAGP. 1988) vision, as the principle of concordance between difference and
Simultaneity-that is, the simultaneous separatio n and intactness
network of the body's tissue, this force wells up within the den- of figure and ground - the beat could , from the point of view of
sity and thi ckness of the carnal being, as, tied to the conditions a modern ist logiC, never be anything more than an interloper
of nervous life, it is by definitio n a functi on of temporality, For 'from the domain of the temporal, the auditory, the discursive. A
the life of neryous tissue is the life of time, the alternating pulse fun cti on of time and of succession, this beat would be something
of stimulation and enervation, the complex feedback relays of re- that modernism had solemnly legislated out of the visual domain ,
tension and protension. So that the temporal is mapped onto the asserting a separation of the se nses that will aJways mean that
figural in the space of Duchamp's Precision Optics as the specifi c the temporal ca n ne\'e r disrupt the visual from within, but only
beat of desire - of a desire that makes and loses its object in one assault it from a position that is necessarily outside, external , ec-
and the same gesture, a gesture that is continua lly losing what it centric. Yet the power of the works that interest me here -in
has found because it has only found what it has already lost. their contestation of what modernism had constructed as " the
To the exampl es of Ernst and Duchamp a third instance visual " - is that thi s beat or pulse is not understood to be struc-
might be added , if o nly to gain a sense of the way this figuration turally distinct from vision but to be at work from deep inside
of a pulse functioned rather widely within the '20s and '30s as it. And from that place, to be a force that is transgressive of
an alternative to or protest against the claims of modernist op- those \'e ry notio ns of "distinctness" upon whi ch a modernist op-
ticality to have both abstracted vision and rationalized form . I tical logic depends. The beat itself is, in thi s sense, figural-but
am thinking of the sculpture by Giacometti called Suspended Ball, of an order of the figure that is fa r away from the realm of space
where the work is organized around the pendular motion of an that ca n be neatly opposed to the modality of time.
orb rhythmically sliding over the recumbent form of a wedge, To discover and theo rize this order is part of the task Jean-
the construction as a whole cast in terms of the anodyne sim- Fran~o i s Lyotard set himself in the work Discours, HaUTe. There

62 II
Rosalind Krauss I THE 1M/PULS E TO SEE

he argued that below the "seen" order of the image (that is, the consciwril:e illlermls c1 discourse, and the rransBression if rhe constiw-
object bounded by its contour) and below the '\'isible but un- rire distances C?f representacion. 7
seen" order of the gestalt, which we could ca ll the formal cond i-
tions of possibility of yisualizing the object, there lies the order T he third feature of the matrix is its formal conditi on as rlwthm
of the "i nYis ible," to which Lyotard giYcs the name marrix. 5 or pulse, a conditio n that might seem to push the matrix Ol;t of
Belonging to the unconsciolls, the matri x is the form of the the realm of the figural altogether and into that of time. That it
primary process as it operates ilwisibly, behind the constra ints of does not do so will beco me eddent from the example of the ma-
tri x that Lyota rd su bmits to analvsis.
, 8
repression, such that only its fantasmatic products e,'er surface
onto the field of the ,'isible. The matri x can, then, o nly be in- ~ "A Child Is Being Beaten" was the description gi,'en to
ferred , only be reconstructed from the figuration provided by Freud by se"cra l patients who located this as an obsess ional
fantasy. But as such the matrix can be seen to possess certa in erotic fantasy.'} As we know, all that analysis could draw fr~m
qualities. First, it inmh-cs a spatiality that is unassimilable to the the particular patient Freud descr ibes was another, more primi-
coord inates of ex ternal space: for in this space of the uncon- ti,'c ,'crsion of the fantasy, enunciated as "The father beats the
sciolls, Lyotard remarks, "places are not panes exrra panes; the child," In relation to this latter statement the only added infor-
interval s required for example in the perceptual order for things mation was that here the child the father was beating was not
of the external world to he recognizable and for them not to pi le the patient herself, but another child; and as for the patient , she
up on one another-depth in short -or, in terms of phe- \\'as stationed as witness. There are se,'eral senses in which ein
nomenological transcendence, negat ion- here these inten 'als are Kind lI'ird Besch/agen sen 'es Lyota rd as a matrix figure. One of
abandoned. "6 But this condit ion of super impositi on and simulta- them is the total im'isi bility of one of its key terms, one that lay
neous presence means that the matrix, e,'en though it possesses so deeply repressed that it had to be ex trapolated or recon-
featu res we identify with the nature of the structural order- structed by Freud. This is that phase of the fantasy whi ch, as it
namely i1wisibility and synchrony-ca nnot be understood in were, puts its erot ic spin on it, ilwesting it with both its exci te-
terms of structure. Fo r the matrix does not order and regulate ment and its anxi ety. It is the phase that the patient nne r artic-
difference, maintaining opposi ti ons in a rul e-gove rned system ; ulated but which Freud vcntri l0'l uized as " I am being beaten by
the father,"
rather, it courts the transformation of e,'erything into its op-
posite, thereby underm in ing the producti"e work of struct ure. But it is preCisely from the perspecth'e of th at intermedi-
So that its second feature is that the elements of the matrix "do ary phase-the one between "the fath er beats the child" and "a
not form a system but a block"; child is being beaten" - that the multiple transmutations at work
in the producti on of the fa ntasy become apparent: the trans-
if the macri" is invisible, ir is nor because it orises fro m the intelligible, mutation fr om acti"c to passive-as beating turn s into being
bur because ir resides in a space lhal is beyond (he intelhaible, is in
beaten; the transmutati on in the field of the subject -as specta-
radical rupture lI'ilh the rules if opposirion . 1r is its characrerisric tor turns into \'ict im; the transmutation in lib idinal zo ne-as
to ho\'e man)' places in one place, and rhey block together whal is nO! genitality re"erts to anality; the transmutation in the contents of
compossible. This is the secrer if che fisuraJ: the transBression cf the the drive- as sadism changes to masochism. And it is this work

.. 6S
Rosalind Krauss I THE ! M/PUL.S!: TO SE E

of o,eriaying contradiction , of creating the simultaneity of in - trix fig ure'S fantasized gesture of a spanking that is also a ca ress
compossible situati ons, that Lyotard identifies as the action of can be mapped ; for it is this form that can represent the rhyth-
the matrix. If it is a matrix, Lyotard maintains, it is because mic oppositions between contact and rupture. But Lyotard cau-
tions that, unlike a pulse whi ch is understood in terms of a law
che SIOlcmenlS one can dccermine there which orBanize ,he Bool (to
of repetition, a principle of recurrence guaranteeing as it were
beal). {he source (the anal zone), and {he object (the father) if one that an "on" will always follow an "off," this pulse inyoh-cs the
senrence, are in their cum condensed inca a sinBle producc:formula-
constant threat of interruption. The anxiety that is part of the
'1\ ch ild is beina beaten" - whose apparenc coherence aJ/olI's ,he psy-
affect of "A Child Is Being Beaten," combining with its erot ic
chic life 1.0 contain in a sinale manifold a multiplici t), if incompossible pleasure, arises preC isely from the force of rupture that is recur-
"sentences. " These do not form a syscem bur a block. Thus ,he drive (0
re nt in the rhythm of the figu re, a rupture whi ch is not experi-
be and to nal'e ,he fa cher is simulcaneous; and the in vestment is bach
enced as the o nset of yet another contact, but as an absolute
aenical-phaJlic and sadistic-anal.]O
break, that discontinuity without end that is death. Thus it is the
The matrix's invisibility is secured, then, by the very ac- death driYe, operating below the pleasure principle, that trans-
tivity of the changes it produces, of the constant nonidentity of codes this rhythm -as it beats with the alternation behveen
its component parts. Yet the product of the matrix is an obses- pleasu re and extinction-into a compulsion to repeat. The ma-
sional fantasy, a recurrence ,vhich, in each of its repetit ions, is trix is, then, the fonn that figures recurrence.
the sa me. And this leads Lyotard to ask how this identity is se- The beating of the zootrope, cranking up to speed, the
cured since at the le\el of the fantasy's contents there is nothing beating of the gull 's wings within the imaginary space, the beat-
that is maintained as stable. To thi s he replies that its identity is ing of all those mechanical devi ces through whi ch the real ap-
formal. "The fantasmatic matrix ," he says, " is eV iden tly a pears to burst into life fro m the shards of the inorgan ic and
'form.'" Yet the diffi culty of thinking this produce r of disorder deathly still , and the parti cular form of the pleasure connected
and disruption as a form is obv ious. "How in ge neral ," Lyotard to that rhythm, became, as I have been claiming, a particular re-
asks, "can that which is form also be transgression? How can source for artisti c pract ice. Focused Simultaneously on the un-
what is dedation , derogation, deconstructi on, be at the same conscious ground or that pleasure and on its media-rorm , whi ch
time form ?"ll The answer he finds is in the ev idence of a form is to say its relation to mechankal reproduction, the artists I've
that is not a good form, not a good gesta lt. Rather, as he shows, been speaking or were concerned, although not all equally so,
"it is a form in which desire remains caught, form caught by with the vehi cles of mass culture.
transgression; but it is also the, at least potential, transgression The analysis of the gesture into its incremental d isplace-
of form ."I! ments, as the same stati c form is slowly maneuvered along the
This form . which is that of on/off on/ofT on/off, is the alter- page of the animation stand; the mechanical process of creating
nati ng charge and di scharge of pleasure, the OSci llating presence the minute variations that can be jerked into motion by their
and absence of contact, the rhythm "in whose regularity the passage through the camera's gate or by the e\en cruder riRing
subject's unconsc ious is, so to speak, 'caught,' the formal matrix of pages in the common Aipbook-all this, as a resource of the
of both dreams and symptoms." It is onto this fo rm that the ma- beat, seems mil es away from that wholly different high-art prac-

67
"
THE 1M / PULSE: TO SEE

is to see the way they fun ctioned as the armatures for a peculi ar
kind of pictorial production: the spinning out o f hundreds of
"preparatory studies" through which the given compositi on
could be thought to be vari ed over the time of the artist's cre-
ative attention, sustain ing and tracki ng the bursts of his imagina-
tive energy. This is of course the way these studi es have been
descr ibed in the unbearably sycophanti c literature on Picasso, as
in the following passage where Douglas Cooper discusses the
sketches leading toward one of Picasso's versio ns of the Dej euner
sur l'herbe:

DuritlB the three days from the 7th to the IOlh ofJuljr Picasso gave
himself up to a period of incense creoUI'e work on ehe Dejeuner. In
that shore rime he drew no less than 28 new compositional swdies-
18 of them in one day - and exewled a second de.ftnitire I'arialian in
PA blo I)icuso. L~ Dljeunu sur /,htr~ d'apris Monel, july 10, 1961 . SualSga le ri e oils. Th ese draWings reveal e"en more chan chose which preceded them
Stullgarl. (Co pyright ARS N.Y./SPAD EM , 1988)
the concentration of [Picasso's] thou8 hr. . .. Here we see him workins
tice of what we think of as the creative generation of variati ons
with the fe n 'our and conscientiousness of a Cezanne. We fi nd him re-
pearedljr correa ina himself and slauina o8ain . . .. Th inas are changed
on a theme. But I would like to turn to this practi ce of \'aria-
around ever so sliahtly [as] an arm or a lea will be mOi'ed Jor ehe sake
tion, and to the assumption (which is the operative notion of the
of the aenerol desi8n.
art historian) that, witrun the age of mechanical reproducti on,
variati on-as resource of voluntary repetition, the outpouring of And, Cooper co ncludes this description, as though we had here
the controll ed play of difference- is secured against the rhyth- to do with the compositional study or bozzeto as it had ex isted
mic pull of the heat. fr om the time of the Renaissance, "So much for the actua l draw-
W ith in twent ieth-century art Pi casso is perhaps the great ings- many of them masterly-and the role they were called on
practiti oner of the theme and variation. Indeed we could say that to play. . " 13
the who le last peri od of his productio n, which is to say his But what arc these actual draWings- eighteen of which
work's final two decades, is structured around the \'ariations he Picasso was able to produce in just one day?
did on old-master paintings -the Femmes d'A lger, the Meniiias, The sketchbooks Picasso fi lled in the two-and-a-ha lf years
the Raphael and the Fornarina, the Dejeuner sur I'herbe. To speak of of his work on the Dijeuner, each page carefull y maintained in
its being structured around these older works is not just to ac- se'luence by its meticulous dating and numbering, are produced
knowledge the way that these pictures- by Delacroix, Velazquez, in the manner of the animation stand, as the draWing on each
Ingres, Manet - provided Picasso \vith the compositi onal ideas page -incised into its soft, thi ck paper with sharp penci led
he no longe r seemed able to derive from life. More than that, it lines- embosses its co ntours into the page below it, that new

" "
Rosalind Krauss I

page etching its own configuration into the succeed ing level of
the sketchbook, and so on. The mode of production Picasso
adopts here is not that of the successive upsurge of renewed in -
spiration but that of the mechanically reproduced series, each
member of which sustains those minute variations that seem to
animate the group as a whole. But this animation is not on the
order of the old organic metaphor applied to compositional uni-
ties. It is an animation that relates to the production of cartoon
draWings. And indeed in the explorat ion of successive layers of
the seCJuence-as peeling them back one fro m the next we see
the tiny anatomi ca l shifts and swellings-we have the impression
not so much of watching an idea in de,'elopment as of observing
gesture in motion. Thus CJuite unexpectedly, we feel ourselves to
be in the presence of a Aipbook.
Much of the energy expended by Pi casso's admirers, when
speaking of these compositions based on the work of others, is
focused on extr icating the master from the toils of the origi-
nal-insisting that he is not caught in the trap of the earlier
modeL "A painter of genius," Coope r assures us, "seems to have
the capacity to surrender voluntarily to inspirat ion deriving
from another work of art and then, escaping from it, find his
imaginati ve strength renewed and capable of projecting an image
of his own."]4 T his discussion of surrender and capture, even
though it is ahvays cl imaxed by reassurances about the artist's
freedom, betrays, I would say, a kind of anxiety about Pi casso's
enterprise in these works, even while it utterly mistakes the na-
ture of the "su rrender" involved, Fo r the surrender of the art-
ist's imagination, the place in which it is caught by being given
over to pleasure, is the functio n of a voluptuous passivity: the
mechanism of the se rial animation of the Aipboo k's beat,
Nowhere is this voluptuous succumbi ng to th e unconscious
productivity of the device clearer than in the sketchbook Picasso
made as a kind of climax towards which all the others were
leading, the sketchbook of August 2, 1962, which both Cooper P~hlo Picas~o. Stud ies for L~ Dijeul1er sur I'huk J'Optts AJanel. Ahon'; April 7. 1961. I;
below: AprIl 7, 1961 , II. (Copyrighl ARS N.Y.lSPADEM, 1988)

10
T HE !M / P U LS!!: TO SEE

and Ze rvos thought it best not to reproduce,ls Here the erotic


im'cstment in the scene is made as expli cit as possible, as
through nine successiye pages the orgiastic subtext of the
Dejeuner is enacted, the important variati ons within this repeated
appear ance and di sappearance of the scene being the migration
of the actors' genitals to vari ous sites on their bodies,
The monstrance of the ge nitals w ithin this matrix of the
Hipbook form ca n, moreover, be seen to be what much of the
preceding two hundred sketches had been preparing for, Cooper
speaks of Pi casso's long-held fasc ination with the figure of the
woman bending ove r and seen from above- bending to tie her
sandal, to d ry herself, or as here, to bathe. In the Dejeuller se-
Guence he sees her presence as the nub of the matter for
Picasso, whether or not her scale is reduced in relation to the
others, And indeed the figure viewed in this posit ion is, as
Robert Rosenblum Signaled in his article on the anatom), of
Pi casso's erotic ism, vulnerable to the transmutation that Picasso
repeatedly performs on it, whether we look at the keening Mag-
dalene from the CrucifiXion or the bather from the Dejeuner. 16
The female head , bent to project below the breasts, submits
again and again to the same transformatio n, as it is recast as
phallic signifi er, the stand-in - mapped onto the nose and hair o f
the femal e face-for the genitals of an absent male.
That Picasso should have pursued this image ove r many
years, that he should ha,'c had frequent and spectacular recourse
to the depi ction of sexual acts, could lead one to object that he
ce rtain ly did not need the Aipboo k structure for permi ss ion to
,'e nt the erotic turn of his imaginatio n, And I would ag ree that
he di d not need it. But I think that as at the end of his life it be-
came the medium of his acti vit)', he did indeed become caught
in its mechanism, his art becoming more and morc a function of
its pulse, And so though he did not need it he yielded to it, to
the appeal of pure recurrence, to the seduction and the content
I'ahlo I'ica~so, Studks for L~ Dljcllncr sur /'hcrlx d'opris II-lone!. AIm"t': F(,' hruar~' 8,
of an endless pulse. The mechanically repeated and the eroti cally
1962, I; F(,'hruar~' 8, 1961, II. (l'op~' ri ght ARS N,Y.lSPADEM , 1988)

"
Rosalind Krauss f THE IM/PUL.SE TO SEE

enacted seemed to have trapped him , and he c reated the meta- Notes
phors of this capture. In 1964 he made some ce ramic tiles on
I. Clement Greenberg, "Modernist Painting," in The Ne'" ATf. ed. Gregory
each of which a priapic sat),r pursues a nymph with the repeti - Hancock (New York : Dutton, 1966), p. 107.
tive exactitude a template provides. He was showi ng Hele ne 1. Jonathan Crary, "Techniques of the Obsen e r," DC/abet. no. 45 (Summer
Parmeiin the dozen or so examples he had made and he asked 1988).

her, "Wouldn't it be pretty to have entire rooms tiled like that?" 3. The zootrope illustration Ernst uses here appears in an article on Jean-
Etienne Marcy's chronophotographic recording of a bird in Right, from which
She includes this re mark in a section of her book titl ed " Picasso,
three.dimensional models were eventually constructed. See La Nawrc ( 1988): 12.
th e Moralist."17 4. See my "The Blink of an Eye," forthcoming in Na wre. Sian. and Ins/illl/ians in
"Picasso, the Moralist" could be the subtitle of almost Ihe Domain if" Discourse. cd . Program in Crit ical Theory, University of Ca lifornia
e\'ery book on Pi casso over the past fifty years, bringing to us (In'inc: University of California Press).
5. J ean Fran ~oi s LyolJrd, Discours. Fi9ure (Paris: Editions Klincksieck, 197 1),
o,'e r and oyer again the message of art's assurance about volun-
p. 283.
tarism, intentiona lit)', and freedom. No one liste ns to Picasso 6. Ibid . p. 338.
himself as he speaks, in all innocence, of the way he is possessed 7. Ibid. , p. 339.
by the disposic!f he has co nstructed. Acknmvledging t hat "with 8. The analysis of this fantasy is conducted under the chapter head ing "Fiscou rs
Digure," ibid., pp. 327-354.
the variations on the old maste rs [Picasso] systematizes the pro-
9. Sigmund Freud. "A Child Is Being Beaten" (1919), in Sewolil), cmd Ihe I's)"chol.
cess; the work is the e nsemble of the ca m'ases on the same
08Y if" Lort. ed. Philip Rieff (New York: Collier Books, 1963).
theme and each o ne is onl), a link of the whole, a suspended 10. Lyotard, pr. 338-339.
moment of c reation," one of the writers on this phase of hi s I I. Ibid., p. 349.
12. Ibid., p. 350.
work quotes him saying that what interests him "is the move-
13. Douglas Cooper, Pablo Picasso; Lt:s Dijeuners (New York: Harrv N. Abrams.
ment of painting, the dramatic push of one vision to the nex t,
1963). p. 19.
eyen if the push is not forced to its conclusion ... I have arrived 14. Ibid., p. 23 .
at the point where the movement of my thought interests me 15. The sketchbook is catalogued as no. 165, in Je suis Ie (a hicr: The SkClchbooks if"
more than my thought itself." 18 The passiv ity of this inte rest Pablo Picasso, ed. Arnold Glimcher and Marc Glimcher (Boston: Atlantic Monthly
Press, 1986), where two images from this sequence are illustrated.
comes out in another remark, where he says, " I make a hundred
16. Robert Rosenblum, "Picasso and the Anatomy of Eroticism," in Swdles in
studies in seve ral days , while another painter might spend a Erolic Arl. ed. Theodore Bowie and Cornelia V. Christenson (New York: Basic
hundred days on a Single picture. In co ntinuing. I will open Hooks, 1970), figu re 198.
windows. I w ill get behind the canvas and perhaps something 17. Hele ne Parmelin, Picasso; The ArtiSI and His Modd (New York: Harry N.

w ill happe n." 19 "Quelque c hose," he says, "se produira." The Abrams, n.d.), p. 153.
18. Marie-Laure Hernaclac, " Picasso, 1953-1973: La peinture commc modele,"
w indow wi ll open and something will happen before the eyes of
in Le dernier Picasso (Paris: Musee National d'Art Mode rne, 1988), p. 49.
the pa.inter who is caught there, fascinated - like the Wolf Man 19. This remark is used. although to support a wholly different argument, by
for whom the window opens onto that beyond whe re something Douglas Cooper, La IUjl!uflt:rJ. p. 33. It originally appeared in Roland I>cnrose,
takes place, as it di splays for him the matrix-figu re of a scene in Picasso (Paris: Aammarion), p. 47.

whi ch he will be, for the rest of his life, entrapped.

14
75
DISC U SSION

way in which they set up a rhythm. He doesn't want this idea to


leak out into the temporal and so once again set up a modernist
condition of separate domains.
Jonotban Crary In your thinking about this idea of the pulse or Now as for the mu sical analogy: one could th ink of twelve-
beat, did you consider neoimpress ionism and the possibility that tone compositio n in terms of the figura l, that is, in terms of a
that perception of organized color contrasts involved some kind structure that has the potential of a sim ultaneity or overlaying
of oscillation or temporal beat? Or is such work within the do- that is con nected to fig urality. But that's just a guess.
main of the purely optical?
Jacqueline Rose There seems to me to be an interesting difference
Rosalind Krauss In fact I didn't consider it. But this is interesting: between concepts like "beat," "pulse," " throb," and "matrix,"
Duchamp hated retinal art, yet when he talked about it -always and the following-through of the stages of fantasy in "A Child Is
to belittle it-he wanted to exempt two artists who he thought Being Beaten." How do these concepts work together, or is
might otherwise be confused with it. One was Mondrian, the there a tension between them?
other was 5eurat. The Mondrian part I can understand, but the
Seu rat part has always mystified me-and you haye just ex- Krauss I assume you are referring to the temporality of the nar-
plained it. rative reconstruction of the fantasy . Now Lyotard insists on the
very figurative compactness of this fantasy, which doesn't seem
Martin Joy I have a question concerning a musical parallel to the to include a narrator or an agent of the beating-and it is even
beat or pulse. During the modernist period there is a move away vague about the nature of the child. That compacted block,
from theme and variation towards a stress on rhythm; one which is then reconstructed according to its contradktory, shift-
thinks of StraYi nsky in part icular. One might argue that this is ing components, creates a parado;x, one which is not containab le
the replacement of one type of musica l form by another type, within the field of vision or three-dimensional space. It is a
and to this extent perhaps the moye towards rhythm or pulse in Auid, amorphic, even dysmorphic thing.
,isual terms is not so much a cr itique of fo rm per se as it is an
introduction of a different model of form , already there in mu- Rose This touches on a tension which see ms to be present in
sic, which is temporal; and this is somewhat different from the the work of Lyotard between concepts like "discourse" and " fig-
absolute breakdown of form which one finds perhaps in atonal ure" on the one hand, and "libidinal economy" on the other.
music. So is there a way to conceptualize this in terms not of The concept of libidinal economy seems to me available for an
rhythm as opposed to form but of rhythm as a different type almost phYSiologica l account of the substrata of conscious per-
of form? ception and identity. And that's where words like pulse, throb,
etc., could then he pulled in the direction of concepts like that
Krauss When Lyotard talks about rhythm in his discussion of the of the "semiotic" in Julia Kristeva's work. In short, there is a
matrix, he insists that it is flaura! - not a temporal rhythm . For kind of lyricism to what we oppose to the dominant psychic
example, he thinks about patte rns of columns on a facade, the trope. Whereas what struck me in your example of "A Child Is

16 71
GENERAL DISCUSSION

Being Beaten!> is that there is always al ready a fantasy in place,


so that e\'en jf we try to put ourseh'es outside a certain visual
register we sti ll call up fo rms of non identification whi ch are
nonetheless positi onaliti es. Now whatever one wants to say Audience (Bernard Flynn) I have a question fo r Martin Jay. I was
about that (and I ag ree with you that it's not the same form of somewhat surprised that you see Descartes as the initiator of a
narrative structure), I don't think. that account is available for the regime of the visual. It seems to me that his tex ts could be read
idealizati on that goes o n within certain other concepts of what a just as well in a radically, mi litantly antivisual sense. Think of
what becomes of the piece of wax in the Meditation: all the in-
matrix might be.
formation that one gets through the senses is fa lse, is never re-
instated ___And even in the Optics, in his theory of perspect ive (as
Merleau -Ponty reads it in "The Eye and the Mind"), one doesn't
see anything at all , one judges. The mind may survey the brain
and then generate a perspective-effect-but not really by sig ht
so much as by mathemati cal judgment. In fact , Descartes even
uses the metaphor of the text: that one reads the brain.

Martin Jay This is an excellent question; it gives me an oppor-


tunity to clarify the dimension of the visual in Descartes. One
could say the same thing about Plato: that he too was hostile to
the illusions of the senses and was anxious to defend the alterna-
ti ve of the mind 's eye. Cartesian ism contains thi s dualism as
well, for Descartes also gives us a critiqu e of the illusions of ob-
servation. But in its place he prov ides a noti on of the mind as
visually constituted. For Descartes the mind contains "clear"
and " distinct" ideas, and clarity and distinctness are essentially
visua l terms. Moreover, the mind perceives natural geometry,
which is commensurate with the geometry that underli es our ac-
tua l empir ical Sight. Descartes believes in the commensurability
of these two realms (which I could also characteri ze in terms of
two notions of light, luminous rays or lux and perceived lumen);
it enables him to argue that inventions like the telescope are val-
uable because they show us visual experience which is commen-
surate with that of natural geometry.

78
"
GENERAL D I SCUSSION

Now the issue of judgment, thc issuc of the tex t, is also modern conception of madness as abnormal and the Renaissance
,c ry interesting. It relates to the point I madc ea rlier regarding conception of madness as a marvel or a monstrosity from an-
the semantic dimension of ,ision. You arc right: Descartes uses other world. So when Martin talks about uthe madness of see-
rhetori cal and lingui sti c exp lanations that take us away from a ing" (10 folje du mir) and suggests, a la Chri stine Buci-
purely imagistic noti on of the mind's eye or of actual eyes. But it Glucksmann. that this is a reactualization of a baroque vision, J
is almost always done in the sen ' ice of a st rong notion of mental am not sure I agree. The baroque did not possess our category
representation where onc sees (as he puts it) "with a clear men of the abnormal, and our visual irrationality (i nfluenced by the
tal gaze." So what 15 at issue is neither actual empiri ca l obscna paradigm that Jonathan sketched) is a different sort of thing. So
tion (which Merl eau-f}onty, with his emphasis on the body and perhaps it is not a reactuali7..ation so much as a rethinking of
binocular vis ion, wants to restore), nor is it an enti rely rhetori- "the madness of seeing" in terms of our own rationality of the
ca l, semanti c, judgmental, or linguisti c altcrnati,c. It is a third abnormal. (To see it in thi s way, inCidentally, would give us a
model, which again I think is parallel to the Platonic traditi on of different perspecth'e from the kind of phobia about irrationality
mental representation-of the mind 's eye, of the purity of an that comes from Ju rgen Habermas.) Isn't there some kind of
optics which is outside actual experience. clash between these sor ts of histor),?

Audience (John Ralchmanl I have a question for both Jonathan and Jay Your point that Buci-G lucksmann co nst ructs a baroque "i-
Martin. J was impressed by your remarks, Jonathan, and I was sion for her own purposes is a valid one, but I think she has also
espec ially interested in the inAuence of Foucault upon them. reco,ercd an attitude which is more pOsitive about "madness."
Your use of Foucault is very different fr om o ne which presents ObViously her interpretati on is deeply imbued with contempo-
him as a denig rator of ,ision, as Mart in has in another context rary concerns-one hears Lyotard , Lacan, and other recent
rUIn the Empire of the Gaze: Foucault and the Denigratio n of thinkers on every page - so it is not simply an historical
Vision in Twentieth-Century French Though,t," in Foucau1r: A account.
Crieical Reader, cd. David Hoy]. It is a Foucault who is more con- Now as for the two registers of madness: 10 folie du voir is a
ce rned with "e\ents" of the \isual. term that has been around for a while (Michel de Certeau also
Foucault argued, of course, that abno rmality or dev iati on is wrote about it). In thi s sense madness is seen as ecstatic, con-
a central category in our modern pe.riod , espec ially when it nected to jouissance, as not constraining. My Habermasian note at
comes to mad ness. (As Jonathan has mentioned-and Georges the end was to suggest that " madness" is neither good nor bad
Ca nguilhem talks about this too-Fechner and Helmholtz con- but is a category we need to problematize. This may require a
ceived vision in terms of the normal and the abnormal , and of return to a noti on that Foucault would find problemati c, but it
course they wcre read by Freud. In fact, in Beyond che Pleasure ,cems to me that he also teaches us to be wary of any return to ) ~
Principle, I belie,c there arc references to both Fechne r and the body. For ~ult, of course, the body is constituted cul-
Helmholtz.) For Foucault there is a great differe nce between this ~ally and historically; therefore we are forced once again to

" 81
GENERAL O I SCUS S ION

-
think about its implications rather than accept it as a sol id
g round or as some antidote to the false-decorporealization of
vision.
fills these pages are endless sketches, and no one (as far as I
know) has mentioned that they are done in an animation-stand
manner where the trace of the image etched onto the page be-
low is used to produce the next image and so on. That process
Jonathan Crary I just want to c.Iarify something. For me the im- interests me very much-its mechanical nature, the passivity of
portance of Helmholtz and Fechner for Freud has to do less Picasso before this process (which in a sense was stronger than
with delineating the normal and the abnormal than with a ce r- he). So the whole discussion of eroti~s in late Picasso, of
tain mode l of an economy of energy. T hi s is interesting in terms whether he was a dirty old man or a voyeur, is irrelevant to
of the positi on of physiology in relation to other sciences in the what we are in fact watching, which is a feeble attempt to erect
nineteenth century. Perhaps the Single most impo rtant achi e\'e- eros in defense aga inst what was really happening to him -
ment of Helmholtz was his work on the conservati on of energy; which was death.
but he began as a med ical student and phYSiologist, and it was
through his study of animal heat that he e"entually arrived at his Audience So there is no distance on his part from his activity?
the rmodynamic formulations. O ne of the tasks of phYS iology in
the 1840s was the refutation of vitalism, the idea that somehow Krauss None. I think he had absolutely no distance.
li\'ing beings operated by \'irtue of their own unique "ital force.
fn this sense, phYSiology was an enterprise of making the body Krauss I have a questi on for Martin, one that relates to John
eqUivalent to and exchangeable with other apparatuses and ma- Rajchman's. I am not sure that seventeenth-century visual re-
chines. Thus Helmholtz, throughout his career, was to describe a gimes can be mapped quite so directly onto late nineteenth- and
human subject that works, produces, and sees within a process of early twentieth-centu ry practices, Are these weak homologies,
mu scular work, combustion of energy, and release of heat ac- or just totally different phenomena? Take your examp le of the
cording to empirica lly verifiable la\.vs. What was important was modernist grid and the map presented by Svetlana Alpers as a
how the body was rendered continuous with its fi eld, making model for seventeenth-century Dutch painting. T he modern ist
obsolete that split between outside and inside which defined a grid is tremendously different from this cartologic g rid, for the
classica l observer. modern ist g rid is reAex.ive: it maps the surface onto which it is
prOjected; its co ntent is that surface itself. A map is not doing
Audience I have a question for Rosalind Krauss. Do you make a that: its content comes from elsewhere; it has nothing to do
distinction between the picture-making activity of an ar tist like with the reAexiye model.
Picasso and his psychiC reality? Do they operate as opposite Another instance is the anamorphic image. Now the
po les or do they ha\'e a mimetic relationship? opaCity that is figured in anamorphosis is a matter of point of
view: one ca n see the image correctly if one can get to the cor-
Rasalind Krau ss In the twenty-thre'e -yolume Oeuvres of Pi casso, rect position. Whereas the invisibility that arises within mod-
thirteen of those yolumes are demted to his last period. What ernism is not so obv iously physical: it is tinged or affected by

82
"
GENERAL DISCUSSION

the unconscious, and in this unconscious invisibility there isn't Finally. as to the Buci-Glucksmann argument: I would
any correct perspective or other vantage point. It can only be agree that one has to take it with a grain of salt; it is written
reconstructed in the modality of a different form like language. I from the perspective of the 1980s, it is not purely an historical
think that's a weak metaphoric use of the idea of anamorphosis. exercise. But I think it helps us to see a potential for another
You seem to accept this Buci-Glucksmann hypothesis; I would vision already there in the Western tradition , even during the
think that as an historian you would not. heyday of Cartesian perspectivalism. It allows us to see what
jacqueline Rose calls "the moment of unease" which is latent but
Joy I share the willingness to problematize these linkages; let now perhaps rediscovered in that tradition- even if ..\Ie have
me see what this might mean in these two cases. First with the partly concocted it as well.
grid. What Alpers tells us is that whereas the p erspectival grid
is wholly different from the modernist grid, the cartographic
grid (""hich is also prese nt in seventeenth-century Dutch art) is
a way-station to the modernist one. It is halfway because it in-
sists not on an illusory reproducti on of an external reality but
rather on a Sign-ordered transfiguration of it. So already there is
a kind of conventionality to this grid, an awareness of the neces-
sity of a mode that is not simply mimetic. And to that extent
maybe it does point the way to a fully nonmirnetic twentieth-
century g rid.
As for anamorphosis, a satisfactory response would require
going into some detail. In his discussion of Sight in The Four
Fundamental Concepts if P~cho-analysis, Lacan is fascinated by the
idea of anamorphi c vision, as is Lyotard in Discours, Fig ure (sig-
nifi cantly, both use the Holbein painting The A mbassadors, with
its anamorphi c skull , on their title pages). In Lacan's discussion
\ ", of vision one gets a sense of crossed visual e.xperi ences, whi ch is
what anamorphi c vision, if seen in tensio n with straightfor\vard
vision, gives us. So to that extent it helps us understand the
complexiti es of a visual register which is not planimetri c but
whi ch has all these compli cated scenes that are not reducible to
any one coherent space .

. 85
NDrman Brvson

THE GAZE IN THE EXPANDED FIELD


.". In this paper I wi ll be examining a term that has become impor-

1 tant in contemporary discussions of painting and of visuality: Je


reBard, "the Gaze." First of all I will do what I can to trace the
concept of the Gaze as it passes from Sartre to Lacan, from
Sartre's description of the Gaze of the other in Being and Norh-
<

ingness to Lacan's reworking of that description in the first two


secti ons of The Four Fundamental Concepts '!f Psycho-analysis. To
some this w ill be familiar territory. to others it will be less fa-
miliar; I will do my best to proceed as clearly as I can. But once
that account of Je resa,d, the Gaze, is stated I want to move to
what may seem at first Sight a quite unconnected account of vi-
sion, the one that emerges in the meditation o n Western phi-
losophy conducted in Japan principally by Kitaro Nishida and
then by Nishida's student Keiji Nishitani. The reason I wish to
invoke Nishida and Nishitani is that their theoretica l develop-
ment seems in many respects to go further than Sartre and
lacan towards a radical reformulation of our thought on visu-
ality, and as a consequence of this our thought on painting.
My argument 'w ill be that the line of thinking that passes
from Sartre to Lacan in crucial respects remains held within a
conceptual enclosure, where vision is still theorized from the
standpoint of a subject placed at the center of a world. Although
that centralized subject is progressively dismantled by Sar tre and
Lacan-and the direction of their thought is unmistakeably to-
wards a radical decentering of the subject-there seem to me to
Figure 1. Jiun. The charact('r "Man."
be areas in which the standpoint of the subject as center is actu-

87
MormDn Bryson I THE GA ZE IN T H E EXPANDED "I ELD

aUy retained; the resu lt of that resid ual centering upon the watcher's solitary domain there enters another, whose intrusion
standpoint of the subject is that ~ is portrayed as menaced brea ks the peace and fract ures the watcher's self-e nclosure. The
at that vestigial center, threatened fro m without, and in some watcher is in t urn watched: obspr \'ed of all obse n -ers, the \'iewe r
sense persecured, in the visua l domain, by the reBord or Gaze. The becomes spectacle to another's Sight. Now all the li nes of force
direct ion of thought that passes from Nishida to Nishitan i un- whi ch had conve rged on the center of the watcher's li\'ed hori-
der takes a much more thoroughgoing displacement of the sub- zon t urn , re\'erse, and reconve rge on the space of the intruder
ject in the field of vision, which fi nds expression in a te rm so far and h is irruption, Before, all of the pe rspecti ve lines had run in
largely neglected in the Western d iscussion of visuality, fiin)'ouJ, fro m the ho rizon towards the watcher in the park; now another
translated as " blankness," "emptiness," or " nihi lity." The con- perspective ope ns up . and the lines of Right race away from the
cept of bl ankness, as it evolves in the thought of Nishi da and watcher self to meet this new point of entry, Fo r the intruder
then of Nishitani , relocates the Gaze, Ie reoord, in an expanded himse lf sta nds at his own center of things, and draws towards
field where a number of conceptua l transformations become and into himself everything he sees; the watcher self is now a
necessa ry and urgent: notably concern ing the as pect of menace tange nt, not a ce nter, a vanishing point, not a \' iewing point, an
\vhi ch still colors Laca n's account of the subject's visual c.x peri- opacity on the other's d istant ho~izon, Everything reconvergesJ v
ence; co ncerning the question of where the subjecr resides, under on thi s intrush'e center where the watcher self is nOl: the in -
the Gaze and in the expanded field of fiin)'alo or " blan kness"; truder beco mes a kind of dra in which sucks in all of the former
and concern ing, in the pract ice of pa inting, the repercuss io ns of plenitude, a black hole pull ing the scene away from the watcher
the structures of Je reaord, the Gaze, and siinyaco, blankness or self into an engul fi ng void.
emptiness, at the level of brush, pigment, and frame. Were we to represent Sartre's scenari o in terms of a pi c-
ture, the Raphael Sposalizio would ill ustrate its general for matio n
II (Figure 2). In one sense all of the architectural spaces tu rn to-
wards the viewer, displaying their adve rtent aspects to one who
Sartre's concepti on of the gaze of the other is clearest in his stands at the place of masterly overview, wi th every line of Right
story or scenario of the watcher in the park. I Sartre's narrati\'c across the corn ices, flagstones, and arcades traveling in towards
involves two stages. In its fi rst movement, Sart re enters a park the soverejgn spectator. But in another sense the architecture of
and discovers that he is alone: everything in the park is there fo r the piazza turns towards a place where the viewer does not and
him to regard from an unchallenged center of the visual ne ld. cannot ex ist . T he moment the viewer appears and takes up posi-
All of th e park unfo lds before this absolute center of a li ved tion at the viewpoint, he or she comes face to face with another
horizon: the subject resides at the still point of the turning term that is the negati ve counterpart to the viewing posit ion:
world, master of its prospects, sO\'ereign sun 'eyor of the scene. the vanishing pOi nt, All of the orthogonal lines across windows,
In this initial exhil aration of self-possessio n, nothing threatens doors, pavements co nverge there at the vanishing point where,
the occu pancy of the self as foc us of its visual kingdom, But in par excellence, the viewer is not. The hnes of the piazza race away
Sart re's second movement, this reign of plenitude and luminous towards thi s drain or black ho le of otherness placed at the hori-
peace is brought abruptly to an end: into the park and into the zon, in a decentering that destroys the subject's un itary self-pos-

. .
THE GA ZE I N THE E X PANDED FIEL.D

session. The viewpoint and the vanishing point are inseparable:


there is no viewpoint without vanishing point, and no vanjshing
point without viewing point. T he self-possess ion of the viewing
subject has built into it, therefore, the principle of its O\vn aboli-
tion: annihilation of the subject as center is a condition of the
"ery moment of the look.
This pictorial example is perhaps closer to Laca n than to
Sar tre, for in Sartre the agent that accomplishes the reve rsal of
the visual field, its peripateia, is personal: another being, before
whom I become opaque, abject, in a dial ecti c of master and
slave. Lacan's re\vorking of Sartre's scenario dispenses with this
personalized other. 2 His story is a good deal stranger. Lacan is
away from Paris, in Brittany, out with fishermen on the open
sea. On the surface of the sea are pieces of Aotsam, in particular
a sar dine ca n, to which one of the men reacts by saying to
Lacan: "You see that can ? Do you see it? Well, it doesn't see
you!"J The remark disturbs Lacan because he can sense a per- )
specth'e in which it is untrue: the world of inanimate objects to
some ex tent always looks back on the percei\er. What is the ..... C - .
sou rce of this strangely empowered look back? Laca n's account I
depends, not on the irruption of another persona l vie",'er but
the irruption, in the visual fi eld, of the Sign ifi er. When I look,
what I see is not simply light but intelligible form: the rays of
light are caught in a rets, a network of meanings, in the same .;.
way that flotsam is caught in the net of the fi shermen. For hu-
man beings collectively to orchestrate their visual expe rience
together it is required that each submit his or her retinal
experience to the socially agreed descr iption(s) of an intelligible eo
world . Vision is socia lized, and thereafter deviat ion from this so-
cial construction of visual reality can be measured and named,
va riously, as halluci nation , misrecognition, or "visual distur-
bance." Between the subj ect and the world is inse rted the entin,) .l-i
sum of discourses wru ch make up visuality, that cultural con- t--.,
Figure 1. Raphael. Marri"8c of 1M \';r9In (Spmal17ia dcllo Madonna). 1504. Br('ra,
Pi nacoteca. (COU rlC5)' Ali llarilA rl Rl"S(lun:e, N.Y.) struct, and make \" isuality different from vision, the notion of Vt., I

91
Normon Bryson I

unmediated vi sual experience. Between retina and world is in-


serted a screen of signs, a screen consisting of all the multiple
discourses on vision built into the social arena.
This screen costs a shadow: sometimes Lacan calls it a
scotoma , sometimes a stain. For when we look through the
screen, what we see is caught up in a network that comes to us
-'
fr om the outside: mobile'-tesserae of~signification , a mosaic that
/'
moves. This network is g reater than its individual agents or op-
'--vi erators. When I learn to speak, I am inse rted into systems of
7 discou rse that were there before I was, and will remain after I
am gone. Similarly when I learn to see socially, that is, when I
begin to articulate my retinal experi ence with the codes of rec-
ogniti on that come to me from my social milieu(s), I am in-
serted into systems of "isual discourse that saw the world before
I did, and will go o n seeing after I see no longer. The screen
casts a shadow '!f dcoch. E" erything I see is orchestrated with a
cultural producti on of seeing that e.xists independently of my life
and outside it: my individual discoveries, the findings of my eye
as it probes through the world, come to unfold in terms not of
my making, and indifferent to my morta lity. The screen morr!fies
-- ~ -
sight. Its terms are points of signifi cati on, chains of signifi ers,
Figure 3. Hans Holbein. The Amboswdon. 1533. London, National Galle ry of Art.
(Courtesy SNA RK/ Art Resource:, N.Y.)
that of themselves have no light. The signifier operates o n light
and with light, but has no light of itself, or onl y the light it bor- The effect of this insertion of the screen, or skull , or
) rows from my eye. The signifier casts its shadow of darkness scotoma , is that th e subj ect who sees is no more the center of
\ if/"
I across my vision, and because of that darkness I am no longe r vi sual exper ience than the subject of language is at the center of
Uf..,r V
bathed in the lustre of a luminous plenitude. Into my visual field speech. W hen I speak, I may try to fill each word I utter with
N'
, \ something Ctlts, cuts across, namely the nehvork of signifiers. To the full meaning of my unique thought. But the fact remains
illustrate in pictorial terms what that something is, Lacan pro- that, in the social arena where I speak, the words I utter have to
vides his example from Holbein. 4 The ambassadors are masters follow paths or networks laid down before I entered their ter-
of lea rni ng, in possessio n of aU the codes of knowledge, of sci- rain . The speake r did not create these, nor does the speaker
ence and art, fashioned in their social mili eu; but their visual control them. In the same way, ...vhen I see, what I see is formed
field is cut across by someth ing they cannot master, the skull by paths or networks laid down in advance of my seeing. It may
whi ch casts itse lf Sideways across their space, through ana- be the case that I feel myself to inhabit some kind of center in
mo rphosis (Figure 3). my speech, but what decenters me is the network of language. It

" "
HormDn Bryson I THE GAZE IN THE E X PANDE D FIELD

may similarly be that I always feel myself to live at the center of ti ons of o ntology, of subject and object, from within the srand-
my vision -somewhere (where?) behind my eyes; but, again, point oj the subject. 6 Nishitani remarks that the Sartrean je is
that visio n is decentet:ed by the network of sigt"!ifiers that come
to me from the social milieu.
--- ~
capable of reaching a level of nihility in whi ch eve rything that
exists is cast into doubt, except the fundamental irreducibility of
- - --Laca n pushes this description further. In place of the the je whi ch does the doubting. For example, when the je full y
speaker in ordinary conversation, he invites us to consider the understands the death of God and comes t o doubt the viability
speech of the analysand. The experi ence of analysis, as Lacan de- of an ethi cs imposed on the subj ect from the outside, the
( (,k'
fines it, forces the speaker to recognize that the words she or he
,rn perturbing life; that they follow paths and
utters have their o . .
Sartrean je reacts by falling back in on itself, and by struggling
to locate an authenti city of the self from whi ch ethi cal action
( "". ,
chains unknown in advance, in movements that circle round yet can emanate directly: when the forms of ethics pass into the
never reach the locus of desire or fear. -/"-
Psychoanalysis is that ex-
-7__......_____ field of nihility and are annulled there, that annihilation is over-
perience of speaking on the field of the other. The analysand come by the je's assertion of itself as authentic core of moral
'- ~
does not stand at the center of control over these motions of the ~e n cy. The passing of ethical forms into the field of annihilatio n
Signi fie r; he or she is more like their bewildered obse rver. d ismantles them, but does not dismantle the je, the self which
Lacan's analysis of vision unfolds in the same terms: the viewing reacts by redoubling the force of the self as it operates on the
subject does not stand at the center of a perceptual horizon, and nothingness outside it. For Nishitani , Sartre's nihilism is half-
cannot command the chains and series of signifiers passing hearted: Sartre places the uni'erse around the self on the field
across the visual domain. Vision unfolds to the side of, in tan- of nihility. yet the self gathers force there, and uses the blank-
gent to, the field of the other. And to that form of seeing Lacan ness surround ing it as, so to speak, a spr ingboard from which to
gives a name: seeing on the fi eld of the other, seei ng under launch its own authentic operations.7 This is to treat the field of
the Gaze. nihility, Nishitani obse rves, as though it were something a8ainst
which the self reacts- in this case by multiplying its effor ts and
III solidifying its centeredness. What does nor happen in Sartre's
work , as Nishitani sees it, is the placing of the je itself on the
I \vant now to pass from the current of thought of Sartre and
fi eld of nihility or emptiness: the je reemerges from its encoun-
Lacan to another current, the one which passes from Europe ter with nihility. reiriforced in its positi on as the center of its
into Japan by way of the most influential Japanese philosopher of experience.
the twenti eth ce ntury, Nishida , and which passes on from So it is wi th Sartre's description of vision, and the sce nari o
Nishida to the writer who, at the level of translation , is much of the watcher in the park. The intrusion of the other makes of
more accessible to Western readers than Nishida himself, Keiji the self a spectacle or object in relation to that other: the self is
Nishitani.S Nishitani 's critique of Sartre occupies a crucial sec- threatened with annihilation by that irruption of alterity on the
ti on of Nishitani 's book Reli8ion and Nothin8ness, and it bases it- subject's horizon. But Sartre's analysis in fact stops a long way
self on the obse rvation that with Sartre there is no radical short of the stage at which this menace to the subject would pass
overturning of the enclosure of thought whi ch treats the ques- on to the field of nihility and become a full decemerin8 of the

94
"
Norman Bryson I THE GAZE IN THE EXP A NOEO F"IELO

i:-J subj ect. Sartre's watcher is objectified by the other's gaze, just as place and one place onl),. It ex ists (ii ) independently of the ob-
that other is objectified by his gaze: but the fundamental terms, jects around it, whose ex istence the subject is free to doubt,
of subject and object, remain intact throughout the encounte r. It without that doubt entailing that the subject come to doubt its
is as though both the watcher in the park and the intruder who olVn ex istence. And the subject (iii) rema ins itself despite trans- ,
disturbs its peace were suppli ed with opt ical frames- binocu- formation in the material wo rld. In addition to these qua lities of
lars, t.elescopes, Yiewfinders-which restricted the surrounding the entity whi ch the subject shares with its object world , the
world to just these two poles, the watcher (now threatened by subject of the cOfJieo has a further characteristic whi ch the ob-
the other's gaze) and the intruder (similarly threatened). T hough jects of the wo rld do not share: 0,') a position of uni"ersai cen-
menaced by each other, neither is Junda menralijl challenged: the ter, around which the obj ect world clusters or co nverges as the
subj ect can su n';l'c such a gaze, and survive more strongly for be- subj ect's experi enti al horizon.
ing exposed to thjs "alterity" which may menace the subject but Like Sartre and like Lacan, Nishitani's aim is to dismantle
whi ch does not in any sense actually dissok e or annihi late it. thi s anthropocentric subj ect, but his critique differs from theirs
The subj ect's sense of being a subject is heightened, not undone: in his insistence on the term { ii'!)'acii, translated as "emptiness,"
and this, folloWing Nishitani's argument, is because the entire " rad ica l imperma nence," "blankness," and "ni hility."ij The en-
scenari o is restricted to its tw in poles of subject and object. tity, as a conceptual category, is found unable to withstand the
What is not thought through is the question o~n's critique of fii n)'Qul, and transposed to the field of siinyaeQ both
wider frame. the subject-entity and the object-entity literally break up, Sta-
bilizing the entity as a fixed Form, with a bounded outline, is
poss2,ble only if the universe surrounding the entity is screened
IV
out and the entity withdrawn from the universa l field of trans-
Like ~~tre's Beina and Nochinaness, Nishitani 's Reliaion and Noeh - formati ons. The co ncept of the entity ca n be preserved only by
inaness sets out to criticize the Cartesian self-enclosure of the an optic that casts around each entity a perceptual frame that
coaito. In the coaieo the subject concei"es of itself as uni ver:.a l makes a cue from the fie ld and immobilizes the cut within the
ce nter, surrounded by the stable plenitude of an object world. stati c fram ework. But as soon as that frame is withdrawn, the
Both subject and object exist in a state of mutual confirmation obj ect is found to ex ist as part of a mobile continuum that ca n-
and fix ity. The subject, from its position of center amidst t~e not be cut anywhere. If the obj ect is, say, a Aower, its existence I
world of things, looks out on its objects and percei" es them _as is only as a phase of incremental transformations between seed ~
separate entie ies. That is, obj ects manjfest to the subject as com- and du st, in a continuous exfoliati on or perturbation of matter:
plete beings hayi ng (i) stable location in a si ngle place; (ii) inde- at no point does the object come under an arrest that would im-
pendent se lf-existence (reqUiring the existence of nothing else in mobilize it as Form or eidos. Moved on to the field of f iinyaea or
order to exist)j (iii) permanent or enduring form. The subject radical impermanence, the entity comes apart. It ca nnot be said
looki ng out upon the world of entities finds itself to be an entity to occupy a sinale location, since its locus is always the universal
symmetrical with them. Like them, the ubject exists (i) in one field of transformations: it ca nnot achieve separati on from that

.+
.. /(
/
,) (. \ ,M,
91
Norman Bryson I THE GAZE IN THE E XPAN OEO rlELO

field or acquire any kind of bounded outline. Because of its in- form of the Rower, and the Rower is already becoming dust. The
separability from the field of impermanence it ca nnot be said to prese nt state of the object appearing as the Rower is inhabited by
enj oy independent self-existence, since the g round of its being is its past as seed and its future as dust, in a continuous motion of
the existence of everything else. And it cannot present itself in postponement, whose effect is that the flower is never presently
the guise of an enduring Form. there, any more than seed or dust are there.
In Nish itani's description, an object's presence can be de- Nishita ni sums up the deferred/differed presence of (what
fined only in negative terms. Since there is no way of singling had been) the entity in a se ries of aphoristic Rashes that illumi-
out an object x without at the same time incl uding it in the nate his text in the same way that the parables of the invaded
global field of transformati ons, what appears as the object x is park and the Roati ng sardine can illuminate the texts of Sartre
, 0nJy the d!.fference between x and the total surrounding field . and Lacan (if one "gets" the aphorisms one has g rasped the core
Similarly what appears as "the surrounding fie ld" is only its dif- argument). T\vo key aphorisms are: "fire does not burn nre ,"
ference from the object x. Nishitani 's thinking is morphologi cally and " water does not wash water."9
close to Saussu re's account of the location of an individual word It would seem to be the essence of fire that it burns; if it
in a language. The word, Saussure maintains, is nothing in itself: does not burn it is not fire. Yet fire cannot burn itself; it cannot
it lacks all the prope rties of the entity. Rather, the word is co n- exist in self-enclosure. Fire can burn everything that can be
stituted "diacritically" in its difference from its surrounding burned, but the one thing fi re cannot burn is fire. For nrc to be
fi eld, in this case all the other words in the language. In the nre it mu st extend out of the enclosure of flame into the sur-
same way, Nishitani argues for the diacritica l e.xistence of ob- rounding fie ld, and o nly when its roots travel into its surround
jects: the system of objects " knows no positive terms." More- ca n it burn. Similarly, it is of the essence of water that it can
ove r, since the object field is a continuous mobility, indiv~ 1 wash e\erything that exists, and if it does not wash it is not wa-
objects are constituted by d!lJerance, deferral in time, a~. ter. Yet the one thing water ca nnot wash is water: it ca nnot exist
Nis hitani's thinking here is close to Derrida's por trayal of dif- inside the self-enclosure of the entity, circumscri bed by a bound-
Jera nce in language. T he mea ning of a word never stands forth in ary or outline, in a Single location that excl udes the surrounding
full array. If we want to know the meani ng of an indi vidual fie ld. For water to be water it must percolate through that
word, and look it up in a dktionary, what the dictionary gives is boundary and infi ltrate the entity's dry surrou_nd , enter into the
not the meani ng of that one word, but other v.'Ords, synonyms. surrounding field across the porous filte rs of irrigation: only
As one reads a se ntence, one does not know what a word in when it does so, when it lea\es the se lf-enclosure of water, can
mid -sentence means until one reaches the end of the sentence, it become water. Its existence comes to it when it has left water
and that sentence in turn changes as one moves to the next sen- behind it and entered what is not itself. Its being is interpene-
tence, or parag raph, or page. Meaning in a sense never arrives!. trated by what it is not : whi ch is to say that things ex ist in the
and in the same way, for Nishitani, being never arrive~ (bei!}g~ ways they do exist, under a mode of const itutive negativity or
never arrive). The form of the seed is already turning into the emptiness, iiinyatii.

.. .
Normon Bryson I THE GAZE IN THI!: I!:XPANDED F I EL D

v not be cut out of the tota l surround, Singled out, and be made to
represent the totality of the viewer's being. What enabled that
Nishitani's ana lysis of vision works in terms that are very dif- narrO\'L.cone or pyramid to feature as the visual fi eld was exactly
. ferent from those of Sartre. In Sartre, the object is what appears -;he enclosure of the frame- the tunnel , the viewfinder, the le-
, to a subject, so to speak at the end of a viewfi nder. The de"v- gi~imate construction. But once that fram e is dissolved on the
finder or legit imate construction creates a kind of tunnel vision field of siinyota or emptiness, that narrow angle is found to be
in which all of the surrounding field is screened out. Only that eme1oped on all sides by a surround of invisibility. O nce dis-
which appears within the framing apparatus- perspective, pic- framed, the brightly luminous segment is found actuaUy to be
( ture frame, camera- exists: the viewer on one side, the object constituted lVithin the invisible, the dark or unmarked remainder
r;.'t. on the other. Nishi tani 's move is to dissol\'e the apparatus of that extends beyond the edge of peripheral vision into the space
( framing which always produces an obj ect for a subject and a sub- that wraps its way round behind the spectator's head and behind
ject for an object. Passing on to the fie ld of f unyala the object is the eyes. W hat can be seen is supported and interpenetrated by
found to exist, not at the other end of tunnel vision, but in the what is outside Sight, a Gaze of the other enveloping Sight on all
total field of the universa l remainder. The object opens out om- sides.
nidirecrionallj' on to the uni\'ersal surround, agai nst which it de-
,; .,
. How can such a Gaze be represented? For surely we now
fi nes itself negati vely and diacritically. The viewer who looks out sta nd at the very limits of representation. From this point on,
at the object sees only one angle of the global fi eld where the only a technique which undermines the fram e can stand in for
object resides, o ne Single tange nt of the 360 degrees of the ci r- the invisible which the frame excludes. And if we try to pi cture
cle, and of the 360 degrees in aU directi ons of the radiating to ourselves the Gaze of f unyald or blankness, it must be in
sphere of light spreading out from the object into the global terms of the nonrepresen~i onal or the anti -r~reseritatjonal.
envelopment. Perhaps the clearest image of this comes from the technique
In the same way that Nisrutani takes the object away fro m which sets out both to assert and to undermine representational
the framing apparatus-the pi cture fram e, the legitimate con- practice, the technique known in Japan as "Aung ink."
structi on-a nd places it on the expanded field of blanllless or The full est expression of f unyata in the visual field is un-
f unyald, so the viewe r is pulled a\vay from the aperture of the doubtedly the practice that immerses itself in this concept,
viewfinder or lens and redefined as radically dis-framed. The Ch'an painting. The landscape by Sesshii ( 1420-1506) is a
viewer still has his or her eyes open: the uni verse does not dis- framed image (Figure 4), and as such might suggest that we are
appear. But the viewe r is now a being that ex ists through the ex - still in the orbit of the framing apparatus-the tunneling of vi-
istence of everything else in the universal fie ld, and not just as sion that fixes a tiny segment of the object world at one end, for
the subj ect-effect of the object that appears at the end of the a segm ented viewing subject at the other. And in fact the image
\iewing tunnel. Let us say that the viewer's eyes look out at a has no wish to transcend t he facts of ordinary vis ion, inasmuch
segment of the total field that surrounds the viewer omnidirec- as these facts involve looking at the object in the form of a sec-
tiona ll),. This small secti on (or cone, or pyramid) is in fact only a tion or profile of the object's being. When we look at things, we
fr action of the field of unive rsal surrou nd i this partia l view can- do see only a tangent, and not the full radiation of light emitted

100 101
THE GAZE IN THE E X PANDED F'IEL.D

omnidirectionally: Ch'an does not dispute that. What Ch'an does


dispute is that the profile which thus appears can be identified
with the object itself, as it exists in the field of empt iness. What
the image needs to include is the fact of the object's remainder, the
other views which pass out from the object to all those un-
countable places where the viewer is not. And what the image
also has to ad.'lOwledge, even while it records the narrow pas-
sage of light that travels to an empiri ca l observer, is the viewer's
remainder, the sum of other views that the viewer excludes by as-
suming this view, the surrounding envelope of invisibility. What
painting risks, in the Ch'an perspective, is the production of a
false ontology in which the seer and the seen commune in tun-
nel vision: the subject mistaking what is only a profile of the ob-
ject for the object itself; the profile, thus cut out, creating for
itself a hypostasized viewing subject, pinned at the other end of
the tunnel.
In the case of the Aung-ink painting, Ch'an's solution is to
disfigure the image, the bipolar view, by opening on to the
whole force of randomness. As the ink is cast, it Aies out of the
enclosure or tunnel of the frame, and opens the image on to the
field of material transformations that constitutes the universa l
surround. The Hinging of ink marks the surrender of the fixed
form of the image to the global configuratio n of force that sub-
tends it. Eidos is scattered to the four winds. The image is made
to Aoat on the forces which lie outside the fram e; it is thrown, as
one throws dice. What breaks inco the image is the rest of the
universe, everything outside of the fram e.
It is the same with the Aung ink of Ch'an calligraphy, so
rapid that the ink cannot be contained by the system of script
(Figure 1). When the graphic gesture is slow, deliberate, the
traces can still be held within a framework of control. The cal-
ligrapher operates on the character, and the character dictates the
movements of the brush. Accelerated, the gesture comes loose
Figure 4. Sesshu. Lamkapt (detail). Tokyo, National Museum. from this bipolar structure of holding- in-place: the ink Aies

'03
Norman Brysan 1 THE GAZE IN THE E:XPANOEO F'IE:LO

faster than the hand can control it, and to areas of the paper or by the sense of menace or persecution, why does Laca n pro\'ide
silk beyond the sway of the character's prescribed structure. It only one model of vision and of painting, that of the negative or
breaks fre e from the subject who controls it, and from scrip- terror izing gaze?

--- --
tural form. The framework of script and calligrapher is cut There seem to me two, related answers. The first concerns
across by another term that stands for everything outside their a rather ricep' uncertainty in Lacan concerning the .!:.o le of cul-
circumscribed enclosure: the rest of the universe, the fi eld of - "--- '- ~.
tural variation in the constructi~~~ct~ ity . Lacan's de-
emptiness that subtends the entit ies of scribe and script and an- scription of how the subject is formed unfolds in terms of
nihilates them as freestanding and independent forms. eltu~e:it is in the irruption of the symboliC order and. of sig-
Something cuts across the field of vision, and invades it ni ~tion that human subjectivity is precipitated, and slllce the
from the outside. Vision is traversed by something wholly un- composition of the symboli C order and of the codes of significa-
governable by the subject, something that harbors within it the tion are historically and culturally variable, the subject in Laca n
force of everything outs ide the visual dyad. Let us ca ll it the is giyen by culture and history, not by nature. Neverthe less,
Gaze. But it is hardly the Gaze of Sartre, or even of Lacan. Laca n says far more about the subject's initial inse rtion into the
symboli C than about the subject's subsequent life there. That
VI subsequent existence is where the variables of history, culture,
and class operate, and construct the subject across the enormous
In Lacan, something cuts across the space of sight and darkens
array of loca l discourses through which the subject moves: in the
i t: the Gaze. And in the Rying of the inks there is an entry into
workplace and the famil y, in the institutions of education , med i-
o- the visual field of something totally dark and opaque that stands
cine, law, property, religion, government, and all the diverse
for absolute alterity: the otherness of the rest of the universe: a
cultural arenas of the social formation. We are ce rtainly invited
surrounding field that decenters the subject and the subject's vi-
to think of Lacan's terms , the SymboliC and the Imaginary, as
\ sion completely. When the painter or calligrapher throws the
operating in all of these adult arenas, and not only at the stage of
ink, there is renunciation of all claim to act as universal center,
the subj ect's initial formation (in childhood). Yet Lacan's descrip-
and at the same time (pace Sartre) renunciation of the object as tions tend to privilege the genet ic and formati\'c moment, not
aiternacjve universal center. Yet these abolitions of self and center the long and diverse elaborations of adult life. This conce ntra-
are not accompanied by any apparent sense of menace, which tion on subjective genesis and installation makes it difficult to
may indicate ways in which Sartre and Lacan still operate from think through the question of cultural \ariation. As part of this,
within a ce rtain intellectual enclosure. it is difficult to think through to the cultura l di\ersity of visua l
What seems questionable in Lacan's account of vision and regimes, some of which may view the decentering of the subjcc
painting is the paranoid coloration given to the Gaze. The Ch'an in terms other than those of menace. .........
examples point to regimes of visuality in whi ch the decentering The second answer is an extension of the first: that Lacan's
of the subject may be thought in terms that are not essentially portrayal of the Imaginary gives a centrality to his argument that
catastrophic. And this in turn prompts the question: if, in cer- is culturally specific, not universal. Nishitani's ana lysis of vision
tain "alternative" scopic regimes, decentering is unaccompanied is of interest because its terms are so close to Laca n: like Lacan,

'04 105
Norman Bryson I THE G A ZE IN THE EXf'ANOI!:O I"IEL.O

Nishitan i engages with Sartre as a precursor, and both regard domai n of retina and light has subtended a number of key ac-
the centering of the universe around the sovereign subject as il- tivities: in art history, fonnalism ; in a~ theory, the approach to
, lusion. In the fie1d of siinyoco the centralized subject falls apart; a,!:! via the psychology of perception.! in the work o!.. Gombri~h
its boundary dissolves, together with the consoling boundary of or Arnheim; in the construction of musemns and exhibition
the object. Nihility and blankness undo the subject's centering of ;Paces premised on the practice of decontextualizing the image
the world upon itself; and , radically decentered, the subject in order to perm it unmediated communi on between the viewer's
comes to know itself in noncentered terms, as inhabiting and in- eye and pure form. From these and related activiti es has
habited by a constitutive emptiness. Such decentering is a cen- emerged the notion of art as a matter of erceptual purity,
tral theme in Lacan and in Nishitani; and yet their approaches timeless, sequestered from the social domain , universa l. Post-
are quite different. Perhaps one ca n illustrate their di"ergen~e by modernism has entailed movin!i beIo~d this~pisteme and ac-
way of the skull in the Holbein, and the flung ink in e h 'a n. T he knowledging the fact that the visual field we inhabit is o ne of
skull appears in and as the protest of the Imaginary aga inst its meanings and not just shap:,s, that it is permeated by verbal and
own decentering, as the menace of death; the flung ink fig ures ~discou rses, by signs; and that these signs are soc ially co n-
instead the subject's acceptance of decentering. The skull repre- structed, as are we.
sents the subject's fear of disso lution, the flung ink embodies in - - "[he rea l discovery here is that things we took to be pri -
stead the subject's renunciation of a central su bject position, o n "atc, secluded, and inward - perception, art, the perception of
a field of radical emptiness where the last rema ins of the coaita art in the museum -are created SOCially. What is at stake is the
are rendered null and void, literally cast out on empty air. What discovery of a politics of"'\ision. W hich is fi nally why one might
changes between them is the cultural construction of the Imagi- want to query the paranoid or terrorist coloratio n that Laca n
nary. Whi ch suggests, finally, that Laca n's account of vision as gives the Gaze. Let us say that it is a bit easier, si nce Lacan, to
persecuted by the Gaze, like Sartre's, itself unfolds lI'irhin lhe think of d suality as something built cooperatively, O\'er time;
lmaBinory. an Imagi nary constructed in a culturally and histo r- that we are therefore responSible fo r it, ethi cally accountable. Yet
ica lly speci fic fashion. If so, then it is that analysis which itse lf Laca n seems to me, at least , to view the subj ect's entry into the
needs to experience some cultural and hi storical decenter ing. socia l arena of visuality as intrinsically disastrous: the vocabu lary
Why should I or anyone spend time wrangling over Laca n's is one of capture, annexation, death. Against this someone else
concept of the Gaze? My own answer must be that, although I might say: the degree of terror depends on how power is dis-
obviously have rese rvations about a ce rtain paranoid coloration tributed within that construct once it is bu ilt, and on where one
within it, nevertheless Lacan's account of visua lity seems to me is made to stand inside it . Under a \'oyeur istic male gaze, a
histor ically extremely important. It marks a funda mental shift \voma n might well experi ence ter ror. And what of the begga r in
away from the grou nd on which vision has been preViously the street, or of a Third World rendered trid al and picturesque
thought. The nineteenth ~ury saw the ri~ of a theory~ \'i- under the gaze of colo nialism? Terror comes from the way that
sion in which the truth of vision lay in the retina , in the phys- Sight is constructed in relation to power, and powerlessness. To
iology of the eye and the neurology OTthe optical apparatus. ~ think of a ter ror intrinsic to sight makes it harder to think what
the twentieth century the concepti on of \'ision as primarily a makes Sight terrori sti c, or otherwise. It naturali zes terror, and

'06 '01
Norman Bryson I
D I S C USSION

that is of course what is terrifying. But what should ensue from Norman Bryson I should clar ify o ne thing. The Ch 'an examples, by
Lacan's portrayal of the terror of sight is analysis, analyses , maoy Sesshu and Murata Shuk6, date from the fifteenth century - I
of them, of ~ow power ,uses the social co nstruct of vis ion ~su wasn't making an histori cal connection between the paintings

\(_ \:
\ I
J
l alit),. And also of how power disguises and conceals its opera---" and Nishi tani . The illustrations I used are simply diagrams of ar-
t ions in visual it)', in myths of pure form , pure perception, and guments; I'm not mak ing historical claims about the East and the
',... culturall), universal vision. West and their traditi ons. But since Sartre uses the visua l sce-
nari o of the pa rk and Laca n involves Holbein to diagrammatize
his argument, I thought Ch'an painting might prov ide a \'isual
form for Nishi tani 's ideas.
Notes
, Rosalind Krauss W hen you descri bed the gaze of s finyato, par ticu-
( I. Jean- Paul Sartre, Beina and NOl hinBness. trans. Hazel E. Barnes (New York:
Philosoph ical Library, 1956), Chapter I, section 4, pp. 254- 302. larly in relation to the noti on of framing deve loped by Nishitani,
2. Jac'Iues Lacan, The Faur Fundamental Cancepu cf PSjcho-anabsis. cd. Jacques- you sa id it has to do with the dar k, unmarked remainder-the
j\lain Miller, trans. Alan Sheridan (Ne\\" York and Londo n: W . W. Norton,
things that fall outside the frame of vision in its Western per-
1978), sect ions 6-9.
spectival sense. I immediately thought of the notion de\-eloped
3. Ibid., p. 95. ~
4. Ibid., pp. 85-90. by Merleau-Ponty in The Phenamen%BJ c! Perception that \'ision is
5. Works by Kitar6 Nish ida (1870-1945) al'ailable in English include: Intd- ..:.:'nst itutecl preCisely by what goes on behind the head and in
/iBibiliry and ,he Philasoph;' if NorhinBness. trans. Robert Schinzinger (Hono lulu: ~he body-all those perspect ives that are the perspecth-es of the
East ~Wes t Center Press, 1958); A SW~I' ?f Good. trans. V. H. Viglielmo (Tokyo:
~ . It is precisely hi s account of the phenomeno logy of \' ision
Printing Bureau of the Japanese GOI"Cr nme nt, 1960); and Lasr Wriring': NorhinB-
nc.lS and rhe ReliBious t-\i1rldl'ic lI". trans. David A. Dilworth (Honolulu: University of that it is dependent on the sum of other views excluded by the
Hawaii Press, 1987). On the rele\'ance of Nishida in the context of poststr uc- position of the \'iewer, an account that he develops speCifica lly
turalism and postmodernism, see W illiam Haver, "The Body of this Death: Al~ in relation to Ce-olanne. I wonder - and this rna)' be pure projec-
te rit)' in Nish ida-Philosophy and Post -Marxism ," Ph.D. d isser tation, Uni\'ersity
tion on my part - if there is not an echo of The Phenomen%BJ if
or Chicago, 1987.
Perception in Nishita ni.
'f..... 6. Kciji Nishitani (b. 19 14), ReliBion ond ;Vorhin8ness, trans. Jan Van Bragt
(Be rkele),: University of Ca lifornia Press, 1982), p p. 30-45 .
Bryson It seems to me that Nishi tani does dra\v on Merleau-
7. Ibid., p. 33.
8. On iinyarii, sec ibid., chapters 4-6. Pont)', but the practi ce of Aung- in k painting is ob\' iously dif-
9. Ibid., p. 116. ferent from that of Cezanne. The emphasis is far more on a
radi cal decenter ing of the subject , and I think th at points to a
difference bet wee n Nishitani and Merleau- Ponty, although in the
thematic of the invisible the), are close. In Merleau - Ponty there
seems to be not a nI), a desocia lization of the body but also a
simplification of the bod),- a simplification because it is st ill re-
garded as the center fro m whi ch one looks out onto the world ,
and it is exactly this center that is cast out in Nishi tan i.

108
".
OISCUSSIO N

Th is leads to the question of the difference between Mer- raised about Merleau-Pont),. Merleau-Ponty seems to me to be a
leau-Ponty and Lacan. At certain points Laca n is asked if his very important transit io nal figure between Sar tre and Lacan , not
position is li ke Merleau-Ponty's and, curiously enough, he says only because he is more interested in the body and the crossing
that it is. But it obviously can't be because the body in Merleau'- of gazes, but also because he is more interested in signs. I think
Pontyis a unified, untroubled place of acrobatic grace and per- it would be wrong to say that, unlike Laca n, Merleau-Ponty only
'c eptual acco rd between subject- world and object-world, an exact talks about the body. In his last writings he actually cites Lacan
fit of the incarnated subject inside the.....Aesh of the world. A nd (" the unco nscious is structured like a language"), and there are
such harmony of the body in its world is preC isely what isn't at least gropings toward a structuralist view of language. I do,
present in any theory in which the sign is seen to troub le this however, ag ree that the later Merleau-Ponty is much more op-
union. Now when I invoked my Oriental example - even though timistic about visual interaction than Lacan, who shares with
it is the only appropriate one for an argument that is in arti cula- Sartre a much more pessimistic, perhaps even paranoid view.
tion with the West from the outside-it might have seemed as But Merleau-Po nty also introduces elem ents whi ch lead us to-
though I was invoking a purel), gestural painting, but my point is wa rd Lacan, including the linguisti c mediation of the viewer and
not the pure gesturalit), of the Japanese work but rather the re- the viewed in the flesh of the world .
nunciation of gesturalit), in the Ainging of ink: the gestu re of the Bryson 1 would agree with both those emphases. About the con-
Merleau- Pontyan body, ce ntralized in its world, is also thrown nectio n between Nishitani and Heidegger: it is via Nishida, more
out by this Ringing of ink. than twenty of whose students, including Nishitani , went to
study wi th Heidegger. But actually I have a question for you. It
Marlin Jay 1 think it is crucial to recognize the e.xistence in this has been very much o n my mind - this issue of the paranoid
Japanese discourse of a Heideggerian motif even more than a coloration given to visua lity in different French traditions of the
Merleau-Pontyan one. W hen H~ggJ. talks about the notion of seventee nth , eighteenth , and twentieth centuri es. I am impressed
Umsicht, of a circumspect yision, he means a visio n that doesn't by what yo u write about this tradition in the twentieth ce ntury
ha"e anyone par ticular vector. And 'when he co ntests the notion [in " In the Empire of the Gaze"], though I also have rese rva-
of enframing as pa rt of the Gesrell of Western science, he attacks tions, espeC ially in relation to Foucault. Nevertheless, I wonder
the same th ing the Japanese thinkers are attacking. His notion of ,..,hether Laca n's rhetoric of decentering as para noid and ter-
LichwnB' of a clearing, is also the notion of a place in which roristi c does not participate in that tradition.
truth is revealed-but not necessar ily to anyone eye or two
eyes in anyone body. The truth is re"ealed, and the eye is sim - Jay I think hi s ea rly discussion of the " mirror stage" as the
ply there to bear wit ness to it; this happens in precisely the way sou rce of a false notion of the integrity of the ego does reAect a
you described it in Japa nese painting. Now Heidegger had an ex- general hostility to the gaze as a source of ideological notio ns of
traordinary impact in Japan fro m the 19205 to 1940s, and I am selfhood. But in the later Four Fundamental Concepts if Psycho-
interested to know whether or not the figu res you d isc ussed ona{ysis, a very difficult text, Lacan pe rhaps moves away from an
we re co nSC ious ly indebted to him. idea of visio n as str ictly paranoid and terroristic, and this may
My seco nd question concerns the issue that Rosa lind just be why he draws on Merl eau-Ponty-to nuance the problem

111
"'
DISCUSSION

somewhat. I agree that Foucault can al so be see n to nuance the of Ch 'an painting, and it is important to get it right. Although
simply hostile tradition; Merl eau-Ponty ob,-iously does. One has there is a renunciation of control over form in an image that in-
to amid making it black and white. But I think that Lacan must volves randomness, it is nevertheless recuperated in Pollock's
be understood largely in the tradition critica l of vision. Al- pa inting: central subject positions return in so many ways-for
thusser, too , when he talks about ideology as produced by the example, in the way randomness becomes his style, so that exactly
gaze, by the mirror stage, draws on Lacan and attacks \ision. at the point where self-control is abandoned it is reinscribed as his
Christian Metz, when he ta lks about the scopic regime of the personal style. That is one place in which there is a recentering at
cinema, also draws on Lacan to denigrate \-ision as welL So I the very moment of a dece ntering. Another way is the manner in
think they arc all part of a larger story. Lacan gets it, as YO LI
which Pollock drips paint: the drips overlay one another to pro-
said, to a great ex tent from Sartre; Sa rtre's vi ew of ,'isio n is "cry duce eidetic depth-one looks at Pollock as if through various
seminal for a lot of these thinkers. O ne might also mention screens-and it is exactly that eidetic depth within the frame that
Bataille- there are many interesting connections between is irrupted and broken by Rung-ink. 50 for those reasons-but not
Bataille and Laca n -and Bataille has a fascinating critique of the because of any uncrossable cultural enclosure -it seemed more
primacy of sight in such works as his pornographi c novel sensible to choose Sesshl1 rather than Pollock.
L'hiscoire de l'oeil and his essays on ,ision. That would have to be
part of the story of Laca n's attitude toward vision as wcll. Jacqueline Rose I have a reply to Martin, one that relates to ques-
ti ons I have about a number of things we have discussed so far
Jonathan Crary Norman, could you clarify something for me? Ini - today. I want bri eRy to historicize Lacan's hosti lity to vision: it
tially you said you didn't want to set up an opposition between a needs to be located in the very origins of psychoanalysis, in the
Western and a non -Western tradition , and then you said you images of Charcot's hysteriCS at the clinic of the 5aIpetriere. It is
could only ha\'e picked a Japanese examplc to inca rnate this a perhaps overworked example but one that, especially in the
other traditio n. Wou ld it have been poss ible for YOLI to ha\'c cho- contex t of the images of wome n shown to us by Rosalind, may
sen an example from, say. twentieth-century Western modernist reinvoke the importance of questioning the immediacy and avail-
art practice. or is it a priori impossible? abi lity of the image as the immediacy and ava ilability of the body
of the woman.
Bryson No. it's not a matter of impOSSibility; it was just a questi on My seco nd point is in response to Norman regarding the
of what images could gi\'e the best form to these arguments. There paranoia of Laca n's model: I'd like to historicize that as wel1.
is no cultural enclosure that makes it impossible for a Western art What Norman calls the terror or paranoia of vision again comes
practice to embody the concepts Nishitani works with. in response to a spec ific historical moment. That moment is
perhaps best summed up in the concept of "genital oblativity,"
Crary Let me then pose a rather crude, formalist- typ e questi on. which (to quote Lacan) is "now being struck up everywhere to
If a Franz Kline had been shown. what would one ha\-e sa id? the tune of salvationist choirs." That is, the negativity of the vi-
sual and the negativity of the psychi c were part of a critique not
Bryson I was thinking more of Pollock's work, but I couldn't use it. only of ego psychology but also of a social demand of the couple
There is an esse ntial difference between Po llock and the Rung ink on the couple to be the couple.

112 113
Jacqueline Rose

SE X UALITY AND VISION :

SOME QUESTIONS

I was asked to speak on the question of sexuality in vision. I


want to start by stretching that brief into the wider domain of
how psychosexua li ty is being mobilized in certa in accounts and
definitions of the postmodern, and ask what image of the psyche
is being deployed, before bringing that back to the questio n of
how the psychoana lytic understanding of the visual field is being
used, what I see as some of the problems, and then how those
problems might relate to recent areas of artistic pract ice which
do not necessarily refer directly to, or usc, psychoanalysis but
which seem to inherit a related set of questions. I also just want
to draw our attention to these practices as they strike me as
forming some of the most crucial and innovati\'e areas of our
contemporary cultural and politi cal li fe.
I think it is becoming clear that many of the debates about
postmodernism and tota li ty t urn on a fu ndamental psychic
trope. From Deleuze and Guattari 's schizo-analyse to Jameso n's
cultu ral logic of ca pital 'wh ich is in fact an a- logic (that is, the
loss of the poss ibility of logiC itself), to Lyotard's " paradoxol-
ogy," the crisis of the totality takes its referen ce from the idea
of a psychic breakdown in whi ch it recogn izes, or rather fa ils to
recognize, itself. I don't want to get into the debate about the la-
ment ing or celebration of that felt loss of tota li ty and narrati" e
which characterizes respecti \'eiy the positions o f Jameson and
Lyotard. But I do want to stress the way that schizophrenia
works as a recurrent image of the socia l and the way that, in the
case of Jameson quite expli citly, this is in deliberate countcrdis-

115
Jacqueline Rose I SEXU .... L.ITy .... NO VISION ; SOME QUESTIONS

tinction to what he refers to as the "hysterics and neurotics of one of its chief objects as an exposing of the force and effects of
Freud's own day."l In the articl e in the collecti on The Anri- that metaphor, the omission can be felt like something of a po-
Aesthetic, edited by Hal Foster, which I am sure you all know, litica l disenfranchisement-unless one wants to argue that it is
Jameson illustrates this argument with an extract from the Auro- the psychoanalytic account itself that inscribes and reinforces
biOlJrophy td' 0 Schizophrenic Girl.2 CrUcially for this context, this that metaphor, holds onto it preCisely in the face of its histori cal
is an argument about \'isual perceptio n. The schizophreni c girl is demise (the feminist version of the celebration of the end of all
there to illustrate the loss of perceptual coordi nates in the ~veform).

postmodern world, its hallucinogeni c hyperreality, an un- Now I don't want to put myself in the position of just
differentiated vision of the world in the present which depr ives "correcting" Jame-;}i\ on this, or reversing his deliberate omis-
the su bj ect of the ability to locate her or himse lf in either space sion, although I do think ~a~ serious implications for his own
or time. If the postmodern subject is schizophrenic, she or he is cultural critique- the omission in turn of any ,.vomen artists
'--
also paranoid, and the image for this too is one of distortion in from his account of postmode rn cultural production, and more
visual space: "the glass skin repels the city outside; a repulsion speCifically of those who might be said to make the representa-
ror whi ch we have analogies in those reRector su nglasses which tion of sexual difference, or sexual difference as representation,
make it impossible for your interlocutor to see your own eyes their chief object of concern (might this not ha\'e something to
and thereby ach ieve a certain aggressivity and power over the do in turn with the negativity of the account?).4 What interests
Other."~ The image fulfills rather graph ica lly, therefore, that me here more is the concept of representation that is at stake,
paranOia of the visua l fie ld which Norman Bryson has just de- fo r it seems to bring w ith it a kind of nosta lgia for direct and
scribed . One of the things that strikes me about these images, unmediated vision: hallucination and the image of the glass skin
however, is their curious desexualization, or rather the way that and reRector sunglasses are being critically juxtaposed to a mo-
this absorbing of sexuality into the visual field closes off the ment or an epoch when vision was direct and possible, when the
question of se.'Xual difference. Schizophreni a and paranoi a oper- viewing subject looked out on and greeted the world, and
ate as the form of postmodern subject ivity, but they have been greeted too, without perversion or aggressivity, the other hu-
divested of their structure, by which I mean the structure of sex- man subjects who peopled it. To stress this can be seen as the
ual difference, whose vicissitudes and misfortun es, at least in the re\'erse move to Norman Bryson's, insofar as I am describing the
psychoanalytic terms on which Jameson partly draws, precipi- discardina of the paranoid instance from the ge nera l theory of vi-
tates the disorder into place. This is in one se nse an old story, sion at the very same moment that the sexual dimension is also
but it might nonetheless be worth noting the form of its repeti- lost to the account. Behind this nostalgia for unmediated repre-
tion here . Jameso n states quite explicitly that he .is detaching the sentat ion there is, perhaps more cruCially, the relegation of psy-
psychi C mechanism from the paternal function with which, for chosis to the status of histor ical co ntingency and a correspond-
Lacanian psychoa nalysis, it is linked. What we have therefore is ing idea lization of psychic life. The use of the psyche as meta-
an account of the postmodern as a form of breakdown which phor of the social leads, paradoxically, to a strange innocenting
could be sa id to imitate that breakdown by foreclOSing the pater- of both the psychiC and the sexual, that is, a loss of the psychic
nal metaphor from the account, For a feminism whi ch has seen dimension at the very moment that it is being evoked.

116 117
Jacqueline Rose \ SEXUAL-ITY ANO VISION : SOME QUESTIONS

What this suggests is a larger problem, one I would include haps be contrasted with the configuration and delineation of fan-
myself in: we ha,e not perhaps thought enough about the status tasy positions which Rosalind Krauss, follO Wing Lyotard, also
of psychoa~lysis in cultural discourse, about whether it is being described). For this realm of the not-yet symbolically coded, of
applied to other aspects of cultural and political life, whether it representation which is not yet, or no longer wishes to be, tied
is being deployed as a mecaphor, whether it is being used as a his- to the centering of subject and vision, is the place of the part-
corical refer ence point for transformations of cultural and repre- object, the projectile, the place of splitting, not only of the ego,
sentatio nal form . Many of the points that have bee n made so far but also of the drives -all dimensions which, as Norman Bryson
today abou t homolOgies between psychoanalysis and philosophy has argued, are indeed general characteristics of the visual in
in relati on to the visual image might reAect something of that Lacan, if not also in Freud, but which start to fade from the im-
co ncern . In relation to the visual image speCifi cally, there seems age when it is in the name of a radical other ing of vision that
to be an inverse but related position, o ne which locates what is the reference to psychoanalysis is being deployed. The phYSiol -
radi cal , or available for a radicalization, as rega rds representa- ogy of vision that Jonathan Crary so graphically describes may
tional practi ces in the disrupti on of the image's relatio n to itself, well be an attempt to give a figure to that space, but I would
in its " knowledge" of the necessary failure of its relation to its still suggest that in so doing it refines-can only refine - some
objects, that is, in the extent to which it foregrounds the inde- of the most diffi cult and unmanageable, for theory as for sub-
terminacy of the linguisti c ancVor visual sign. It can be described jects, aspects of the psychi c dynamiC it evokes. What body are
as a return to a constructivist ethic, or as a retrieval in new ,~aling with here? What desire? (Compare again the terms of
form of the possibilities for represe ntation of a pre-Renaissance taday's discussion - "voluptuous succumbing," " desire as erotic
or nonperspeclival o rganization of the visual image. The politi cs and metaphysical ," " a charge and discharge of pleasure," "the
of this practice, or of the practices it addresses, then li es in their body as thickness.")
Withholding or refusal of perceptual mastery, which mastery is Another way of putting this would be to say that Jameso n
identified as an ideological-as che ideological - myth . The ques- pushes back into a psychOSiS of the visua l field, whereas these
tion this raises is a similar one to the question I raised above, other accounts remain more in the framework of a neurosis of
and that is the nature of the positive term that is mobilized once vision. In the first, therefore , aggressivity without the sexual
psychoanalysis is brought in to reinforce or expand this essen- structure; in the seco nd, the form of desire and its othering, but
tially deconstructive account. For aren't we equally at risk of re- without aggressivity and its defense.
ifying the concepts of desire and the unconscious, idealiZing Furthermore, how much can we invest in those concepts
them as the site of an endless displacement of body and of lan- when we noti ce the forms of sexual differentiation in which they
guage, reading their angUish as our pleasure, discarding therefore so readily and repeatedly find themselves caught? Thus in Tradi-
the speCific vicissitudes and misfortun es of the psyche from this tion and Desire, Norman Bryson saves Ingres's La Grande Odalisque
psychopolitics of the sign? We have see n something of this in from one feminist critique by its self-disruption into jou;ssance
many of the terms used today - " the ecstasy of theJolie du voir," (one might argue that it is precisely the image of the woman that
" the excitement and wonderment of the body," " the beat, pulse, ree ncodes that disruption into form, gives the viewer a measure
or th rob" (a lthough in this last example, the terms could per- of retrieved control). 5 And the images that Rosalind Krauss has

118
"'
Jacqueline Rose I SEXUA L ITY AND VISION: SOME OUI!:STIONS

shown us today-the zootrope, which turns its beat of represen- of sexual self-recogniti on, identity, and ease, we could oppose it
tation and its doubling on a girl trapped within its space, or the with a disrupted and disrupting body and desire. But today that
cartoons of Picasso, whose multiple repetitions gradually body ideology works as much on the edge of ter ror and violence as it
forth as their most appropriate image the genitali a of the man does with increaSingly prescripti,e sexual norms, that is, terror
and then the fundamental copulatory pair -ar e each brilliant ex- and violence as something both abhorred (in England the in-
am pies of the way ~l diffe~e, if you give it half a chan3 creasing force against, and defin it ion of, "terro rism," the assau lt
( \~ke over any subversion or mutation of visual space. In re- on telev ision vio lence) and desired (the Falklands war and the
lation to the visua l image, concepts like desi re seem, therefore, annual vote on capital punishment). Today. therefore, the domi-
to be hemmed in on either Side-by the psychic economy which nant ideological configuration, or crucial parts of it, seems to
they both draw on and part ly suppress, by the always-waiting draw on an aspect of the unconscious whi ch was missing fr om
structure of sexual difference which gives to their attempted either side of the earlier account. This fo rces us to rethink the
bodying and disembodying the most predictable and stereotyped quest ion of the unconscious and polit ics si nce nobody would, I
of sexual tropes. Another way of putting the first part of this think, want to ascribe to unconscious violence the potentia lly
comment would be to say that the relationship of psychoanalysis radical force which we tr ied to locate in that earlie r concept of
and the visual image may have got caught in the terms of its own sexual desire, the concept that has been moved across-,ia
reference. for to argue that there is a sexuality of the visual fie ld Barthes- into the ana lysis of ,'isual space. In this context, it is
is not-or should not be-the same as saying that sexuality can interesting to note that if psychoanalysis is the intellectual tab-
be absorbed into, or exhausted by, the fie ld of vision. loid of our culture ("sex and violence" being its chief objects of
If I stress this, it may also be because I think there is a concern), then we have recently pr ivileged-sought indeed to
more general shi ft taking place in the way that psychoa nalysis base the politi cization of psychoanalysis on that privilege -the
and cultural politi cs needs to be thought. For that critique of the first over the second. For good reason, since violence does not
ideology of mastery. for which the visua l field was seen as the present itself for polit ica l asserti on and mobil ization in the same
predom inant site, ca n be traced back to the moment of Barthes's \Nay. It might also be the case that this problem simply reveals
MythoJo8ies when ideology was seen to fu nction as interpellation, the limits of any psychopo liti cs based on an assertion of the un -
that is, as the more or less comfortable calling up of subjects conscious -or on the unconscious as counterasserti on -as such.
into an essentially bourgeois and collective psychic space. 6 To- In relation to visual analysis, the unconsc ious of the image, or
day, as the terms of our collective imaginary move into a mode what has come to be read as the unconscious of the image, has
which is both more directly repressive (repression rather than yet to take on the more negative and troubling under face of its
interpellation as one of the chief mechanisms of the right-wing own category of desire.
state) and more extreme and hallucinatory in its fantasmatic I have already mentioned that both of the theories I have
forms (the resurgence of authoritarianism and the phenomenon concentrated on here-the postmodern " loss" of subjectivity as
of the New Right), neither the category of interpellation nor the the end of political space, and the politics of visual space as the
forms of sexual disruption we thought to oppose to it seem ade- very same demise or self-undOing of the subject-recognize a
quate. As long as the dominant ideology called up a facile image fu ndamenta l loss of innocence, or of reference, in relat ion to the

120 121
Jatquellne Rose I SEXUALITY AND VISION: SOME QUESTIO N S

linguistic sign, whether this is exper ienced as cause for celebra- Something of this tension, and of the need to think about it dif-
tion or lament. In relation to psychoanalysis, that loss can alter- ferently. was brought home to me particularly strongly at an
natively be described in terms of the category of the ego, either event on Cultural Identities held at the Commonwealth Institute
as the loss of a needed integration of selfhood or as the funda- in 1986, which sought to br ing together black and white fi lm-
mental misrecogn itio n of the subject who persists in his cOIl\'ic- makers and theorists in relation to the idea of a polit ica lly avant-
tion that he is precisely a subject in place. These two positi ons garde film, and it is what I want to end with today.8 (We should
have histori ca lly presented themselves as antagon istic; the dis- note here the e,ent organ ized by Y,onne Rainer, which took
agreement between them merely repeats itself in the different place concurrently with this vision symposium and whi ch pro-
accounts of, and reactions to, the postmodern by Jameso n and duced a similar set of encounters betwee n filmmakers and critics
Lyotard . But how viable, finally, is thi s opposition in some of its of the First and Third Worlds.) What struck me most forCibly
more polarized versions or forms? For one cannot of course reify was the set of analogies and differences in the way the problem
the ego any more than its opposite, as if the one could in fact of racial and sexual identity and difference was being posed in
exist without the other as its necessary and antagonistic term. If relation to representation and, more specifically, to the visua l
Lacan says in Seminar II that the point of haVi ng ana lysts is to representation of fi lm. Fo r it has been the strength of the femi-
ha,e "subjects such that the ego he absent," his work must nist challenge to dominant cinematic institutions that it has lo-
nonetheless be read as the tracking of the ego- necessary illu- cated its perversion of the sexual in the very framing and
sion, master, dupe, and bait of his practice-through wh ich sub- encoding of the image, a challenge which has as its logical co nse-
jects misrecognize themselves into place.? quence a distrust of the possibility of cinematic represe ntation
If there ca n be no ideal ization of the unconscious, there- itself. Yet, for more than reasons of the impasse to which this
fore, it is not just because of the negative of its contents, but be- has led, feminist and other form s of political cinema have not
cause without the category of the ego to which it is opposed, the wanted to discard the image as available for po liti ca l self-recog-
unconscious would not even be available to thought. One so lu - nition and cri tiqu e. This means that femin ist fi lmmak ing is
ti on is to identify that ego with the fantasy of the post-Cartesia n caught in a paradox whi ch was succinctly put by Felicity Collins
Western subject. But that unconscious? Or that body " in all its in a recent editi on of Screen: "a political cinema must be a
physiologi ca l possi bilities"? It ca n easily seem to escape that fetishist's cinema, "':,I must, as I read it, deploy the very fo rms of
same recognition or demand, holding itself up as the idea l dis- identification through the image that it has itself deSignated as
persa l of su bjectiv ity across visual space ('..vhile paranoia then be- cor ru pt. The problem is brilliantly focused by Peter Gida l's film
comes just another turn of the Western subject). We saw the Close-Up, which follows its own (non)fi lming of an object world
problem in the response to Norman Bryson's paper, when the with a blank leader sequence whose soundtrack is the voiceove r
corpus of Western philosophy started to move in to recla im the of Nicaraguan revolutionaries-a film which the refore gives you
very visua l dimension that he \.\'as so carefully attempting to lo- that systematic refusal of identification with the visual image for
cate somewhere else. Theoretically. no more than psychi ca lly, which Peter Gida l is best known and then doubles it over, at the
therefore, can we take one half of that dial ect ic in the search for point of political affirmation, with the voice (solicit ing, one
alternative visual forms. could argue, no Jess full an identification) of political truth .

122 123
Jocqllellne Rose I SEXU .... I..IT y .... ND VISIO N : SOME QUEST10NS

And this question of identificat ion, and something of its tached, is being reformulated and inRected in films which are in-
paradox, was also present in the discussion of the politics of tervening into cultural practice in the name of a politi cs of both
race. It was argued by Paul Gilroy, opening the event , that the sexua lity and race.
current forms of racism base themselves on cultural rather than Thus Sankofa's more recent film, Passion if Remembrance,
bio logical difference, but still on difference as tota l difference takes up these two issues, and then mixes the surreal and verite
(extolled and used for purposes of degradati on at the same time); at the level of ci nematic form to represent their incommen-
and yet it was also argued that the imperial image most urgently surability and their relation: the direct address to camera by the
in need of deconstruction is the one that denies all difference in woman narrator, located in a quaSi-surrea l space, from which
the name of an international "family of man" (the deconstruc- she interrogates both the spectator and the male comrade who is
tion of this image was the basis of the slide-tape SiBns if Empire allowed, in the only ever partial form of a dialogue, to enter the
made by the Black Audi o Film Co llective, one of the films shown visual field-all techniques which deconstruct the positionality
at the e,ent). Agai n, and without reducing them to each other, of the spectator as controller of the field of vision, and genders
the link ca n be made with a feminism which repudi ates a dif- quite expli citly that deco nstruction ; and then the documenting
ference which always and necessarily encodes itself as sexual dif- as domestic and soc ial detail of urban black life, the politics of
ference, and yet rests on that difference as the only place fro m sex uality given here as the story of the confrontation of genera-
which it can construct polit ical solidarities, the only place from t ions, in the representation of homosexuality, in the sexual self-
which it can in fact speak. In relation to the black filmmaking fashi oning of the young girl s. This is a film whose political forc e
represe nted at this event, it became clear that there could be no stems from this inmixing, from its refusal to settle the question
political filmmabng that wd not take up the very images that it of representation , in the way that it uses Simultaneously what
simultaneously designated as corrupt, whether directly as in SiBm have been histOrically two antagonistic cinematic forms. As if
if Empire or in the more documentary form of Sankofa's Territo- one of the questions whi ch race poses to sexual politics in the
ries which used, while also undOi ng by double commentary, in- fie ld of representation was neither that of addition nor supple-
terruption and repetition, the documenting of a history that it mentation, but more a collision of two types of visual space: a
was still-despite, or through, that deco nstruct ion - trying to story to be told alo ngSide the radical distrust and undOing of the
retrieve. possibility of story- of the possibility of containing all those
The point of mentioning this event and these films is not fo rms of antagonism within the visual field of the story or narra-
just to add racia l to sexual difference, as if to imply that psycho- tive as such. It seems that the sexual and politica l identification,
ana lysis could be modified by a wider cultural recognition which what is both a necessity and a refusal of identification within the
would balance the attentio n it pays to sex uality and identity available visual and psychiC parameters, can only be represented
above all else. To suggest that would be to disavow the fact that in the two forms of visual space. This is not, I hope, to appro-
psychoanalysis does indeed place sexua lity at the heart of psychi c priate these films, but rather to note how the introduction of ra-
orga nizati on and in the most fundamental dynamiC of the sign. cial politics into visual space, a racial politics which is also a
Rather, it is to stress the ways in which that very dynamic, and sex ual politics, reconfigures the relati on of image to identity, of
the questions of the image and identifi cation to which it is at- identity to its undOing - reconfigures what we might call, echo-

124 125
Jacqueline Rose I SEXU .... LITy .... NO VISION: SOME QUESTIONS

ing Norman Bryson's terms, tradition and des ire. I also wanted 6. Roland Barthes, A'~l rhoIOf/ies (1957), selected and trans. Annette Lavers (New
to end with this because of where I am talking, the Dia Art York: Hill and Wang, 1972).
7. Jacques Lacan, Lt seminairt de Jocques Lacan, Vol. 2: Le mo; dans Ie lhiorie de
Foundation, which seemed an appropriate place to introduce
Freud ond dons 10 rechnique de 10 psychonalj'se (Paris: Editions du Seuil, 1978),
these films. 10 p. 287. The quote continues: "It is an ideal of analysis which of course remains
virtual. There is ne\'er a subject, a fully realized subject, without ego, even
To sum up the t ..vo points which I have been arguing today: though it is what one should aim to obtain of the subject in analysis" (translated
by Sylvana Tomaselli, The E80 in Freud 's Theory ond in rhe Technique cif Ps),choonalysis
First, that the use of psychoanalysis in relation to the visual im-
[Cambridge: Cambridge Uni\'ersity Press, 1987]).
age is in danger of evacuating what is most psycbkally difficult 8. The papers and discussions at this event ha\'e been published in a special is-
from the concept of the unconscious and desire. This seems es- sue of Undercur, entitled Cu/ruro/ldemiries (no. 17, Spring 1988), edited by Nina
pecially important insofar as it is these very aspects of the un - Danino and published by the London Filmmakers' Coop.
conscious which seem to be mobili zed by the worst of right- 9. Felicity Collins, "A (Sad) Song of the Body," Screen 28, no. I (Winter 1987):
80 (special issue entitled deconsrfuclina 'ddforence'),
..."ing fantasy in our wider contemporary political life. Secondly,
10. For other discussions of Passion cif Remembrance and of the work of Sankofa,
that this is the precondition of a reification of the unconscious sec "An Inten'iew with Martina Attille and Isaac Julien of Sankofa," in )oun8,
over identity-an accusation aaainsr identity-which cannot be Black, ond British: A MonOSraph on Ihe Work qf SankaJo Film ond Video Callecril'e and
sustained in the form of this opposition psychoana lytica lly, nor if BJack Audio Film Colleelit'e, by Coco Fusco (Buffalo, N.Y.: Hallwalls, 1988).

we look at some of the most challenging interventions into what


has come to be defined, and for some lamented in all its cultural
manifestations, as the postmodern world.

Notes

I. Fredric Jameson, " Postmodernism or the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism,"


New Lifr Rel'iel!' 146 (July-August 1984): 63.
2. Fredric jameson, "Postmodernism and Consumer Society," in The Ami-
Aestheric: &says on POl/ modern Cu/rure, cd. Hal Foster (Port Townsend, Wash.: Ba),
Press, 1983), p. 120.
3. Jameson, "Postmodernism or the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism ," p. 8l.
( 4. See Jacqueline Rose, "'The Man Who Mistook His Wife For a Hat' or 'A
Wife Is Like an Umbrella' -Fantasies of the Modern and Post modern, " in Iden-
tity: The Reol A~e (London: Institute of Contemporary Arts, ICA Documents, no.
\ 6, 1988); also In UnirersoJ Abandon? The Polirics qf Posrmodernism. ed. Andrew Ross
d'
"
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1988).
'
5. Norman Bryson, Tradition and Desire: From Dat'id ro Delacroix (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge Unh'ersity Press, 1984), pp. 136-137.

11. 121
D I S C U S SI ON

lence within feminism itself. It is a complicated issue in relation


both to discussions of another po litics and to the resurge nce of
right-wing fantasies, which is the other reaso n why the issue of
Martin Jay I want to express my support for your powerful cri- psychi C negativity seems politically important. These right-wing
tique of an idealization of the psyche as some sort of antidote to fantasies act according to a paranoid trope (militarism, the Cold
soci al and other types of alienati on and dislocation. We have War, the Falk lands, capital punishment, the Bomb, South Afri ca,
seen many attempts in the twenti eth century to turn Freud in etc.), and these paranoid im ages serve to secur e an increaSingly
that direction - from Wilhelm Reich to Herbert Marcuse and repressive state apparatus. So I'm not posing what an ideal form
Norman O. Brown. I think we are now rather less inclined to do of medium subjecti vity might be; rather, I want to ask where are
this, though it is clear that with Deleuze and Guattari and others the Aashpoints of the soc ial and the psychi c that are operating
there are still versions of this attempt. Bu t J am also nervous most forcefull y at the moment. It is that which we need to un-
about the oppos ite inclinatio n, which is to accept the paranoid derstand , and in this context to discard the paran oid aspect of
view of the psyche, or of vision in the psyche, that Norman the lacanian account of vision would be unfortunate.
talked about in relation to Lacan. I think we have to find some Incidentally, when you talk about Lacan's paper on the
way to art iculate vari eties of visual-cum-psychic interacti on mirror stage, you take it out of the contex t of the paper next to
which are neither utopian and filled with a plenitude that is easy it, which is "Aggress ivit)' in Psychoanalysis." The idealization of
to dismiss nor somehow equivalent to all the types of non- the ego, which then everyone can set themsel ves against, is only
plenitudinous alienati on. The task is to come up with some sort possible because that other half of his argument has been dis-
of articulated register of visual-cum-psychic experiences- \vhich carded . And that is not an excl USively visual problem; it is also
include of Course the gender dimension - that would allow us to tactile, so I'm not sure we can mobilize touch as a so lution.
make rusc riminati ons. We ought not fall into the either-or of a
perfect plenitude - the Jameson problem -or some sort of Norman Bryson I think you are pointing to some very deep rhetor-
overly tragic psychoanalytic position in whi ch nothing rea lly can ical tropes that cut across all of us. One of these has to do with
be changed (which of course can also be read out of Freud). our celebration of " alternatives" -our desire here to find other
This is a g reat task, and I don't have any so luti ons. But I won- scopic regimes (is it going to be Dutch? baroque? Japanese?), to
dered . . vhat thoughts you might have about an intermediate range make them idyll iC and to take all of the diffi culty out of them.
that would avoid such an either-or. And a re\'ised, neutralized unco nscious is one of the idylliC fi c-
tions that result. To what ex tent would a revival of Merleau-
Jacqueline Rose I think f ag ree. I return to the negatke dimension Pont)'. or a return to phenomenology, be a perpetuatio n of that
for two reaso ns: one is because there is a ce rtain feminist inter- idyll ic, undiffi cult world ?
est in pre-Oedipal forms of sexual ity as that whi ch we can jux-
tapose to the dominant copulatory pair. T he problem here is Rose I didn't th ink people wanted to red ve hi m. I thought the
that it has to evacuate certain negativities, negativiti es which idea was that at the "ery point where one thinks one has got
have then returned in debates about se:..-uality and sexua l vio- somewhere else one has simply gone back to phenomenology.

128 ".
GENERAL DISCUSSION

/"
The problem is that this too can be set up as an "a l ~h'e"
the notion of the physiology of perception seen as a n otherness
in phenome nologica l te rm s. T his is one reason why there was so
much interest in interrogating the visual image via psycho- Audience (Sanford Kwinter) I'd like to address my question to Nor-
ana lysis-it became a search for an alternati\'e visual register. man and to push it in the direction of Jonathan's earlier ques-
But as soon as one begi ns to locate an alternative-which J tion. I appreciated your exposition, espeCially insofar as it
thought you did beautifully in your Rung-ink examples-then seemed , at least potentially, to be a construction of a typology
refe rences start flooding in to Heidegger, Merleau-Po nty, etc., rather than a comme nt on an essenti al opposition between a
and suddenly this othe rness belongs to a network which is the Western and an Eastern "'vision." Yet for me the interest of any'"
vcry corpus of Western philosophy and its institutional effects. typology is not to erect rubr ics to which one can t he n assign )
Also, from where can we talk about this othe r~s? It is the various objects, but rather to understand that any object man - -l
J,
same problem as that of the uni\'e rsa lity of psychoanalysis. What
\....ould be a non-Eurocentric respo nse to that question? For to
ifests distinctions within itself which the typology can then es-
tablish and ana lyze. So to me the power of your paper lies
o
say that psychoanalysis does not, or ca nnot, refer to non-Euro- outside the speci fic proposals that you made; it lies instead in
pean cultures, is to co nstitute those cultures in total "othe rness" the he uristi c capacity of your typology: in its capacity to be ap-
or "difference"; to say, or to try to demonstrate, that it can, is plied to "any object whatever" irrespective of traditi on, or, for
to constitute them as the "same." This is not to say that the example, to fold these different ideas back into our own Western
questi on mustn't still be asked. tradition, to define objects w ithin this traditi on and to under-
stand the ways in whi ch t he elements represented by this typol-
ogy play themsel\'es out in anyone of them. It is not necessary,
it seems to me, to have gone to a Japanese Heideggeri an to dis-
co\'er ideas which are finally quite Western ideas, or whic h are
not altogether d iffe rent from quite classical Western types of
thinking immane nce, for exam ple.
Let me then ask these two questions. First of all, would
you like to comment on the historical antecedents of this typol-
ogy already at work in Western painting, espeCially modernist
painting? One could, for example, elaborate a theory of modern-
ity based on this t ypology. It would consist in showing the shi ft
in emphasiS or mixture that one finds in t he twentieth century
as different from the mixtures one finds be fore the n. It seems to
me that in some such approach one might find - to address your
question, Jacqueline-a n alternati\'e to the search for alterna-

131
'"
G ENERAL OISCUSSION

tives, not from outside but, precisely with the aid of this applied pology, but havi ng done so I am surprised you have not taken
typology, from within, where one can see the field as constantly me up on it-for I know you are tryi ng to stay away fro m essen-
producing, perhaps microscopically, little alternatives, if you tializing these two traditions, It was really two different kinds of
li ke, shifts and changes and mixtures within some kind of mod- vis ion, each with their own correlative space, that you wanted to
ern immanence, Second, do you see in Western culture or the distinguish,
Western phil osophical tradition elements or precursors of these
ideas, especia lly those that you have here identified only with ex- Bryson Or three different ways of thinking decentering: Sartre,
amples from the East? Lacan, Nishitani .

Norman Brvson If one generalizes the ideas away from the Ch'an Kwinter So for you neither Western art nor Western philosophy
tradition in which they are embedded, then o ne will begin to suggests interna l co ntradicti ons of \'ision ?
find analogies, but Ch 'an is an independent philosophical t radi -
tion in its or igins, Bryson As soon as a step is made outside of the Western tradi -
t ion-and here a step not "ery far outs ide because those con-
Kwinler I don't want to look for analogies, I want to know to cepts are cycled from Heidegge r and others-it seems as though
what extent this typology can be brought back and acti,'ated one is invoking enormous totalities and worlds, and I really
within the Western-or any other single-context, and whether wasn't, If there is a misunderstanding hcre, it points to the
or not you can identify subtraditions within the Western philo- powerfulness of the tropes that totalize "the West" or even a
sophical tradition, "Cartesian perspecti\'alism ,"

Bryson I'm not sure I'm producing a typological argument; that's Audience Can you speCify an)' other artists who are examples of
the difficulty I have with your question, If I were, then it wou ld this Japanese idea of emptiness?
be "ery interesting to look not at Japanese traditions but at
Western subtraditions or moments and practices disengaged Bryson So many, so man)" But I wasn't ta lki ng histor ically,
from Cartesian perspectin lism, But I don't think my argument
is typo logica l, it is dealing ,'ery specifi cally with small sections of Audience (Catherine Liu) I want to comment on this exchange be-
a tex t of Lacan, of a tex t of Sartre, and of a book by Nis hitani , I cause I find it rather disturbing, I think if Norman had chosen a
don't see where I'm mobili zing typologies that wou ld make one Western art object as his example we wouldn't be forcing him to
quest for Western examples rather than Eastern o nes, whether draw other examples fr0111 thc bod)' of Western art, If he had
mi cro-examples or large total iti es, It's not an argument that has shown us a Franz Kline wc wouldn't be asking him if there are
to do with great blocks of art or e,'en thought, other artists that manifest this decentering. Here we are in our
strange igloo looking out through little wi ndows, I think the re-
Kwinter Clearly it is I who ha,'c introduced the question of ty- sistance that wc ha,'e to the O riental obj ect that was shown is

132
CONTRIBUTORS

ind icat ive of a whole theater of magic that we get into when we
dea l \vith the other-and this other is not char much other of
an other.
Norman Bryson is the author of three books, Word and Imoae (Cam-
bridge UniYersity Press), Vision and Paint ina: The Laaic cf the Gaze
(Yale University Press), and Tradition and Desire: From David ro
Delacraix (Cambridge University Press), and editor of a collection
of poststructuralist texts on art, Cal/iaram (Cambridge Uni"ersity
Press); he presently teaches at the University of Rochester.

Jonathan Crory teaches art history at Columbia University, where


he is cur rently a fellow in the Society of Fellows in the Human-
iti es; co-editor of Zone, he will soon publish a book on the ob-
se rver in the nineteenth century (M IT Press).

Martin Jay is professor of history at the University of California,


Berkeley, and author of The Dialectical Imaainatian (Little,
Brown), Adorno (Han'ard Uni\'ersit)' Press), and Marxism and
Tacalic), (University of California Press).

Rosalind Krauss, co-editor of Ocrober, is professor of art history at


Hunter College and the CUNY Graduate Center; her books in-
clude Passases in Modern Sculpture and The Oriaina/ity of the
Avance-Garde and Ocher Modernist Myths (both MIT Press).

Jacqueline Rose teaches at the University of Sussex; she is the


author of The Case of Peler Pan, or the Impossibilityof Children's
Ficrion and Sexualjcy in the Field of Vision (Verso), and editor (with
Juli et Mitchell) and translator of Feminine Sexuality: Jacques Lacan
and the Ecole Freudienne (W. W. Norton).

'" '"

Anda mungkin juga menyukai