Anda di halaman 1dari 9

What Is Complexity Science?

It is Really Order-Creation Science


Emergence, 3, 2001, 137157.
Please check for changes in published version before quoting or paraphrasing.

Bill McKelvey
The Anderson School at UCLA, 110 Westwood Plaza, Los Angeles, CA 90095-1481
tel 310/825-7796 fax 310/206-2002 mckelvey@anderson.ucla.edu
Complexity science appears to be problematic and inconsistent in accounting for processes of order-creation, as indicated by a review beginning with
coarse-graining in quantum entanglement fields and ending with emergent order from social entanglement ties: A theory about the engine of order-creation at
any of the several levels of order (atoms to social systems), or across the levels, is missing as a collective belief among complexity scientists. The classic
concept of external (Bnard) energy-differentials (as control parameters) that cause emergence at the edge of chaos is frequently missing. The nature of the
entanglement pool or basemore broadly the set of network ties among agents such as atoms, molecules, organisms, human actorsfrom which emergent
order, is often ignored. The implications for the adaptive efficaciousness of subsequent emergence events, of the possibility in biological and social systems
that prior emergence events could have fed back to irrevocably corrupt the entanglement or network base, also are not considered. The interaction of
Bnard, Darwinian and rational order-creation processes is barely considered. Finally, attention to the basic causal processes underlying emergent order
largely has been ignored in most managerial and organizational applications of complexity science. The paper concludes by outlining essential problematics
of order-creation science.

1 INTRODUCTION are what cause order (Ashby 1956). This results in his
law of requisite variety (1956): For a biological or
Order and its synonyms means put persons or social entity to be efficaciously adaptive, the variety of its
things into their proper places in relation to each other. internal order must match the variety of the
Disorder, to natural scientists, means the 2nd law of environmental constraints. Furthermore, he also observes
thermodynamics, namely, inexorable dissipation toward that order does not emerge when the environmental
entropy and randomness. Kauffman (1993) and Holland constraints are chaotic (1956, pp. 131132).
(1995) use the term, order, in the titles of their books,
respectively The Origins of Order and Hidden Order. But what causes emergent order and self-
Mainzer (1997) titles his book Thinking In Complexity, organization? What is the underlying generative
but on page one he says: The theory of nonlinear mechanism or engine of order-creation? How is the order-
complex systemsis an interdisciplinary methodology to creation process inside firms linked to their competitive
explain the emergence of certain macroscopic phenomena context? Science is about finding causes of phenomena
via the nonlinear interactions of microscopic elements in (Pearl 2000, Salmon 1998). If you start with the Prigogine
complex systems. And then every subsequent chapter line of thought (updated in Nicolis and Prigogine 1989)
starts with a question about the emergence of orderin and continue with Mainzers development, it is clear that
matter, life, brain, computer, and social systems. It is not the only engine of order-creation considered in
by happenstance that our journal is titled EMERGENCE! complexity science, so far, is the Bnard Process:
1. Negentropy becoming available because of the energy differential
Views of order-creation have changed over the last or adaptive tension existing between a system and its surroundings, and
century, as one might expect. Classical management imposing upon microagents within the system, causes emergence; and
theorists (Massie 1965) say order comes solely from the 2. The 1st and 2nd critical values of R, the measure of tension, define
(rational?) thoughts and actions of owner/managers, the upper and lower bounds of the region of emergence (self-
captured nicely in the following quote attributed to Henry organization or complexity) sandwiched between the regions of order
(slow change) and chaos (dysfunctional change).
Ford: Why is it that whenever I ask for a pair of hands, a
brain comes attached?1 The Darwin-Wallace theory of Prigogines basic argument is that the 1st and 2nd laws
natural selection (Darwin 1859) explains speciation in the of thermodynamics would not exist if order has not
biological world, that is: Why are there different kinds of been created in the first place. Darwins process of
organisms? Durkheim (1893) and Spencer (1898) also natural selection is irrelevant if order has not been
define order as the emergence of kinds, specifically, created in the first place. Complexity scienceas a
social entities. Half a century later, however, Sommerhoff general explanation of emergent orderis problematic
(1950), Ashby (1956, 1962), and Rothstein (1958) define and inconsistent in accounting for the Bnard process, as
order not in terms of entities but rather in terms of the is evident in the literature emerging from the physical,
connections among them. Ashby adds two critical biological, and social sciences. Worse, attention to the
observations. Order (organization), he says, exists basic causal process underlying emergence has largely
between two entities, A and B, only if the link is been ignored in most managerial and organizational
conditioned by a third entity, C (1962, p. 255). If C applications of complexity science.
symbolizes the environment, which is external to the First, I review explanations of how order in matter
connection between A and B, environmental constraints (what Gell-Mann calls coarse-graining) emerges from the
fine-grained structure of the entangled (correlated)
histories of pairs of agents. Then I consider biological
systems, dissipative structures, the Bnard process, and
1 Quoted in Hamel (2000, p. 102). order-creation in organizations. Following Mainzer
2

(1997), my analysis leads to the inescapable conclusion temperature, wind, swirling dust, flies, nature of the other
that complexity science is really order-creation science people betting, track owners, mental state and health of
mistakenly characterized by a relatively extreme end the jockeys, and a hundred other factors that conceivably
state, complexity. could affect the outcome of a race. All other times and the
history of everything else in the universe is ignored.
2 ORDER-CREATION THEORY
How do the race probabilities emerge from the
IN COMPLEXITY SCIENCE interference of the fine-grained structure? Gell-Mann says
Coarse-graining. In a book written for popular that when we sum over all of the detailed factors left
consumption, Gell-Mann (1994, Ch. 11) uses a few outthat are not the tips of the noses of the few horses
simple terms to explain how electrons interact with one in, say, the fourth racethe interference effects average
another such that the quantum state of the one is affected out at approximately zero. Hence all the effects of the
by the otherthus, over a series of time intervals, their myriad tiny correlations among the details have no effect.
quantum states are correlated.2 This is referred to as The context of our interest in the winning horse causes us
entanglement. The quantum state of a given electron is, to sum-over all the other fine-grained correlations. The
thus, a function of its entanglement with all the other race-relevant correlations among all the fine-structure
electrons it is correlated with. At any given time, in a effects are focused onto become the coarse-grained
sequence of time intervals, each electron has a history of structurewhereas all the other detail correlations are
effects from all the other electrons it has come in contact summed-over and their interference made irrelevant.
with. Because of the countless correlations, and the When this happens, there are really three effects: (1) most
differing quantum states of all the other electrons, each of the history quantities, D, are ignored, that is, summed
individual history is likely unique. Consequently quantum over; (2) the few correlated histories that become
theorists cannot attach a probability of occurrence to each important do so because of the particular time and
individual electrons history. Instead, they use a quantity, placethe contextmeaning that the histories are similar
D(A, B) to record the relation between the quantum and conjoined or the horses wouldnt be in the same race
histories of two correlated electrons over timethus D is at the same place at the same time.
always assigned to pairs of individual electron histories, Gell-Mann says: A coarse-grained history may be
A and B. Entanglement occurs when the correlated regarded as a class of alternative fine-grained histories, all
histories of pairs of electrons are greater than zero. If the of which agree on a particular account of what is
individual histories are correlated, they are said to followed, but vary over all possible behaviors of what is
interfere with each other. Since most histories are not followed, what is summed over (p. 144). Empirical
correlated with other histories, D is seldom a probability. researchers play this game every time they assume that
If histories almost always interfere, and thus D is almost the various effects not specifically hypothesized, or
never a probability, the root question is: How can designed into the study as control variables, are
physicists predict with probability, let alone with what randomized. That is, they neutralize each other and are,
seems to most of us, virtual certainty? thus, summed over. The emergent coarse-graining process
Gell-Mann refers to the world of interference-prone overcomes the interference-term effect by translating
histories as fine-grained structure. Thus, the quantum entanglement into probability, what Gell-Mann speaks of
world is the fine-grained structure whereas he labels the as decoherence (p. 146).3 Recall that the interference
world of quasiclassical physics as the coarse-grained terms are the myriad correlations between pairs of
structure. The question then arises, How does coarse- particles in the fine-grained structure. Coarse-graining
grained structure emerge from fine-grainedentangled results in the selecting out from the myriad the correlated
structure? He uses the metaphor of a race-track. As you histories of the same kind and the same level of
get to your seat at the race track and consider the odds on relationship. Gell-Mann says coarse-graining washes
your favorite horse to win, you eventually ignore all of out the interferences among histories in the fine-grained
the other factors that could affect the racequality of structure (p. 145146).
horse feed and vets, the state of the track, sunlight, Roland Omns4 (1999) develops an interpretation that
connects better with complexity science. He makes a

2 I have double checked everything Gell-Mann says with the recent


modern interpretation by Omns (1999), whom Gell-Mann cites with
3 Omns (1999, p. 75) defines decoherence as the absence of
approval. The Omns treatment is more technical and treats in book-
length what Gell-Mann covers in one chapter. Their views are macroscopic interferences.
consistent, but, for example, they do view the collapse of the collective 4 It is worth noting that Gell-Mann (1994) says of Roland Omns as
wave packet(s) that is Mars in somewhat different ways. In addition, follows: Among those who have made especially valuable contributions
Omns holds that decoherence in the universe is so pervasive and are Robert Griffiths and Roland Omns, whose belief in the importance
instantaneous that decoherence has happened long before any observer of histories we [referring to James Hartle and himself] share. Hartle
happens upon the scenethus observers such as the watcher (Mills and I, like Griffiths and Omns, make use of the fact that the questions
1994) are superfluous. always relate ultimately to alternative histories of the universe. (A
3

strong association between irreversibility, dissipation, and nature are [coarse-grained] features. They are structured
decoherence, arguing that the essential character of patterns that collapse an underlying sea of chaos [the fine-
decoherence appears to be irreversibility (p. 196). He grained entanglement pool], and they are conditioned by
shows that decoherence is an irreversible dynamical context (1994, p. 433). Their explanation is
process (p. 206). Complexity scientists should note the contextualist rather than reductionist. Their prime
parallel of Omnss and Prigogines treatment of time example is evolution (p. 418); really coevolution (p. 420).
irreversibility (Prigogine and Stengers 1984). Omns Cohen and Stewart see emergent order as resulting from
suggests a total Hamiltonian: H = Hc + He + H1, where Hc several dynamics:
is the Hamiltonian of the relevant internal variables of a First, there is the emergence of feedback loops that
system, He is the Hamiltonian of the environmental join entities that otherwise could evolve separately. For
variables (potentially all other variables or degrees of example, Cohen and Stewart say that DNA sequences
freedom in the Universe) and H1 a coupling of the two live in DNA space, and in the absence of any other
systems representing how the environmental variables influences would wander around dynamically through the
affect or are affected by the internal variables (1999, p. geography of DNA space, seeking attractors and settling
198). He shows that the dynamical suppression of the on them. Similarly [for] organisms [that] live in creature
environmental interferences of He Hamiltonian almost space. They, too, can evolve independently
immediately produces a large decoherence effect (p. 203). seeking attractors and settling on them (p. 419). Both
He bases many of his statements on an axiom by the DNA and organism could evolve independently of each
French mathematician Borel (1941) that: one must other. But, it is the joining of these two spaces by
consider that events with too small a probability never feedback loopsthe coevolution of hierarchically related
occur (Omns 1999, p. 84, 236). While probability spacesthat counts. This parallels Omnss coupling of
mathematicians have to take vanishingly small Hc and Hc. More broadly, it is the interaction of
probabilities into account, he summarizes Borel as saying, heretofore independent spaces that are inherently
this kind of event cannot be reproducible and should conflicting, but coupled because of the effect of other
be left out of science (p. 84). influences, that causes coarse-graining (p. 414). Because
Omns view is essential. His introduction of He the attractors in DNA space are likely to differ from those
recognizes that decoherence and emergent coarse- in creature space, once the feedback loop exists, novel
graining, even in quantum theory, are now subject to the structures are apt to emerge. In this example, and indeed
regular-to-chaotic forces imposed upon these fields. The all of the examples Cohen and Stewart give, the
external force, and its nature, results from the tension mechanisms for coarse-graining in biology are Darwinian
created by the Bnard energy-differentials recognized by selectionist processes.
chaos and complexity scientists that foster negentropy Second, Cohen and Stewart argue that entanglement
and create emergent structure. In the simple Bnard cell, pools are seldom purely randomreally random
and in the atmosphere, an energy-differential causes systems would not possess statistical regularities (p. 233;
energy transfer via bulk (current) movements of gas their italics). Thus, emergent structure can follow from
molecules rather than via in-place vibrations and statistical features. Absent pure randomness, the
collisions. More broadly, think of an energy-differential correlated histories of quanta or higher level entities
as producing coarse-graining among histories of the molecules, genes, organisms, etc.are distributed
vibrating moleculesor among histories of bottom-level probabilistically, with the more probable correlations
microagents in general. In this view, the energy- more likely to lead to emergent coarse-grained structure
differentials of complexity theory become the causes of or the observation of same. Instead of Gell-Manns
emergent coarse-grained structure from entanglement dependence on photon scattering to create collapsed wave
pools. functions in purely random entanglement pools, they
Collapse of chaos. Cohen and Stewart (1994) refer to argue that many, if not most, pools are not purely random,
naturally occurring coarse-graining as emergent and therefore coarse-graining is probable.
simplicity and the collapse of chaos. Their explanation Third, Cohen and Stewart observe that many kinds of
of how coarse-grained structure emerges from fine- emergence do not stem from statistical distributions.
grained structure is the opposite of reductionismthus, There is nothing statistical about , the Feigenbaum
their explanation is the antithesis of Gell-Manns. Gell- number, the Mandelbrot setor chlorophyll, DNA, or
Manns laws of nature, to Cohen and Stewart, are homeotic genes, for that matter. Statistics is just one
Sherlock Holmes stories scientists use to explain way for a system to collapse the chaos of its fine structure
emergent simplicity. That they are predictive, especially and develop a reliable large-scale feature. Other kinds of
in physics, is a fortuitous accident. In their view, laws of feature can crystallize out from underlying chaos
numbers, shapes, patterns of repetitive behavior (pp.
233234).
history is merely a narrative of a time sequence of eventspast, present, Fourth, Cohen and Stewart identify some kinds of
or future.) (pp. 138, 140)
4

emergencespecifically crystallographyas immune to theory of irreversibility, that is, entropy, demonstrating


the state of entanglement (p. 237). Recall that in Gell- systematically the process whereby atoms and molecules
Manns view of quantum mechanics, the correlated showing different momenta and coordinatesthe qs and
histories of quanta result in purely random quantum states ps in a Hamiltonian expressionreduce to a sea of
and a purely random entanglement pool. And, in his view, highly multiple incoherent correlations (1962, p. 8).
coarse-graining is only a function of photon scattering. In Having translated the qs and ps into correlated histories,
contrast, Cohen and Stewart see the correlated histories of Prigogine, sets the stage for carrying his analysis across
atoms as following the rules of deterministic chaos the seeming discontinuity between atoms and molecules
since the motion of atoms is chaotic, their precise and the lower-level correlated histories that Gell-Mann
behavior is sensitive to initial conditions (p. 236; their mentions in his analysis. Prigogines analysis shows how
italics). They say: Quantum systems dont exhibit chaos the coarse-graining apparent in the universe can actually,
in the conventional sense, but any classical (that is, and eventually, reduce to the random correlated quantum
nonquantum) theory of large numbers of particles histories in the fine-grained structure.
certainly does. Quantum systems arent chaotic because Control Parameters. Control parameters, as
the infinitely fine structures that are important for chaos Mainzer (1997) uses the term, refers to external forces
are forbidden in quantum mechanics, thanks to the causing the emergence of dissipative structures in the
uncertainty principle (p. 236). But then they say: region of complexity. He begins with a review of
Quantum mechanics has its own form of small-scale Lorenzs (1963) discovery of a deterministic model of
chaosgenuinely random fluctuations, rather than the turbulence in weather systems. A discussion of research
deterministic but effectively random fluctuations of focusing on Benrd cells follows. Here we discover that
conventional chaos (p. 237). What emerges is a level-of- critical values in the energy (temperature, T)
analysis effect: In their view, correlated histories of differential between warmer and cooler surfaces of the
quantum states are purely random, but the correlated cell affect the velocity, R, of the air flow, which correlates
histories of atomsand derivatively, all higher levels with T. The surfaces of the cell represent the hot surface
are deterministically chaotic (p. 236). of the earth and the cold upper atmosphere. The critical
Finally, they say: Crystal lattices are not just immune values divide the velocity of air flow in the cell into three
to small-scale chaos; they are immune to most of quantum kinds: (1) Below the 1st critical value, heat transfer occurs
mechanics (p. 237). Why? The main thing we need to via conductiongas molecules transfer energy by
know is that physical systems tend to minimize their vibrating more vigorously against each other while
energy. This argument in favor of an atomic lattice is remaining essentially in the same place; (2) Between the
independent of the shape of the atoms or their detailed 1st and 2nd critical values, heat transfer occurs via a bulk
properties; energy minimization is enough. Crystal movement of air in which the gas molecules move
lattices are not just phenomena that emerge from quantum between the surfaces in a circulatory pattern. We
mechanics. They have a universal aspect; they will encounter these in aircraft as up- and down-drafts; and (3)
emerge from any theory sufficiently close to quantum Above the 2nd critical value a transition to chaotically
mechanics that involves identical roughly spherical atoms moving gas molecules is observed.
and energy minimization. This kind of universality is Prigogines emergent dissipative structures form in
common to many, perhaps all, emergent phenomena the region of emergent complexity in between the critical
(p. 237; my italics). values. Cramer (1993) observes that the three regions
Cohen and Stewart focus on the selectionist effect in defined by the critical values define three kinds of
biology and the chaos and energy minimization effects in complexity: subcritical 1st critical 2nd
physics at the level of atoms. They recognize that fundamental. His definitions appear in Table 1. The
selection effects produce increasing complexity and algorithmic compressibility characterizing all the laws of
increasing degrees of freedom. And though they dont use classical Newtonian science appears mostly in the
the term, still, in their view, biological organisms are subcritical region but also in the fundamental region of
emergent dissipative structures that, once formed, deterministic chaos. Mainzer (1997, p. 63) says,
dissipate imported negentropy. In this sense, their mathematical symmetry is defined by the invariance of
collapse of chaos produces coarse-graining far from certain laws with respect to several transformations
equilibrium, to use Prigogines phrase. between the corresponding reference systems of an
Dissipative Pressure. Prigogine uses dissipative observer. Thus, symmetry dominates the subcritical
structures to explain both the cause and disappearance of region and to some extent also applies to the fundamental
coarse-graining. Dissipative structures are shown to exist region. Furthermore, the invariant laws are reversible
far from equilibrium and seemingly counter to the 2nd (Prigogine and Stengers 1984). But, as a control
law of thermodynamicsthe entropy law holding that parameter causes R to move across the critical values,
all order in the universe eventually reverts to purely however, the consequence is symmetry breaking, at least
random disorder and thermal equilibrium (Prigogine in part, because the laws of classical physics do not
1962). In this classic monograph, he develops a general
5

remain invariant. stochastically driven by the tail end of the disappearing


>>> Insert Table 1 about here <<< unstable vectors. By this process, at the phase transition,
most of the vectors simply disappear into entanglement.
As Prigogine (1962, Nicolis and Prigogine 1989)
But the trace number at the end collapses the vectors
observes, in the region of emergent complexity are
(wave packets) thereby creating the order parameters
created emergent dissipative structures far from
governing the emergence of dissipative structures. This
equilibrium as a result of importing energy into the
amounts to an explanation of emergent quantum chaos
system (at some rate) as negentropy. Though this process
and the vanishingly small initial order parameters that,
is nonlinear and not subject to symmetry, Cramer (1993)
like the butterfly effect, eventually influence the forms of
observes that once created, dissipative structures become
emergent dissipative structures of quasiclassical physics.
subject to the symmetry and invariant laws of classical
physics. The final state of dissipation, that is, of perfect The Bnard energy-differential figures centrally in
entropy, is easily describable by a master equation from Mainzers treatment of complexity theory. Omns does
statistical mechanics; the probable positions of millions of not refer explicitly to something akin to the Bnard
particles subject to Brownian motion can be reduced to process, but he does focus on an external Hamiltonian
minimal degrees of freedom. In reverse, the creation of and context. Ashby and Rothstein emphasize external
emergent dissipative structures is in fact a creation of environmental constraints as causes of order, but they do
degrees of freedom. As Mainzer puts it, complexity not define constraints in terms of anything looking like an
means that a system has a huge number of degrees of energy-differential. The latter might be inferred vaguely
freedom (p. 65). in the background, perhaps, in the Cohen and Stewart
treatment. And energy-differentials do not figure in Gell-
Phase Transition. In the following bullets I trace out
Manns photon scattering caused coarse-graining, though
the order Mainzer describes and match his steps with
the photons do represent the context of an external energy
Gell-Manns coarse-graining process:
source. But no mention is made as to whether they can
1. Start with an existing dissipative structure behaving according to a
appear below, between or above the 1st and 2nd critical
Newtonian Hamiltoniana coarse-grained structure in Gell-Manns
terms. valuesthough presumably, and perhaps rather
2. Just before the 1st critical value is reached (from below), unstable obviously, back radiation could be below the 1st and an
vectors (wave packets, modes, energy, forces, motions) appear along exploding star well above the 2nd. But Mainzer and
with the stable waves. Omns argue that energy-differentials could or should be
3. As the unstable vectors multiply they begin to enslave the stable taken into account.
vectors, thus eliminating the latter. Degrees of freedom are thereby
reduced, as is complexity. Decoherence is crumbling, resulting in Mainzer views complexity science as an exploration
interference and entanglement. Consequently, coarse-graining is of endogenously created nonlinearities operating in the
reduced. context of control parameters and threshold effects. His
4. The unstable vectors and their degrees of freedom disappear into a analysis carries this theme across matter, life, mind (real
stochastic pool of Brownian motion. This leads to a vast reduction in and artificial), and into economic and other social
degrees of freedom. Decoherence has nearly disappeard.
systems. Whether firms are analogized as biological
5. The last few unstable vectors remaining become order parameters ecologies governed by Darwinian selection, as brains and
acting to create the emergent dissipative structures as the system tips
over the 1st critical value into the region of emergent complexity distributed intelligence, as economies, or as networks of
meaning that the order parameters surviving across the complete phase human and social capital Morgan (1997, McKelvey
transition are totally the result of a stochastic process. forthcoming-a), Mainzers analysis applies. Following
6. At this juncture, order, complexity, and increased degrees of Schumpeter, Mainzer identifies innovation and
freedom emerge. The result is decoherence and emergent coarse- technological change as the primary engine setting both
graining. This is where context has greatest impact.
the nonlinear and Bnard processes in motion and, thus,
7. The region of emergent complexity persists until the energy-
differential is reduced by virtue of the continuing emergence of
creating dissipative structures and emergent order. He
dissipative structures. That is, coarse-graining continues until the specifically mentions Allens (1988) discovery of these
energy-differential is reduced. Of course, if the energy-differential is processes at work in urban development as a social
continuously renewed equal to, or even faster that the existing system application. Allens study of Atlantic fisheries
dissipative structures can reduce it, more dissipative structures will
(Allen and McGlade 1986, 1987) and recent analysis of
continue to emerge. Unless of course the energy-differential rises over
the 2nd critical value. Then chaotic processes take over. knowledge management (Allen forthcoming) also
instruct.
Mainzer teases out the fine-grained process events just
before and after the phase transition at the 1st critical An even broader extension of the Bnard process
value. Recalling Omnss (1999) argument, that stems from Swensons work (1989, 1998). His law of
decoherence processes occur more rapidly than can ever maximum entropy production holds that a system will
be measured, we realize that a physical system passes select the path or assembly of paths out of otherwise
through the several states outlined in the bullets above available paths that minimize the potential or maximize
very rapidlyperhaps too rapidly to measure. the entropy at the fastest rate given the constraints. The
Nevertheless, we see that emergent structure is world will select order whenever it gets the chancethe
world is in the order-production business because
6

ordered flow produces entropy faster than disordered according to thick description researchers (Geertz 1973)
flow (1998, p. 173, his italics). Consider the Big Bang as and relativists and postmodernists (Burrell and Morgan
the ultimate heat source and outer space as the ultimate 1979, Lincoln 1985, Reed and Hughes 1992, Hassard and
heat sink. At some point in time, every particle of matter Parker 1993, Weick 1995, Chia 1996), naturally
in the universe will pass through the 1st and 2nd critical occurring order in firms emerges from the conflation of
values of the Bnard process. Order-creation of the inherent stochastic idiosyncrasies of individuals
dissipative structures is pervasive and inevitable. aspirations, capabilities, and behaviorsthe social
Galaxies, the Sun, and the Earth are all order-creations for scientists analog of entanglement, I argue.5
maximizing entropy creation. Life on the surface of the Where to look for developing a theory of natural
Earth emerged in the context of the giant atmospheric and order emergence in firms? Complexity science, of
plate tectonic Bnard processes. Western civilization, course.6 Management writers mostly emphasize chaos and
including all its social systems, organizations, and firms, complexity theories as a means of better understanding
is a lesser order-creation device that, in fact, is so the behavior of firms facing uncertain, nonlinear, rapidly
effective a dissipative process that it is rapidly depleting changing environments (Maguire and McKelvey 1999b).
the resources upon which it depends. Innovations and This view is somewhat off the track (McKelvey 1999b).
new technologies create energy and resource disparities in As demonstrated above, going back to the roots of
economiesBnard thresholdsthat firms, as order- complexity science in quantum physics and Prigogines
creations, emerge to dissipate the energy/resource work, we see more accurately that complexity science is
differentials. Complexity science applications have now fundamentally aimed at explaining order-creation. Much
spread to the physical, life, social, and management of normal science focuses on equating energy translations
sciences (Nicolis and Prigogine 1989, Cowan, Pines and from one form of order to anotherworking under the 1st
Meltzer 1994, Belew and Mitchell 1996, Arthur, Durlauf, law of thermodynamics. This is all in the context of the
and Lane 1997, Mainzer 1997, McKelvey 1997, Byrne order within existing dissipative structures. The 2nd law of
1998, Cilliers 1998, Anderson 1999, Maguire and thermodynamics focuses on the inevitable disintegration
McKelvey 1999a, b), among many others. Complexity of existing order. Also, I have argued that complexity
science is now pervasive and at its core are endogenous science aims to explain the emergence of orderit is
nonlinearities and the Bnard process. order-creation science.
3 EXPLAINING ORDER IN Decoherence and Emergence. Using complexity
science, I have outlined the idea that quantum wave
ORGANIZATIONS packets are collapsed by external forces and particularly
Kinds of Order. Three kinds of order exist in by imposed energy-differentials, following the Modern
organizations: rational, natural, and open systems (Scott Interpretation. Not to have done this would have left
1998). Rational systems result from prepensive conscious entanglementand the decoherence of it via the human
intentionalities, usually by managers. Natural systems, observer (Mermin 1991, or Mills (1994) watcher of the
such as informal groups, typically emerge as employees universesolidly in the hands of relativists and
attempt to achieve personal goals in the context of a postmodernists who decry normal science because
command-and-control bureaucracy. Open systems are in everything that is ostensibly and objectively detected
various ways defined by external forces. That all three by science is interpreted subjectively by the human
exist goes unquestioned. What remains vague, however, observerswhat we see is nothing more than the result of
are explanations about how they emerge, coevolve, come wave packets collapsed by subjective human observers.
to dominate one another, and collectively impact This would encourage the subjective, loose, metaphorical
organizational performance. Specifically, how do these treatment of the term, entanglement, as it is applied to
three forces combine to produce the order we see in firms, social systems.
where order is defined in terms of formal structure and
I can now remind organization scientists that the most
process and other patterns of behavior within and by a
fundamental question of complexity science: What
firm?
McKelvey (1997) defines organizations as quasi-
natural phenomena, caused by both the conscious
intentionality of those holding formal office (rational 5 See McKelvey (forthcoming-c) for further discussion of the marriage
systems behavior) and naturally occurring structure and of postmodernist ontology and normal science epistemology.
process emerging as a result of coevolving individual 6 Sociologists have studied the process of emergent social order since
employee behaviors in a selectionist context (natural and Durkheim (1893) and Spencer (1898). For recent examples, see
open systems behavior). With respect to the latter, two Ridgeway and Berger (1986, 1988), Berger et al. (1998) and Mark
general order-causing effects appear in firms: (1) (1998). Ridgeway and Berger focus on power legitimation. For them,
differentiation follows from the influence of forces external to the social
selectionist microcoevolution (McKelvey 1997, 1999a, c; system. Mark focuses on information effects. For him, however,
forthcoming-a); and (2) complexity catastrophe differentiation can emerge in totally undifferentiated systems without the
(Kauffman 1993, McKelvey 1999a, c). More broadly, effect of external forces.
7

Causes Order-Creation? Complexity theory 1. There is some level of correlation between the histories of all
possible pairs of agents in the fine-grained structure.
applications to firms rest on environmental constraints in
the form of Bnard energy-differentials as the engines of 2. Because each agent interferes with all the others, probabilities of
how one agent affects another cannot be assignedtheir destinies, thus,
order-creationdefined as the emergence of both entities are entangled.
and connections constrained by context. The latter, when 3. Coarse-graining washes out interference terms in the fine-grained
applied to firms, are best thought of as adaptive tension structure, which is to say, coarse-graining washes out entanglement and
parameters (McKelvey forthcoming-a). Going back to the results in probabilitiesand probabilistic natural lawsrather than
Bnard cellthe hot plate represents a firms current interferences.
position; the cold plate represents where the firm 4. Energy-differentialsadaptive tensionimpinging on agents can,
therefore, cause coarse-graining and the creation of probable outcomes
should be positioned for improved success. The
emerging from the pool of entangled agents.
difference is adaptive tension. This tension motivates
5. In addition to causing coarse-graining, the likelihood that the
the importation of negentropy and the emergence of energy-differential field effect will disrupt the entanglement pool so as
adaptation fostering dissipative structuresassuming the to corrupt the purity of entanglement, so to speak, increases, going
tension lies between the 1st and 2nd critical values. from physical to biological to social worlds.
My review of entanglement, decoherence, and coarse- 6. Because of the feedback effect, the interrelation of entanglement
and adaptive tension in social systems sets them apart from physical and
graining, modified by reference to complexity science and to some extent biological systemsthough I would not rule out the
ranging from quanta to social systems, uncovers the effect in physical systems. For example, in a Bnard cell, if one removes
second fundamental question in applying complexity the energy differential the molecules revert to the conductivity state and
science to firmsso far totally unrecognized: Emergence it is if there had been no emergent structure. With organizations,
however, successive emergent orders leave an accumulated legacy that
from What? Organization scientists and managers about usually does not disappear if the adaptive tension is removedthough it
to apply complexity science to firms cannot willy-nilly could easily deteriorate into a somewhat different coarse-graining.
assume that entanglement exists uncorrupted in a given Given the definition of complexity science presented
firm. Absent entanglement, altering adaptive tension here, what should managers worry about? I dont have
parameters could produce maladaptive results. The space for details (see instead McKelvey forthcoming-a,
nature of the initial pool of entangled particles appears b), but some key elements are:
essential to the coarse-graining process. In Gell-Manns
1. Before emergent order-creation has any chance of being
view, coarse-grained structure emerges from entangled efficacious, the uncorrupted entanglement pools from which order
fine-grained structure as a result external influences. emerges have to already exist or be created. This creates initial
Remove the external influence and macro structure conditions.
disappears in the Bnard cell and coarse-grained quanta 2. Goal-setting becomes a context identification process. This is a
disappear back into wave packets. If energy-differentials process of identifying which kinds of adaptive tension parameters should
be the center of attention. Besides being identified, incentives for paying
are viewed as causes of coarse-graining, four critical attention to them have to be put in place. A classic example is Jack
differences appear: Welchs Be #1 or #2 in your industry or you will be sold. It defines
1. Given an initially pure, uncorrupted, or untampered-with pool of context, an adaptive tension, and motivation all in one short phrase. This
entanglements, the first coarse-graining resulting from an imposed sets up the Bnard process.
energy-differential could alter entanglement in an irrevocable fashion 3. Focus on enlarging the region of emergent complexity (order-
whether in physical, biological, or social entanglement pools. creation). Some firms cycle between bureaucracy and chaos because the
2. Whereas in the Newtonian physical world (Cramers (1993) region of emergence is virtually nonexistent. Focus on lowering the 1st
subcritical complexity) of quanta and molecules the energy-differential and raising the 2nd critical values. This increases the probability of
effect is time-reversible, in the biological and social worlds, as Prigogine Bnard processes and emergence.
would say (Prigogine and Stengers 1984), it is a time-irreversible 4. Agency problems and other noxiants need to be avoided (via
process. Omns includes the physical world as well. strange attractor management) so as to avoid emergence in directions
3. As a consequence, especially in biological and social clearly not in a firms best interest.
entanglements, any subsequent coarse-graining starts with some vestige
of the prior coarse-graining effects remaining in the entanglement pool. 4 CONCLUSION
This means that complexity science in the biological and social worlds is My review suggests that:
fundamentally different than in the physical world.
1. A theory about the engine of order-creation at any of the several
4. In the social worldand particularly in the world of firmsthere
levels of order (atoms to social systems), or across the levels, is not
is the possibility, if not actual advantage or necessity, of constantly
obvious as a coherent collective belief among complexity scientists, but
managing to preserve or recreate one or more pools of fine-grained
Mainzers analysis is the most comprehensive available to date;
entanglements as primordial bases from which subsequent energy-
differential caused coarse-grained structures emerge. 2. The classic concept of external (Bnard) energy-differentials (as
control parameters) that cause emergence at the edge of chaos is at the
To summarize, the logic sequencein agent terms 7
heart of complexity science, but is frequently missing in much of the
is as follows: complexity science literature. Especially it is missing in organizational
applications;
3. The nature of the entanglement pool or basemore broadly the
set of network connections among agents such as atoms, molecules,
7 In agent-based computational models, an agent can represent any organisms, human actorsfrom which emergence arises, is frequently
microentity, such as electrons, atoms, molecules, cells, organisms, unspecified as the initial condition. This concern is mostly missing in
species, language/process/conversation elements, individuals, groups, organizational applications;
divisions, firms, etc. I use it in this catch-all sense here.
8

4. The implications for adaptive efficaciousness of successive Cowan, G. A., Pines and D. Meltzer (eds.) (1994). Complexity:
emergence events, that is, of the possibility in biological and social Metaphors, Models, and Reality. Proceedings of the Santa Fe
systems that prior emergence events could have fed back to irrevocably Institute, Vol. XIX. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
tarnish the entanglement or network base, also seems missing; and. Cramer, F. (1993). Chaos and Order: The Complex Structure of Living
5. The interaction of Bnard and Darwinian and rational processes Things (trans. D. L. Loewus). New York: VCH.
is barely considered. Darwin, C. (1859). On the Origin of Species. London: John Murray.
The root question in quantudm theory expands, in Durkheim, . (1893). De la Division du Travail Social: tude sur
complexity science, into a multidisciplinary concern lorganization des Socits Suprieures. Paris: F. Alcan.
about the engine that causes order-creation in matter, life, Eddington, A. (1930). The Nature of the Physical World. London:
brains, artificial intelligence, and social systems (Mainzer Macmillan.
1997). And, needless to ask: Is there one primary engine Geertz, C. (1973). The Interpretation of Cultures. New York: Basic
Books.
working up and down the hierarchy of phenomenafrom
matter to social systemsor are there several and do they Gell-Mann, M. (1994). The Quark and the Jaguar. New York: Freeman.
differ across disciplines? From all of this, I draw out two Hamel, G. (2000). Reinvent Your Company, Fortune, 141 (June 12),
98118.
key elements that seem particularly relevant in the
Hassard, J. and M. Parker (1993). Postmodernism and Organizations.
application of complexity theory to organizations: (1) the Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
notion of correlated histories between pairs of agents
Holland, J. H. (1995). Hidden Order. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
that is entanglementas the initial condition; and (2) the
Kauffman, S. A. (1993). The Origins of Order: Self-Organization and
Bnard process as the main engine of order-creation so Selection in Evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.
far discovered that applies across the hierarchy of Lincoln, Y. S. (Ed.) (1985). Organizational Theory and Inquiry.
phenomenaand down into organizationsin addition to Newbury Park, CA: Sage.
the Darwinian selectionist process, and human rationality, Lorenz, E. N. (1963). Deterministic Nonperiodic Flow, Journal of the
of course, that we already know about. Atmospheric Sciences, 20, 130141.

References Maguire, S. and B. McKelvey (1999a). Complexity and Management:


Moving from Fad to Firm Foundations, Emergence, 1, (2), 1961.
Allen, P. M. (1988). Self-organization in the Urban System, in W. C. Maguire, S. and B. McKelvey (eds.) (1999b). Special Issue on
Schieve and P. M. Allen (eds.), Self-Organization and Dissipative Complexity and Management: Where Are We? Emergence 1, (2).
Structures: Applications in the Physical and Social Sciences.
Austin, TX: University of Texas Press, 142146. Mainzer, K. (1997). Thinking in Complexity: The Complex Dynamics of
Matter, Mind, and Mankind (3rd ed.). New York: Springer-Verlag.
Allen, P. M. and J. M. McGlade (1986). Dynamics of Discovery and
Exploitation: The Scotian Shelf Fisheries, Canadian Journal of Massie, J. L. (1965). Management Theory, in J. G. March (ed.),
Fisheries and Aquatic Sciences, 43, 11871200. Handbook of Organizations. Rand McNally, Chicago, 387422.
Allen, P. M. and J. M. McGlade (1987). Modelling Complex Human McKelvey, B. (1997). Quasi-natural Organization Science,
Systems: A Fisheries Example, European Journal of Operations Organization Science, 8, 351380.
Research, 30, 147167. McKelvey, B. (1999a). Avoiding Complexity Catastrophe in
Anderson, P. (1999). Complexity Theory and Organization Science, Coevolutionary Pockets: Strategies for Rugged Landscapes,
Organization Science, 10, 216232. Organization Science, 10, 294321.
Arthur, W. B., S. N. Durlauf and D. A. Lane (eds. ) (1997). The McKelvey, B. (1999b). Complexity Theory in Organization Science:
Economy as an Evolving Complex System. Proceedings of the Santa Seizing the Promise or Becoming a Fad? Emergence, 1, 332.
Fe Institute, Vol. XXVII. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. McKelvey, B. (1999c). Self-Organization, Complexity Catastrophe, and
Ashby, W. R. (1956). An Introduction to Cybernetics. London: Chapman Microstate Models at the Edge of Chaos, in J. A. C. Baum and B.
& Hall. McKelvey, eds. Variations in Organization Science: In Honor of
Donald T. Campbell. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage, 279307.
Ashby, W. R. (1962). Principles of the Self-Organizing System, in H.
von Foerster and G. W. Zopf (eds.), Principles of Self-Organization. McKelvey, B. (forthcoming-a). Dynamics of New Science Leadership:
New York: Pergamon, 255278. Strategy, Microcoevolution, Distributed Intelligence, Complexity,
in A. Y. Lewin and H. Volberda (eds.), Mobilizing the Self-
Belew, R. K. and M. Mitchell (eds.) (1996). Adaptive Individuals in Renewing Organization. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Evolving Populations. Proceedings of the Santa Fe Institute, Vol.
XXVI. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. McKelvey, B. (forthcoming-b). Emergent Order in Firms: Complexity
Science vs. the Entanglement Trap, in E. Mitleton-Kelly (ed.),
Berger, J., C. L. Ridgeway, M. H. Fisek and R. Z. Norman (1998). The Organizations Are Complex Social Systems, The Netherlands:
Legitimation and Delegitimation of Power and Prestige Orders, Elsevier.
American Sociological Review, 63, 379405.
McKelvey, B. (forthcoming-c). From Fields to Science, in R.
Borel, E. (1937). Valeur Pratique et Philosophie des Probabilits. Paris: Westwood & S. Clegg (eds.), Point/Counterpoint: Central Debates
Gauthier-Villars. in Organization Theory, Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
Burrell, G. and G. Morgan (1979). Sociological Paradigms and Mermin, D. N. (1991). Is the Moon There When Nobody Looks?
Organizational Analysis. London: Heinemann. Reality and the Quantum Theory, Physics Today, in R. Boyd, P.
Byrne, D. (1998). Complexity Theory and the Social Sciences. London: Gasper, and J. D. Trout (eds.), The Philosophy of Science.
Routledge. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 501516.
Chia, R. (1996). Organizational Analysis as Deconstructive Practice. Mills, R. (1994). Space, Time and Quanta: An Introduction to
Berlin, Germany: Walter de Gruyter. Contemporary Physics. New York: Freeman.
Cilliers, P. (1998). Complexity and Postmodernism. London: Routledge. Morgan, G. (1997). Images of Organization, 2nd ed. Thousand Oaks,
Cohen, J. and I. Stewart (1994). The Collapse of Chaos: Discovering CA: Sage.
Simplicity in a Complex World. New York: Viking. Morrison, F. (1991). The Art of Modeling Dynamic Systems. New York:
9

Wiley Interscience. (eds.), Status Generalization: New Theory and Research. Stanford,
Nicolis, G. and I. Prigogine (1989). Exploring Complexity: An CA: Stanford University Press, 207231.
Introduction. New York: Freeman. Rothstein, J. (1958). Communication, Organization and Science. Indian
Omns, R. (1999). Understanding Quantum Mechanics. Princeton, NJ: Hills, CO: Falcons Wing Press.
Princeton University Press. Salmon, W. C. (1998). Causality and Explanation. New York: Oxford
Pearl, J. (2000). Causality. New York: Cambridge University Press. University Press.
Prigogine, I. (1962). Non-Equilibrium Statistical Mechanics. New York: Scott, W. R. (1998). Organizations: Rational, Natural, and Open
Wiley Interscience. Systems (4th ed.). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Prigogine, I. and I. Stengers (1984). Order Out of Chaos: Mans New Sommerhoff, G. (1950). Analytical Biology. London: Oxford University
Dialogue with Nature. New York: Bantam. Press. [Chapter 2 reprinted as Purpose, Adaptation and Directive
Correlation, in W. Buckley, ed. 1968. Modern Systems Research
Reed, M. and M. Hughes (eds.) (1992). Rethinking Organization: New for the Behavioral Scientist. Chicago: Aldine, 281295.]
Directions in Organization Theory and Analysis. London: Sage.
Spencer, H. (1898). The Principles of Sociology. New York: D.
Ridgeway, C. L. and J. Berger (1986). Expectations, Legitimation, and Appleton & Co.
Dominance Behavior in Task Groups, American Sociological
Review, 51, 603617. Weick, K. E. (1995). Sensemaking in Organizations. Thousand Oaks,
CA: Sage.
Ridgeway, C. L. and J. Berger (1988). The Legitimation of Power and
Prestige Orders in Task Groups, in M. Webster Jr. and M. Foschi

Table 1. Definitions of Kinds of Complexity by Cramer (1993)


Subcritical complexity exists when the amount of information necessary to describe the system is less complex than the system itself. Thus a rule,
such as F = ma = md2s/dt2 is much simpler in information terms than trying to describe the myriad states, velocities, and acceleration rates pursuant to
understanding the force of a falling object. Systems exhibiting subcritical complexity are strictly deterministic and allow for exact prediction
(1993, p. 213) They are also reversible (allowing retrodiction as well as prediction thus making the arrow of time irrelevant (Eddington 1930,
Prigogine and Stengers 1984).
At the opposite extreme is fundamental complexity where the description of a system is as complex as the system itselfthe minimum number of
information bits necessary to describe the states is equal to the complexity of the system. Cramer lumps chaotic and fundamental systems into this
category, although deterministic chaos is recognized as fundamentally different from fundamental complexity (Morrison 1991, Gell-Mann 1994),
since the former is simple rule driven, and fundamental systems are random, though varying in their stochasticity. Thus, three kinds of fundamental
complexity are recognized: purely random, probabilistic, and deterministic chaos. For this essay I narrow fundamental complexity to deterministic
chaos, at the risk of oversimplification.
In between Cramer puts critical complexity. The defining aspect of this category is the possibility of emergent simple deterministic structures
fitting subcritical complexity criteria, even though the underlying phenomena remain in the fundamentally complex category. It is here that natural
forces ease the investigators problem by offering intervening objects as simplicity targets the behavior of which lends itself to simple-rule
explanation. Cramer (1993, p. 215217) has a long table categorizing all kinds of phenomena according to his scheme.

Anda mungkin juga menyukai