Anda di halaman 1dari 5

Human Rights and Cultural Relativism: The Need for a New Approach

Ronald Cohen

American Anthropologist, New Series, Vol. 91, No. 4. (Dec., 1989), pp. 1014-1017.

Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0002-7294%28198912%292%3A91%3A4%3C1014%3AHRACRT%3E2.0.CO%3B2-K

American Anthropologist is currently published by American Anthropological Association.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained
prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in
the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/journals/anthro.html.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.

JSTOR is an independent not-for-profit organization dedicated to and preserving a digital archive of scholarly journals. For
more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

http://www.jstor.org
Tue Apr 17 11:42:29 2007
on 'genuine' Black behavior" (p. 708). In say- the "real" or "authentic" behavior of the
ing this he has approached Rose's work as a other in unpreplanned contexts; nonetheless,
"standard ethnography." Rose's research, if it who we are-the privileged stranger and
could be called research in the traditional anomalous friend-is ever present. What we
sense, runs against the established grain of ac- come to know, in the end, is based on who we
ceptable academic discourse, and largely be- are perceived to be. Dan Rose was not per-
cause it does, it deserves our serious attention. ceived as an anthropologist, and what he came
In the winter of 1969, Dan Rose took up res- to know is deeply informing to anthropolo-
idence in South Philadelphia, entered into the gists.
employ of a Black man as an automobile me-
chanic, and for two years lived as a local actor
in the Black street life. As a covert researcher, Human Rights and Cultural
Rose did not have the status of the anthropol-
ogist, the transcendent vantage point from Relativism: The Need for a
which to observe everyday life, nor did he have New Approach
the authority to interrupt the everyday life of
people in order to ask questions. T o have RONALD COHEN
iskid questions, to have engaged in inquiry, University of Florida
would have created suspicion, especially in a
community where the majority of the people
had some kind of police record. As a local ac- The recent discussions of cultural relativisrri
tor, Rose had to flow with the events; his and of human rights in the pages of this jour-
knowledge about Black life thus developed at nal grow out of an old controversy. And as
the same slow pace as the flow of local life. Washburn (AA 89:939-942, 1987) points out,
Rose's book, in his own words, is "a succes- Geertz's "Distinguished Lecture: Anti Anti-
sion of movements in the longer history of the Relativism" (1984) resuscitated the debate.
self" and represents a chronological unfold- Although readers of this journal would cer-
ing of experience, an extension of the self into tainly agree about the moral and logical flaws
the culture of the other. Rose draws the reader in the arguments of the relativists, unfortu-
into his experience as he is gradually appro- nately the relevant issues lie elsewhere. An-
priated by the world of the hustle, the theater thropologists may ignore these problems,
of the street, and the complex and often dan- leaving discussion and research to others, or
gerous relationships in which he becomes join in. Meanwhile, the questions being raised
embedded. ~ o s e ' narrative
s is frequently have in effect shifted the emphasis from rela-
punctuated by thought-provoking reflec- tivism as creed and/or epistemology (Geertz
tions-theoretical/interpretive asides-on 1984; Nissim-Sabat 1987) to a set of more con-
the character of Black street life as it comes to troversial and more immediately practical
be juxtaposed against the popular and intel- considerations. These have to do with the rel-
lectual culture of Rose's White middle-class ative value and validity of contradictory
upbringing. These extended anecdotes flow as claims by those from different cultural and
logical outcomes of the narrative, and in turn ideological traditions about human rights. At
enrich the narrative and force the reader to issue are questions about when and under
critically assess the assumptions of his or her what (if any) circumstances contradictory hu-
own culture. man rights beliefs and practices are support-
What Rose has written presents ethical and able. Contrarily, when do they run counter to
epistemological issues that Williams has cho- truly human interests, if such a quality can be
sen not to articulate. First, there is the ethical defined; and when, ifat all, or under what con-
issue of covert research. Was Rose right in ditions can we expect basic research to inform
what he did? Is it right to pretend not to be an such questions?
anthropologist and then to appropriate the i he sad and interesting feature of this new
knowledge of another culture-an oppressed concern with the importance, or lack of it, of
and powerless culture-for academic publi- cultural relativism is the absence of anthro-
cation? The other issue is epistemological. pologists from the discussions. A recent con-
How do we know what we know? As anthro- ference on human rights in Africa (Shepherd
pologists, we enter the field as anomalous and 1987) has only a limited contribution from an-
somewhat privileged persons who are given thropology. (One anthropologist, B. Harrell-
the right to inquire into the lives of others. In Bond, is included as junior author ofone of the
return, the "others," knowing more or less papers.) A major book on human rights in Af-
who we are, manage the knowledge they rica with an entire chapter devoted to cultural
choose to present us. Granted, we can observe relativism (Howard 1986:ch. 2) has been writ-
ten by a sociologist whose work owes much to development" (African Charter, quoted in
the contribution of a political scientist (Don- Sieghart 1986:236). And this rests on a theo-
nelly 1984, 1985). In her references to cultural retical premise that collectivities have rights
relativism Howard (1986:34-36) cites forty- that vary across cultures, in relation to other
five separate scholars, only three of whom collectivities and to individuals. Conse-
(Bidney 1968; Kopytoff 1977; and Legesse quently, the empowerment of states to accom-
1980) could be considered anthropological in plish goals of human betterment and the pub-
their approch to the problem. Spawned by the lic good, above and beyond the protection of
researches and methods of anthropology, cul- the individual, is claimed to be a justifiable
tural relativism has become a topic of interest feature of African concepts of human rights,
to the history of the discipline, and possibly to given the moral validity of relativist perspec-
epistemological controversies (how far can we tives. And by derivation, as long as it can be
succeed in understanding another culture), argued that the state is carrying out its cultur-
but of little relevance to those dealing with hu- ally defined obligation, thereby its mandate,
man rights and relativism in the 1980s. to foster development, then there exists a de-
The reasons for this avoidance are not sim- fensible logic for abrogating the rights of in-
ply that anthropology is the bad guy of the dividuals if such actions and expectations are
comparative social science community-the said to stand in the way. Those defending the
studv, of "~rimitive"behavior is bv definition
&
African position argue that the Western-in-
an insult; anthropology is tied up with colo- spired and ethnocentric concern for individual
nialism; anthropologists highlight practices rights leads to institutionalized support for
that many contemporary Third World peo- greed, poverty, and a lack of concern for the
ples feel are uncomplimentary to their image collective and public good (see Bellah et al.
internationallv. It is rather that much of the 1985, for a discussion of this same point within
relativism argument, particularly the human the context of U.S. culture). Contrarily, the
rights domain, has shifted to national and in- African position is attacked as a sophist ra-
ternational levels of interaction, leaving an- tionale for unfettered state power that claims
thropologists in advocacy roles for the welfare the right to rule by virtue of good intentions,
of those they study, or mired in the microlevel and the right to suppress opposition because
of face-to-face, small-scale social life. What for of its African cultural heritage (Howard
instance has anthropological research (not sim- 1986).
ply pious pronouncements) to say about the Some would go even further and argue that
rights described in the U.N. Charter, or the the right to development means that the ineq-
African Charter, o r the demand for a new uities of power in the world between the poor
world order of equitable power over resources and the wealthy nations must be set aside.
and information by all peoples and nations- This "third generation" of human rights (the
or contradictions among these claims, even first being the individual vs. the state, the sec-
when all such claims are defended as stem- ond being the welfare of people within states)
ming from a common humanity? must be pressed into existence in contradis-
Let me be more specific. T h e Universal tinction to sovereign rights of nation-states
Declaration of Human Rights emphasizes the that stand as barriers to international justice
Western tradition of individual human rights, (Shepherd 1990). Others would argue that
which asserts that persons must be protected such idealistic outcomes cannot obtain under
against the arbitrary use of power by the state real world conditions. And even if redistribu-
to limit their freedom of expression, and as- tion on a worldwide scale were possible, the
serts their rights to safety and security of per- equity demanded would have to be supported
son and ideas (Sieghart 1986). The African by internal societal processes of transforma-
Charter on Human and Peoples' Rights af- tion. Otherwise the campaign for interna-
firms t h e "virtues of [ t h e African] tional justice is a rhetorical sanctuary behind
. . . historical tradition and the values of Afri- which Third World elites enrich themselves
can civilization which should inspire and while failing to alleviate poverty and injustice
characterize. . . the concept of human and in their own societies.
peoples' rights" (Sieghart 1986:23 1-237). I n Which of these "rights" is primary? Which
other words, added to or in contradistinction takes precedence when, as they inevitably
to Western traditions of individual human must, they conflict? And what yardstick(s) can
rights there are both similar and different as- be used to make such judgments? These are
simptions said to be rooted in the African so- the kinds of issues (among many, including
cial and cultural heritage. This provides the such matters as gender, freedom of expression,
basis for asserting that the state has an obli- property, children, religion, health, freedom of
gation "to ensure the exercise of the right to movement, residential freedom, the rule of
law, and refugees) that inform the contempo- And how does this question inform the relativ-
rary debate over relativism, and that seem to ity of rights today and tomorrow across cul-
be missing in the discussion of the concept in tures? Do regimes ruling over cultures that
anthropology. have downplayed individualism in the past
Given the urgency of such issues, it is at best have the right, on grounds of relativity of val-
irrelevant, or worse even mischievous, to as- ues, character structure, and sentiments, to
sert and defend simplistic polarities of relativ- stress collective goals at the expense of indi-
ism versus universal moral imperatives. What vidual rights when these conflict-in a chang-
is desperately needed-and anthropology ing world?
should be central to this quest-is a search for There are no easy answers to such ques-
some middle ground. Possibly African social tions, beyond those of personal beliefs, preju-
theorists have overdone the collective nature dices, and tradition-guided responses. What is
of African cultural traditions and the lack of a needed is to transform such issues into empir-
just concern required for non-Western indi- ically based research, the very hallmark of our
viduals in the modern nation-state. Possibly own anthropological past. It wasn't easy to es-
we in the West do in fact overstress the re- tablish the decentering (i.e., comparative) ba-
quirements of individual freedom and self-re- sis of kinship, religion, personality, and the
alization at the expense of the public good. host of institutions we have shown to have
Possibly; but the answer to such questions lies valid variability among human groups. But
out in the hurly-burly amid the blooming, the most difficult task remains. Which among
buzzing confusion of real world experience, the relativity of moral values judged to be an
where rights or a sense of what is just and fair aspect of our common humanity have true or
emerge, rather than in the philosopher's study supportable validity, and which are simply
or in the anthropologist's cranky (and some- context-determined aspects of specific tradi-
times) justifiable urge to advocacy. Without tions? The Values Project at Harvard tried
the crutches of relativism, or the unthinking this same task years ago, but the time wasn't
arrogance of ethnocentric Kantianism, differ- ripe for its acceptance as an enduring enter-
ences have to be judged not just as "varia- prise. We are now faced with contradictory
tions"-interesting scientifically and morally claims of universal values and human rights
defensible, or indefensible. There is today an that are conflict-inducing and possibly capa-
obligation to ask as well whether or not such ble of becoming justifications for cruel and ty-
differences enhance or degrade the lives of rannical conditions, whether they refer to the
those who hope to survive and flourish under homeless in America, the rusticated in Cam-
their sway. And we must search for valid bodia, or the stateless in the Near East. There
measuring devices to evaluate and derive is a pressing need to go beyond moralist po-
workable solutions to these questions. larities, simple-minded advocacy, distaste for
Although these issues are difficult enough, our own society, or uninformed ethnocentric
they rest on even more fundamental questions, judgments-relativism versus universalism-
again within the purview of anthropology. to real world issues that must be faced coura-
There are grounds, theoretically, for hypoth- geously. There is work to do, and anthropol-
esizing that we in the West with our strong de- ogists have an important role to play-if we
fense of individual rights have quite different choose to do so.
characterological and socialization experi-
ences from those in other cultures. I would ar- References Cited
gue that the degree to which the self incorpo-
rates (cognitively, emotionally, and morally) Bellah, R. H., R. Madsen, W. M. Sullivan, A.
the acts and the fate of related persons into the Swidler, and S. M. Tipton
organization of personal understanding and 1985 Habits of the Heart. New York: Har-
reactions varies significantly across cultures as per and Row.
a function of threats to personal security and Bidney, D.
rewards of the shared fate of group members. 1968 Cultural Relativism. I n Interna-
In other words, cultures have evolved institu- tional Encyclopedia of the Social Sci-
tions and norms to support more and less con- ences, Vol. 3. P. 545. New York: Mac-
cern over the rights and obligations of individ- millan/Free Press.
uals as opposed to those of collectivities. Fur- Donnelly, J.
thermore, the conditions determining these 1984 Cultural Relativism and Universal
outcomes change over time, so that what was Human Rights. Human Rights Quar-
defensible (at least logically, if not morally, terly 6(4):400-410.
from a universalist point of view) may not be 1985 T h e Concept of Human Rights.
argued for under conditions of modern life. London: Croom Helm.
Geertz, C. Gerber's account of 1975 has since been
1984 Anti Anti-Relativism. American An- supplemented by other comparable reports.
thropologist 86:263-278. Thus, P. A. Cox, of the Department of Botany
Howard, R. E. in the University of California, Berkeley, writ-
1986 Human Rights in Commonwealth ing in the American Scientist (1983:407), states:
Africa. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Little- "Several years ago during an ethnobotanical
field. survey in Ta'u, I asked several older Samoans
Kopytoff, I., and S. Miers for their opinions on the Samoan studies of
1977 African Slavery as an Institution of Margaret Mead. They told me she could not
Marginality. In Slavery in Africa. S. speak Samoan; this coupled with 'teasing' (tau
Miers and I. Kopytoff, eds. Pp. 3-81. fa'ase'e) on the part of her informants, had
Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. led her into serious error in her characteriza-
Legesse, A. tion of Samoan culture."
1980 Human Rights in African Political Again, in the Pact& Islands Monthly ( 1984), a
Culture. In The Moral Imperatives of Samoan, Falani Peters, has claimed that Com-
Human Rights: A World Survey. K. W. ing of Age in Samoa consists mainly of "chil-
Thompson, ed. Pp. 21-34. Washington, dren's jokes, swallowed by the gullible Mead"
DC: University Press of America. ( P 9).
Nissim-Sabat, C. Peters, like the informants of Gerber and
1987 On Clifford Geertz and His "Anti Cox, is referring to what O'Meara (1988) has
Anti-Relativism." American Anthropol- termed "recreational lying," a practice which
ogist 89:935-938. is "one of the main forms of entertainment in
Shepherd, G. W., Jr. a Samoan village." Called tau fa'ase'e, tau
1987 [ed.] Selected Papers from the Inter- fa'alili, or ula (depending on the intentions of
national Conference on Human Rights in its perpetrators), "recreational lying," as
the African Context, Port Harcourt (June O'Meara notes, "happens continually" with
9-1 1, 1987). Africa Today, 34 (1-2). "all ages" engaging in it: "people tell you sto-
1990 Human Rights in an Unjust World. ries," especially "about sex," to try to get you
The Carter Lectures on Africa, Series No. to believe them, and then "sort of chuckle in-
3. Given a t the University of Florida, side."
Gainesville, Feb. 16. (In vol. 3, Carter In my book of 1983, in discussing the sup-
Studies on Africa, in preparation.) position of Gerber's informants that Mead
Sieghart, P. was lied to in this way (an explanation which
1986 The Lawful Rights of Mankind. I had myself frequently encountered in
New York: Oxford University Press. Manu'a and elsewhere in Samoa) I concluded
(p. 291) that although this might have hap-
pened, the available reports were no more
Fa'apua'a Fa'amii and Margaret than hearsay, and we could not "in the ab-
sence of corroborative evidence be sure about
Mead the truth of this Samoan claim." Yet, as Ber-
nard has noted (1988:I 78), "it is not unheard
DEREKFREEMAN of for informants to lie to anthropologists."
Australian National Uniuersit_y With the provision of quite specific, direct
evidence by Mead's close friend and principal
informant of 1926, Fa'apua'a Fa'amu, our
In this brief communication I report cru- knowledge of Mead's much discussed Samoan
cially important new evidence on Margaret researches has been transformed.
Mead's Samoan researches of 1926. The account that follows is based on infor-
According to Gerber ( 1975:126), all of her mation provided by Fa'apua'a Fa'amii, at Fi-
Samoan informants of the early 1970s on the tiuta, Ta'u, Manu'a, in an interview on No-
island of Tutuila were agreed, in discussing vember 13, 1987, with Galea'i Poumele, the
Samoan sexual behavior, that in the 1920s then secretary of Samoan affairs in the govern-
"parents were extremely strict, and all daugh- ment of American Samoa; on May 2, 1988,
ters virginal." Further, "educated Samoans," with Leulu F. Va'a, M.A. (Australian Na-
who had read Coming of Age in Samoa, automat- tional University), lecturer in Samoan studies
ically rejected what they euphemistically in the National University of Samoa; and from
called "all that sex stuff," and claimed that my own questioning of Fa'apua'a on Novem-
"Mead's informants must have been telling ber 13, 1987.
lies in order to tease her," a behavior known Fa'amu, as she was called before being
to the Samoans as taufa'ase'e or taufa'alili.' given the nickname Fa'apua'a when she be-

Anda mungkin juga menyukai