Anda di halaman 1dari 20

Psychological Bulletin Copyright 2004 by the American Psychological Association

2004, Vol. 130, No. 5, 793– 812 0033-2909/04/$12.00 DOI: 10.1037/0033-2909.130.5.793

Psychological Mechanisms of Medically Unexplained Symptoms:


An Integrative Conceptual Model

Richard J. Brown
University of Manchester and Institute of Neurology

Theories of medically unexplained illness based on the concepts of dissociation, conversion, and
somatization are summarized. Evidence cited in support of these theories is described and the conceptual
strengths and shortcomings of each approach are considered. It is argued that each of these approaches
adds to the understanding of unexplained illness but that none is able to provide a comprehensive
explanation of the phenomenon. An integrative conceptual model of unexplained illness based on
cognitive psychological principles is then presented. This model attempts to combine existing theoretical
approaches within a single explanatory framework, extending previous theory by explaining how
compelling symptoms can exist in the absence of organic pathology. The clinical and empirical
implications of the model are then considered.

Throughout history, medical practitioners have encountered in- nomena have been advanced since this time. This article provides
dividuals with symptoms of physical illness for which no adequate a critical review of the different theories purporting to explain the
organic basis can be found. According to some estimates, between pathogenesis of medically unexplained symptoms, considering
25% and 60% of the symptoms investigated in family medical both the merits and the limitations of current ideas in this area. On
centers defy adequate physical explanation (Kirkwood et al., the basis of this review, I argue that (a) different theories are able
1982). In some cases, symptoms represent the somatic component to account for certain features of medically unexplained illness, but
of a diagnosable psychiatric condition, such as anxiety or depres- no one theory can accommodate all of the available evidence
sion, but are not recognized as such by the patient or the physician; concerning these conditions, and that (b) no theory provides a
in others, normal bodily sensations or minor physical ailments may satisfactory account of how apparently compelling symptoms can
be perceived as evidence of serious underlying pathology by a exist in the absence of significant organic pathology. I then de-
hypochondriacal individual. In many cases, however, there is no scribe a novel model that aims to address these shortcomings by
obvious psychiatric explanation for the symptoms in question reference to contemporary cognitive psychological research.
(Kroenke & Swindle, 2000). Although many such “medically Rather than superceding existing theories in this area, this model
unexplained” symptoms resolve quickly and spontaneously, symp- has been developed with a view to integrating current theoretical
toms often remain unresolved, causing distress and disability that concepts within a single explanatory framework. This framework
persists over time. In addition to the suffering and uncertainty provides a useful tool to organize available research and theory
faced by patients in this context, the cost of repeated consultation concerning medically unexplained symptoms and allows for the
and investigation for these individuals represents a considerable generation of new hypotheses concerning these phenomena.
burden to the health care services. This is particularly true in the
case of individuals who experience and seek help for multiple
unexplained symptoms, for whom health care costs may be up to Background
nine times the primary care average (G. R. Smith, Monson, & Ray,
Classification
1986).
The psychological origin of medically unexplained symptoms Broadly speaking, the fourth edition of the Diagnostic and
has been widely recognized since the 18th century (Merskey, Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM–IV; American Psy-
1979), and a number of models attempting to explain these phe- chiatric Association, 1994) categorizes medically unexplained
complaints according to the nature, number, and duration of the
symptoms in question. The somatoform disorders category encom-
Richard J. Brown, Academic Division of Clinical Psychology, Univer- passes a range of complaints characterized by the symptoms of
sity of Manchester, Manchester, United Kingdom, and Department of somatic illness (e.g., pain, fatigue, general malaise) that cannot be
Clinical Epilepsy, Institute of Neurology, London, United Kingdom. accounted for by identifiable physical pathology, including the
I thank Chris Frith, Francesca Happé, David Oakley, Karin Roelofs, contemporary manifestation of polysymptomatic hysteria (“Bri-
Maria Ron, Michael Trimble, and particularly Amanda Barnier for reading
quet’s syndrome”), so-called somatization disorder. The conver-
and commenting on earlier versions of this article.
Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Richard
sion disorders category, a subcategory of the somatoform disor-
J. Brown, Academic Division of Clinical Psychology, University of ders, encompasses unexplained symptoms suggestive of a
Manchester, Second Floor Research and Education Block, Wythenshawe neurological condition, such as gait disturbances, convulsions,
Hospital, Manchester M23 9LT, United Kingdom. E-mail: sensory loss, and cognitive decline; symptoms specifically involv-
richardjamesbrown@hotmail.com ing a disruption of memory, perception, and identity are classified

793
794 BROWN

as dissociative disorders, as are the phenomena of depersonaliza- women than in men, although the phenomenon is no longer con-
tion and derealization. DSM–IV also identifies hypochondriasis sidered an exclusively female problem.
and body dysmorphic disorder as somatoform phenomena; neither
of these conditions has medically unexplained symptoms as a
defining feature, and they are not considered in any detail here.
Diagnosis
In all cases, symptoms are classified as medically unexplained if Distinguishing somatoform symptoms from their organic coun-
adequate investigation has failed to identify a plausible physical terparts can be extremely difficult and typically requires extensive
cause for their occurrence or their associated level of impairment; physical investigation before a firm diagnosis can be made (see,
they must also cause clinically significant functional disability or e.g., Brown & Ron, 2002; Brown & Trimble, 2000). In a small
distress to meet diagnostic criteria. Moreover, the symptoms can- proportion of cases, symptoms are physiologically impossible
not be solely attributable to diagnosable anxiety, depression, hy- (e.g., triple vision); in others, a somatoform or dissociative diag-
pochondriasis, or psychosis. nosis may be suspected because of the variability or medical
implausibility of the symptom in question. In cases of conversion
Epidemiology aphonia, for example, the patient may have a preserved ability to
cough (requiring intact vocal chord function) despite being unable
Unexplained symptoms are ubiquitous, representing the com- to speak or whisper. Similarly, unexplained sensory loss is often
monest single category of complaints encountered in primary care inconsistent with actual patterns of sensory innervation (e.g., as in
(Kirmayer & Taillefer, 1997). Evidence suggests that more than a “glove” and “stocking” anesthesia in the absence of neuropathy).
quarter of unselected primary care patients meet criteria for Although the validity of making a firm diagnosis of unexplained
DSM–IV undifferentiated somatoform disorder, defined as the illness has been questioned over the years (e.g., Slater & Glitherco,
presence of one or more debilitating unexplained symptom of at 1965), recent research by Crimlisk et al. (1998) has shown that
least 6 months duration (Fink, Sørensen, Engberg, Holm, & Munk- very few symptoms are actually misdiagnosed as unexplained if
Jørgensen, 1999). Patients with a history of multiple unexplained appropriate investigations have been carried out. Nevertheless,
symptoms are also extremely common. Data reported by Escobar, where doubt exists, diagnoses should remain tentative until careful
Waitzkin, Cohen Silver, Gara, and Holman (1998), for example, follow-up has unequivocally ruled out a physical explanation
indicate that 22% of primary care patients meet criteria for the (Brown & Ron, 2002).
so-called abridged somatization construct, defined as the lifetime
occurrence of four unexplained symptoms in men, six in women.
Treatment
Many patients with a history of multiple unexplained symptoms
report experiencing several symptoms simultaneously. Kroenke et Although a large proportion of unexplained symptoms remit
al. (1997), for example, presented data indicating that more than spontaneously, many continue to cause distress and disability over
8% of unselected primary care patients meet criteria for so-called time (e.g., Stone, Sharpe, Rothwell, & Warlow, 2003). Several
multisomatoform disorder, defined as the presence of three or different treatment options are available, including short-term
more currently distressing unexplained symptoms alongside a his- group therapy (e.g., Kashner, Rost, Cohen, Anderson, & Smith,
tory of somatoform illness. 1995), cognitive– behavioral therapy (CBT; e.g., Chalder, 2001)
Research investigating the epidemiology of conversion disorder and psychodynamic psychotherapy (e.g., Temple, 2001). Research
has typically used specialist populations, and consequently, little is suggests that each of these treatments can be used successfully
known about its primary care prevalence. Mace and Trimble with certain cases of somatoform illness (Blanchard & Scharff,
(1996) suggested that as many as 20% of specialist neurological 2002; Kashner et al., 1995; Kroenke & Swindle, 2000). Treating
patients present with symptoms that defy adequate organic expla- these conditions can be notoriously difficult, however, and many
nation (for a review, see Akagi & House, 2001). unexplained symptoms remain resistant to treatment. This is par-
ticularly true when symptoms are chronic or occur in the absence
of obvious psychopathology (Brown & Ron, 2002). In such cases,
Clinical Features
somatoform illness is often managed by limiting patients’ expo-
The most commonly observed unexplained symptoms in pri- sure to unnecessary investigations and interventions; encouraging
mary care are pain, fatigue, and general malaise (Kirkwood et al., them (and their physicians) to accept a psychological interpretation
1982), although gastrointestinal and sexual/reproductive symp- of their symptoms; and offering symptomatic treatments such as
toms are frequently found. Within neurological settings, both pain management, physiotherapy, and occupational therapy (e.g.,
“negative” (i.e., those characterized by a loss of normal function- Brown & Ron, 2002; G. R. Smith, Rost, & Kashner, 1995). It is
ing; e.g., sensory loss, amnesia, paralysis, nonconvulsive pseudo- noteworthy that the management approach in such cases is the
seizures) and “positive” symptoms (i.e., those characterized by the same regardless of the assumed etiology of the symptoms.
presence of additional symptoms that disrupt functioning; e.g., gait
disturbance, tremor, pseudohallucinations, convulsive pseudosei- Theoretical Concepts
zures) are common. Broadly speaking, the most common somato-
form phenomena involve a significant subjective component (e.g., Recent attempts to explain the pathogenesis of medically unex-
pain, fatigue, dizziness) or involve a disruption in the voluntary plained symptoms can be grouped according to three explanatory
control of action (e.g., gait disturbance, urinary retention, dyspha- themes that are based on the concepts of dissociation, conversion,
gia). Unexplained symptoms are significantly more common in and somatization.
MECHANISMS OF MEDICALLY UNEXPLAINED SYMPTOMS 795

Dissociation Scherrer, Barbizet, Calvet, & Verley, 1958; Behrman & Levy,
1970; Halliday, 1968). Indeed, normal somatosensory evoked po-
Probably the earliest systematic account of medically unex- tentials are often regarded as positive support for a diagnosis of
plained illness— originally couched in the language of hysteria— unexplained sensory loss. More recent electrophysiological studies
was Janet’s dissociation theory (e.g., Janet, 1889, 1907; for theo- appear to suggest that conversion disorder is associated with
retical origins, see Charcot, 1889). According to this account, normal early evoked potentials but a disruption in the later P300
“hysterical” individuals experience a spontaneous narrowing of component (e.g., Fukudu et al., 1996; Lorenz, Kunze, & Bromm,
attention when exposed to traumatic events. This narrowing of 1998). These findings seem to indicate that conversion disorder
attention leads to the development of unexplained symptoms via involves the selective attentional gating of processed information
two basic mechanisms. On the one hand, attentional narrowing at a late stage in the processing chain, prior to the generation of
limits the number of sensory channels that can be attended to conscious awareness (Sierra & Berrios, 1999). This is consistent
simultaneously. Over time, the individual may develop a habitual with Ludwig’s (1972) assertion that the inhibitory process in
tendency to concentrate on some sensory channels at the expense unexplained illness occurs after cortical responses are evoked, at a
of others, leading to the loss of deliberate attentional control over level beyond the primary receptor cortex.
neglected channels. As a result, the individual is rendered anes- Further evidence for Ludwig’s (1972) reinterpretation of the
thetic for any information in the previously unattended modality; dissociation model has been obtained in cognitive studies that
nevertheless, the information in this channel is still processed seem to confirm the presence of an attentional deficit in individ-
outside conscious awareness (i.e., in a dissociated fashion). Janet uals with unexplained illness. This deficit appears to extend across
(1907) cited this mechanism as an account of unexplained sensory a range of attentional measures, with patients showing decrements
loss, which at that time was regarded as a cardinal symptom of on high-level tasks assessing vigilance, habituation, cognitive flex-
hysteria. ibility, set shifting, and mental transformation (Bendefeldt, Miller,
Other symptoms reflect the activation of memories that have & Ludwig, 1976; Hernández-Peón et al., 1963; Horvath, Friedman,
become dissociated from the main body of knowledge representing & Meares, 1980). Currently, however, the precise nature of this
the patient’s personality. By this view, attentional narrowing cre- attentional deficit remains unclear; further research using standard-
ates a paucity of information within consciousness that prevents ized measures of attention, as well as controls for motivation and
new memories from being integrated with existing aspects of anxiety, is required (Lader, 1982).
personal knowledge. Because of the lack of competing informa- According to Janet (1889, 1907), the fragmentation of memory
tion, however, these memories may take on a compelling subjec- associated with unexplained symptoms is triggered by the occur-
tive quality that causes them to be misinterpreted as perceptions rence of traumatic events, which were regarded as having a desta-
rather than recollections. Moreover, in the absence of integration, bilizing influence on mental processing more generally. Consistent
the patient has little or no control over the activation of these with this, there is good evidence to suggest that traumatized
memories, which may be triggered by related events in the internal individuals have more dissociative experiences and more instances
or external environment. According to Janet (1907), this process is of medically unexplained symptoms than those who have not
the same as that operating when comparable phenomena are cre- experienced trauma. Childhood sexual, physical, and emotional
ated using hypnotic suggestion. Indeed, Janet (1907) argued that abuse have all been linked to unexplained illness (e.g., Badura,
both suggestion and hypnosis are essentially pathological phenom- Reiter, Altmaier, Rhomberg, & Elas, 1997; Brown, Schrag, &
ena, possible only in those individuals with the mental weakness Trimble, in press; Kinzl, Traweger, & Biebl, 1995; Nijenhuis,
characteristic of hysteria. Spinhoven, van Dyck, van der Hart, & Vanderlinden, 1998; Pribor,
Although a century old, the theoretical analysis offered by Janet Yutzi, Dean, & Wetzel, 1993; Reilly, Baker, Rhodes, & Salmon,
(1889, 1907) continues to influence nosology, theory, research, 1999; Roelofs, Keijsers, Hoogduin, Näring, & Moene, 2002;
and clinical practice concerning the somatoform and dissociative Walker et al., 1988; for a review, see Brown, in press), and many
disorders. Ludwig (1972), for example, argued that the primary somatoform symptoms develop following exposure to acute stres-
pathophysiological mechanism involved in the creation and main- sors (Binzer, Andersen, & Kullgren, 1997), such as recent loss
tenance of unexplained symptoms is an attentional dysfunction, (Van Ommeren et al., 2001), relationship difficulties (Craig,
resulting from an increase in the corticofugal inhibition of afferent 2001), and exposure to dead bodies (Labbate, Cardeña, Dimitreva,
stimulation (cf. Whitlock, 1967). This process of inhibition gen- Roy, & Engel, 1998). Nevertheless, a number of commentators
erates a dissociation between attention and sources of afferent have questioned the necessity of identifying psychosocial precip-
stimulation, preventing the integration of sensory information itants in making a firm somatoform or dissociative diagnosis (e.g.,
within subjective awareness. In many respects, this view is a American Psychiatric Association, 1994; Merskey, 1979; Ron,
modern-day manifestation of Janet’s (1907) argument that hyster- 1994; Wessely, 2001; cf. World Health Organization, 1992). Al-
ical phenomena arise from functional dissociations related to a though clear precipitants are often found, they are absent in many
deficit in attention. cases (Ron, 1994; Wessely, 2001).
Evidence for afferent inhibition in unexplained illness was ob- Although the similarities between Janet’s (1889, 1907) original
tained in an earlier electrophysiological study by Hernández-Peón, model and more recent accounts of medically unexplained symp-
Chávez-Ibarra, and Aguilar-Figueroa (1963). In that study, so- toms (e.g., Kihlstrom, 1992; Ludwig, 1972; Whitlock, 1967) are
matosensory evoked responses were found to be lower in the considerable, there is one fundamental difference. According to
affected leg of a patient with unexplained hemianesthesia when Janet (1907), dissociation is an abnormal process provoked by
compared with those evoked from the patient’s unaffected leg. stress in the constitutionally weak mind of the hysterical patient; as
Other studies have failed to find this effect, however (Alajouanine, such, only those individuals with such a psychological weakness
796 BROWN

will experience dissociation and hence unexplained symptoms. In nesia, for example, would be linked to a dissociation that prevents
contrast, the majority of contemporary models adopt the view that the systems responsible for encoding and storing memorial infor-
dissociation is a normal psychological process, used by the organ- mation from communicating with the executive (see Brown, 2002,
ism as a defense mechanism in the face of trauma (see, e.g., in press). Despite this lack of communication, memorial systems
Ludwig, 1972; Whitlock, 1967); unexplained symptoms arise themselves remain intact and continue to function as normal.
when this normally adaptive process is overgeneralized to a point Compelling support for this hypothesis comes from an elegant
at which it becomes maladaptive. By this view, dissociation is a study by Kuyk, Spinhoven, and van Dyck (1999). Kuyk et al.
coping response available to all individuals, although the degree to (1999) compared a group of patients reporting postictal amnesia
which it is used varies from person to person. following nonepileptic seizures and a group reporting similar
Hilgard’s (1977) neodissociation theory, itself a partial rework- memory loss following generalized epileptic events. All partici-
ing of Janet’s (1889, 1907) original model, has been particularly pants were hypnotized and given suggestions designed to facilitate
influential in its support of the notion that dissociation is an the recovery of material encoded during the ictal period. Using a
adaptive mechanism that can become pathological if overused. free-recall paradigm, 85% of the nonepileptic seizure patients
Unlike other models, Hilgard’s model is noteworthy in its assertion recalled events occurring during the ictus that could be corrobo-
that dissociation is actually a fundamental aspect of cognitive rated by independent observations. None of the epilepsy patients
processing in general, rather than an unusual response elicited by recalled ictal material. This study clearly demonstrates that the
traumatic events. According to Hilgard, the majority of behavior is nonepileptic attack patients had encoded information during the
controlled by a set of functionally autonomous but interconnected ictal period but were unable to recall it because of a retrieval
cognitive control systems (schemata) specialized for the execution deficit; in this sense, the “forgotten” material could be regarded as
of particular behavioral acts. These control systems are hierarchi- dissociated from conscious awareness. The epilepsy patients, in
cally organized beneath an executive ego, which selects the cog- contrast, experienced a disruption in encoding during the seizure
nitive control systems required at any given moment. Once se- and therefore had no ictal information in memory to retrieve.
lected, these systems are able to function without ongoing input Further support for this account comes from studies demonstrat-
from the executive ego. This “dissociation” between the executive ing that individuals experiencing unexplained blindness exhibit
ego and the systems responsible for action control allows well- intact visual perception in the absence of visual experience (e.g.,
learned behaviors to be performed effortlessly, concurrently, and Bryant & McConkey, 1989; Sackeim et al., 1979; for related
outside awareness. examples, see Kihlstrom, 1992; cf. Kirsch & Lynn, 1998). A
Although originally developed as a general account of the similar phenomenon is also observed in hypnosis, with participants
mechanisms underlying behavioral control, neodissociation theory displaying intact processing of information that is otherwise un-
has been particularly influential as an account of hypnotic behav- available to awareness because of suggestion (so-called implicit
ior. According to the theory, hypnosis represents one situation in processing; see, e.g., David, Brown, Pojoga, & David, 2000;
which the communication between individual control systems and Kihlstrom, 1987, 1992). Other findings also lend support to the
the executive ego is subject to change. Following suggestions notion that medically unexplained symptoms involve similar
aimed at inhibiting the executive, a vertical dissociation can be mechanisms to those underlying hypnotic phenomena. Many un-
created within the ego forming two separate executive “streams,” explained symptoms (e.g., amnesia, sensory loss, paralysis) have a
one of which is concealed beneath an amnesic barrier. This un- hypnotic counterpart, and these conditions are often accompanied
conscious part of the executive is able to communicate with by high levels of hypnotic suggestibility (Bendefeldt et al., 1976;
targeted subsystems and therefore control behavior as normal, Janet, 1907; Ludwig, 1972; Roelofs, Hoogduin, et al., 2002). There
although this is not represented in conscious awareness. As the is also good evidence to suggest that the occurrence of both
conscious part of the executive has no direct access to the systems unexplained symptoms and suggested phenomena are subject to
controlling the suggested behavior, it is perceived as occurring similar moderating factors, such as belief, expectation, and atten-
involuntarily. More recently, Bowers (1992; see also Woody & tional focus (e.g., Kirsch, 1985; McConkey, 2001; Salkovskis,
Bowers, 1994) has suggested that hypnotic phenomena result from 1989; Tellegen & Atkinson, 1974). Furthermore, recent functional
a horizontal dissociation between the executive and low-level neuroimaging studies provide some support for the idea that sug-
control systems. According to this “dissociated control” theory, gested and unexplained medical phenomena involve similar cere-
hypnosis serves to inhibit the executive altogether, allowing low- bral mechanisms. In a positron emission tomography (PET) study
level control systems to be automatically activated by the words of of unexplained paralysis, Marshall, Halligan, Fink, Wade, and
the hypnotist. By this view, hypnotic involuntariness reflects the Frackowiak (1997) found increased activation in the right orbito-
fact that hypnotic phenomena are generated without executive frontal and anterior cingulate cortices, as well as an absence of
involvement (i.e., automatically). activity in the right primary motor cortex, when an attempt to
Echoing the earlier work of Janet (1889), Kihlstrom (1992) has move the paralyzed left leg was made. A similar pattern of acti-
applied neodissociation theory to the unexplained neurological vation was found in a case of hypnotic left leg paralysis in a PET
symptoms characteristic of the dissociative and conversion disor- study conducted by Halligan, Athwal, Oakley, and Frackowiak
ders, citing the same kinds of functional dissociations as those (2000). These findings have been taken as evidence for the idea
outlined by Hilgard (1977) for hypnotic phenomena. (For other that unexplained paralysis (both hypnotic and nonhypnotic) in-
accounts that have endorsed the idea of common mechanisms for volves the inhibition of primary motor activity by areas in the
hypnotic and unexplained medical phenomena, see Bryant & Mc- prefrontal cortex (Halligan et al., 2000; Marshall et al., 1997).
Conkey, 1999; Ludwig, 1972; Oakley, 1999; Sackeim, Nordlie, & Although its influence remains ubiquitous within contemporary
Gur, 1979; Whitlock, 1967.) The symptoms of unexplained am- theorizing, a number of recent commentators have raised doubts
MECHANISMS OF MEDICALLY UNEXPLAINED SYMPTOMS 797

about the explanatory significance of the dissociation construct of unexplained illness can describe cases of this nature, which
(e.g., Cardeña, 1994; Frankel, 1994). Frankel (1994), for example, probably accounts for the continuing popularity of the conversion
has argued that the concept of dissociation has been reified and concept within clinical circles.
overextended within clinical practice to the point where it has only This emphasis on the concept of psychological defense serves to
descriptive and not mechanistic significance. According to differentiate the work of Breuer and Freud (1893–1895/1991) from
Frankel, any symptom that appears to involve some loss of control the simple dissociation model described by Janet (1889, 1907).
or experience has been described by clinicians as dissociative, According to this view, unexplained symptoms reflect an uncon-
despite there being no substantive grounds to assume that disso- scious emotional conflict that must be resolved if the patient is to
ciative mechanisms (in the Janetian sense) are responsible for the experience relief from symptoms. To achieve this, the underlying
clinical presentation in such cases (see also Brown, 2002; Cardeña, conflict must be made conscious, and its accompanying affect
1994). Depersonalization and derealization, for example, are typ- expressed appropriately (Temple, 2001). In earlier versions of the
ically regarded as dissociative phenomena (see, e.g., American theory (e.g., Breuer & Freud, 1893–1895/1991), the process of
Psychiatric Association, 1994), despite the fact that neither in- conversion was viewed as the product of early sexual abuse. This
volves any profound alternation in perception, memory, or per- view was subsequently modified by Freud, who argued that pa-
sonal identity (World Health Organization, 1992). Indeed, recent tients’ memories of abuse actually reflect an unresolved Oedipus
theoretical developments indicate that these phenomena involve complex driven by the repression of unacceptable sexual fantasies
entirely different pathogenic mechanisms from those underlying concerning the opposite-sex parent (see Temple, 2001). In con-
medically unexplained symptoms (Holmes et al., 2004; Sierra & trast, later analytic theorists have placed greater explanatory em-
Berrios, 1998). This could explain why studies using measures
phasis on patients’ internal representations of significant others
such as the Dissociative Experiences Scale (Bernstein & Putnam,
and their influence in subsequent relationships (e.g., Temple,
1986) have often failed to find elevated levels of dissociativity in
2001).
patients with unexplained symptoms (e.g., Alper et al., 1997;
Although Breuer and Freud’s (1893–1895/1991) views concern-
Pribor et al., 1993; Roelofs, Keijsers, et al., 2002; for a review, see
ing psychic energies have long since been abandoned, the influ-
Brown, in press). It is also possible to draw a meaningful link
ence of these authors remains pervasive to this day. The notion that
between somatoform symptoms and hypnotic phenomena without
hysterical phenomena are created by the conversion of psycholog-
relying on the dissociation hypothesis (e.g., Oakley, 1999).
ical distress into physical symptoms is widely endorsed, particu-
larly within medical circles. Like Janet’s (1889, 1907) model, such
Conversion a view is supported by studies showing that many patients with
The concept of conversion was introduced by Breuer and Freud unexplained illness have experienced extreme stress or trauma
(1893–1895/1991) as an extension to Janet’s (1889, 1907) disso- (often sexual) prior to the development of symptoms (see Brown,
ciative framework. According to Breuer and Freud, the brain often in press). In cases in which the patient reports no significant
attempts to regulate the conscious experience of negative affect by psychological problems or early trauma, it is assumed that the
unconsciously suppressing (or repressing) the conscious recall of underlying conflict and its associated affect have been repressed
memories associated with personal trauma. This process of repres- out of consciousness. The apparent lack of concern displayed by
sion can provide the basis for the creation of dissociated knowl- many such patients, so-called la belle indifférence, is also regarded
edge structures that are kept outside awareness by an amnesic as being consistent with the conversion concept (Iezzi & Adams,
barrier. Although the repression and dissociation of traumatic 1993). By this view, one would not anticipate significant psycho-
memories may protect the individual from potentially overwhelm- pathology in cases of unexplained illness if the patient were
ing negative affect, this process prevents the neural energy asso- successfully converting psychological distress into somatic
ciated with that affect from being discharged in the usual fashion. symptoms.
As this must occur if the energetic balance of the brain is to be In addition, research concerning the alexithymia construct (Sif-
preserved, the negative affect is “converted” into a somatic symp- neos, 1973) has offered some support for the assertion that con-
tom that either was present at the time of the original trauma or is version occurs as a means of discharging unexpressed emotion. A
some symbolic representation of it. In this way, the individual is number of studies have demonstrated that individuals who are less
able to express psychological distress without consciously ac- able to identify and report on their emotional states (i.e., alexithy-
knowledging the psychic conflict responsible for it. As such, mia) are significantly more likely to exhibit unexplained medical
unexplained symptoms can be viewed as serving a defensive phenomena than those who do not display this tendency (e.g.,
function, with the reduction of anxiety representing the primary Shipko, 1982). Other concepts introduced by Breuer and Freud
gain from developing symptoms; in contrast, any additional ad- (1893–1895/1991) have been adopted by theorists working outside
vantage associated with being ill (e.g., sympathy, attention, avoid- a psychoanalytic framework. In particular, the concepts of primary
ance of work) represents the secondary gain from symptoms. The and secondary gain are consistent with a behavioral approach that
appeal of the conversion concept is well illustrated in clinical case emphasizes the role of reinforcement in the creation and mainte-
examples, such as that of the doctoral student who developed nance of unexplained symptoms (Kellner, 1986). Some studies
right-arm paralysis shortly before the deadline for his dissertation.1 suggest that clear gains are associated with many cases of unex-
According to the conversion model, the student’s paralysis pro- plained illness (e.g., Raskin, Talbott, & Myerson, 1966).
vides a means of avoiding his anxiety about completing, or failing
to complete, his dissertation in a way that is both emotionally
1
palatable and socially acceptable. Most clinicians with experience I thank the anonymous reviewer who provided this case example.
798 BROWN

Despite its continuing popularity, there are significant problems


with the approach to unexplained illness described by Breuer and
Freud (1893–1895/1991). In particular, there are doubts surround-
ing the assumption that symptoms are necessarily the product of an
unresolved and unconscious psychological conflict (e.g., Ron,
1994; Wessely, 2001). Although obvious conflicts or psychosocial
precipitants are present in a proportion of cases, they are absent in
many others (for a review, see Brown, in press). According to the
psychoanalytic approach, such patients are unable to describe the
conflict underlying their symptoms because repression has ren-
dered it unconscious; the absence of apparent conflict is taken as
evidence for the operation of repression. Such circular reasoning
clearly raises doubts concerning the testability of the conversion
model. The problem is compounded by the assumption that unex-
plained symptoms are a symbol of the underlying conflict, rather
than a direct expression of it. Taken together, these assumptions
allow for an ad hoc approach to the formulation and treatment of
medically unexplained illness that may be both misleading and
potentially damaging. In particular, relentlessly probing for for-
gotten material, especially concerning sexual victimization, carries
a risk of creating compelling but false memories of abuse (see,
e.g., Lindsay & Read, 1994).
Research has also raised doubts concerning the validity of la
belle indifférence as a diagnostic indicator for the presence of
medically unexplained illness. Many patients with unexplained
symptoms are acutely upset about their problems (e.g., Lader &
Sartorius, 1968), for example, and an apparent indifference to
symptoms is also common in general medical illness (Brown, in
press; Gould, Miller, Goldberg, & Benson, 1986; Raskin et al.,
1966). Other studies have questioned the relationship between
alexithymia and unexplained illness (e.g., Cohen, Auld, &
Brooker, 1994), with evidence indicating that the measurement of
alexithymia is confounded by psychopathology in general (e.g., Figure 1. A multifactorial model of somatization. Reprinted from p. 353
of “Somatoform Disorders,” by L. J. Kirmayer and S. Taillefer. In S. M.
Bach, Bach, Böehmer, & Nutzinger, 1994). Research also suggests
Turner and M. Hersen (Eds.), Adult Psychopathology and Diagnosis, 3rd
that significant secondary gains are absent in many instances of ed., 1997, pp. 333–383. Copyright © 1997 by Wiley. This material is used
medically unexplained illness and are no more common than in by permission of John Wiley & Sons, Inc.
general medical illness (Brown, in press).

Somatization ease (i.e., symptoms), an attribution that may serve to generate


illness worry, catastrophizing, and demoralization. As a result,
Dissociation and conversion represent the main conceptual pre- individuals may adopt the “sick role” by pursuing assessment and
cursors to contemporary accounts of unexplained illness based on treatment for their putative condition, thereby exposing themselves
the concept of somatization. Lipowski (1968) has defined soma- to social forces (e.g., the reactions of others, the media, etc.) that
tization as the tendency to experience or express psychological may reinforce their illness behavior and experience. Although such
distress as the symptoms of physical illness. Somatization models a process is a normal response to the signs of illness, in some cases
place less explanatory emphasis on the specific mechanisms of it may reach disabling proportions, depending on the nature of the
unexplained illness, concentrating instead on the processes under- individual and the sociocultural context in which he or she is
lying normal somatic perception and the biopsychosocial context embedded. This process can be moderated by a number of con-
surrounding the experience of physical and mental illness (for textual and dispositional factors, including previous illness expe-
reviews, see, e.g., Kellner, 1986, 1990; Kirmayer & Robbins, rience; the response of significant others; illness worry; and indi-
1991a; Lipowski, 1988). Research inspired by the somatization vidual differences in personality, attentional set, coping behavior,
concept has identified a number of factors that may be important and autonomic reactivity (for evidence, see Kirmayer & Robbins,
in the generation and maintenance of medically unexplained symp- 1991a; Kirmayer & Taillefer, 1997; Robbins & Kirmayer, 1991;
toms. A recent model of the interaction between several of these the empirical literature in this area is discussed below).
factors has been described by Kirmayer and Taillefer (1997; see The model provided by Kirmayer and Taillefer (1997) offers a
Figure 1). According to Kirmayer and Taillefer, illness, emotional useful scheme for understanding the relationship between the
arousal, or everyday physiological processes produce bodily sen- different factors underlying somatization. It is particularly appeal-
sations that capture attention to varying degrees. In some in- ing because it provides a model of normal illness behavior that can
stances, these sensations may be interpreted as indicators of dis- be generalized to more maladaptive circumstances. The model also
MECHANISMS OF MEDICALLY UNEXPLAINED SYMPTOMS 799

provides a useful account of the evolution of unexplained symp- traumatic events and other emotional disturbances are often asso-
toms through its emphasis on the temporally extended aspects of ciated with the development of unexplained symptoms. More
somatization. Moreover, it is consistent with the available empir- recently, the somatization concept has placed current understand-
ical evidence concerning the risk factors for medically unexplained ing of unexplained illness in the wider biopsychosocial context,
illness. providing a framework that elucidates the risk factors associated
Despite its obvious appeal, however, there are a number of with this phenomenon. Converging evidence from several different
problems with the somatization concept. In particular, it concen- sources supports this approach.
trates primarily on the factors that moderate the occurrence of Nevertheless, it is clear that there are problems with the con-
medically unexplained symptoms and only speaks in very general cepts of dissociation, conversion, and somatization. Dissociation
terms about the psychological mechanisms involved in their me- models have been widely criticized for lacking precision (e.g.,
diation. Such a gap in the model is problematic because it obscures Frankel, 1994), something that has generated confusion about the
potentially important etiological differences between different nature of dissociation as a psychological phenomenon. Although
types of somatization (Kirmayer & Robbins, 1991a, 1991b). Ac- concepts such as attentional gating and top-down inhibition have
cording to Kirmayer and Robbins (1991a, 1991b), a distinction advanced the argument, these are essentially descriptive labels for
should be drawn among unexplained physical symptoms that are the processes they purport to explain. In contrast, the conversion
(a) the physiological components of anxiety or depressive psycho- model can be criticized for its circularity, something that has
pathology ( presenting somatization), (b) normal bodily sensations rendered many aspects of this approach unfalsifiable. Moreover,
or minor pathological events that are misinterpreted as signs of the fact that emotional and motivational factors appear to play a
serious illness (hypochondriacal somatization), and (c) subjec- significant role in only a proportion of cases of unexplained illness
tively compelling symptoms that cannot be attributed to either casts doubts on the generality of the model (Ron, 1994; Wessely,
physical or psychiatric illness or hypochondriasis (functional so- 2001). The somatization approach can also be criticized for its
matization). Although there is substantial comorbidity among reliance on the concept of emotional precipitation, and its descrip-
these different forms of somatization, they can be differentiated tive nature prevents the generation of precise hypotheses.
both conceptually and empirically (Kirmayer & Robbins, 1991a,
1991b). Only the concept of functional somatization is of rele- An Integrative Conceptual Model of Medically
vance in this context.
Unexplained Symptoms
Also problematic is the assumption that medically unexplained
symptoms are the result of identifiable physiological processes that The remainder of this article focuses on a novel account of
are exacerbated by social, cognitive, and perceptual factors. Al- unexplained illness that builds on the strengths of existing models
though this may be appropriate in some cases, particularly those while attempting to address some of their shortcomings. The
involving presenting and hypochondriacal somatization, it does not model is integrative in that it accommodates the basic elements of
provide a compelling account of the processes involved in the the dissociation, conversion, and somatization concepts within a
generation of many medically unexplained complaints. It is, for common explanatory framework. As such, it should be viewed as
example, difficult to conceive of unidentified physical pathology an extension of, rather than an alternative to, these approaches. The
that could be responsible for the profound disruptions of function model has two principal aims. First, it aims to provide a precise,
observed in unexplained neurological illness. mechanistic account of how it is possible to experience compelling
A further problem is the assumption, intrinsic also to the con- symptoms in the absence of underlying pathology. Thus, the
cepts of dissociation and conversion, that medically unexplained proposed model explicitly assumes that genuine somatoform
symptoms must be the product of psychological distress. Although symptoms are subjectively “real” (i.e., similar to explained phys-
such an assertion may be appropriate in the case of presenting and ical symptoms) to the individual reporting them; the model there-
hypochondriacal somatizers, this is not well established empiri- fore has little to say about malingering, which is regarded as a
cally in the case of individuals with somatoform (i.e., functional) separate phenomenon entirely. Second, the model aims to clarify
symptoms (Ron, 1994; Wessely, 2001). how the development and maintenance of unexplained symptoms
are moderated by different risk factors associated with the phe-
Interim Summary nomenon. In achieving these aims, the model attempts to explain
unexplained illness in a way that does not rely on the concept of
The dissociation, conversion, and somatization models have psychosocial precipitation but accommodates its undoubted im-
added much to the field’s understanding of medically unexplained portance in many cases.
illness. Each offers a different perspective on the pathogenesis of
these phenomena, and each is able to accommodate different Explanatory Domain
aspects of the available empirical evidence. The dissociation
model and its derivatives have helped illuminate the basic process- The model is intended as an account of functional somatization
ing mechanisms involved in the generation of unexplained symp- (Kirmayer & Robbins, 1991a, 1991b), encompassing all of the
toms. This perspective is supported by evidence from a number of DSM–IV somatoform and dissociative disorders, with the excep-
cognitive, electrophysiological, and neuroimaging studies. The tion of hypochondriasis, body dysmorphic disorder, depersonal-
concept of conversion has extended the dissociation model by ization disorder, and dissociative identity disorder. Depersonaliza-
providing a more detailed account of the way in which emotional tion disorder is regarded here as distinct from other dissociative
and motivational factors contribute to unexplained illness. The phenomena, involving mechanisms that are qualitatively different
conversion model is supported by research demonstrating that to those described below (Holmes et al., 2004). Dissociative iden-
800 BROWN

tity disorder, in contrast, may have certain mechanisms in common Attention, Consciousness, and Control
with functional somatization, although a comprehensive under-
standing of this condition is beyond the scope of this model. Other The central tenet of the proposed model is that unexplained
unexplained symptom syndromes, such as chronic fatigue, fibro- symptoms can be understood by reference to research and theory
myalgia, and irritable bowel syndrome, are also outside the remit from mainstream cognitive psychology. In particular, the model is
of this account, as are unexplained symptoms with an observable informed by research concerning the nature of different attentional
physical component (e.g., phantom pregnancy). Finally, the model mechanisms in the cognitive system and their role in (a) shaping
does not attempt to explain why some individuals with unex- the contents of consciousness and (b) controlling thought and
plained symptoms display disproportionate levels of abnormal action.
illness behavior (Pilowsky, 1978; e.g., “doctor-shopping,” refusal At any given time, the cognitive system is inundated with
to comply with treatment, demands for repeated investigation). information that has the potential to influence thought and behav-
Inevitably, there will be variation in the specific processes ior. The selection of relevant aspects of this information for further
underlying different medically unexplained symptoms. In line with processing and the control of action is generally regarded as one of
most previous theories in this domain, however, the model at- the most important tasks of the attentional system (Styles, 1997).
tempts to provide a general account of medically unexplained Much of the research in this area has focused on the so-called locus
phenomena that can accommodate all members of this category. of selection, that is, the point in the processing chain where
Such an approach is necessitated by the fact that many individuals attentional selection occurs. Evidence suggests that complex per-
suffering from unexplained illness are polysymptomatic, often ceptual and semantic analyses are often performed prior to the
displaying a combination of neurological and nonneurological selection process (although see Lavie, 1995) through a parallel
symptoms. This approach is not without its critics. Kihlstrom spread of activation in associative networks triggered directly by
(1992), for example, has argued that the mechanisms of somato- the receipt of sense data (e.g., Kosslyn, 1996; Marcel, 1983a,
1983b; Neely, 1977; Posner & Snyder, 1975; Rumelhart, McClel-
form complaints, including somatization disorder, are fundamen-
land, & the PDP Research Group, 1986; for reviews, see Styles,
tally different from those involved in the generation of unex-
1997, and Velmans, 2000). This spread of activation can be re-
plained neurological symptoms (conversion disorder). However,
garded as an inferential process (Sloman, 1996; Marcel, 1983a)
apart from differences in symptom numbers (including the pres-
whereby existing knowledge assists in the identification of rele-
ence of unexplained symptoms in other systems) and illness chro-
vant material for priority processing and hence attentional selec-
nicity, the available data indicate that there is very little that
tion. The selection process itself is thought to integrate the most
distinguishes between conversion and somatization disorders
active information in sensory, perceptual, and memorial systems,
(Ron, 2001). Although such differences are important, they do not
producing multimodal representations that allow for the control of
provide sufficient grounds to assume a priori that fundamentally
routine behavior as well as further processing by attentional mech-
different mechanisms are operating in these conditions.
anisms at higher levels of the system (e.g., Allport, 1987; Colt-
It has also been argued that, unlike conversion disorder, soma-
heart, 1980; Crick & Koch, 1990; Logan, 1988; Marcel, 1983b;
tization disorder is simply an extreme form of abnormal illness
Neuman, 1987; Norman & Shallice, 1986; Velmans, 1991, 2000);
behavior, whereby symptom reports are used as a means of emo- the representations produced by this process are thought to relate
tional expression and social control (Kihlstrom & Canter Kihl- closely to the contents of conscious awareness (Allport, 1988;
strom, 1999). By this view, distortions in somatic perception (i.e., Coltheart, 1980; Crick & Koch, 1990; Marcel, 1983a; Velmans,
the experience of unexplained symptoms) may not be part of 1991, 2000).
somatization disorder at all. It is unclear, however, why the symp- A summary model of the cognitive system based on this re-
tom reports of patients with conversion disorder should be con- search is presented in Figure 2. In this model, the parallel spread
sidered any more reliable than those of patients with multiple of activation in perceptual and memorial systems generates a
unexplained symptoms. In the absence of data to the contrary, it number of perceptual hypotheses, each representing a possible
seems appropriate to pursue an explanation of unexplained illness interpretation of the stimulus world on the basis of previous
that can accommodate both neurological and nonneurological experience (Marcel, 1983a). The most active perceptual hypothesis
symptoms. is then selected by a primary attentional system (PAS) and used to
Although the proposed model assumes that there are common organize relevant sensory information into integrated multimodal
mechanisms underlying different unexplained symptoms, it is clear perceptual units, or primary representations, that provide a work-
that a range of factors moderate the occurrence of this phenome- ing account of the environment for the control of action; in this
non and that the relative contribution of these factors will vary model, perceptual awareness corresponds broadly to the content of
from case to case. As such, exactly the same processes may not be these representations (cf. Allport, 1988; Coltheart, 1980; Crick &
involved in the creation and maintenance of otherwise apparently Koch, 1990; Marcel, 1983b; Neuman, 1987). The PAS is influ-
similar cases of unexplained illness. Moreover, if one regards the enced by several factors, including the nature of the available sense
development of medically unexplained symptoms as a temporally data, the activation of competing and complementary representa-
extended process, it is possible that a variety of different moder- tions in memory, the selection threshold of the perceptual hypoth-
ating factors will be implicated over the course of individual cases eses in question, and top-down input from high-level attention.
also. In the next section, I describe the psychological character of Behavior is controlled via two basic routes in this model, which
unexplained symptoms and the processes involved in their gener- follows from the work of Norman and Shallice (1986). By this
ation. The factors moderating the creation and maintenance of view, routine behaviors are controlled by a hierarchical system of
these complaints are then addressed. procedural representations (schemata) specifying the attentional,
MECHANISMS OF MEDICALLY UNEXPLAINED SYMPTOMS 801

Figure 2. The generation of experience and control of action by the cognitive system. Please note, the
activation levels of thought and action schemata are also influenced by the preattentive spread of activation in
the memory network (not shown).

cognitive, and motoric processes involved in executing well- illness. First, it suggests that the management of behavior is
learned actions. In the proposed model, schemata are activated governed by systems that operate without direct volitional control.
automatically (in the sense used by Logan, 1988) by the construc- This is important in that it allows for functional dissociations
tion of primary representations and are triggered when a threshold between the experience of volition and the control of thought and
level of activation has been reached (in accordance with a com- action. Second, it identifies subjective awareness as a construction
petitive scheduling mechanism; see Norman & Shallice, 1986). or interpretation of the world rather than an unqualified account of
This automatic activation of schemata by the products of PAS objective reality (for a similar view related to normal somatic
selection provides the system with a means of controlling cogni- perception, see Leventhal, 1986). This underscores the fact that on
tion and action that is rapid, highly efficient, and consumes rela- some occasions there may be no direct mapping between sensory
tively few processing resources. Behaviors controlled in this way stimulation and the contents of subjective experience. Indeed,
are experienced as occurring without conscious effort, whereas there are numerous examples of how experience is often more
perception and cognition at this level are associated with a sense of consistent with what people know, believe, and want to believe
intuition and self-evident validity. In situations in which the sys- about the world than with sensory data itself (e.g., hallucinations,
tem does not possess the appropriate schemata, an additional certain illusions, misperceptions, “perceptual set” phenomena, pla-
means of control is required. In this model, novel actions are cebo effects, hypnotic phenomena, defense mechanisms; see, e.g.,
controlled by a secondary attentional system (SAS; equivalent to Bruner & Postman, 1949; Gregory, 1970; Hilgard, 1977; Vaillant,
the supervisory attentional system in the Norman & Shallice, 1986,
1993; Wall, 1993). Phenomena of this sort are important because
model) that controls action indirectly by biasing the relative acti-
they demonstrate how the generation of perceptual experience can
vation levels of schemata via the PAS, in accordance with general
be overdetermined by prior information (e.g., memories) in the
purpose algorithms (for recent theoretical developments, see Bur-
cognitive system (Gregory, 1970; Leventhal, 1986). In the pro-
gess & Shallice, 1996; Shallice, 1988; Shallice & Burgess, 1996).
posed model, medically unexplained symptoms represent a com-
The SAS is the province of self-regulatory processing, moderating
pelling example of this phenomenon.
cognition and action in the pursuit of high-level system goals (cf.
By this view, unexplained symptoms arise when the chronic
Wells & Matthews, 1994). Processing controlled by the SAS
draws on a limited pool of resources, is perceived as mentally activation of stored representations in memory causes the PAS to
demanding, and is associated with a sense of conscious volition select inappropriate information during attentional selection and
and self-awareness (cf. Norman & Shallice, 1986; Wells & Mat- the automatic control of processing. The result is a misinterpreta-
thews, 1994). tion of the sensory world that is experienced as subjectively valid
(i.e., “real” symptoms) because the individual does not have in-
trospective access to the inferences made during the creation of
Medically Unexplained Symptoms as Alterations in
experience and control of action. The nature of the resulting
Perception and Control
symptom reflects the kind of information involved in this process.
The cognitive research and theory outlined above has a number Certain symptoms, such as those characterized by alterations in
of important implications for understanding medically unexplained experience (e.g., pain, feelings of discomfort, nausea, pseudohal-
802 BROWN

lucinations), arise when inappropriate (i.e., inconsistent with in- the operation of the SAS, but the ultimate locus of cognitive and
formation provided by the senses) perceptual hypotheses are se- behavioral control is with the PAS and the schemata underlying
lected during the creation of primary representations by the PAS. routine action. When the patient attempts to control cognition or
In contrast, symptoms characterized by an inability to control action, he or she is engaging the SAS; the attempt is unsuccessful
perception, cognition, or action arise when inappropriate cognitive because the locus of the patient’s deficit is the chronic activation
schemata are automatically triggered by the process of PAS and selection of representations by the PAS. One important impli-
selection. cation of this approach is that symptoms are generated by psycho-
In a case of unexplained sensory loss, for example, the relevant logical mechanisms but are not produced deliberately.
schema would be one instructing the PAS to inhibit attention either Unlike Janet’s (1889, 1907) original dissociation theory, how-
to a particular sensory modality (as in blindness or deafness), a part ever, the proposed model rejects the idea that unexplained symp-
of the body (as in focal sensory loss), or an aspect of the external toms are the product of a purely pathological process. In the
phenomenal world (as in tunnel vision). Similarly, dissociative proposed account, symptoms result from a subtle disruption in
amnesia would be generated by schemata directing the PAS to processes that are fundamental to the everyday control of behavior
withdraw attention from certain types of memorial information or and experience (cf. Hilgard, 1977; Kihlstrom, 1992); in this sense,
inhibiting the operation of certain memory retrieval routines. Sche- unexplained symptoms are essentially “normal” psychological
mata preventing the recall of all autobiographical information phenomena (cf. Halligan & David, 1999). This is clearly consistent
would lead to amnesia with an associated loss of personal identity, with epidemiological evidence demonstrating the ubiquity of un-
as observed in cases of dissociative fugue. In the case of certain explained illness (Escobar et al., 1998; Fink et al., 1999; Kroenke
unexplained motor symptoms, schemata specifying particular limb et al., 1997) and the fact that many individuals experience dis-
positions or body postures (as in fixed dystonia, gait disturbance, abling symptoms in the absence of other psychopathology (Wes-
etc.) or the inhibition of movement altogether (as in paralysis) sely, 2001).
would be involved. In each case, this selection of inappropriate
schemata is often driven by the creation of relevant primary The Origins of “Rogue Representations”
representations by the PAS. In the case of unexplained paralysis,
for example, the underlying schema may be triggered by primary According to this approach, unexplained symptoms constitute
representations consistent with the idea that limb movement is an alteration in the body image generated by information in the
deficient in some way. cognitive system, rather than disturbances in the neural hardware
Unlike other somatoform symptoms, unexplained seizures (so- itself (cf. Leventhal, 1986; Ramachandran & Hirstein, 1998). The
called nonepileptic attacks) are intermittent time-limited phenom- term rogue representation is used here as a generic label for the
ena that probably involve slightly different mechanisms to those inappropriate information that is selected by the PAS during this
outlined above. Whereas other symptoms involve the chronic process. Broadly speaking, any kind of information within the
activation and selection of perceptual or behavioral representa- cognitive system concerning the nature of physical symptoms can
tions, unexplained seizures may involve the automatic activation provide a template for the development of an unexplained com-
of a schema as an acute response to cues from the internal or plaint. Rogue representations can therefore be acquired from many
external environment (Brown, 2002). The same mechanism may different sources, including direct exposure to physical states in the
be responsible for other time-limited behavioral symptoms, such as self, indirect exposure to physical states in others, the sociocultural
pseudoballismus (unexplained violent movements of the limbs, transmission of information about health and illness, and direct
akin to those seen in chorea). In cases involving repetitive move- verbal suggestion.
ments that occur in a time-limited fashion (e.g., tremors), schemata Exposure to physical states in the self. The fact that somato-
may be subject to repeated reactivation through the operation of form patients often have a history of physical illness (e.g., Crimlisk
the SAS. This notion accords well with the common clinical et al., 1998; Merskey & Buhrich, 1975; Slater & Glitherco, 1965;
experience that such movements are often considerably reduced cf. Schrag, Brown, & Trimble, 2004) suggests that many rogue
when the patient is distracted. representations arise out of memory traces acquired during epi-
The model proposed here is clearly consistent with contempo- sodes of organic pathology. Similar traces are also established
rary dissociation theory, which asserts that unexplained symptoms when symptoms result from minor pathological events, such as the
are generated preconsciously by an attentional gating mechanism loss of sensation in a limb following transient ischemia (Breuer &
operating late in the processing chain (e.g., Ludwig, 1972; Sierra Freud, 1893–1895/1991; see also Sharpe & Bass, 1992). The
& Berrios, 1999). It also captures Janet’s (1889) original idea that physical components of emotional states, such as those associated
unexplained symptoms reflect a distortion in awareness resulting with anxiety (e.g., shaking, palpitations, nausea, muscle tension,
from information that has become “stuck” in the cognitive system chest pain, dizziness, dysphagia, light-headedness, visual distur-
(so-called fixed ideas). The proposed model also assumes that a bance, tinnitus), also leave representations in memory that could
horizontal dissociation between different levels of processing in provide the basis for the later development of unexplained symp-
the cognitive system is central to all somatoform symptoms (cf. toms. Also included in this category are the sensorimotor compo-
Hilgard, 1977; Janet, 1907; Kihlstrom, 1992; Oakley, 1999). In- nents of certain defensive reactions that can occur in response to
deed, it is this assumption that allows the model to resolve the traumatic events, including numbing and analgesia (Nijenhuis,
apparent paradox presented by unexplained symptoms character- Vanderlinden, & Spinhoven, 1998), freezing (Nijenhuis, Vander-
ized by an inability to control perception, cognition, or action linden, & Spinhoven, 1998), the sham-death reflex, and the violent
despite repeated and honest attempts to exert control by the suf- motor reaction (Kretschmer, 1926; Ludwig, 1972). The storage of
ferer. In this model, the experience of volition is associated with representations pertaining to these events could account for some
MECHANISMS OF MEDICALLY UNEXPLAINED SYMPTOMS 803

of the most common unexplained neurological symptoms, includ- representations in the memory network (Marcel, 1983a, 1983b;
ing sensory loss, paralyses, and certain types of nonepileptic Neely, 1977), including those representing conceptual and seman-
seizure (Kretschmer, 1926; Ludwig, 1972; Nijenhuis, Vanderlin- tic information. As a result, symptoms tend to become more
den, & Spinhoven, 1998). Arguably, traumatic experiences such as consistent with other information in the system over time (see also
physical or sexual abuse provide one of the richest sources of Kihlstrom, 1992; Leventhal, 1986), which could help account for
material for the development of rogue representations, often en- the influence of beliefs in the development of unexplained
compassing organic damage, intense emotional arousal, and the symptoms.
defensive use of physical reactions within the same experience. Verbal suggestion. The processes identified here as central to
Exposure to physical states in others. There is good evidence the development of unexplained symptoms have also been linked
to suggest that rogue representations can be acquired indirectly to the creation of hypnotic phenomena (Brown & Oakley, 2004; cf.
through exposure to physical symptoms in others (e.g., Charcot, Janet, 1907; Kihlstrom, 1992; Ludwig, 1972; Bryant & McCon-
1889; Fallik & Sigal, 1971; Van Ommeren et al., 2001). Many key, 1999; Oakley, 1999). Assuming that similar processes are
somatoform patients have been exposed to abnormal levels of involved in these phenomena, it seems likely that some unex-
illness in the family environment (Hotopf, Mayou, Wadsworth, & plained symptoms originate from rogue representations developed
Wessely, 1999), and unexplained complaints seem to be more in response to direct verbal suggestions, akin to those encountered
common in individuals who are exposed to physical illness on a in the hypnotic setting. These could either be in the form of
regular basis (e.g., medical students; Woods, Natterson, & Silver- autosuggestions (e.g., thinking “I still won’t be able to see when
man, 1966). The effect is also illustrated by the occurrence of they take the bandages off”) or heterosuggestions from relevant
so-called mass hysteria, when unexplained symptoms can spread others (e.g., being told “This may hurt” during a physical exami-
through a community like a contagious physical condition (e.g., nation). This process may also overlap with that involved in
Van Ommeren et al., 2001). To account for these findings, the phenomena such as the placebo effect; in this case, however, the
model assumes that observing symptoms in others creates memory result is the absence of genuine symptoms rather than the presence
traces that are functionally similar to those generated when the of unexplained ones, reflecting the activation of different repre-
same symptoms are experienced in the self. This is consistent with sentations in each case.
evidence demonstrating that observing actions in others creates
representations that are comparable with those involved in the
production of the same act (e.g., Jeannerod, 1994; Prinz, 1997; Self-Focused Attention and the Development of Symptom
Sebanz, Knoblich, & Prinz, 2003). Chronicity
Sociocultural transmission. It is also well established that
unexplained symptoms can be shaped by sociocultural conceptions According to this account, all people possess material about
of illness, with many somatoform phenomena conforming to a symptoms that could provide the basis for rogue representations
popular conception of what constitutes a “genuine” symptom (e.g., and somatoform conditions. Although some people have much
Reynolds, 1869). Thus, a higher proportion of nonepileptic attacks more material in this respect, it is unlikely that this alone could
involve collapse or prominent motor activity when compared with account for why there are such marked individual differences in
seizures resulting from epilepsy (Meierkord, Will, Fish, & Shor- the tendency to develop unexplained symptoms. How does the
von, 1991). Similarly, the experience of nonpsychotic parasitosis model account for these differences?
(the sensation of insects crawling beneath the skin) and burning The answer to this question lies in understanding how the initial
hands and/or feet, are considerably more common in African and selection of a rogue representation can lead to the development of
Asian cultures than in North America (American Psychiatric As- a chronic problem. Evidence from a number of sources suggests
sociation, 1994), demonstrating the role of local concerns about that self-focused attention is an important factor in this respect.
illness in the development of unexplained symptoms (see Isaac et Robbins and Kirmayer (1991), for instance, have identified a
al., 1995; Van Ommeren et al., 2001). Indeed, all cultures have body-focused attentional bias in patients with unexplained symp-
socially sanctioned models of illness (the so-called sick role; toms, and a link between self-focused attention and subjective
Parsons, 1964) that are likely to shape the representations respon- symptom reports has been obtained in several nonclinical studies
sible for the development of unexplained symptoms. These views (e.g., Pennebaker & Brittingham, 1982; Wegner & Guiliano,
are generated and transmitted by many different sources, including 1980). A number of investigators, for example, have found that
the family, the medical profession, the media, the Internet, and introspective individuals are more likely to experience somatic
society more generally (Fallik & Sigal, 1971; Stewart, 1990). symptoms (e.g., Hansell & Mechanic, 1986; Pennebaker, 1982;
The proposed model assumes that the creation and alteration of Robbins & Kirmayer, 1986), and manipulations aimed at directing
rogue representations through sociocultural transmission involve a attention toward the self tend to increase physical symptom reports
similar process to that operating when symptoms develop after (e.g., Pennebaker & Brittingham, 1982; Wegner & Guiliano,
exposure to illness in others. In other words, exposure to general 1980). Evidence also suggests that elevated symptom reports are
information about physical illness creates memory representations associated with boring environments rather than stimulating ones,
that are functionally equivalent to those encoded during episodes apparently because of the decreased attentional load in the former
of illness in the self. This is consistent with research showing that (e.g., Fillingim & Fine, 1986; Pennebaker & Lightner, 1980). In
executing an action and thinking about that action involve similar addition, there is strong evidence that self-focus is a feature of
neurocognitive processes (e.g., Jeannerod, 1994; Prinz, 1997). The depression and anxiety (e.g., Hope & Heimberg, 1985; T. W.
model also assumes that the activation levels of rogue representa- Smith & Greenberg, 1981; Wells & Matthews, 1994), which often
tions are partly determined by the activation of any associated occur alongside somatoform illness (Brown & Ron, 2002). Attend-
804 BROWN

ing to the body has also been identified as an important factor in


hypochondriacal somatization (Salkovskis & Warwick, 1986).
In the proposed model, the recurrent redirection of attention
onto symptoms by the SAS is the primary pathogenic factor in the
development of symptom chronicity (see Figure 3). Allocating
high-level attention to a symptom (e.g., checking to see if is still
present) serves to augment the activation of the rogue representa-
tion and lowers the amount of activation required for it to be
selected in future (i.e., the selection threshold). This is a relatively
self-perpetuating process, facilitated by the automatic allocation of
SAS-level attention onto environmental events that are consistent
with currently selected representations (a form of confirmatory
bias). If symptom-focused attention is maintained for a sufficient
period, the activation levels of rogue representations may become
high enough to ensure their continued selection over time. In such
cases, the generation of an unexplained symptom is complete.
According to this account, anything that serves to increase
symptom-focused attention will contribute to the development and
maintenance of medically unexplained symptoms. Included in this
category are the misattribution of symptoms to physical illness,
negative affect, illness worry and rumination, illness behavior, and
certain personality factors. To this extent, the proposed model
overlaps considerably with the model of somatization described by
Kirmayer and Taillefer (1997; see also Chalder, 2001). The rela-
tionship between these different factors is shown in Figure 4.
Misattribution of symptoms. It is well established that patients’
experiences of symptoms, and their behavioral responses to them,
are strongly influenced by how they interpret their symptomatol- Figure 4. Factors involved in the development of symptom chronicity
ogy (e.g., Cioffi, 1991; Leventhal, 1986; Pennebaker, 1982; Skel- (feedback loops to rogue representations not shown).
ton & Croyle, 1991). A number of studies have shown, for exam-
ple, that symptoms perceived as a sign of serious physical
pathology are more likely to attract attention than those that are system. On the one hand, misattribution may arise automatically
attributed to a benign cause (e.g., Cioffi, 1991). For this reason, it during the creation of primary representations by PAS selection.
is likely that misattributing somatoform symptoms to a serious Misinterpretations of this sort may be in the form of “negative
medical cause—akin to the catastrophic misinterpretation of nor- automatic thoughts” associated with a subjective sense of sponta-
mal sensations found in hypochondriacal somatization—will con- neity and inevitability (cf. Beck, 1976). On the other hand, mis-
tribute to their maintenance in many cases. interpretations may be the product of ruminative activity associ-
There are two basic routes to symptom misattribution in the ated with the SAS (see Illness worry and rumination section; also
proposed model, reflecting the hierarchical nature of the cognitive Wells & Matthews, 1994). In both cases, however, the product is
an escalation of negative affect and perceived disability, increased
worry and rumination about illness, and potentially inappropriate
illness behavior. In turn, these factors increase the likelihood of
symptoms being misattributed to a physical illness, setting up a
vicious cycle (see Figure 4).
It is likely that several different factors can contribute to the
misattribution of symptoms to a physical cause. Unusual, painful,
or debilitating symptoms are likely to be associated with a greater
degree of negative affect and are therefore more likely to be
appraised as a threat warranting attention and self-regulatory ac-
tion (Cioffi, 1991). Maladaptive beliefs concerning the nature of
health and the meaning of symptoms are also likely to be impor-
tant, particularly the beliefs that health is a state devoid of symp-
toms and that symptoms always indicate pathology, both of which
are commonly found in patients with unexplained symptoms (Rief,
Hiller, & Margraf, 1998). “Irrational” beliefs of this sort are likely
Figure 3. The role of secondary attention in the development of unex- to originate in the familial context, particularly where an individual
plained symptoms. Factors perpetuating the allocation of secondary atten- has been exposed to high levels of illness (Hotopf et al., 1999) or
tion to rogue representations are shown in the dotted box (see the Self- disproportionate parental concern over benign physical symptoms
Focused Attention and the Development of Symptom Chronicity section). (Benjamin & Eminson, 1992). In itself, catastrophic misinterpre-
MECHANISMS OF MEDICALLY UNEXPLAINED SYMPTOMS 805

tation is not necessarily irrational, however. Indeed, attributing Once an individual has begun to worry and ruminate about their
subjectively compelling symptoms to a serious physical cause symptoms, terminating these processes may prove difficult unless
could be regarded as a normal part of the sick role, particularly symptoms improve. Over time, this may lead to the development
where certain symptoms are concerned (e.g., unexplained neuro- of a “cognitive–attentional syndrome” characterized by chronic
logical symptoms). It may even be positively sanctioned by contact rumination, worry, and symptom focus; maladaptive coping; and a
with health care professionals (Lipowski, 1988), who often collude reduction of central processing resources (Wells, 2000). This could
with patients’ attributions about their conditions (Salmon, Peters, account for the attentional deficit seen in some patients with
& Stanley, 1999), refer for unnecessary investigations and physical unexplained symptoms (Bendefeldt et al., 1976; Horvath et al.,
treatments (paradoxically “to put the patient’s mind at rest”), and 1980; Janet, 1907). Chronic rumination may also lead to the
even misdiagnose somatoform symptoms as physical problems development of ruminative schemata that can be triggered by PAS
(Kouyanou, Pither, Rabe-Hesketh, & Wessely, 1998). selection alone, producing the same cognitive effects in the ab-
Negative emotional states. Negative affect is not only a prod- sence of SAS-level activity (cf. Wells, 2000). In this way, a
uct of somatoform symptoms and their attribution to physical
previously held element of control over the processes involved in
illness but also a potential contributor to the development and
the generation and maintenance of symptoms is lost.
maintenance of these conditions. As well as increasing the likeli-
Illness behavior. Depending on the way symptoms are inter-
hood of catastrophic misinterpretation, ongoing negative emo-
preted, the individual may engage in several different types of
tional states (such as those associated with anxiety and depression)
illness behavior, including “checking,” medical consulting, infor-
serve to increase symptom-focused attention (see Wells & Mat-
thews, 1994) and may trigger or perpetuate both rumination and mation seeking, reassurance seeking, avoidance, and doctor shop-
illness behavior. It is also possible that negative affect directly ping, each of which directs attention toward the body and symp-
influences the actual encoding and storage of rogue representa- toms. Continued attempts to check whether symptoms are present
tions. Such a concept could help explain the spontaneous devel- (e.g., by mentally and physically scanning the body) is likely to be
opment of unexplained symptoms in the face of acute stressors. It particularly important in this respect (cf. Salkovskis, 1989; Sal-
may be that extreme fear or anxiety leads to the chronic selection kovskis & Warwick, 1986), especially when behavior has become
of rogue representations, rather like the acquisition of conditioned automatized over time and introspective access to the process has
aversion to noxious stimuli. A second, and perhaps related, pos- been reduced. Repeated help seeking may also be central in main-
sibility might be that symptoms are acquired as the result of a taining attention to symptoms, especially when casual instructions
spontaneous narrowing of attention occurring as a biological re- to keep an eye on symptoms explicitly endorse this process. In
sponse to extreme anxiety or fear (Cardeña & Spiegel, 1993; Janet, addition, attempts to seek reassurance through the acquisition of
1907). It may be that this narrowing of attention serves to increase illness-related information (e.g., from the Internet) may serve to
the activation level of rogue representations, thereby contributing increase anxiety and provides ambiguous material that could serve
to the development of symptom chronicity. as a basis for rumination, catastrophic misinterpretation, and the
Illness worry and rumination. Both negative affect and the development of new rogue representations. Similarly, doctor shop-
process of symptom misattribution trigger illness worry and rumi- ping may lead to patients receiving conflicting advice and diag-
nation, which may play a particularly important role in the devel- noses, increasing the likelihood of rumination and misinterpreta-
opment of symptom chronicity. Following Wells (2000), illness tion and reducing patients’ faith in the reliability of the health care
worry and rumination are defined as repetitive forms of self- system. In contrast, avoidance of illness-related material serves to
regulatory activity by the SAS aimed at reducing the discrepancy prevent the disconfirmation of any negative beliefs about symp-
between current and desired states related to the presence of toms, as does avoidance of activities that are perceived as having
physical symptoms. Subjectively, they are experienced as streams the potential to exacerbate symptoms (Chalder, 2001); the latter
of conscious, typically negative mental activity concerning the may be particularly problematic in that it can lead to physical
nature, meaning, and implications of symptoms and appropriate
deconditioning and health problems in its own right.
courses of action to be taken in their presence. They are also
Personality factors. The proposed model is consistent with
associated with a state of self-focused attention and constant
evidence demonstrating that individuals with certain personality
monitoring of the body for symptom-relevant information. In
features are particularly vulnerable to developing unexplained
general, these forms of cognition contribute to the maintenance of
symptoms. Trait measures of negative affectivity (Watson &
unexplained symptoms by perpetuating the allocation of high-level
attention to rogue representations (and other perceptual and me- Clark, 1984), for example, consistently correlate with subjective
morial information that supports their activation) and by increasing symptom reports but show little or no correlation with objective
negative affect, symptom misinterpretation and illness behavior. health markers. Studies show that high negative affectivity is
The degree of rumination and worry depends on a number of associated with introspection, self-focus, worry, symptom misin-
factors, including the level of associated affect, the nature of any terpretation, and illness behavior (Watson & Clark, 1984; Watson
symptom misinterpretation, and the information available to indi- & Pennebaker, 1989), each of which has been linked to the
viduals about their problems. Certain beliefs may also perpetuate development of unexplained symptom chronicity in this account.
illness worry and rumination, particularly “positive” metabeliefs, In addition, individuals high in hypnotic susceptibility may be
which suggest that these processes are useful for ensuring appro- particularly sensitive to the automatic activation of cognitive and
priate vigilance, mental preparation, and illness behavior (Wells, behavioral schemata by internal and external events (Brown &
2000). By maintaining rumination and worry, however, such be- Oakley, 2004), which could increase their vulnerability to devel-
liefs can have the paradoxical effect of perpetuating symptoms. oping somatoform symptoms.
806 BROWN

Body-Focused Attention as Psychological Defense: a concept that is central to the original conversion model. In
Conversion Reconsidered addition to the primary gain of reducing negative affect, symptoms
may also confer additional advantages to the individual, or sec-
The processes outlined thus far provide an explanation of how ondary gains, with both positive (e.g., greater emotional support
unexplained symptoms can develop in the absence of trauma. Why and affection from others) and negative reinforcement (e.g., pre-
is a history of trauma so common in patients with these conditions? vention of revictimization) contributing to their maintenance (e.g.,
The model accounts for this by assuming that traumatic events Breuer & Freud, 1893–1895/1991; Kellner, 1986; Kretschmer,
such as physical, sexual, and emotional abuse often lead to the use 1926; Ludwig, 1972).
of body-focused attention as a means of avoiding the affect and
cognitive activity associated with experiences of this sort.
Implications
Under normal circumstances, the individual is able to manage
negative affect via self-regulatory processing and goal-oriented Treatment
action (Wells, 2000; Wells & Matthews, 1994). The high level of
negative affect associated with trauma, however, increases the The proposed model has obvious implications for the treatment
difficulty of effective self-regulation, particularly when previous of patients with medically unexplained symptoms. Given the cog-
assumptions about the self, others, and the world have been vio- nitive foundations of the model, it is particularly amenable to CBT,
lated by the nature of the traumatic event (cf. Horowitz, 1986; although other treatments such as psychodynamic psychotherapy,
Janoff-Bulman, 1992). Self-regulation may also be impeded by physiotherapy, occupational therapy, and pharmacotherapy (e.g.,
appraisals indicating that externally oriented actions (e.g., resist- antidepressants) are also consistent with this approach. Once the
ing, attempting to escape) could prove futile or even lead to extent of any physical pathology has been established and an
retaliatory revictimization. Under these circumstances, the system organic explanation for symptoms has been ruled out, the treat-
is forced to rely almost exclusively on internal processes for the ment of choice depends on a detailed assessment of the patient’s
regulation of traumatic affect. According to the proposed model, symptoms and the factors associated with their onset and mainte-
one way of reducing this potentially overwhelming affect is to nance, including the number, nature, and history of both current
divert SAS resources from self-regulatory processing and onto the and previous symptoms; the presence of any obvious emotional or
body. Such a strategy could be used both during an episode of relational difficulties associated with the onset of symptoms; the
victimization and/or afterward, when a motivation to avoid nature and extent of emotional disturbance more generally; the
trauma-related material and its associated affect remains; this is degree of disability associated with symptoms; the patient’s illness
particularly likely in cases in which revictimization is perceived as beliefs and attributions about the causes of his or her symptoms
inevitable (e.g., in a consistently abusive family environment). (particularly when anxious) and the patient’s tendency for cata-
These defensive actions serve to protect the individual from over- strophic misinterpretation; the extent of any worry and rumination
whelming affect, although the resulting body-focused attention about symptoms; the nature and extent of any illness behavior,
facilitates the creation and maintenance of unexplained symptoms including body checking, help seeking and consulting behavior,
via the processes outlined above. reassurance seeking, information seeking, avoidance, and doctor
Peritraumatic body-focused attention would also increase the shopping; any history of traumatic events, particularly in child-
salience of the physiological aspects of trauma-related emotion hood; the presence of possible secondary gains (e.g., litigation
(including those related to emotional behavior) while suppressing claims); and relevant personality factors (e.g., negative affectivity,
its affective and cognitive components. This could go some way dispositional self-focus). The likely impact of these factors on the
toward explaining the development of symptoms that in the tradi- individual’s tendency to allocate attention to symptoms should be
tional conversion model would be regarded as symbolic of their considered throughout. Establishing the possible origins of the
underlying psychodynamics. Thus, the rogue representation under- rogue representations underlying symptoms is not essential, al-
lying a fixed dystonic hand could result from a clenched fist though doing so could assist in socializing the patient to a psy-
associated with angry feelings experienced at the time of trauma; chological account of his or her problems.
the individual may not recall these feelings, however, due to the The assessment provides the basis for an idiosyncratic formu-
inhibition of high-level cognitive and affective processing during lation identifying the factors involved in the creation of symptoms
the event. Focusing attention on the body during trauma would and the processes maintaining symptom-focused attention, allow-
also augment the salience of other somatosensory or sensorimotor ing avenues for intervention to be identified. When symptoms are
experiences associated with the event, such as pain (cf. Badura et thought to result from interpersonal difficulties and/or unresolved
al., 1997), sexual feelings and movements (cf. Betts & Boden, emotional conflicts, such as those pertaining to early abuse or other
1992), and different physical defense mechanisms (Nijenhuis, childhood traumas, psychodynamically oriented therapy may be an
Spinhoven, et al., 1998; Nijenhuis, Vanderlinden, & Spinhoven, appropriate treatment option. In cases in which interpersonal or
1998), which could lead to the development of symptoms that emotional conflicts do not appear to be relevant, or a psychody-
recapitulate other aspects of the initial trauma. Where other effec- namic approach is precluded for other reasons (e.g., client prefer-
tive self-regulatory strategies are unavailable, focusing attention ence, unsuitability), the use of CBT is indicated. The present
on the body may become a habitual mode of dealing with negative model extends current cognitive– behavioral work in this area by
affect and stressful life events, producing a traitlike vulnerability to (a) providing a detailed rationale for the use of CBT with unex-
unexplained symptoms such as that seen in somatization disorder. plained symptoms, (b) identifying the mechanisms involved in
The development of symptoms also provides a way of express- clinical change, and (c) suggesting certain additions to the thera-
ing negative affect without acknowledging its psychosocial source, peutic arsenal.
MECHANISMS OF MEDICALLY UNEXPLAINED SYMPTOMS 807

From the outset, efforts should be directed toward helping explained symptoms. This prediction could be addressed in stud-
patients accept a psychological interpretation of their problems. ies investigating the comorbidity between unexplained illness and
This could be facilitated by presenting a rationale for therapy other conditions associated with body-focused attention, such as
based on the model proposed here. The advantage of this approach body dysmorphic disorder (e.g., Veale, 2001) and the eating dis-
is that it provides a normalizing interpretation of somatoform orders (e.g., Fairburn, Shafran, & Cooper, 1999; for preliminary
illness that does not rely on the concept of unconscious conflict, an data, see Krishnamoorthy, Brown, & Trimble, 2001). Further
idea that is often explicitly rejected by patients. Possible social- research investigating the occurrence of unexplained symptoms in
ization exercises might include the use of analogies demonstrating individuals with personality traits such as high private self-
how experience often misrepresents reality, such as the placebo consciousness (Fenigstein, Scheier, & Buss, 1975) is also
effect, battlefield analgesia, and hypnotic phenomena. The creation warranted.
or removal of symptoms using suggestion or hypnosis may provide Hypothesis 4: The relationship between traumatic experience
particularly compelling real-time examples of this process (Oak- and unexplained symptoms is mediated by the use of body-focused
ley, 2001). Once patients are suitably socialized to the model, attention as a coping strategy. The use of mediator analysis (e.g.,
interventions aimed at reducing symptom-focused attention can be Baron & Kenny, 1986) may be particularly useful in this context.
considered. Maladaptive beliefs, catastrophic misinterpretations, Hypothesis 5: Modalities affected by unexplained symptoms will
and illness behaviors can all be addressed using conventional be associated with deficits in high-level postattentive processing
verbal and behavioral reattribution techniques, and the use of but not low-level preattentive processing. A number of different
controlled worry periods and “detached mindfulness” may assist in cognitive methodologies could be used to assess this hypothesis
minimizing patients’ worry and rumination about symptoms (see, e.g., Roelofs et al., 2001; Roelofs, van Galen, Eling, Keijsers,
(Wells, 1997, 2000). Symptom-focused attention could also be & Hoogduin, 2003).
addressed more directly by the use of techniques such as attention Hypothesis 6: The catastrophic misinterpretation of symptoms,
training (Wells, 1990), which aims to foster increased control over illness worry and rumination, illness behavior, and negative affect
attentional processing. Unlike traditional CBT, the current ap- are all linked to the occurrence and severity of unexplained
proach also provides a rationale for the use of techniques such as symptoms by their effect on symptom-focused attention and vice
suggestion (with or without hypnosis), to deactivate rogue repre- versa. Multivariate research using appropriate analytic tech-
sentations more directly (Oakley, 2001), as well as treatments that niques (e.g., mediator analysis, path analysis, structural equation
could help replace them with more adaptive representations (e.g., modeling) may be a useful option in this case. Such research could
occupational therapy, physiotherapy). Finally, the role of possible also help identify which, if any, of these factors (or combination of
secondary gains should be considered and interventions applied factors) is the most important in the development of unexplained
where feasible. symptoms.
Further research should also be conducted to establish the va-
Testing the Model lidity of the link between suggestion and unexplained illness. In
particular, research should address the possibility of using sug-
At the heart of the present approach is the assumption that all gested phenomena as laboratory analogues of medically unex-
somatoform conditions (with the exception of those involving plained symptoms. The development of such analogues would
observable physical phenomena) are governed by the same basic facilitate controlled investigation of the factors that mediate and
mechanism, namely, the repetitive reallocation of high-level atten- moderate the creation and maintenance of unexplained symptoms.
tion onto symptoms. This basic assumption allows for the gener- Other studies should further investigate the relationship between
ation of several novel hypotheses by which the model might be unexplained illness and suggestibility, using well-defined patient
falsified. groups and validated instruments that assess both objective and
Hypothesis 1: The severity and duration of unexplained symp- subjective responses to suggestions. It would also be instructive to
toms will be increased or decreased by manipulations directing address levels of suggestibility in both hypnotic and nonhypnotic
attention toward or away from symptoms, respectively. In addi- contexts, with a view to assessing the relative contribution of
tion to simple laboratory studies, this prediction could be assessed hypnosis and suggestibility per se to the creation of unexplained
clinically by investigating the impact of attention training (Wells, symptoms (cf. Brown & Oakley, 2004; Kirsch, 1997).
1990, 2000), a procedure designed to improve attentional control
and the ability to focus externally, on patients with unexplained Summary
symptoms.
Hypotheses 2a and 2b: Patients with unexplained symptoms will This review has attempted to describe current theoretical models
show a symptom-focused attentional bias when compared with of medically unexplained symptoms and the research cited in their
nonsomatoform controls; individuals with a traitlike tendency to support. It is clear that research motivated by the concepts of
develop unexplained symptoms will show a body-focused bias even dissociation, conversion, and somatization has added much to the
when asymptomatic. These hypotheses may be particularly ame- understanding of unexplained symptoms. Nevertheless, it is clear
nable to investigation using electrophysiological (e.g., event- that there are certain shortcomings— both empirical and concep-
related potentials), neuroimaging (e.g., functional magnetic reso- tual—with existing approaches in this area. In particular, none of
nance imaging) and cognitive (e.g., modified emotional Stroop) the available models is able to provide an adequate account of how
paradigms. subjectively compelling symptoms can persist in the absence of
Hypothesis 3: Individuals with a tendency to focus attention on organic pathology. In this article, an integrative conceptual frame-
the body will be disproportionately vulnerable to developing un- work that attempts to address these shortcomings, and that explic-
808 BROWN

itly endorses the idea that unexplained symptoms are subjectively with hysterical disturbances of vision. Journal of Psychosomatic Re-
real to the sufferer, has been described. search, 14, 187–194.
The proposed model is consistent with Janet’s (1889, 1907) Bendefeldt, F., Miller, L. L., & Ludwig, A. M. (1976). Cognitive perfor-
dissociation theory in its assertion that symptoms are caused by mance in conversion hysteria. Archives of Psychiatry, 33, 1250 –1254.
stored information in the cognitive system that disrupts the inter- Benjamin, S., & Eminson, D. M. (1992). Abnormal illness behavior:
Childhood experiences and long-term consequences. International Re-
action between conscious and preconscious aspects of information
view of Psychiatry, 4, 55–70.
processing. In line with conversion theory, the model suggests that Bernstein, E. M., & Putnam, F. W. (1986). Development, reliability, and
this process is often driven by a defensive reaction that operates to validity of a dissociation scale. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease,
reduce the individual’s exposure to traumatic affect. Like somati- 174, 727–735.
zation theory, the model identifies symptom-focused attention as Betts, T., & Boden, S. (1992). Diagnosis, management and prognosis of a
central to the creation and maintenance of unexplained symptoms, group of 128 patients with non-epileptic attack disorder. Part II. Previous
and highlights the importance of catastrophic misinterpretation, childhood sexual abuse in the aetiology of these disorders. Seizure, 1,
illness beliefs, rumination and worry, illness behavior, negative 27–32.
affect, and personality features in this process. Although consistent Binzer, M., Andersen, P. M., & Kullgren, G. (1997). Clinical characteris-
with the concepts of dissociation, conversion, and somatization, tics of patients with motor disability due to conversion disorder: A
the model extends existing theories in this area by reformulating prospective control group study. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery,
and Psychiatry, 63, 63– 68.
them within a common explanatory framework that is based on
Blanchard, E. B., & Scharff, L. (2002). Psychosocial aspects of assessment
cognitive psychological principles. In this way, the model attempts
and treatment of irritable bowel syndrome in adults and recurrent ab-
to place the current understanding of unexplained symptoms dominal pain in children. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychol-
within the remit of everyday psychology, allowing for a more ogy, 70, 725–738.
normalizing interpretation of this phenomenon. It is hoped that the Bowers, K. S. (1992). Dissociated control and the limits of hypnotic
model provides a useful scheme for organizing existing research responsiveness. Consciousness & Cognition, 1, 32–39.
and theory in this area, as well as an impetus for further research Breuer, J., & Freud, S. (1991). Studies on hysteria. In J. Strachey & A.
into unexplained symptoms and the development of more effective Strachey (Eds. & Trans.), The Penguin Freud library (Vol. 3). London:
strategies for their treatment. Penguin. (Original work published 1893–1895)
Brown, R. J. (2002). Epilepsy, dissociation and nonepileptic seizures. In
M. R. Trimble & B. Schmitz (Eds.), The neuropsychiatry of epilepsy (pp.
References 189 –209). Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Brown, R. J. (in press). Dissociation and conversion in psychogenic illness.
Akagi, H., & House, A. (2001). The epidemiology of hysterical conversion.
In M. Hallett, S. Fahn, J. Jankovic, A. E. Lang, C. R. Cloninger, & S. C.
In P. W. Halligan, C. Bass, & J. Marshall (Eds.), Contemporary ap-
Yudofsky (Eds.), Psychogenic movement disorders: Psychobiology and
proaches to the study of hysteria: Clinical and theoretical perspectives
treatment of a functional disorder. Philadelphia: Lippincott, Williams &
(pp. 73– 87). Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
Alajouanine, T., Scherrer, J., Barbizet, J., Calvet, J., & Verley, R. (1958). Wilkins.
Potentiels évoqués corticaux chez des sujets atteints de troubles somes- Brown, R. J., & Oakley, D. A. (2004). An integrative cognitive model of
thésiques [Cortical evoked potentials in patients with sensory loss]. hypnosis and high hypnotisability. In M. Heap, R. J. Brown, & D. A.
Revue Neurologique, 98, 757. Oakley (Eds.), The highly hypnotizable person: Theoretical, experimen-
Allport, A. (1987). Selection for action: Some behavioural and neurophys- tal and clinical issues (pp. 152–186). London: Brunner-Routledge.
iological considerations of attention and action. In H. Heuer & A. F. Brown, R. J., & Ron, M. A. (2002). Conversion and somatoform disorders.
Sanders (Eds.), Perspectives on selection and action (pp. 395– 419). In V. S. Ramachandran (Ed.), Encyclopedia of the human brain (Vol. 2,
Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. pp. 37– 49). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Allport, A. (1988). What concept of consciousness? In A. J. Marcel & E. Brown, R. J., Schrag, A., & Trimble, M. R. (in press). Dissociation,
Bisiach (Eds.), Consciousness in contemporary science (pp. 159 –182). childhood interpersonal trauma, and family functioning in somatization
Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. disorder. American Journal of Psychiatry.
Alper, K., Devinsky, O., Perrine, K., Luciano, D., Vazquez, B., Pacia, S., Brown, R. J., & Trimble, M. R. (2000). Dissociative psychopathology,
& Rhee, E. (1997). Dissociation in epilepsy and conversion nonepileptic non-epileptic seizures, and neurology. Journal of Neurology, Neurosur-
seizures. Epilepsia, 38, 991–997. gery, and Psychiatry, 69, 285–291.
American Psychiatric Association. (1994). Diagnostic and statistical man- Bruner, J. S., & Postman, L. (1949). On the perception of incongruity: A
ual of mental disorders (4th ed.). Washington, DC: Author. paradigm. Journal of Personality, 18, 206 –223.
Bach, M., Bach, D., Böehmer, F., & Nutzinger, D. O. (1994). Alexithymia Bryant, R. A., & McConkey, K. M. (1989). Visual conversion disorder: A
and somatization: Relationship to DSM-III diagnoses. Journal of Psy- case analysis of the influence of visual information. Journal of Abnormal
chosomatic Research, 38, 529 –538. Psychology, 98, 326 –329.
Badura, A. S., Reiter, R. C., Altmaier, E. M., Rhomberg, A., & Elas, D. Bryant, R. A., & McConkey, K. M. (1999). Functional blindness: A
(1997). Dissociation, somatization, substance abuse, and coping in construction of cognitive and social influences. Cognitive Neuropsychi-
women with chronic pelvic pain. Obstetrics & Gynecology, 90, 405– atry, 4, 227–241.
410. Burgess, P. W., & Shallice, T. (1996). Confabulation and the control of
Baron, R. M., & Kenny, D. A. (1986). The moderator–mediator variable recollection. Memory, 4, 359 – 412.
distinction in social psychological research: Conceptual, strategic, and Cardeña, E. (1994). The domain of dissociation. In S. J. Lynn & J. W. Rhue
statistical considerations. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, (Eds.), Dissociation: Clinical and theoretical perspectives (pp. 15–31).
51, 1173–1182. New York: Guilford Press.
Beck, A. T. (1976). Cognitive therapy and the emotional disorders. New Cardeña, E., & Spiegel, D. (1993). Dissociative reactions to the Bay Area
York: International Universities Press. earthquake. American Journal of Psychiatry, 150, 474 – 478.
Behrman, J., & Levy, R. (1970). Neurophysiological studies on patients Chalder, T. (2001). Cognitive behavioural therapy as a treatment for
MECHANISMS OF MEDICALLY UNEXPLAINED SYMPTOMS 809

conversion disorders. In P. W. Halligan, C. Bass, & J. Marshall (Eds.), cognitive neuropsychological account. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 4,
Contemporary approaches to the study of hysteria: Clinical and theo- 161–163.
retical perspectives (pp. 298 –311). Oxford, England: Oxford University Hansell, S., & Mechanic, D. (1986). The socialization of introspection and
Press. illness behavior. In S. McHugh & T. M. Vallis (Eds.), Illness behavior:
Charcot, J. M. (1889). Clinical lectures on diseases of the nervous system A multidisciplinary model (pp. 253–260). New York: Plenum Press.
(Vol. 3). London: New Sydenham Society. Hernández-Peón, R., Chávez-Ibarra, G., & Aguilar-Figueroa, E. (1963).
Cioffi, D. (1991). Beyond attentional strategies: A cognitive-perceptual Somatic evoked potentials in one case of hysterical anesthesia. Electro-
model of somatic interpretation. Psychological Bulletin, 109, 25– 41. encephalography and Clinical Neurophysiology, 15, 889 – 892.
Cohen, K., Auld, F., & Brooker, H. (1994). Is alexithymia related to Hilgard, E. R. (1977). Divided consciousness: Multiple controls in human
psychosomatic disorder and somatizing? Journal of Psychosomatic Re- thought and action. New York: Wiley.
search, 38, 119 –127. Holmes, E., Brown, R. J., Mansell, W., Fearon, R. P., Hunter, E.,
Coltheart, M. (1980). Iconic memory and visible persistence. Perception & Frasquilho, F., & Oakley, D. A. (2004). Are there two qualitatively
Psychophysics, 27, 183–228. distinct forms of dissociation? A review and some clinical implications.
Craig, T. K. J. (2001). Life events: Meanings and precursors. In P. W. Manuscript submitted for publication.
Halligan, C. Bass, & J. Marshall (Eds.), Contemporary approaches to Hope, D. A., & Heimberg, R. G. (1985). Public and private self-
the study of hysteria: Clinical and theoretical perspectives (pp. 88 –101). consciousness and social phobia. Journal of Personality Assessment, 52,
Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. 626 – 639.
Crick, F., & Koch, C. (1990). Towards a neurobiological theory of con- Horowitz, M. J. (1986). Stress response syndromes (2nd ed.). Northvale,
sciousness. Seminars in the Neurosciences, 2, 263–275. NJ: Aronson.
Crimlisk, H. L., Bhatia, K., Cope, H., David, A., Marsden, C. D., & Ron, Horvath, T., Friedman, J., & Meares, R. (1980). Attention in hysteria: A
M. A. (1998). Slater revisited: 6 year follow up of patients with medi- study of Janet’s hypothesis by means of habituation and arousal mea-
cally unexplained motor symptoms. British Medical Journal, 316, 582– sures. American Journal of Psychiatry, 137, 217–220.
586. Hotopf, M., Mayou, R., Wadsworth, M., & Wessely, S. (1999). Childhood
David, D., Brown, R. J., Pojoga, C., & David, A. (2000). The impact of risk factors for adults with medically unexplained symptoms: Results
posthypnotic amnesia and directed forgetting on implicit and explicit from a national birth cohort study. American Journal of Psychiatry, 156,
memory: New insights from a modified process dissociation procedure. 1796 –1800.
International Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis, 48, 267– Iezzi, A., & Adams, H. E. (1993). Somatoform and factitious disorders. In
289. P. B. Sutker & H. E. Adams (Eds.), Comprehensive handbook of
Escobar, J. I., Waitzkin, H., Cohen Silver, R., Gara, M., & Holman, A. psychopathology (pp. 167–201). New York: Plenum Press.
(1998). Abridged somatization: A study in primary care. Psychosomatic Isaac, M., Janca, A., Burke, K. C., Costa e Silva, J. A., Acuda, S. W.,
Medicine, 60, 466 – 472. Altanura, A. C., et al. (1995). Medically unexplained symptoms somatic
Fairburn, C., Shafran, R., & Cooper, Z. (1999). A cognitive behavioural in different cultures: A preliminary report from Phase I of the World
theory of anorexia nervosa. Behaviour Research and Therapy, 37, 1–13. Health Organization international study of somatoform disorders. Psy-
Fallik, A., & Sigal, M. (1971). Hysteria: The choice of symptom site. A chotherapy and Psychosomatics, 64, 88 –93.
review of 40 cases of conversion hysteria. Psychotherapy and Psycho- Janet, P. (1889). L’automatisme psychologique [Psychological automa-
somatics, 19, 310 –318. tisms]. Paris: Alcan.
Fenigstein, A., Scheier, M. F., & Buss, A. H. (1975). Public and private Janet, P. (1907). The major symptoms of hysteria. New York: Macmillan.
self-consciousness: Assessment and theory. Journal of Consulting and Janoff-Bulman, R. (1992). Shattered assumptions: Towards a new psychol-
Clinical Psychology, 43, 522–527. ogy of trauma. New York: Free Press.
Fillingim, R. B., & Fine, M. A. (1986). The effects of internal versus Jeannerod, M. (1994). The representing brain—Neural correlates of motor
external information processing on symptom perception in an exercise intention and imagery. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 17, 187–202.
setting. Health Psychology, 5, 115–123. Kashner, T. M., Rost, K., Cohen, B., Anderson, M., & Smith, G. R. (1995).
Fink, P., Sørensen, L., Engberg, M., Holm, M., & Munk-Jørgensen, P. Enhancing the health of somatization disorder patients. Effectiveness of
(1999). Somatization in primary care. Prevalence, health care utilization short-term group therapy. Psychosomatics, 36, 462– 470.
and general practitioner recognition. Psychosomatics, 40, 330 –338. Kellner, R. (1986). Somatization and hypochondriasis. New York:
Frankel, F. H. (1994). Dissociation in hysteria and hypnosis: A concept Praeger-Greenwood.
aggrandized. In S. J. Lynn & J. W. Rhue (Eds.), Dissociation: Clinical Kellner, R. (1990). Somatization: Theories and research. Journal of Ner-
and theoretical perspectives (pp. 80 –93). New York: Guilford Press. vous and Mental Disease, 178, 150 –160.
Fukudu, M., Hata, A., Niwa, S., Hiramatsu, K., Yokokoji, M., Hayashida, Kihlstrom, J. F. (1987, September 18). The cognitive unconscious. Science,
S., et al. (1996). Event-related potential correlates of functional hearing 237, 1445–1451.
loss: Reduced P3 amplitude preserved N1 and N2 components in a Kihlstrom, J. F. (1992). Dissociative and conversion disorders. In D. J.
unilateral case. Neuropsychiatry and Clinical Neurosciences, 50, 85– 87. Stein & J. Young (Eds.), Cognitive science and clinical disorders (pp.
Gould, R., Miller, B., Goldberg, M., & Benson, D. (1986). The validity of 247–270). San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
hysterical signs and symptoms. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, Kihlstrom, J. F., & Canter Kihlstrom, L. (1999). Self, sickness, somatiza-
174, 593–597. tion, and systems of care. In R. J. Contrada & R. D. Ashmore (Eds.),
Gregory, R. L. (1970). The intelligent eye. London: Weidenfeld & Rutgers series on self and social identity: Vol. 2. Self, social identity, and
Nicolson. physical health: Interdisciplinary explorations (pp. 23– 42). New York:
Halliday, A. M. (1968). Computing techniques in neurological diagnosis. Oxford University Press.
British Medical Bulletin, 24, 253. Kinzl, J. F., Traweger, C., & Biebl, W. (1995). Family background and
Halligan, P. W., Athwal, B. S., Oakley, D. A., & Frackowiak, R. S. J. sexual abuse associated with somatization. Psychotherapy and Psycho-
(2000, March 18). Imaging hypnotic paralysis: Implications for conver- somatics, 64, 82– 87.
sion hysteria. Lancet, 355, 986 –987. Kirkwood, C. R., Clure, H. R., Brodsky, R., Gould, G. H., Knaak, R.,
Halligan, P. W., & David, A. S. (1999). Conversion hysteria: Towards a Metcalf, M., & Romeo, S. (1982). The diagnostic content of family
810 BROWN

practice: 50 most common diagnoses recorded in the WAMI community sensory loss and malingering by P300 in a modified oddball task.
practices. Journal of Family Practice, 15, 485– 492. NeuroReport, 9, 187–191.
Kirmayer, L. J., & Robbins, J. M. (Eds.). (1991a). Current concepts of Ludwig, A. M. (1972). Hysteria: A neurobiological theory. Archives of
somatization: Research and clinical perspectives. Washington, DC: General Psychiatry, 27, 771–777.
American Psychiatric Press. Mace, C. J., & Trimble, M. R. (1996). Ten-year prognosis of conversion
Kirmayer, L. J., & Robbins, J. M. (1991b). Three forms of somatization in disorder. British Journal of Psychiatry, 169, 282–288.
primary care: Prevalence, co-occurrence, and sociodemographic charac- Marcel, A. J. (1983a). Conscious and unconscious perception: An approach
teristics. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 179, 647– 655. to the relations between phenomenal experience and perceptual pro-
Kirmayer, L. J., & Taillefer, S. (1997). Somatoform disorders. In S. M. cesses. Cognitive Psychology, 15, 238 –300.
Turner & M. Hersen (Eds.), Adult psychopathology and diagnosis (3rd Marcel, A. J. (1983b). Conscious and unconscious perception: Experiments
ed., pp. 333–383). New York: Wiley. on visual masking and word recognition. Cognitive Psychology, 15,
Kirsch, I. (1985). Response expectancy as a determinant of experience and 197–237.
behavior. American Psychologist, 40, 1189 –1202. Marshall, J. C., Halligan, P. W., Fink, G. R., Wade, D. T., & Frackowiak,
Kirsch, I. (1997). Suggestibility or hypnosis: What do our scales really R. S. (1997). The functional anatomy of a hysterical paralysis. Cogni-
measure? International Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis, tion, 64, B1–B8.
45, 212–225. McConkey, K. M. (2001). Hysteria and hypnosis: cognitive and social
Kirsch, I., & Lynn, S. J. (1998). Dissociation theories of hypnosis. Psy- influences. In P. W. Halligan, C. Bass, & J. Marshall (Eds.), Contem-
chological Bulletin, 123, 100 –115. porary approaches to the study of hysteria: Clinical and theoretical
Kosslyn, S. M. (1996). Image and brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. perspectives (pp. 203–215). Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
Kouyanou, K., Pither, C. E., Rabe-Hesketh, S., & Wessely, S. (1998). A Meierkord, H., Will, B., Fish, D., & Shorvon, S. (1991). The clinical
comparative study of iatrogenesis, medication abuse, and psychiatric features and prognosis of pseudoseizures diagnosed using video-EEG
morbidity in chronic pain patients with and without medically explained telemetry. Neurology, 41, 1643–1646.
symptoms. Pain, 76, 417– 426. Merskey, H. (1979). The analysis of hysteria. London: Balliere, Tindall &
Kretschmer, E. (1926). Hysteria. New York: Nervous & Mental Disease. Cassell.
Krishnamoorthy, E. S., Brown, R. J., & Trimble, M. R. (2001). Personality Merskey, H., & Buhrich, N. A. (1975). Hysteria and organic brain disease.
and psychopathology in non-epileptic attack disorder (NEAD): A pro- British Journal of Medical Psychology, 48, 359 –366.
spective study. Epilepsy & Behavior, 2, 418 – 422. Neely, J. H. (1977). Semantic priming and retrieval from lexical memory:
Kroenke, K., Spitzer, R. L., deGruy, F. V., Hahn, S. R., Linzer, M., Roles of inhibitionless spreading activation and limited capacity atten-
Williams, J. B. W., et al. (1997). Multisomatoform disorder. An alter- tion. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 106, 226 –254.
native to undifferentiated somatoform disorder for the somatizing patient Neuman, O. (1987). Beyond capacity: A functional view of attention. In H.
in primary care. Archives of General Psychiatry, 54, 352–358. Heuer & A. F. Sanders (Eds.), Perspectives on selection and action (pp.
Kroenke, K., & Swindle, R. (2000). Cognitive-behavioral therapy for 361–394). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
somatization and symptom syndromes: A critical review of controlled Nijenhuis, E. R. S., Spinhoven, P., van Dyck, R., van der Hart, O., &
clinical trials. Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics, 69, 205–215. Vanderlinden, J. (1998). Degree of somatoform dissociation and psy-
Kuyk, J., Spinhoven, P., & van Dyck, R. (1999). Hypnotic recall: A chological dissociation in dissociative disorder is correlated with re-
positive criterion in the differential diagnosis between epileptic and ported trauma. Journal of Traumatic Stress, 11, 711–730.
pseudoepileptic seizures. Epilepsia, 40, 485– 491. Nijenhuis, E. R. S., Vanderlinden, J., & Spinhoven, P. (1998). Animal
Labbate, L. A., Cardeña, E., Dimitreva, J., Roy, M., & Engel, C. C. (1998). defensive reactions as a model for trauma-induced dissociative reactions.
Psychiatric syndromes in Persian Gulf War veterans: An association of Journal of Traumatic Stress, 11, 243–260.
handling dead bodies with somatoform disorders. Psychotherapy and Norman, D. A., & Shallice, T. (1986). Attention to action: Willed and
Psychosomatics, 67, 275–279. automatic control of behavior. In R. J. Davidson, G. E. Schwartz, & D.
Lader, M. (1982). The psychophysiology of hysteria. In A. Roy (Ed.), Shapiro (Eds.), Consciousness and self-regulation: Vol. 4. Advances in
Hysteria (pp. 81– 87). New York: Wiley. research and theory (pp. 1–18). New York: Plenum Press.
Lader, M., & Sartorius, N. (1968). Anxiety in patients with hysterical Oakley, D. A. (1999). Hypnosis and conversion hysteria: A unifying
conversion symptoms. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery, and Psy- model. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 4, 243–265.
chiatry, 31, 490 – 495. Oakley, D. A. (2001). Hypnosis and suggestion in the treatment of hysteria.
Lavie, N. (1995). Perceptual load as a necessary condition for selective In P. W. Halligan, C. Bass, & J. Marshall (Eds.), Contemporary ap-
attention. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and proaches to the study of hysteria: Clinical and theoretical perspectives
Performance, 21, 451– 468. (pp. 312–329). Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
Leventhal, H. (1986). Symptom reporting: A focus on process. In S. Parsons, T. (1964). Social structure and personality. London: Collier
McHugh & T. M. Vallis (Eds.), Illness behavior: A multidisciplinary MacMillan.
model (pp. 219 –237). New York: Plenum Press. Pennebaker, J. W. (1982). The psychology of physical symptoms. New
Lindsay, S. D., & Read, J. D. (1994). Psychotherapy and memories of York: Springer-Verlag.
childhood sexual abuse: A cognitive perspective. Applied Cognitive Pennebaker, J. W., & Brittingham, G. L. (1982). Environmental and
Psychology, 8, 281–338. sensory cues affecting the perception of physical symptoms. In A. Baum
Lipowski, Z. J. (1968). Review of consultation psychiatry and psychoso- & J. Singer (Eds.), Advances in environmental psychology (Vol. 4, pp.
matic medicine. III. Theoretical issues. Psychosomatic Medicine, 30, 115–136). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
395– 422. Pennebaker, J. W., & Lightner, J. M. (1980). Competition of internal and
Lipowski, Z. J. (1988). Somatization: The concept and its clinical appli- external information in an exercise setting. Journal of Personality and
cation. American Journal of Psychiatry, 145, 1358 –1368. Social Psychology, 39, 165–174.
Logan, G. D. (1988). Toward an instance theory of automatization. Psy- Pilowsky, I. (1978). A general classification of abnormal illness behaviors.
chological Review, 95, 492–527. British Journal of Medical Psychology, 51, 131–137.
Lorenz, J., Kunze, K., & Bromm, B. (1998). Differentiation of conversive Posner, M. I., & Snyder, C. R. R. (1975). Facilitation and inhibition in the
MECHANISMS OF MEDICALLY UNEXPLAINED SYMPTOMS 811

processing of signals. In P. M. A. Rabbitt & S. Dornick (Eds.), Attention Schrag, A., Brown, R. J., & Trimble, M. R. (2004). The reliability of
and Performance V (pp. 669 – 682). New York: Academic Press. self-reported diagnoses in patients with somatoform disorder. Journal of
Pribor, E. E., Yutzi, S. H., Dean, T. J., & Wetzel, R. D. (1993). Briquet’s Neurology, Neurosurgery, and Psychiatry, 75, 608 – 611.
syndrome, dissociation, and abuse. American Journal of Psychiatry, 150, Sebanz, N., Knoblich, G., & Prinz, W. (2003). Representing others’ ac-
1507–1511. tions: Just like one’s own? Cognition, 88, B11–B21.
Prinz, W. (1997). Perception and action planning. European Journal of Shallice, T. (1988). From neuropsychology to mental structure. Cam-
Cognitive Psychology, 9, 129 –154. bridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Ramachandran, V. S., & Hirstein, W. (1998). The perception of phantom Shallice, T., & Burgess, P. W. (1996). The domain of supervisory pro-
limbs: The D. O. Hebb lecture. Brain, 121, 1603–1630. cesses and temporal organization of behavior. Philosophical Transac-
Raskin, M., Talbott, J., & Myerson, A. (1966). Diagnosis of conversion tions of the Royal Society of London, Series B, 351, 1405–1412.
reactions: Predictive value of psychiatric criteria. Journal of the Amer- Sharpe, M., & Bass, C. (1992). Pathophysiological mechanisms in soma-
ican Medical Association, 197, 530 –534. tization. International Review of Psychiatry, 4, 81–97.
Reilly, J., Baker, G. A., Rhodes, J., & Salmon, P. (1999). The association Shipko, S. (1982). Alexithymia and somatization. Psychotherapy and
of sexual and physical abuse with somatization: Characteristics of pa- Psychosomatics, 37, 193–201.
tients presenting with irritable bowel syndrome and non-epileptic attack Sierra, M., & Berrios, G. E. (1998). Depersonalization: Neurobiological
disorder. Psychological Medicine, 29, 399 – 406. perspectives. Biological Psychiatry, 44, 898 –908.
Reynolds, J. R. (1869). Paralysis and other disorders of motion and Sierra, M., & Berrios, G. E. (1999). Towards a neuropsychiatry of con-
sensation dependent on idea. British Medical Journal, 1, 483– 485. version hysteria. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 4, 267–287.
Rief, W., Hiller, W., & Margraf, J. (1998). Cognitive aspects of hypochon- Sifneos, P. E. (1973). The prevalence of “alexithymic” characteristics in
driasis and somatization syndrome. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, psychosomatic patients. Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics, 22, 255–
107, 587–595. 262.
Robbins, J. M., & Kirmayer, L. J. (1986). Illness cognition, symptom Skelton, J. A., & Croyle, R. T. (1991). Mental representations in health
reporting, and somatization in primary care. In S. McHugh & T. M. and illness. New York: Springer-Verlag.
Vallis (Eds.), Illness behavior: A multidisciplinary model (pp. 283–302). Slater, E. T. O., & Glitherco, E. (1965). A follow-up of patients diagnosed
New York: Plenum Press. as suffering from “hysteria.” Journal of Psychosomatic Research, 9,
Robbins, J. M., & Kirmayer, L. J. (1991). Cognitive and social factors in 9 –13.
somatization. In L. J. Kirmayer & J. M. Robbins (Eds.), Current con- Sloman, S. A. (1996). The empirical case for two systems of reasoning.
cepts of somatization: Research and clinical perspectives (pp. 107–141). Psychological Bulletin, 119, 3–22.
Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Press. Smith, G. R., Monson, R. A., & Ray, D. C. (1986). Patients with multiple
Roelofs, K., Hoogduin, C. A. L., Keijsers, G. P. J., Näring, G. W. B., unexplained symptoms: Their characteristics, functional health, and
Moene, F. C., & Sandijck, P. (2002). Hypnotic susceptibility in patients health care utilization. Archives of Internal Medicine, 146, 69 –72.
with conversion disorder. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 111, 390 – Smith, G. R., Rost, K., & Kashner, M. (1995). A trial of the effect of a
395. standardized psychiatric consultation on health outcomes and costs in
Roelofs, K., Keijsers, G. P. J., Hoogduin, K. A. L., Näring, G. W. B., & somatizing patients. Archives of General Psychiatry, 52, 238 –243.
Moene, F. C. (2002). Childhood abuse in patients with conversion Smith, T. W., & Greenberg, J. (1981). Self-focused attention and depres-
disorder. American Journal of Psychiatry, 159, 1908 –1913. sion. Motivation and Emotion, 5, 323–333.
Roelofs, K., Näring, G. W. B., Keijsers, G. P. J., Hoogduin, C. A. L., van Stewart, D. E. (1990). The changing faces of somatization. Psychosomat-
Galen, G. P., & Maris, E. (2001). Motor imagery in conversion paralysis. ics, 31, 153–158.
Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 6, 21– 40. Stone, J., Sharpe, M., Rothwell, P. M., & Warlow, C. P. (2003). The 12
Roelofs, K., van Galen, G. P., Eling, P., Keijsers, G. P. J, & Hoogduin, year prognosis of unilateral functional weakness and sensory distur-
C. A. L. (2003). Endogenous and exogenous attention in patients with bance. Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery, and Psychiatry, 74, 591–
conversion paresis. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 20, 733–745. 596.
Ron, M. A. (1994). Somatisation in neurological practice. Journal of Styles, E. A. (1997). The psychology of attention. Hove, England: Psy-
Neurology, Neurosurgery, and Psychiatry, 57, 1161–1164. chology Press.
Ron, M. A. (2001). The prognosis of hysteria/somatization disorder. In Tellegen, A., & Atkinson, G. (1974). Openness to absorbing and self-
P. W. Halligan, C. Bass, & J. Marshall (Eds.), Contemporary ap- altering experiences (“absorption”), a trait related to hypnotic suscepti-
proaches to the study of hysteria: Clinical and theoretical perspectives bility. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 83, 268 –277.
(pp. 271–282). Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. Temple, N. (2001). Psychodynamic psychotherapy in the treatment of
Rumelhart, D. E., McClelland, J. L., & the PDP Research Group. (1986). conversion hysteria. In P. W. Halligan, C. Bass, & J. Marshall (Eds.),
Parallel distributed processing. Explorations in the microstructure of Contemporary approaches to the study of hysteria: Clinical and theo-
cognition. Volume 1: Foundations. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. retical perspectives (pp. 283–297). Oxford, England: Oxford University
Sackeim, H. A., Nordlie, J. W., & Gur, R. C. (1979). A model of hysterical Press.
and hypnotic blindness: Cognition, motivation, and awareness. Journal Vaillant, G. E. (1993). The wisdom of the ego. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
of Abnormal Psychology, 88, 474 – 489. University Press.
Salkovskis, P. M. (1989). Somatic problems. In K. Hawton, P. M. Sal- Van Ommeren, M. V., Sharma, G. K., Komproe, I., Sharma, G. K.,
kovskis, J. Kirk, & D. M. Clark (Eds.), Cognitive behaviour therapy for Cardeña, E., de Jong, J. T., et al. (2001). Trauma and loss as determi-
psychiatric problems: A practical guide (pp. 235–276). Oxford, En- nants of medically unexplained epidemic illness in a Bhutanese refugee
gland: Oxford University Press. camp. Psychological Medicine, 31, 1259 –1267.
Salkovskis, P. M., & Warwick, H. M. C. (1986). Morbid preoccupations, Veale, D. (2001). Cognitive-behavioural therapy for body dysmorphic
health anxiety and reassurance: A cognitive behavioural approach to disorder. Advances in Psychiatric Treatment, 7, 125–132.
hypochondriasis. Behaviour Research and Therapy, 24, 597– 602. Velmans, M. (1991). Is human information processing conscious? Behav-
Salmon, P., Peters, S., & Stanley, I. (1999). Patients’ perceptions of ioral and Brain Sciences, 14, 651–726.
medical explanations for somatisation disorders: Qualitative analysis. Velmans, M. (2000). Understanding consciousness. London: Routledge.
British Medical Journal, 318, 372–376. Walker, E., Katon, W., Harrop-Griffiths, J., Holm, L., Russo, J., & Hickok,
812 BROWN

L. R. (1988). Relationship of chronic pelvic pain to psychiatric diag- Wells, A., & Matthews, G. (1994). Attention and emotion: A clinical
noses and childhood sexual abuse. American Journal of Psychiatry, 145, perspective. Hove, England: Erlbaum.
75– 80. Wessely, S. M. (2001). Discrepancies between diagnostic criteria and clinical
Wall, P. D. (1993). Pain and the placebo response. In J. Marsh (Ed.), Ciba practice. In P. W. Halligan, C. Bass, & J. Marshall (Eds.), Contemporary
Foundation Symposium: Vol. 174. Experimental and theoretical studies approaches to the study of hysteria: Clinical and theoretical perspectives
of consciousness (pp. 187–216). Chichester, England: Wiley. (pp. 63–72). Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
Watson, D., & Clark, L. A. (1984). Negative affectivity: The disposition to Whitlock, F. A. (1967). The aetiology of hysteria. Acta Psychiatrica
experience aversive emotional states. Psychological Bulletin, 96, 465– Scandinavica, 43, 144 –162.
490. Woods, S. M., Natterson, J., & Silverman, J. (1966). Medical students’
Watson, D., & Pennebaker, J. W. (1989). Health complaints, stress and disease: Hypochondriasis in medical education. Journal of Medical
distress: Exploring the role of negative affectivity. Psychological Re- Education, 41, 785–790.
view, 96, 234 –254. Woody, E. Z., & Bowers, K. S. (1994). A frontal assault on dissociated
Wegner, D. M., & Guiliano, T. (1980). Arousal-induced attention to the control. In S. J. Lynn & J. W. Rhue (Eds.), Dissociation: Clinical and
self. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 38, 719 –726. theoretical perspectives (pp. 52–79). New York: Guilford Press.
Wells, A. (1990). Panic disorder in association with relaxation-induced World Health Organization. (1992). The ICD-10 classification of mental
anxiety: An attentional training approach to treatment. Behavior Ther- and behavioural disorders: Clinical descriptions and diagnostic guide-
apy, 21, 273–280. lines. Geneva, Switzerland: Author.
Wells, A. (1997). Cognitive therapy of anxiety disorders. Chichester,
England: Wiley. Received June 24, 2003
Wells, A. (2000). Emotional disorders and metacognition. Chichester, Revision received March 2, 2004
England: Wiley. Accepted March 3, 2004 䡲

Call for Nominations


The Publications and Communications (P&C) Board has opened nominations for the
editorships of Clinician’s Research Digest, Emotion, JEP: Learning, Memory, and Cog-
nition, Professional Psychology: Research and Practice, and Psychology, Public Policy,
and Law for the years 2007–2012. Elizabeth M. Altmaier, PhD; Richard J. Davidson, PhD,
and Klaus R. Scherer, PhD; Thomas O. Nelson, PhD; Mary Beth Kenkel, PhD; and Jane
Goodman-Delahunty, PhD, respectively, are the incumbent editors.
Candidates should be members of APA and should be available to start receiving manu-
scripts in early 2006 to prepare for issues published in 2007. Please note that the P&C Board
encourages participation by members of underrepresented groups in the publication process
and would particularly welcome such nominees. Self-nominations also are encouraged.
Search chairs have been appointed as follows:

• Clinician’s Research Digest: William C. Howell, PhD


• Emotion: David C. Funder, PhD
• JEP: Learning, Memory, and Cognition: Linda P. Spear, PhD, and Peter Ornstein, PhD
• Professional Psychology: Susan H. McDaniel, PhD, and J. Gilbert Benedict, PhD
• Psychology, Public Policy, and Law: Mark Appelbaum, PhD, and Gary R. VandenBos,
PhD

Candidates should be nominated by accessing APA’s EditorQuest site on the Web. Using
your Web browser, go to http://editorquest.apa.org. On the Home menu on the left, find
Guests. Next, click on the link “Submit a Nomination,” enter your nominee’s information,
and click “Submit.”
Prepared statements of one page or less in support of a nominee can also be submitted by
e-mail to Karen Sellman, P&C Board Search Liaison, at ksellman@apa.org.
The deadline for accepting nominations is December 10, 2004, when reviews will begin.

Anda mungkin juga menyukai