Anda di halaman 1dari 25

Law & Ethics of Human Rights

Volume 3, Issue 1 2009 Article 5


L ABOR R IGHTS IN THE E RA OF G LOBALIZATION

Voluntary Slavery and the Limits of the Market


Debra Satz⇤


Stanford University

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Voluntary Slavery and the Limits of the
Market⇤
Debra Satz

Abstract

This paper considers the normative assessment of bonded labor from the perspectives of lib-
ertarianism and Paretian welfare economics. I argue that neither theory can account for our objec-
tions to bonded labor arrangements; moreover, they fail in interesting ways. Reflecting on their
normative failures focuses us on other considerations besides individual choice and efficiency.
Such considerations include: the effects of labor markets on workers’ preferences and capacities;
the exploitation of the vulnerabilities of the poor; and the permanent binding of one person to
another.

KEYWORDS: bonded labor, libertarianism, Paretian welfare economics


Marta Sutton Weeks Professor of Ethics in Society and Political Science, Stanford University.
This paper was presented at the “Equality and Markets” Conference at Stanford University, at
BAFFLE, at the University of Toronto Law School, at the NYU School of Law Colloquium on
Law, Economics and Politics and at a conference in Ramat Gan on Labor Rights in the Era of
Globalization, organized by Yossi Dahan and Faina Milman-Sivan. I have benefited from written
and verbal comments from Barbara Fried, Josh Cohen, Yossi Dahan, Rob Reich, Seana Shiffrin,
Elizabeth Anderson, Elizabeth Hansot, Marc Fleurbaey, Meir Dan-Cohen, Eric Rakowski, Andrew
Levine, Lewis Kornhauser, Jonathan Wolff, and many other members of the audiences. Thanks
also to the editors of this journal, and to an anonymous referee.

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Satz:  Voluntary  Slavery  and  the  Limits  of  the  Market

Most  anyone  ought  to  know  that  a  man  is  better  off  free  than  as  a  slave,  even  if  he  
did  not  have  anything.    I  would  rather  be  free  and  have  my  liberty.    I  fared  just  as  
well  as  any  white  child  could  have  fared  when  I  was  a  slave,  and  yet  I  would  not  
give  up  my  freedom.1  

E.P.  Holmes,  1883.

INTRODUCTION

One  of  the  most  momentous  achievements  of  modern  capitalism  was  the  transition  
from  a  system  of  bonded  labor,  indentured  servitude  and  forced  work  to  a  system  
of  formally  free  contractual  labor.    Fifty  years  ago,  it  might  have  been  assumed  that  
just  as  indenture  and  bondage  declined  in  the  industrial  world,  it  would  eventually  
disappear  everywhere  with  capitalism’s  globalization.    But  bondage  has  not  faded  
away.    In  parts  of  the  world  today,  labor  bondage  and  similar  practices  persist  under  
other  names  (e.g.,  debt  peonage,  attached  labor,  serfdom,  and  debt  slavery).    In  a  
bonded   labor   arrangement,   “a   person   is   tied   to   a   particular   creditor   as   a   laborer  
for   an   indefinite period until some loan in the past is repaid.”   2     In   practice,   this  
indefinite period can last a lifetime.  Bonded workers are often completely servile,
forced  to  exhibit  deference  and  subordination  to  their  employers  both  on  and  off  the  
job.3    Even  those  who  have  defended  the  economic  rationality  of  such  relationships  
have  noted  the  “ugly  power  relations”  involved  in  the  phenomena.4    The  ILO  has  
estimated  that  some  12.3  million  people,  many  of  them  children,  are  held  as  bonded  
laborers  around  the  globe.5  
Although  bonded  labor  is  considered  by  many  to  be  a  paradigm  of  un-­free  
labor  and  is  often  analogized  to  slavery,  it  is  sometimes  chosen  voluntarily.    Indeed,  
while   slavery   itself   is   usually   rooted   in   an   initial   act   of   coercion,   it   is   not   even  
necessary  for  slavery  to  originate  in  violence  and  force.    Slavery  has  been  reported  
to  be  voluntary  in  a  number  of  important  historical  instances.  6

1
 Reverend  E.P  Holmes,  a  black  clergyman,  testifying  before  a  congressional  committee  in  
1883.    Quoted  in  ERIC  FONER,  NOTHING  BUT  FREEDOM:  EMANCIPATION  AND  ITS  LEGACY  7  (1983).  
2
 Pranab  Bardhan,  Labor  Tying  in  a  Poor  Agrarian  Economy:  A  Theoretical  and  Empirical  
Analysis,  98(3)  Q.  J.  ECON.  502  (1983).  
3
 Julie  A.  Schaffner,  Attached  Farm  Labor,  Limited  Horizons  and  Servility,  47  J.  DEV.  ECON.  
241-­70  (1995).
4
 PRANAB  BARDHAN,  THE  ECONOMIC  THEORY  OF  AGRARIAN  INSTITUTIONS  (1991)  see  ch.  12  “A  
note  on  interlinked  rural  economic  arrangements.”
5
 A  Global  Alliance  against  Forced  Labour,  54  WORLD   OF  WORK  MAGAZINE  (Aug.  2005),  
available  at  http://www.ilo.org/wow/Articles/lang-­-­en/WCMS_081360/index.htm.  
6
 Cf.  ORLANDO  PATTERSON,  SLAVERY  AND  SOCIAL  DEATH  ch.  4  (1982).  

87

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Law  &  Ethics  of  Human  Rights,  Vol.  3  [2009],  Iss.  1,  Art.  5

How   might   labor   bondage   arise   voluntarily?     Since   poor   peasants   have  
no   assets,   they   have   no   formal   collateral.     Furthermore,   the   wages   they   receive  
tend  to  vary  with  the  agricultural  seasons:  wages  are  lower  during  the  lean  seasons  
when   unemployment   is   high   and   higher   during   the   peak   growing   seasons   when  
unemployment  is  low.    In  many  cases,  their  survival  from  one  harvest  season  to  
the  next  will  depend  on  borrowing  for  consumption  during  the  lean  seasons—they  
simply  do  not  earn  enough  during  peak  seasons  to  save.7
Consider  the  case  of  a  landlord  who  offers  credit  in  exchange  for  a  laborer’s  
agreement  to  pledge  his  future  services  as  collateral  for  the  loan.    In  so  doing,  the  
landlord  increases  his  power  to  enforce  the  agreement  since  he  can  directly  deduct  
the   amount   due   from   the   worker’s   wages   during   peak   season.     Furthermore,   the  
laborer  now  has  access  to  credit  that  might  not  otherwise  have  been  available  to  him.    
From  the  perspective  of  contract  theory,  it  is  not  evident  that  there  should  be  any  
legally  imposed  limits  on  competent  adult  landlords  and  laborers  who  seek  to  enter  
such  contracts.8    For,  if  agents  are  rational  and  can  foresee  the  future  consequences  
of  their  contractual  provisions,  then  there  is  no  reason  not  to  allow  borrowers  the  
freedom  to  commit  to  providing  indentured  services  to  lenders  should  they  lack  the  
resources  to  repay  their  loans.  
In   this   Article,   I   examine   the   ways   that   two   different   frameworks   with  
different  underlying  normative  assumptions  view  the  phenomenon  of  bonded  labor:  
libertarian  laissez  faire  theory  and  Paretian  welfare  economics.    Libertarians  believe  
that  agreements  between  competent  adults  should  be  respected.9    Paretians  endorse  
exchanges   that   leave   both   parties   better   off   in   terms   of   their   preferences.     Each  
theory  gives  us  reasons  for  endorsing  many  if  not  most  instances  of  the  practice  of  
bonded  labor,  reasons  that  are  intuitively  plausible.    But  each  theory  also  ignores  or  
dismisses  other  considerations  that  might  lead  us  to  view  these  very  same  instances  
of  labor  bondage  more  critically.    
I  argue  that  neither  theory  fully  accounts  for  our  objections  to  bonded  labor,  
objections   that   are   codified in the laws of most developed capitalist countries.10  
In   the   United   States,   for   example,   there   are   important   restrictions   on   labor  
contracts:   The   state   does   not   enforce   voluntary   slavery   contracts,   debt   slavery,  
specific performance as a remedy for breach, or contracts that are considered

7
 There  are,  of  course,  other  forms  of  bonded  labor:  in  factories,  in  prisons,  and  among  
prostitutes.    My  discussion  focuses  on  the  phenomena  of  labor  tying  in  rural  areas.    
8
 See  the  discussion  infra  on  children.
9
  Some   libertarians   will   be   accepting   of   regulating   transactions   that   have   external   third  
party  effects.    See  the  discussion  infra.  
10
  Indeed,   many   developing   countries   have   signed   the   international   labor   conventions  
against  slavery,  child  labor  and  bondage,  although  these  are  often  not  enforced.

88
10.2202/1938-­2545.1032

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Satz:  Voluntary  Slavery  and  the  Limits  of  the  Market

“unconscionable.”    Paretianism  and  libertarianism  do  not  adequately  account  for  


these  restrictions.    Moreover,  their  failures  to  do  so  are  interesting,  because  they  
point   out   the   limits   of   using   overly   abstract   concepts   of   freedom,   equality,   and  
externality  to  evaluate  market  exchanges.11  
In  considering  the  adequacy  of  these  theories  to  account  for  our  objections  
to  bonded  labor,  I  distinguish  between  two  important  dimensions  of  bonded  labor:  
the  background  circumstances  in  which  bonded  labor  arises  (ideal  versus  non-­ideal  
markets)  and  the  nature  of  the  agent  whose  labor  is  bonded  (adult  laborer  versus  
child  laborer).    With  respect  to  the  first dimension, bonded labor arrangements tend
to   arise   in   desperate   circumstances   where   they   exploit   the   vulnerabilities   of   the  
most  vulnerable,  and  make  some  people  utterly  dependent  upon  the  will  and  whims  
of   other   people.     While,   libertarianism   cannot   even   condemn   these   instances   of  
bonded  labor,  Paretianism  can  show  why  labor  bondage  under  these  circumstances  
might  be  objectionable.    But  we  can  imagine  more  ideal  circumstances  in  which  
these  conditions  do  not  obtain,  circumstances  where  such  Paretian  accounts  offer  
no  criticism.
But  even  in  more  ideal  circumstances—where  there  are  no  market  failures  
and  no  dire  poverty—I  argue  that  we  still  have  reasons  not  to  enforce  labor  bondage  
agreements.12    Beginning  with  the  case  of  children,  I  argue  that  bondage  of  children’s  
labor  can  stunt  the  development  of  the  capacities  needed  for  people  to  stand  as  social  
equals.    I  then  suggest  that  this  argument  provides  a  lever  to  mount  a  principled  
objection  to  binding  the  labor  of  adults:  just  as  capacities  can  be  stunted  by  certain  
labor   arrangements,   so   they   can   be   lost.     I   draw   on   some   empirical   evidence   to  
suggest  that  the  capacity  for  autonomy  is,  as  Mill  put  it:
in   most   natures   a   very   tender   plant,   easily   killed,   not   only   by   hostile  
influences, but by mere want of sustenance;; and in the majority of young
persons  it  speedily  dies  away  if  the  occupations  to  which  their  position  in  
life  has  devoted  them,  and  the  society  into  which  it  has  thrown  them,  are  not  
favorable  to  keeping  that  higher  capacity  in  exercise…13

11
 Some  theorists  think  that  we  have  paternalistic  reasons  to  prevent  people  from  entering  
into  voluntary,  but  self-­destructive  or  degrading  activities.    See,  e.g.,  the  discussion  of  dwarf  tossing  
in  AMY  GUTMANN  &  DENNIS  THOMPSON,  DEMOCRACY  AND  DISAGREEMENT  252-­54  (1996).
12
 Admittedly,  much  of  the  phenomenon  does  occur  precisely  under  the  circumstances  of  
dire  poverty  and  market  failure.
13
  JOHN   STUART   MILL,   UTILITARIANISM   14   (1957).     Mill   himself   considers   any   defense   of  
voluntary   slavery   to   be   self-­defeating:   it   is   self-­contradictory   to   say   we   should   be   free   not   to   be  
free.    See  his  discussion  in  ON  LIBERTY  (1865).    This  argument  faces  some  serious  problems,  since  
Mill  defends  liberty  as  non-­interference  and  there  is  nothing  paradoxical  about  giving  someone  the  
ability  to  enslave  themselves  without  interference.

89

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Law  &  Ethics  of  Human  Rights,  Vol.  3  [2009],  Iss.  1,  Art.  5

Reflecting on contractual bonded labor arrangements in ideal and non-­ideal


circumstances  and  with  children  and  adult  agents  helps  us  to  see  that  markets  not  
only   allocate   resources   and   distribute   income,   but   also   shape   our   culture,   foster  
or  thwart  desirable  forms  of  human  development  and  enable  or  hinder  egalitarian  
social  relationships  between  persons.    The  central  idea  I  defend  here  is  that  where  
competitive  markets  support  relationships  of  extreme  domination  and  subordination,  
there  is  a  case  for  market  regulation,  even  when  such  markets  are  otherwise  efficient
or  arise  on  the  basis  of  individual  rational  choice.  14

I.  LIBERTARIANISM
Libertarians  believe  in  the  principle  of  freedom  of  contract  within  the  bounds  of  
justice.15    If  two  or  more  rational  adults  agree  to  an  exchange,  provided  that  they  
are  actually  entitled  to  the  goods  they  are  exchanging  and  that  no  one  else’s  rights  
are  thereby  violated,  the  government  (and  other  agents)  ought  not  to  interfere.    In  
Robert  Nozick’s  pithy  formulation,  libertarians  do  not  forbid  “capitalist  acts  between  
consenting  adults.”16    While  economists  typically  value  free  market  exchange  as  an  
instrument  of  efficiency, the ability to freely exchange one’s own property is seen by
libertarians  as  closely  connected  to  the  freedom  and  inviolability—the  separateness  
and  sanctity—of  the  individual  person.17
In   evaluating   the   permissibility   of   a   particular   bonded   labor   contract,   a  
libertarian   will   consider   whether   the   goods   and   services   to   be   exchanged   were  
acquired  by  legitimate  means,  and  whether  or  not  the  exchange  was  voluntary.    If  
these  conditions  are  met,  then  according  to  the  libertarian  the  exchange  should  be  
allowed.    In  Anarchy  State  and  Utopia,  Nozick  claims  that  respect  for  the  principle  
of  freedom  of  contract  entails  that  individuals  even  have  the  right  to  sell  themselves  
into  slavery.18  
Since   the   libertarian   justification of the freedom to participate in bonded
labor   or   slavery   contracts   refers   to   the   idea   of   voluntary   choice,   its   application  
seems  to  depend  on  an  understanding  of  what  makes  an  act  of  exchange  voluntary  
as  opposed  to  coerced.19    What  coercion  consists  of,  however,  is  an  elusive  matter:  
The  distinction  between  offers  that  are  coercive  and  those  that  are  not  is  notoriously  

14
 See  ROHINTON  MISTRY,  A  FINE  BALANCE  (2001),  for  a  novelist’s  moving  depiction  of  the  
lives  of  India’s  poor  in  which  lifetime  bondage  to  a  creditor  appears  as  a  rational  response  to  an  
irrational  world.
15
  Nozick   has   three   principles   of   justice:   justice   in   acquisition,   justice   in   transfer,   and   a  
principle  of  rectification.  See  ROBERT  NOZICK,  ANARCHY  STATE  AND  UTOPIA  (1974).
16
 Id.  at  163.
17
   NOZICK,  supra  note  15,  at  32.
18
 Id.  at  331.  
19
 Indeed,  it  is  curious  that  given  the  centrality  of  the  idea  of  “consenting  parties”  to  the  
justification of market exchange,  there  has  been  so  little  attention  paid  to  it  in  economics.

90
10.2202/1938-­2545.1032

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Satz:  Voluntary  Slavery  and  the  Limits  of  the  Market

difficult to draw.  Indeed, coercion rarely takes the form of direct compulsion that
deprives  individuals  of  all  choice.    For  example,  when  a  gunman  threatens  “your  
money  or  your  life,”  what  makes  the  offer  coercive  is  clearly  not  that  you  have  no  
power  to  choose.    “Coerced”  cannot  be  the  opposite  of  “chosen,”  since  even  in  our  
gunman  case  the  victim  will  intentionally  make  the  necessary  physical  movements  
to  surrender  (or  not)  his  money.    
On  Nozick’s  account,  what  makes  an  offer  coercive  is  that  it  decreases  an  
agent’s  position  with  reference  to  their  legitimate  baseline  situation.  20    Even  though  
an  individual  confronted  with  a  gunman’s  threat  might  well  decide  “freely”  to  hand  
over  her  money,  she  is  coerced  given  that  the  gunman  has  no  right  to  her  money  
and   by   taking   it   he   impermissibly   worsens   her   situation,   violating   her   baseline  
entitlements.21
Nozick’s  point  is  that  coercion  is  essentially  a  normative  concept.22    Two  
people  can  agree  on  all  the  facts  about  an  exchange  and  still  reasonably  disagree  as  
to  whether  one  party  to  the  exchange  was  coerced  by  the  other.    Whether  or  not  they  
each  find an offer coercive is parasitic on their prior determination that the coerced
party   had   a   baseline   entitlement   that   was   violated.     In   other   words,   in   Nozick’s  
view,  calling  an  offer  “coercive”  or  not,  simply  follows  from  one’s  prior  view  of  
what  is  morally  justified.  Thus, if I believe that a trade made under circumstances
of  poverty,  lack  of  education,  and  so  forth,  is  coerced  it  follows  that  I  believe  that  
people  have  a  right—of  some  kind—not  to  be  in  such  circumstances.      
Libertarians,  of  course,  do  not  generally  think  that  the  state  has  any  affirmative
duty   to   improve   the   background   circumstances   of   an   individual,   no   matter   how  
bad   these   circumstances   are.     In   thinking   about   the   legitimacy   of   bonded   labor  
contracts,  then,  a  main  issue  between  egalitarians  and  libertarians  is  the  nature  of  
agents’  underlying  entitlements—the  morally  acceptable  baseline  for  agreeing  to  
(or  threatening  not  to)  contract.  
What   kind   of   underlying   entitlements—systems   of   property   rights—do  
libertarians  think  that  people  have?    Libertarians  tend  to  think  that  property  rights  
rest   on   something   like   the   rights   of   first claimants.23    As   long   as   a   landlord   was  

20
  Robert   Nozick,   Coercion,   in   PHILOSOPHY,   SCIENCE   AND   METHOD:   ESSAYS   IN   HONOR   OF  
ERNEST  NAGEL  440  (Sidney  Morgenbesser,  Patrick  Suppes,  &  Morton  G.  White  eds.,  1969).  
21
 For  most  libertarians,  this  baseline  involves  few,  if  any,  positive  rights.    In  particular,  it  
does  not  involve  rights  to  sustenance  or  to  aid.
22
  One   worry   is   that   Nozick’s   approach   makes   it   impossible   to   ask   whether   a   form   of  
coercion—say  by  the  state—might  be  justified.  For an attempt to distinguish between coercion and
compulsion  see  Joel  Feinberg,  Coercion,  in  ROUTLEDGE  ENCYCLOPEDIA   OF  PHILOSOPHY  387  (Edward  
Craig  ed.,  1988).
23
 Of  course,  the  justification for the initial appropriation of natural resources is notoriously
vexed.  

91

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Law  &  Ethics  of  Human  Rights,  Vol.  3  [2009],  Iss.  1,  Art.  5

the  first to produce goods on the land or acquired property in land via a voluntary
transfer  from  the  first claimant, libertarians will grant the landlord an exclusive right
to  determine  how  this  land  is  used.    On  the  libertarian  view,  the  state  acts  unjustly  
if  it  prevents  the  landlord  from  using  his  land  and  the  surplus  that  it  generates  as  he  
wishes.    If  an  individual  landlord  wishes  to  loan  some  of  his  surplus  to  others,  then  
he  should  be  free  to  decide  the  terms  under  which  he  is  willing  to  forgo  the  private  
use  of  some  of  his  own  resources.    It  is  the  landlord’s  piece  of  good  luck  if  he  finds
others  willing  to  accept  his  highly  unequal  terms  but,  on  the  libertarian  view,  this  
good  luck  generates  no  injustice.24  
While   libertarianism   is   often   seen   as   a   theory   that   embraces   and   justifies
a   pure   form   of   capitalism,   it   is   important   to   notice   that   it   can   also   embrace   and  
justify  a  system  of  voluntary  feudalism.25    Indeed,  if  a  feudal  lord  acquired  his  land  
by  first title, and offered employment on his land to all those who wished to live
under  his  protection,  then  a  libertarian  would  have  to  condemn  a  state  that  acted  to  
break  up  his  monopoly  power.    This  means  that,  at  least  in  theory,  libertarianism  is  
compatible  with  the  permanent  direct  subjection  of  one  individual  to  another.    This  
puts  libertarians  in  a  difficult position, for there seems something self-­defeating about
a  theory  that  invokes  the  values  of  individual  freedom  as  a  basis  for  permanently  
stripping  individual  freedom  away.26
At  this  point,  the  libertarian  may  protest  that  there  are  obvious  rejoinders  to  
the  charge  that  libertarianism  endorses  feudalism  and  feudal  type  relations  between  
people.    He  might  point  out  that,  in  fact,  much  of  the  lords’  initial  acquisition  during  
feudalism  was  based  on  plunder,  fraud,  and  violence.    Libertarians  do  not  accept  
as  legitimate,  agreements  based  on  force  or  fraud.    If  the  agreements  that  are  today  
reached  between  a  landlord  and  a  bonded  laborer  had  “dirty”  origins—if  they  are  
based  in  employer  malfeasance  or  maintained  only  by  physical  violence—then  this  
is  a  reason  for  not  respecting  these  agreements.  27    
Not   all   libertarians   worry   about   the   origins   of   property   rights—rather,  
some   libertarians   emphasize   the   importance   of   respecting   individual   rights   in  
property;;   however   these   rights   have   been   erected.28     But   even   these   libertarians  
recognize   some   limits   on   private   property   rights.29     Nozick   argues   that   a   person  

24
 See  NOZICK,  supra  note  15,  at  263-­64.
25
 Samuel  R.  Freeman,  Illiberal  Libertarians,  30(2)  PHIL.  &  PUB.  AFFAIRS  105  (2001).  
26
 I’ll  return  to  the  suggestion  that  libertarianism  is  not  a  stable  theory  below.
27
 Some  instances  of  bonded  labor  do  originate  in  force  and  are  maintained  by  violence.    
See  KEVIN  BALES,  DISPOSABLE  PEOPLE:  NEW  SLAVERY  IN  THE  GLOBAL  ECONOMY  (1999).
28
 See  JAMES  BUCHANAN,  THE  LIMITS   OF  LIBERTY:  BETWEEN  ANARCHY   AND  LEVIATHAN  59-­60  
(1975)  for  a  discussion  of  slavery  as  the  result  of  bargaining  from  an  anarchistic  equilibrium.
29
 Randy  Barnett  may  be  unique  among  libertarians  in  advocating  debt  slavery  for  those  
who  impose  costs  on  others  through  wrongdoing.    See  RANDY  E.  BARNETT  THE  STRUCTURE  OF  LIBERTY  
35  (1998).    Thanks  to  Arthur  Ripstein  for  the  citation.

92
10.2202/1938-­2545.1032

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Satz:  Voluntary  Slavery  and  the  Limits  of  the  Market

cannot  legitimately  acquire  all  of  the  water  in  the  world.    And  some  libertarians  
have   argued   that   individuals   have   non-­alienable   rights   to   self-­ownership,   so   that  
they  cannot  contract  themselves  into  slavery.30
Let’s  consider  in  more  detail  the  example  of  a  very  poor  laborer  who  has  
agreed  to  bond  himself  to  a  landlord  in  order  to  attain  a  loan.    In  theory,  a  state  can  
set  limits  on  the  private  property  rights  involved  in  this  transaction  in  a  number  of  
very  different  ways:31
(i)   The   state   can   give   the   laborer   subsistence   income,   or   other   employment  
choices,  to  enlarge  her  background  alternatives;;  if  she  still  enters  into  the  
bonded  labor  contract,  it  can  refuse  to  enforce  the  contract  as  written.
(ii)   The  same  as  in  the  case  above,  except  that  if  the  laborer  under  improved  
circumstances  still  enters  into  the  bonded  labor  contract,  then  the  state  will  
enforce  the  contract  as  written.      
(iii)   Although  it  has  no  affirmative duty to improve the background options of
the  laborer,  the  state  can  refuse  to  enforce  the  bonded  labor  contract  in  any  
fashion,  if  the  laborer  breaches.    
(iv)   The  state  can  enforce  the  contract  through  specific performance, but alter
the  substantive  terms  of  the  exchange  to  make  it  less  lopsidedly  favorable  
to  the  landlord.      For  example,  the  state  can  set  legal  limits  on  the  amount  of  
interest  that  a  lender  can  charge  for  a  loan.
(v)   The  state  can  refuse  to  enforce  the  contract  through  a  specific performance
decree,   but   give   the   employer   some   other   sort   of   monetary   or   equitable  
remedy  (e.g.,  allowing  the  employer  to  garnish  the  wages  of  the  employee  
when  she  goes  to  work  for  someone  else).  32  
(vi)   The  state  can  enforce  the  contract  as  written  through  a  specific performance
decree,   and   in   the   event   the   employee   fails   to   comply   with   it,   enjoin   her  
from  working  for  anyone  else.    
(vii)   Same  as  above,  but  the  state  can  enforce  the  decree  by  jailing  the  employee  
if  necessary.
Which   of   these   scenarios   is   a   libertarian   committed   to   accept?     Libertarians   do  
not   generally   hold   that   the   state   has   any   affirmative obligation to improve the
background  circumstances  of  a  laborer  and  hence  they  tend  to  reject  (i),  (ii),  and  
(iv).    Libertarians  believe  that  treating  people  with  respect  precludes  the  state  from  

 See  JOHN  LOCKE,  TWO  TREATISES  OF  GOVERNMENT  ch.  4  (1988).


30

 Thanks   to   Barbara   Fried   for   suggesting   that   I   separate   out   the   different   ways   that   an  
31

individual  might  have  a  right  not  to  be  in  the  circumstances  which  give  rise  to  bonded  labor.
32
 In  fact,  specific performance is an exceptional remedy for breach of contract in employment
contracts  Anglo-­American  law.    The  normal  remedy  is  money  damages.  

93

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Law  &  Ethics  of  Human  Rights,  Vol.  3  [2009],  Iss.  1,  Art.  5

compelling   its   citizens   to   transfer   any   of   their   resources   to   others,   even   if   those  
others  are  in  dire  need.    But  in  practice,  almost  no  libertarian  would  go  all  the  way  
to  either  (vi)  or  (vii).      Nozick,  for  example,  doesn’t;;  when  faced  with  some  de  facto  
monopolistic  markets,  such  as  a  monopoly  over  water  in  a  desert,  even  go  as  far  as  
(v).33
In   Anarchy   State   and   Utopia,   Nozick   defends   a   version   of   the   “Lockean  
proviso”  which  argues  that  an  initial  act  of  appropriation  must  not  leave  anyone  
worse  off  than  they  would  have  been  had  there  been  no  appropriation  at  all.34    This  
appeal  to  the  Lockean  proviso—and  to  welfare  based  restrictions  on  the  principle  of  
freedom  of  contract—sits  uncomfortably  within  the  confines of libertarian theory.35  
After   all,   the   Nozickean-­style   libertarian’s   commitment   to   liberty   is   in   principle  
meant   to   be   independent   of   its   consequences   for   human   welfare.     Libertarians  
generally  assume  that  individuals  have  no  welfare  rights  that  give  them  claim  over  
the  labor  or  property  of  others.    For,  once  we  admit  that  the  welfare  consequences  for  
individuals  can  form  a  basis  for  evaluating  other  people’s  entitlements,  why  should  
we   not   contrast   the   private   property   ownership   regime   embraced   by   libertarians  
with  other  alternatives  such  as  a  mixed  economy  that  limits  background  property  
rights  and  redistributes  income?    Perhaps  a  poor  landless  peasant  would  be  better  
off  under  some  alternative  form  of  ownership  than  he  would  be  under  a  libertarian  
regime  of  private  property.    At  the  very  least,  the  peasant  might  be  better  off  if  his  
background  assets  were  more  equal  to  his  employer’s.
It  is  striking  how  strongly  Nozick’s  version  of  the  Lockean  proviso  resembles  
the   Pareto   efficiency criterion appealed to by welfare economists.   But although
libertarians  sometimes  cite  the  efficiency benefits of a  laissez faire economy,36  the  
core  of  the  libertarian  case  for  private  ownership  and  laissez  faire  is  that  these  are  
necessary  for  individual  freedom,  not  that  they  are  more  efficient than alternatives.  
If  we  shift  the  ground  to  consider  the  effects  of  private  property  and  unrestrained  
freedom  of  contract  on  wellbeing,  we  have  opened  the  door  to  the  consideration  
of   other   property   arrangements   and   market   regulations   that   might   be   superior   to  
laissez  faire  on  welfare  grounds.  
Even  if  we  admit  some  version  of  the  Lockean  proviso,  however,  it  won’t  
necessarily  kick  in  with  respect  to  bonded  labor  arrangements.    What  if  the  employer’s  

33
 Not  all  de  facto  monopolistic  markets  violate  Nozick’s  Lockean  proviso.    See  infra.
34
 NOZICK,  supra  note  15,  at  178.
35
 Recall  that  Locke’s  founding  principle  was  a  positive  duty  to  protect  and  preserve  human  
life.  It  was  this  duty  that  was  the  basis  of  his  restriction  on  individual  property  rights.    See  Second  
Treatise  of  Government,  in  TWO  TREATISES  OF  GOVERNMENT  ch.  v  (Peter  Laslett  ed.,  1988).
36
 For  a  libertarian  argument  that  stresses  the  negative  efficiency consequences of government
intervention  in  people’s  lives  see  MILTON  FRIEDMAN,  CAPITALISM   AND  FREEDOM  (1962)  and  RICHARD  
EPSTEIN,  PRINCIPLES   FOR   A  FREE  SOCIETY:  RECONCILING  INDIVIDUAL  LIBERTY   WITH   THE  COMMON  GOOD  
(1998).

94
10.2202/1938-­2545.1032

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Satz:  Voluntary  Slavery  and  the  Limits  of  the  Market

monopolizing  power  is  based  not  on  appropriated  natural  resources,  like  land,  but  
instead  simply  on  social  power  and  capital?    Nozickean  libertarians  would  deny  the  
application  of  the  proviso  at  all  in  that  situation,  unless  one  could  trace  such  power  
all  the  way  back  to  first appropriation of scarce natural resources.
Of  course,  the  fact  that  libertarians  think  that  people  can  legitimately  enter  
into   bonded   labor   agreements   does   not   itself   entail   that   they   think   that   the   state  
is  required  to  enforce  such  agreements  in  any  particular  way  (or  even  to  enforce  
them   at   all.     Nozick,   for   example,   says   surprisingly   little   about   the   enforcement  
of  rights.)    My  point,  however,  is  that  there  is  nothing  in  libertarian  theory  which  
rules  out  the  state  demanding  that  a  laborer  comply  with  the  terms  of  his  contract  
by  specific performance or from imprisoning him if he fails to perform his part of
the  agreement.
A   libertarian   might   yet   have   another   objection   to   press   against   many  
bonded  labor  arrangements.    Jane  Humphries  has  pointed  out  that  there  is  no  infans  
economicus  responding  to  market  signals:  Most  children  are  put  to  work  by  their  
parents.37    Libertarians  might  claim  that  parents  are  not  entitled  to  bond  the  labor  of  
their  children;;  at  least  not  into  adulthood.    To  the  extent  that  the  libertarian  defense  of  
the  principle  of  freedom  of  contract  rests  on  the  idea  that  individuals  are  voluntarily  
contracting  on   their   own   behalf,   or   for   others   who   have   (voluntarily)  designated  
them  to  act  on  their  behalf,  then  there  is  room  for  libertarian  criticism  of  practices  
that  involve  parents  using  their  children’s  labor  as  collateral  for  their  own  loans.38    
Nozick,  like  most  libertarians,  says  little  about  children’s  positive  rights.    In  
fact,  some  libertarians  argue  that  while  it  would  be  a  good  thing  if  parents  cultivate  
their  children’s  abilities,  they  have  no  obligation  to  do  so.    Their  only  obligation  
is  not  to  harm  their  children.39    However,  to  identify  “harm”  to  children  we  have  
to  know  the  appropriate  baseline  for  comparison.    There  are  tricky  issues  here  for  
libertarians   since   young   children   cannot   provide   for   their   own   needs   but   require  
others  to  do  so  for  them.40    Is  a  child  harmed  if  she  becomes  malnourished  through  
neglect  of  others?    Or  does  she  have  rights  over  the  time,  nurturing,  and  labor  of  
her  parents?    

37
  Jane   Humphries,   Cliometrics,   Child   Labor,   and   the   Industrial   Revolution,   13   (3-­4)  
CRITICAL  REV.  269  (1999).
38
 Parents  transact  with  respect  to  their  children’s  labor;;  except  in  exceptional  circumstances  
children  do  not  make  the  decision  to  work.    See  Debra  Satz,  Child  Labor:  A  Normative  Approach,  
17(2)  WORLD  BANK  ECON.  REV.  297-­309  (2003).
39
 See  NOZICK,  supra  note  15,  at  38,  arguing  that  children  have  a  right  not  to  be  eaten  by  
their  parents  (!)
40
 Libertarians  who  base  their  doctrine  on  a  principle  of  self-­ownership  have  struggled  with  
the  question  of  why  children  are  not  owned  by  their  begetters.    Susan  Okin  advanced  this  objection  
to  Robert  Nozick’s  views  in  JUSTICE,  GENDER  AND  THE  FAMILY  ch.  4  (1989).

95

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Law  &  Ethics  of  Human  Rights,  Vol.  3  [2009],  Iss.  1,  Art.  5

Moreover,   whatever   baseline   of   entitlement   we   take   young   children   to  


have  will  closely  be  connected  with  the  baseline  of  entitlement  of  their  parents.    If  
children  have  a  right  not  to  starve,  then  their  parents  as  their  caretakers  must  have  
this  right  as  well.    Many  parents  bond  their  children’s  labor  as  part  of  a  strategy  to  
stave  off  starvation,  not  only  their  own  but  also  their  children’s.    If  children  have  
a  right  not  to  starve,  then  the  best  way  to  ensure  that  right  (if  we  ban  bondage  of  
children’s  labor)  may  be  to  improve  the  background  circumstances  of  their  adult  
parents,  a  strategy  that  libertarians  generally  reject.  
I  now  want  to  make  a  key  claim:  unless  parents  (and  failing  parents,  society  
or  some  other  agent)  have  positive  responsibilities  to  children,  responsibilities  that  
are  backed  up  by  the  state,  libertarianism  will  not  be  able  to  generate  a  stable  political  
ideal.    Children  are  not  born  with  all  the  requisite  capacities  for  making  choices,  
acting   justly,   and   supporting   themselves,   already   given.    The   development   of   an  
independent  individual  depends  on,  among  other  things,  nourishment,  education,  
information,  and  favorable  social  circumstances.  
In  particular,  children  raised  to  be  servile  laborers  tied  to  a  single  employer  
for  a  lifetime  will  likely  lack  the  habits  and  dispositions  that  enable  them  to  see  
themselves   as   rights   bearers   and   independent   sources   of   moral   claims.     Indeed,  
children   whose   parents   are   bonded   laborers   may   find their own self-­conceptions
shaped  by  the  relations  of  domination  and  subordination  around  them.    If  this  is  
so,  then  there  is  a  long-­term  instability  to  a  libertarian  regime  that  does  not  prevent  
the  bondage  of  children’s  labor:  it  will  fail  to  reproduce  itself  because  it  will  create  
people   who   lack   the   dispositions   and   capacities   to   sustain   libertarian   values   and  
conceptions  of  the  self.41
With   the   exception   of   malfeasance,   libertarianism   has   no   principled  
objection   to   even   life   long   bonded   labor   arrangements,   as   long   as   the   baseline  
entitlements   of   the   contractors   are   legitimate.     It   has   no   principled   objections   to  
feudal  arrangements,  so  long  as  these  were  established  by  contract  rather  than  by  
birth  or  conquest.    Ironically,  far  from  being  the  natural  ideology  for  a  capitalist  
society,  libertarians  will  have  difficulty representing capitalism as a moral  advance  
over  feudalism,  to  the  extent  that  its  rise  depended  on  curtailing  feudal  property  
rights  over  labor.42  

41
 Rawls  considered  long  term  stability  to  be  critical  to  the  justification of his two principles
of  justice  and  devoted  a  large  part  of  Theory  of  Justice  to  this  concern.    See  A  THEORY   OF  JUSTICE  
398-­99  (1999).
42
 See  Elizabeth  Anderson,  Ethical  Assumptions  in  Economic  Theory,  7  ETHICAL  THEORY  &  
MORAL  PRACTICE  345-­60  (2004).

96
10.2202/1938-­2545.1032

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Satz:  Voluntary  Slavery  and  the  Limits  of  the  Market

II.  WELFARE  ECONOMICS

Welfare   economics   evaluates   institutions   in   terms   of   whether   or   not   they   make  


people  better  or  worse  off.    Typically,  welfare  economists  operate  with  a  view  of  
human  welfare  (or  well-­being)  that  identifies it with the satisfaction of preferences.43  
Unfortunately,   the   extent   to   which   the   preferences   of   different   individuals   are  
satisfied is difficult if not impossible to compare. How, then, can we say anything
substantive  about  whether  an  institution  is  good  for  welfare?    One  answer  to  this  
question  appeals  to  the  concepts  of  Pareto  optimality  and  Pareto  improvement.    A  
social  state  is  Pareto  optimal  if  and  only  if  no  one’s  welfare  (defined in terms of
their   preferences)   can   be   raised   without   reducing   the   welfare   of   someone   else.44  
A  Pareto  improvement  is  a  change  in  a  social  state  that  leaves  at  least  one  person  
better  off  and  no  one  worse  off.    
Some   welfare   economists   have   defended   the   principle   of   freedom   of  
contract  in  Paretian  terms.    Perfectly  competitive  markets  have  been  shown  to  yield  
outcomes  that  are  Pareto  optimal.45    Indeed,  two  people  are  unlikely  to  enter  into  
a  market  transaction  if  it  doesn’t  represent  an  improvement  in  each  of  their  own  
situations.  
The  principle  that  tells  us  to  accept  Pareto  improvements  is  an  intuitively  
appealing  normative  principle:  if  a  situation  (A)  leaves  some  people  better  off  and  
no  one  worse  off  than  an  alternative  situation  (B),  then  it  seems  absurd  to  say  that  
the  latter  situation  (B)  is  preferable  to  the  former  one  (A).46    If  this  is  so,  it  seems  to  
follow  that  if  a  transaction  is  Pareto  improving,  then  the  state  should  not  interfere  
with  this  transaction.47    Notice  that  this  principle,  so  stated,  makes  no  reference  to  
the  content  of  the  transaction:  it  applies  equally  to  trades  in  apples  and  to  trades  in  
persons.  
There   is   a   large   literature   that   argues   that   under   certain   assumptions,   the  
practice  of  labor  bondage  is  a  Pareto  improvement,  even  if  it  is  not  Pareto  optimal.    
Bhardan   shows   that   landlords   have   incentives   to   offer   such   long   term   contracts  

43
 Cf.  HAL  VARIAN,  MICROECONOMIC  ANALYSIS  94-­97  (3rd  ed.  1992).  
44
 As  its  critics  have  noted,  the  concept  of  Pareto  optimality  does  not  deliver  very  much:  a  
state  can  be  Pareto  optimal  with  some  people  in  extreme  poverty  and  others  living  in  extreme  luxury,  
as  long  as  making  the  poor  better  off  requires  redistributing  from  the  rich.
45
  GERARD   DEBREU,  THEORY   OF  VALUE:  AN  AXIOMATIC  ANALYSIS   OF   ECONOMIC   EQUILIBRIUM  
94-­95  (1959).
46
 See  John  Broome,  Should  Social  Preferences  be  Consistent?,  5  ECON.  &  PHIL.  11  (1989).    
Although   the   principle   endorsing   Pareto   improvements   seems   attractive,   there   are   actually   some  
powerful  objections  to  it.    See  ANNE  PHILLIPS,  WHICH  EQUALITIES  MATTER?  (1999).
47
 See  Kaushik  Basu,  The  Economics  and  Law  of  Sexual  Harassment  in  the  Workplace,  17  
J.  ECON.  PERSPECTIVES  141  (2003)  for  an  argument  that  we  should  accept  all  Pareto  improvements  
while  rejecting  Pareto  optimality  as  a  normative  criterion.

97

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Law  &  Ethics  of  Human  Rights,  Vol.  3  [2009],  Iss.  1,  Art.  5

so  as  to  avoid  costly  recruitment  of  workers  in  the  peak  season.48    He  also  argues  
at  a  later  date  that  such  contracts  can  provide  risk-­averse  laborers  with  insurance  
against  income  fluctuations through varying seasons and risk-­neutral landlords with
assured  cheap  labor  during  peak  season.   49    Braverman  and  Stiglitz  analyze  how  
labor-­tying   contracts   can   give   incentives   for   agricultural   laborers   to   work   more  
productively  in  the  slack  season.50    Srinivasan  argues  that  attempts  to  reduce  the  
landlord’s  power  by  restricting  his  credit  activities  will  lower  agrarian  output  and  
make  tenants  worse  off.51    Some  economists  have  even  argued  that  under  non-­ideal  
conditions,  labor  bondage  is  Pareto  optimal.52  
Of   course,   a   Paretian   justification of bondage as optimal   depends   on  
the   assumption   that   the   parties   to   an   agreement   are   rational   and   have   adequate  
information—but   a   peasant   who   agrees   to   borrow   from   a   lender   at   the   interest  
rate   of   20%   per   month   may   not   understand   what   he   is   actually   agreeing   to.     It  
also  depends  on  the  absence  of  transaction  costs.    Thus,  Paretians  might  argue  that  
the   circumstances   of   bonded   labor—circumstances   characterized   by   transaction  
costs  and  asymmetric  and  imperfect  information—give  us  reasons  to  endorse  state  
intervention  in  such  markets,  where  such  intervention  is  possible  and  likely  to  be  
effective.53    

48
  See   Pranab   K.   Bardhan,   Wages   and   Employment   in   a   Poor   Agrarian   Economy:   A  
Theoretical  and  Empirical  Analysis,  87  J.  POLITICAL  ECON.  479  (1979).
49
 See  Pranab  K.  Bardhan,  Labor  Tying  in  a  Poor  Agrarian  Economy:  A  Theoretical  and  
Empirical  Analysis,  98  Q.  J.  ECON.  14  (1983).
50
  See  Avishay   Braverman   &   Joseph   E.   Stiglitz,   Sharecropping   and   the   Interlinking   of  
Agrarian  Markets,  72  AM.  ECON.    REV.  695  (1982).
51
 On  the  Choice  among  Creditors  and  Bonded  Labor  Contracts,  in  THE  ECONOMIC  THEORY  
OF  AGRARIAN  INSTITUTIONS  203  (P.K.  Bardhan  ed.,  1989).  
52
 One  reason  that  a  Paretian  might  think  bonded  labor  arrangements  are  Pareto  optimal  
under  certain  circumstances  is  that  if  the  parties  to  a  bonded  labor  agreement  are  free  to  bargain  over  
their  property  rights  and  have  information  about  the  effects  of  different  labor  and  credit  policies,  
then  following  Coase,  we  can  assume  that  an  alternative  allocation  would  have  emerged  if  it  were  
more  efficient.  The Coase theorem states that property rights make no difference to efficiency as
long  as  the  parties  are  free  to  bargain  their  way  to  an  alternative  allocation  of  property  rights.    If  a  
bonded  laborer  could  be  alternatively  employed  in  a  more  productive  way,  then  he  would  have  been  
able  to  persuade  his  landlord  to  accept  a  contract  that  did  not  include  bonded  labor.
Coase  was,  of  course,  very  careful  to  say  that  his  theorem  held  only  in  a  world  without  
transaction   costs.    We   do   not   live   in   such   a   world.    To   the   extent   that   transactions   costs   prevent  
parties  from  reaching  an  optimal  bargain,  all  bets  are  off:  there  is  no  reason  to  think  that  the  existing  
system  of  distribution  is  optimal.  
53
 For  literature  on  flaws in the formation of people’s preferences, see  AMOS  TVERSKY   AND  
DANIEL   KAHNEMAN,  AVAILABILITY:  A   HEURISTIC   FOR   JUDGING   FREQUENCY   AND   PROBABILITY   185,   207  
(1974).

98
10.2202/1938-­2545.1032

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Satz:  Voluntary  Slavery  and  the  Limits  of  the  Market

What  about  under  more  ideal  conditions,  where  there  is  adequate  knowledge  
and   no   transaction   costs?     In   such   a   world   wouldn’t   Paretians   have   to   reject  
restrictions  on  the  freedom  to  contract  as  inefficient?  Doesn’t prohibiting a landlord
and  peasant  from  contracting  as  they  wish  stand  in  the  way  of  obvious  gains  from  
trade?
One  possible  argument  for  banning  such  exchanges  goes  like  this.    When  
an  individual  acts  so  to  maximize  his  welfare,  we  should  not  assume  that  he  does  
so  within  a  set  of  constraints  that  is  exogenously  defined.  The set of choices that
an  agent  faces  is  often  endogenous,  affected  by  the  choices  of  others.    Allowing  
laborers   the   option   to   bond   themselves   to   their   creditors   may   make   alternative  
options  (that  the  laborers  would  actually  prefer)  unavailable  to  them.54
Consider  the  practice  of  child  labor.    Poor  parents  in  developing  societies  
often  send  their  children  to  work  because  they  can  see  no  other  way  of  supporting  
their  families.    For  each  individual  family,  child  labor  looks  to  be  the  family’s  best  
option  for  survival:  Child  labor  can  generate  the  income  that  keeps  family  members  
from  starving.    At  the  same  time  however,  the  widespread  availability  of  child  labor  
can  serve  to  drive  down  the  wages  of  the  adult  laborers,  thus  making  child  labor  
necessary  for  every  family’s  survival.    The  institution  of  child  labor  restrains  the  set  
of  alternatives  available  to  poor  families,  so  that  they  now  have  no  better  choice  than  
to  send  their  children  to  work.    While  an  individual  act  (token)  of  child  labor  may  
be  Pareto  improving  when  we  consider  its  consequences  for  a  single  poor  family,  
the  practice  (type)  of  child  labor  may  make  other  families  worse  off  by  changing  
the  range  of  options  that  are  open  to  them.55    Interestingly,  permitting  child  labor  is  

54
 See  Garance  Genicot,  Bonded  Labor  and  Serfdom:  A  Paradox  of  Voluntary  Choice,  67  J.  
DEV.  ECON.  101  (2002).    Genicot  argues  that  the  existence  of  bonded  labor  hinders  the  development  
of   welfare   enhancing   credit   opportunities   for   laborers.     Given   poor   peasants’   lack   of   collateral,  
asymmetries   of   information,   and   ineffective   enforcement   institutions,   credit   contracts   tend   to   be  
implicit  self-­enforcing  agreements.    The  loss  of  future  credit  opportunities  from  lenders  provides  
peasant  borrowers  with  an  incentive  not  to  default  on  their  loans.    In  the  absence  of  such  incentives,  
enforcement  would  be  extremely  costly,  and  creditors  would  have  less  reason  to  make  such  loans.    
Bonded   labor,   by   providing   an   alternative   opportunity   for   obtaining   credit   besides   formal   credit  
institutions,  decreases  the  costs  of  reneging  on  the  agreement.    Bonded  labor  thereby  renders  the  
implicit   promise   to   repay   a   loan   from   a   formal   credit   institution   unenforceable.     Genicot   argues  
that  the  existence  of  bonded  labor  can  lead  local  credit  institutions  to  deny  loans  to  poor  laborers;;  
it   might   also   prevent   such   institutions   from   forming   or   thriving.    A   ban   on   bonded   labor,   if   this  
contributes  to  the  creation  of  formal  credit  institutions,  might  make  some  poor  laborers  better  off  by  
enabling  them  access  to  credit  on  terms  they  would  prefer.
55
 As  Derek  Parfit has noted, our evaluation of a set of acts is not the same as our evaluation
of   each   of   the   acts   contained   in   the   set.     Even   if   each   single   act   of   labor   bondage   is   a   Pareto  
improvement,  it  does  not  follow  that  the  practice  of  labor  bondage  is.    See  DEREK  PARFIT,  REASONS  
AND  PERSONS  (1984).

99

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Law  &  Ethics  of  Human  Rights,  Vol.  3  [2009],  Iss.  1,  Art.  5

in  the  interests  of  some  employers  since  it  provides  them  with  a  cheaper  source  of  
labor  than  adults.    Such  employers  may  seek  to  manipulate  the  choice  environment.56  
And,  once  child  labor  is  the  norm,  the  incentive  for  the  state  to  invest  in  education  
may  be  diminished,  thus  further  restricting  parent’s  options.  
In  cases  of  multiple  equilibria,  Paretianism  does  not  yield  a  determinative  
result.    Let’s  consider  the  limits  and  implications  of  a  Paretian  argument  in  support  
of  banning  labor  bondage,  given  the  possibility  of  multiple  equilibria:
First,  recognizing  the  ways  that  the  set  of  choices  that  an  agent  faces  are  
endogenously  determined,  this  line  of  argument  undercuts  one  classic  defense  of  
the  market.    It  is  circular  to  endorse  a  set  of  market  relationships  on  the  grounds  
that  they  (optimally)  promote  the  satisfaction  of  preferences  if  those  preferences  are  
themselves  substantially  the  result  of  the  very  market  arrangements  under  question.    
More  crucially,  the  recognition  of  the  endogenous  nature  of  choice  sets  leaves  open  
the  question  of  institutional  evaluation.    If  two  different  systems  create  and  satisfy  
different  preferences,  on  what  grounds  should  we  choose  between  them?57
Second,  the  endogeneity  of  choice  sets  shows  us  that  the  distinction  between  
a  voluntary  choice  and  an  imposed  form  of  servitude  is  not  so  clear.58    Powerful  
agents  often  act  to  restrict  the  set  of  choices  open  to  less  powerful  agents,  who  then  
choose  the  best  option  that  is  now  available.    (Indeed,  the  choices  of  poor  peasants  
are  inevitably  made  against  a  background  of  property  rights  and  market  institutions  
that  they  are  not  able  to  choose.)  
Third,   because   the   argument   is   made   in   terms   of   Pareto   non   comparable  
multiple  equilibria,  they  do  not  entail  that  it  is  better  than  not  to  have  a  legal  ban  on  
debt  bondage.    Prohibiting  bondage  makes  some  agents  better  off  and  some  agents  
worse   off   than   they   would   be   otherwise;;   allowing   bondage   makes   some   agents  
better  off  and  some  agents  worse  off  than  they  would  be  otherwise.    Parents,  for  
example,  who  have  no  objection  to  child  labor,  might  prefer  an  equilibrium  outcome  
with  low  adult  wages  and  child  labor  to  an  equilibrium  outcome  without  child  labor  
but  with  only  somewhat  higher  adult  wages.    Indeed,  many  types  of  transactions,  
including  types  of  transactions  we  might  well  want  to  endorse,  are  likely  to  make  
some  agents  worse  off.59  
To  draw  the  conclusion  that  bans  on  labor  bondage  are  justified (or bans on
child  labor),  we  have  to  leave  the  ground  of  Paretian  reasoning  and  appeal  to  other  

56
 See  Debra  Satz,  Child  Labor:  A  Normative  Approach,  17  WORLD  BANK  ECON.  REV.  297  
(2003).
  I   do   not   mean   to   suggest   that   this   problem   arises   only   for   the   Paretian   welfare  
57

economist.
58
 See  Genicot,  supra  note  54.
59
 Many  transactions  generate  pecuniary  externalities,  for  example.

100
10.2202/1938-­2545.1032

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Satz:  Voluntary  Slavery  and  the  Limits  of  the  Market

normative  considerations  or  standards.    Broadening  our  conception  of  welfare,  for  
example,  might  lead  us  to  consideration  of  questions  of  interest  and  need,  as  well  as  
to  attempt  to  make  interpersonal  comparisons.  
Of   course,   there   is   indeed,   no   reason   for   economists   to   limit   themselves  
to   the   Paretian   idea   of   efficiency.   Indeed, some economists endorse the idea of
potential  Pareto  improvements,  in  effect,  cost-­benefit analysis.  In theory, if banning
child  labor  raised  the  productivity  of  labor  so  that  winners  could  compensate  the  
losers,  then  the  ban  would  be  justified.  One problem for this approach, of course, is
that  compensatory  mechanisms  are  rarely  in  place  and  in  their  absence  it  is  unclear  
why  economists  would  accept  a  policy  that  makes  some  people  worse  off.
Alternatively,  one  could  move  away  from  the  assumption  that  preference  
satisfaction  is  the  correct  measure  of  welfare.    On  Amartya  Sen’s  view,  for  example,  
there  are  certain  basic  functionings—“beings  and  doings”—that  an  individual  needs  
to  achieve  a  certain  quality  of  life.60    These  basic  functionings  include  nourishment,  
literacy,  life  expectancy,  satisfying  work,  and  the  ability  to  appear  in  public  without  
shame.    Well-­   being   or   quality   of   life   or   welfare   does   not   consist   exclusively   in  
a  person’s  level  of  subjective  preference  satisfaction  but  is  primarily  a  matter  of  
the  objectively  defined functionings that she actually achieves.  Sen designates a
person’s  “capability  set”  as  the  set  of  functionings  that  are  really,  that  is,  effectively  
open  to  her.    If  we  accept  Sen’s  view,  we  might  try  to  rank  alternative  equilibria  
in   terms   of   the   important   functionings   that   they   actually   make   open   to   people,  
including  such  considerations  as  whether  the  contracting  parties  live  at  the  mercy  
of  their  creditors.61    
Fourth,  and  finally, the endogenity of both preferences and choice sets in
bonded  labor  suggests  that  in  some  exchanges,  the  parties  themselves  –their  culture,  
their   values   and   their   preferences—might   be   partly   constituted   by   the   exchange  
itself.    This  insight—that  certain  kinds  of  exchanges  not  only  distribute  things  but  
also  distribute  power  and  shape  the  kind  of  people  we  become—is  missing  from  the  
conventional  welfare  economist’s  approach  to  markets.62    If  we  incorporate  the  idea  
that  our  preferences  and  capacities  are  not  fixed into our economic models, then we
cannot  ignore  the  ways  that  a  set  of  social  arrangements  is  likely  to  change  us.  

60
  See   JEAN   DRÈZE   &   AMARTYA   SEN,   HUNGER   AND   PUBLIC   ACTION   (1989);;   AMARTYA   SEN,  
COMMODITIES  AND  CAPABILITIES  (1985,  republished  OUP  1999).  
61
 See  AMARTYA  SEN,  INEQUALITY  RE-­EXAMINED  (1992).
62
  Interestingly,   this   recognition   was   an   important   part   of   classical   political   economy’s  
heterogeneous   approach   to   markets.     See   Debra   Satz,   Nineteenth   Century   Political   Economy,   in  
NINETEENTH  CENTURY  PHILOSOPHY  (Allen  Wood  ed.,  forthcoming  2007).

101

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Law  &  Ethics  of  Human  Rights,  Vol.  3  [2009],  Iss.  1,  Art.  5

III.  OTHER  CONSIDERATIONS

Let’s  consider  bonded  labor  more  closely.    Although  bonded  labor  can  be  the  product  
of  an  agreement  and  although  it  can  improve  a  worker’s  welfare,  it  can  have  other  
features  that  make  such   labor  arrangements  (and  especially  state  enforcement  of  
these   arrangements)   especially   problematic.     I   have   already   alluded   to   some   of  
these  problematic  features  in  the  case  of  children.    

A.  EXPLOITATION  OF  THE  VULNERABILITIES  OF  THE  MOST  VULNERABLE

Labor   bondage   arises   in   circumstances   in   which   some   people   lack   the   resources  
to  protect  themselves  against  life  threatening  risks  due  to  crop  failures  or  seasonal  
unemployment.    Lenders  take  advantage  of  the  vulnerability  of  workers  in  these  
situations,   offering   credit   on   terms   that   are   well   below   what   people   who   were  
less  desperate  would  accept.63    The  background  inequality  and  desperation  behind  
this  agreement  arouses  our  suspicion  that  the  exchange  is  unfair  and  exploitative.    
Perhaps  in  more  ideal  circumstances,  we  could  imagine  bonded  labor  that  did  not  
arise  on  the  basis  of  a  desperate  exchange  and  which  was  not  exploitative.    But  this  
consideration  certainly  should  give  us  pause  in  accepting  libertarian  and  welfarist  
arguments  in  favor  of  existing  systems  of  labor  bondage.64

B.  DE  FACTO  OR  DE  JURE  LIFETIME  LENGTH  OF  CONTRACT

Although   most   bondage   arrangements   allow   for   the   termination   of   the   contract  
once   the   debt   is   repaid,   in   practice,   these   arrangements   often   last   a   lifetime.    
Bonded  laborers  are  not  free  to  leave  their  employment,  even  when  they  can  obtain  
employment  on  better  terms  (and  thus  accelerate  repayment  of  his  debt).  Agricultural  
workers  in  India  and  Pakistan,  where  labor  bondage  is  a  frequent  occurrence,  rarely  
pay  off  their  debts  in  their  own  lifetimes.    Indeed,  when  they  die  before  their  debts  
are  repaid,  their  children  and  grandchildren  are  sent  to  work  in  their  place.  
Why  shouldn’t  people  be  able  to  contract  themselves  to  an  employer  for  a  
lifetime?    It  might  be  argued  that  no  one  should  be  able  to  bind  her  future  self  in  
such  a  manner.    Not  only  does  an  individual  lack  complete  knowledge  about  her  
future  self,  but  also  her  conditions  are  likely  to  change  in  ways  that  she  cannot  now  
predict.  

 In  many  of  these  cases,  it  might  be  argued  that  we  have  de  facto  monopoly  pricing.
63

 Is  exploitation  unjust?    This  is  disputed  territory,  and  I  do  not  resolve  the  issue  here.    For  a  
64

different  view,  which  draws  a  distinction  between  exploitation  and  coercion  see  David  Zimmerman,  
Coercive  Wage  Offers,   10(2)   PHIL.   &   PUB.  AFFAIRS   121   (1998).    Thanks  to  one  of   the  editors  for  
raising  the  issue.

102
10.2202/1938-­2545.1032

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Satz:  Voluntary  Slavery  and  the  Limits  of  the  Market

But   there   is   a   more   principled   reason   why   someone   might   think   that  
permanent  labor  tying  contracts  should  not  be  binding.    Part  of  being  a  free  person  
is  having  the  ability  to  use  one’s  powers  and  set  and  pursue  one’s  own  purposes.    
Permanent   bondage   contracts   create   a   class   of   people   who   are   unable   to   use   or  
regain  their  capacity  to  set  their  own  ends;;  moreover,  they  give  this  power  to  another  
person.    But  no  one  should  have  that  kind  of  power  over  another  person:  even  in  
ideal  circumstances.    I’ll  elaborate  on  this  point  below  when  I  discuss  the  ways  that  
labor  bondage  does  and  does  not  resemble  slavery.

C.  TOTAL  DEPENDENCE  AND  SUBORDINATION  OF  WORKER  TO  CREDITOR/EMPLOYER

In  practice,  in  the  non-­ideal  conditions  in  which  bondage  appears,  bonded  workers  
lack  the  freedom  to  disobey  their  employer’s  commands,  no  matter  how  arbitrary,  
humiliating,   or   personally   costly   such   commands   are.     Workers   are   expected   to  
answer  to  their  employer’s  demands  “around  the  clock”  both  in  the  fields and in
their  own  homes.    Although  poor  peasants  retain  some  formal  control  over  their  
bodies   and   their   labor,   in   bonded   labor   arrangements   they   most   often   lack   any  
meaningful  substantive  control.    Like  the  worker  in  a  company  town,  the  bonded  
laborer  lives  in  situation  of  complete  dependence  on  his  employer,  vulnerable  to  the  
employer’s  whims  and  abuse.    

D.  EROSION  OF  IMPORTANT  CAPACITIES

Labor  bondage  is  not  only  a  contractual  phenomenon,  but  it  is  also  a  psychological  
one.     In   a   study   of   workers   held   in   debt   bondage   in   northeastern   Brazil,   subject  
workers  referred  to  their  employers  as  men  (homens)  and  to  themselves  as  goats  
(cabras)   perhaps   indicating   their   social   subordination.65     Researchers   have   also  
reported   on   the   role   of   social   norms   in   preparing   women   and   lower   caste   men  
for  lives  of  submissiveness  and  compliance.    Women  who  have  been  abducted  as  
sexual   slaves,   and   children   who   have   been   repeatedly   sold,   sometimes   return   to  
their  owners  when  freed.
Consider   the   example   of   Baldev,   a   bonded   laborer   who   managed   to   free  
himself  through  a  windfall  inheritance  from  a  relative.    Two  years  later,  lacking  any  
preparation  for  freedom,  he  reentered  bondage.    In  an  interview,  he  explained:
After  my  wife  received  the  money,  we  paid  off  our  debt  and  were  free  to  
do  whatever  we  wanted.  But  I  was  worried  all  the  time—what  if  one  of  our  

  See   Schaffner,   supra   note   3,   for   a   discussion   of   this.     However,   Prof.   Mariana   Mota  
65

Prado  cautioned  that  the  language  in  this  example  may  have  other  explanations,  based  on  race  and  
on  culture.

103

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Law  &  Ethics  of  Human  Rights,  Vol.  3  [2009],  Iss.  1,  Art.  5

children  got  sick?  What  if  our  crop  failed?  What  if  the  government  wanted  
some  money?  Since  we  no  longer  belonged  to  the  landlord,  we  didn’t  get  
food  everyday  as  before.  Finally,  I  went  to  the  landlord  and  asked  him  to  
take  me  back.  I  didn’t  have  to  borrow  any  money,  but  he  agreed  to  let  me  be  
his  halvaha  [bonded  plowman]  again.  Now  I  don’t  worry  so  much;;  I  know  
what  to  do.66
Baldev  places  little  value  on  his  rights,  exhibiting  a  condition  that  Tom  Hill  
has  referred  to  as  “servility.”67    A  servile  person  is  not  simply  a  person  who  refuses  
to  press  his  rights  in  certain  cases,  but  does  not  see  himself  as  having  rights  in  the  
first place.  Even when he is able to walk away, his mind is unfree, shaped by a
world  in  which  others  set  ends  for  him.    
When   workers   have   been   bonded   for   decades,   when   they   know   no   other  
reality,   when   their   employers   constantly   reinforce   their   inferiority   and   the   pre-­
ordained   nature   of   their   bondage,   it   can   be   frightening   for   them   to   contemplate  
disobedience  or  flight.68    Bonded  workers  are  often  purposively  isolated  from  non-­
bonded  laborers  and  so  they  do  not  even  know  their  rights.    But  even  when  they  
know  their  rights  intellectually,  they  may  lack  the  capacity  to  really  see  themselves  
as  independent  beings  with  rights  and  standing.
These  four  aspects  of  contemporary  labor  bondage  are  reasons  not  to  enforce  
or   support   such   arrangements   even   where   they   arise   through   an   agreement   and  
represent  welfare  improvements.    The  state  has  good  reasons  not  to  lend  its  support  
to  arrangements  that  depend  on  the  exploitation  of  the  vulnerabilities  of  the  most  
vulnerable,   permanently   bind   one   person   to   another,   give   one   person   inordinate  
power   over   another,   or   undermine   the   capacities   of   laborers   to   stand   in   society  
as   equals.    Arguably,   several   of   these   reasons   are   relevant   to   the   desperate   and  
non-­ideal  circumstances  under  which  bondage  arises.    But  my  argument  also  calls  
attention  to  the  need  for  society  to  produce  and  reproduce  certain  capacities  in  its  
members,  a  need  which  would  hold  even  under  more  idealized  circumstances.
Every  society  depends  on  its  members  having  the  capability  to  behave  in  
ways  that  realize  and  reproduce  it.    Democratic  societies,  in  particular,  depend  on  

66
  Cf.   Kevin   Bales,   The   Social   Psychology   of   Slavery,   SCIENTIFIC   AMERICAN   (Apr.   24,  
2002).  
67
 See  discussion  in  Thomas  Hill,  Servility  and  Self  Respect,  57  MONIST  87  (1973).
68
 Schaffner,  supra  note  3  argues  that  employers  attempt  to  manipulate  the  psychology  of  
their  employees  to  reduce  the  costs  of  enforcing  the  bondage  relationship.    To  the  extent  that  an  
individual’s  preferences  are  conditioned  by  the  behavior  of  those  that  he  meets  daily,  then  employers  
have  an  incentive  to  restrict  the  access  of  their  servile  workers  to  others  whose  presence  might  widen  
their  horizons  and  thereby  change  their  sense  of  what  kind  of  relationships  at  work  are  possible.    Id.  
at  247ff.  

104
10.2202/1938-­2545.1032

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Satz:  Voluntary  Slavery  and  the  Limits  of  the  Market

the  ability  of  their  citizens  to  operate  as  equals.    This  means  not  only  that  in  such  
societies  people  have  equal  rights,  but  also  that  they  see  themselves  as  having  equal  
basic  rights;;  understand  and  act  on  the  requirements  of  justice;;  and  see  themselves  
as  self  authenticating  sources  of  claims.      I  have  already  alluded  to  the  ways  that  
such  considerations  give  us  an  interest  in  how  children  are  treated  in  my  discussion  
of  libertarianism.    But  the  examples  of  Baldev  and  other  bonded  laborers  show  us  
that  we  have  a  related  interest  in  how  adults  are  treated.
Employment   occupies   a   large   fraction   of   most   adult   individuals’   time  
and  attention.    Acting  as  a  bonded  laborer  may  lead  to  a  failure  to  develop  and/or  
an   erosion   of   a   person’s   capacities   for   independence   and   equal   relations   among  
others.    The  long  term  experience  of  social  subordination,  dependence  and  servility  
may  dampen  a  person’s  ability  to  see  him  or  herself  as  a  source  of  interests  and  
rights  that  matter  and  matter  equally  to  those  of  others.    Such  a  person  may  find
it  more  comfortable  to  allow  others  to  make  decisions  for  him.    If  labor  bondage  
has  such  effects,  then  democratic  societies  have  a  special  interest  in  discouraging  
or  prohibiting  the  practice  of  bondage.    (Indeed,  they  may  also  have  an  interest  in  
continuing   the   skill   education   for   adults,   as   well   as   restructuring   some   forms   of  
non-­bonded  labor.69)  
Although  the  idea  that  labor  markets  have  potentially  powerful  effects  on  
the  way  that  human  beings  are  shaped  is  most  often  associated  with  the  writings  of  
Karl  Marx,  it  was  noted  as  well  by  the  classical  economists,  including  Adam  Smith.    
In  the  Wealth  of  Nations,  Smith  wrote:
The  employment  of  the  great  body  of  the  people  comes  to  be  confined to a
few  operations;;  frequently  to  one  or  two.  But  the  understandings…of  men  are  
necessarily  formed  by  their  ordinary  employments.  The  man  whose  whole  
life  is  spent  performing  a  few  simple  operations  of  which  the  effects  too  are  
perhaps  always  the  same  …  has  no  occasion  to  exert  his  understanding  or  
to  exercise  his  invention  in  finding out expedients for removing difficulties
which  never  occur.  He  naturally  loses,  therefore,  the  habit  of  such  exertion  
and  generally  becomes  as  stupid  and  ignorant  as  it  is  possible  for  a  human  
creature   to   become   …   [he   is   incapable]   of   forming   any   just   judgment  
concerning  many  even  of  the  ordinary  duties  of  private  life.  Of  the  great  and  
extensive  interests  of  his  country,  he  is  altogether  incapable  of  judging...70  
It   is   not   enough,   in   thinking   about   these   effects,   to   call   attention   to   the  
endogeneity  of  preferences  I  alluded  to  above.    Our  evaluative  frameworks  need  to  
go  further  if  we  are  to  understand  what  is  objectionable  about  bondage.    Not  only  

69
 This  argument  may  also  have  implications  for  the  long  term  incarceration  of  prisoners.
70
 ADAM  SMITH,  WEALTH  OF  NATIONS  2-­781  (1976).

105

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Law  &  Ethics  of  Human  Rights,  Vol.  3  [2009],  Iss.  1,  Art.  5

are   preferences   created   through   bonded   laborer,   but   also   and   perhaps   primarily,  
certain  skills  and  capabilities  are  enabled  while  others  are  hindered  or  eroded.71    If  
egalitarians  are  to  embrace  the  aim  of  ensuring  that  people  have  the  ability  to  stand  
in  society  and  relate  to  one  another  as  equals,  then  they  cannot  be  neutral  about  
the  effects  of  institutions  on  those  skills  and  capabilities.    Nor  can  they  be  neutral  
about  relationships  that  subject  one  person  to  the  complete  domination  of  another.    
Slave   contracts,   bonded   labor   contracts,   and   severe   inequality   are   objectionable  
because   they   render   one   person   utterly   dependent   on   the   whims   of   others.     The  
project  of  creating  and  sustaining  a  democratic  society  itself  depends  upon  there  
being  the  kinds  of  people  who  care  about  functioning  as  equals.    Our  evaluation  of  
institutions,  including  markets,  then,  also  needs  to  consider  their  possible  effects  on  
human  motivations  and  aspirations.72

IV.  WHAT’S  SO  SPECIAL  ABOUT  LABOR  BONDAGE?

It  might  be  argued  that  all  labor  contracts  involve  at  least  one  of  the  parties  surrendering  
some  aspects  of  control  over  her  self.    Furthermore,  many  unskilled  workers  who  
retain  the  formal  ability  to  exit  from  their  employers  have  no  realistic  alternative  
options.    Moreover,  it  is  unclear  that  the  practice  of  bonded  labor  inherently  hostile  
to  the  capacities  needed  for  independence  and  equal  social  relations.    Aren’t  there  
forms  of  contract  that  while  enacting  “specific performance” or restrictions on a
worker’s  ability  to  exit,  are  perfectly  compatible  with  equality  of  social  relations?    
What   about   professional   sports   players   tied   to   a   particular   team   or   soldiers   in   a  
volunteer  army?73    
Undoubtedly,   many   of   the   problems   associated   with   bonded   labor   have  
to   do   not   with   the   bondage   per   se,   but   with   extreme   poverty,   lack   of   education,  
imperfect   information,   incomplete   credit   markets   and   lack   of   decent   alternatives  
for   the   poor.     My   claim   in   this   Article,   however,   is   that   poverty,   information  

71
 Thanks  to  Seana  Shiffrin  for  suggesting  that  I  emphasize  my  expansion  of  the  vocabulary  
of  endogeneity  and  underscore  its  relationship  to  skills  as  well  as  preferences.
72
  The   idea   that   works   is   a   source   of   personal   development   has   received   support   in  
experimental  studies.    Studies  have  measured  the  effect  of  work  organization  on  worker’s  capacities  
for  independence;;  attitudes  towards  conformity;;  self-­concepts;;  and  sense  of  moral  responsibility.  
Indeed,   if   workplaces   are   in   fact   schools   for   the   development   of   cognitive   and   moral   capacities,  
then  this  has  implications  beyond  bonded  labor.    See  MELVIN  KOHN  &  CARMI  SCHOOLER,  WORK   AND  
PERSONALITY:  AN  INQUIRY  INTO  THE  IMPACT  OF  SOCIAL  STRATIFICATION  55ff  (1983).
73
 Michael  Blake  raised  this  objection  to  my  argument  in  discussion.    But  see  BRAD  SNYDER,  
A  WELL-­PAID  SLAVE:  CURT  FLOOD’S  FLIGHT   FOR  FREE  AGENCY   IN  PROFESSIONAL  SPORTS  (2006)  for  an  
argument  that  even  high  pay  may  not  compensate  for  the  right  to  exit.    Military  service  is  exceptional  
in  ways  that  perhaps  justify  its  hierarchical  and  authoritative  structure.

106
10.2202/1938-­2545.1032

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Satz:  Voluntary  Slavery  and  the  Limits  of  the  Market

problems,  and  inefficiency do not exhaust our potential concerns with employment
relationships,   including   those   of   contemporary   bondage.     Some   contracts   are  
affronts  to  the  equal  standing  of  the  agents  by  their  overt  content.    In  this  category  
would  likely  fall  employment  contracts  that  give  an  employer  an  unbounded  control  
over  the  worker’s  entire  days  and  nights,  allow  the  employer  to  sexually  harass  his  
employees,  or  give  the  employer  the  right  to  flog or otherwise physically discipline
his  employees.    Other  contracts  may  be  objectionable  because  of  their  scope.    While  
people  frequently  enter  into  agreements  that  bind  their  future  selves  (that’s  what  
most  contracts  do,  after  all),  I  have  argued  that  we  have  reasons  to  reject  permanent  
labor  tying  contracts.    To  the  extent  that  we  value  allowing  people  to  form,  revise  
and  act  on  their  conceptions  of  value,  we  have  strong  reasons  to  allow  people  to  
retain  the  legal  right  to  exit  (at  some  point)  from  their  employment  relationships  
with  other  adults.    To  the  extent  that  we  seek  to  place  limits  on  the  power  that  one  
person  can  exercise  over  another,  and  to  maintain  the  conditions  for  autonomy,  we  
have  strong  reasons  not  to  enforce  permanent  labor  tying  contracts  even  when  they  
offer  fair  renumeration  and  are  the  products  of  an  agreement.
I  believe  that  this  is  true  even  of  labor  tying  contracts  that  limit  the  power  
of  employers  on  the  job  because  I  think  that  work  has  a  special  role  in  a  person’s  
conception  of  their  good.    While  not  everyone  pursues  meaning  through  their  work,  
many  do.74    Because  the  development  and  exercise  of  one’s  capacities  and  skills  is  
such  an  important  element  of  human  well-­being,  and  because  they  are  so  intimately  
tied  up  with  our  notions  of  self-­respect,  we  have  reasons  to  protect  the  opportunity  
to  have  a  range  of  work  choices,  even  to  people  who  turn  out  not  to  value  having  
that  opportunity.  
Labor   movements   have   long   recognized   the   centrality   of   concerns   about  
self   respect.     Workers   have   struck   not   only   over   wages   and   hours,   but   also   for  
the   right   to   organize,   and   for   the   establishment   of   limits   on   the   non-­job   related  
discretionary   power   of   their   employers.     More   generally,   liberal   societies   have  
typically   placed   limits   on   the   discretion   that   one   person   has   over   another:   they  
do   not   enforce   “specific performance” in the majority of contracts;; they do not
enforce  contracts  whose  terms  are  considered  “unconscionable,”  and  they  do  not  
throw  people  into  prison  for  non-­payment  of  a  debt.    Such  societies  also  recognize  
the  right  of  people  to  divorce  one  another,  even  after  they  have  pledged  life  long  
fidelity.75    The   prohibition   on   such   contracts   gives   expression   to   a   richer   idea   of  

74
 For  discussions  of  the  role  of  work  in  sustaining  personal  welfare,  self-­respect  and  social  
and  civic  status  see  CYNTHIA  ESTLUND,  WORKING  TOGETHER  (2003),  Vicky  Schultz,  Life’s  Work,  100  
COLUMBIA  L.  REV.  1881  (2000).
75
  Some   of   the   restrictions   on   length   of   contract   can   be   explained   on   informational  
grounds:  tomorrow’s  hunger  cannot  be  felt  today,  etc.    Thus,  some  restrictions  have  a  welfare  based  
rationale.

107

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Law  &  Ethics  of  Human  Rights,  Vol.  3  [2009],  Iss.  1,  Art.  5

equality   and   freedom   in   social   relationships   than   is   found   in   the   libertarian   or  


welfarist  perspectives  on  bonded  labor.76

V.  CONCLUSION  AND  IMPLICATIONS

The  two  dominant  schools  of  liberal  economics—Paretian  welfarism  and  libertarian  
public   choice—are   committed   in   theory   to   an   ideal   market   without   limits.     The  
normative  properties  of  the  neoclassical  general  equilibrium  system  depend  on  there  
being  markets  in  everything  (including  futures,  uncertainty  and  the  like.)    The  very  
different  contributions  of  the  libertarian  Chicago  school  are  derived  from  assuming  
that   commodity-­like   relationships   determine   outcomes   in   arenas   not   customarily  
thought  of  as  economic,  including  voting  and  family  life.    Neither  theory  would  
condemn  bondage  contracts—nor  indeed,  voluntary  slavery  contracts—in  principle.    
Instead,  such  arrangements  are  condemned  insofar  as  they  generate  externalities,  
reflect imperfect information, are the effects of incomplete markets, or are based on
physical  force  or  theft.  
Ironically,  neither  theory  has  the  resources  to  fully  appreciate  capitalism’s  
advance  over  its  feudal  predecessor.    Capitalist  labor  markets  are  not  facts  of  nature,  
but  are  shaped  by  social  preconditions,  including  underlying  entitlements  and  social  
norms.     In   order   to   transform   feudal   relations,   capitalism   had   to   limit   property  
rights  and  transform  the  ways  that  people  related  to  one  another,  conceived  of  one  
another  and,  indeed,  conceived  of  themselves.    Currently,  millions  of  people  in  the  
developing  world  have  no  rights  against  employer  violence,  little  political  voice  or  
civil  rights,  and  are  routinely  exploited,  sexually  abused,  traded  to  others,  or  simply  
disposed  of.    Bonded  labor  thrives  in  societies  without  compulsory  education  (either  
in  law  or,  more  typically,  in  practice),  with  weak  rule  of  law,  weak  formal  credit  
or   labor   markets,   weak   rights   of   exit,   and   where   caste-­like   social   divisions   and  
conflicts are common.77    That’s  not  capitalism,  that’s  feudalism.    
Banning  bonded  labor—or  at  least  failing  to  enforce  its  terms—may  be  an  
important  step  in  creating  the  capacities  and  norms  that  people  need  for  egalitarian  
social  relationships  with  one  another.    Even  then,  banning  such  markets  is  unlikely  
to   do   that   alone:   creating   genuinely   free   capitalist   labor   markets   requires   also  
developing   the   formal   credit   sector   of   the   economy,   enforcing   restrictions   on  
monopoly  and  monopsony,  strengthening  education  systems,  combating  caste  and  

76
 Convention  Concerning  the  Prohibition  and  Immediate  Action  for  the  Elimination  of  the  
Worst  Forms  of  Child  Labor,  (ILO  No.  182),  ¶  182,  2133  U.N.T.S.161,  entered  into  force  Nov.  19,  
2000  emphasizes  the  special  wrong  of  labor  bondage  a  perspective  that  resonates  with  the  approach  
I  adopt  here.
77
 Cf.  MYRON  WEINER,  THE  CHILD  AND  STATE  IN  INDIA  (1991).

108
10.2202/1938-­2545.1032

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM
Satz:  Voluntary  Slavery  and  the  Limits  of  the  Market

gender  subordination,  and  perhaps  having  the  state  serve  as  an  additional  source  of  
credit  for  poor  families.78
In  my  view,  our  evaluation  of  labor  bondage  contracts  needs  to  take  into  
account  a  number  of  parameters  missing  from  the  standard  libertarian  and  welfarist  
economic  theories  of  markets:  the  extent  to  which  bondage  depends  on  exploitation  
of  the  vulnerabilities  of  the  most  vulnerable;;  the  extent  to  which  bondage  places  one  
person  wholly  under  the  power  of  another,  the  unlimited  duration  of  contemporary  
labor  bondage,  and  finally the effect of bondage on the capabilities people need to
operate  in  society  as  equals.    We  also  need  to  attend  to  the  nature  of  and  relation  
between  the  contracting  agents,  especially  when  one  of  the  agents  is  a  child.
Both  Paretianism  and  libertarianism  operate  with  a  very  abstract  idea  of  what  
a  market  is.    Yet,  if  different  markets  have  different  effects  on  our  capabilities—
effects   that   differ   in   kind   from   those   produced   by   other   markets—then   it   is   a  
mistake  to  treat  all  markets  in  the  same  way.    In  particular,  a  democratic  society  has  
a  strong  interest  in  supporting  institutions  that  cultivate  egalitarian  motivations  and  
capacities   and   withholding   support   from   institutions   that   cultivate   subordination  
and  servitude,  even  if  these  institutions  are  not  strictly  illegal.79    A  certain  level  of  
income   is   undoubtedly   needed   to   function   as   an   equal   in   society,   but   we   should  
not  focus  only  on  income.    To  the  extent  that  we  endorse  the  idea  that  members  of  
society  should  interact  as  equals,  we  will  have  strong  and  principled  reasons  to  limit  
the  scope  of  markets  in  labor.  

78
 One  innovation  that  may  help  governments  intervene  in  cushioning  the  vulnerability  of  
the  poor  involves  group  lending.    Group  lending  seems  to  reduce  the  costs  of  collecting  information  
and  enforcing  repayment.    The  idea  was  pioneered  by  the  Grameen  Bank  in  Bangladesh  and  spread  
to   many   other   countries.     Currently   about   10   million   households   are   served   by   micro-­finance
programs.
79
 An  example  would  be  the  state’s  withholding  of  tax  exempt  status  from  racially  exclusive  
or  segregated  private  schools.

109

Brought to you by | Stanford University


Authenticated | 171.67.216.21
Download Date | 6/28/13 4:00 AM

Anda mungkin juga menyukai