Anda di halaman 1dari 14

CHAPTER 8

Aesthetic Appreciation of the Natural Environment

ALLEN CARLSON

TheCentralProblem of the Aesthetics preciation of nature. The natural land-


ofNature scape, he says, is indeterminate and
promiscuous. To be appreciated, it must

I
n his classic work, The Sense of Beauty, be composed. Yet it is so rich in diversity,
aesthetician, philosopher, and poet suggestion, and emotional stimulus that
George Santayana characterizes the it allows great liberty in selecting, empha-
natural landscape as follows: sizing, and grouping . Thus the problem is
what and how to select, emphasize , and
Thenatural landscape is an indeterminate group and what and how to compose for
object;it almost always contains enough appropriate appreciation.
diversityto allow ... great liberty in There is no parallel problem, however,
selecting,emphasizing, and grouping its concerning the appreciation of art. With
elements,and it is furthermore rich in traditional works of art, we typically know
suggestionand in vague emotional stimu- both the what and the how of appropriate
lus.A landscape to be seen has to be aesthetic appreciation. We know what to
composed... then we feel that the land- appreciate in that we know the difference
scapeis beautiful. ... The promiscuous between a work and what is not it or a
naturallandscape cannot be enjoyed in any part of it and between its aesthetically rel-
otherway.1 evant qualities and those not aesthetically
relevant. We know that we should appre-
With these few words, Santayana poses ciate the sound of the piano in the concert
the central question of the aesthetic ap- hall and not the coughing that interrupts

119
NATURE AND AESTHETIC VALUE

it; we know that we should appreciate a how to appropriately appreciate. Ziff


painting's delicacy and balance but not again:
where it happens to hang. Similarly, we
know how to appreciate works of art in Generally speaking, a different act of
that we know the modes of appreciation aspection is performed in connection with
appropriate to different kinds of works. works belonging to different schools of art,
We know that we should listen to the which is why the classification of style is of
sound of a piano and look at the surface the essence.Venetian paintings lend
of a painting. Moreover, we know that we themselves to an act of aspection involving
must use different approaches for differ- attention to balanced masses; contours are
ent types of paintings, for instance. Philos- of no importance .... The Florentine school
opher Paul Ziff introduced the notion of demands attention to contours, the linear
"acts of aspection," pointing out that dif- style predominates. Look for light in a
ferent acts of aspection are suitable for Claude, for color in a Bonnard, for con-
different types of works and therefore that toured volumes in a Signorelli.3
"to contemplate a painting is to perform
one act of aspection; to scan it is to per- Even though we create art and so know
form another; to study, observe, survey, what and how to appreciate it, this does
inspect, examine, scrutinize, are still not solve the central problem of aestheti-
other acts of aspection. . . . I survey a cally appreciating nature. Nature is not
Tintoretto, while I scan an H. Bosch .... art, and it is not our creation. Rather, it is
Do you drink brandy in the way you drink our whole natural environment, our nat-
beer?" 2 ural world. It surrounds us and confronts
With art, our knowledge of what and us, in Santayana's words, indeterminately
how to appreciate is grounded in the fact and promiscuously, rich in diversity, sug-
that works of art are our creations. We gestion, and stimulus. But what are we to
know what are and are not parts of works, appreciate in all this richness? What are
which of their qualities are aesthetically the limits and the proper foci of apprecia-
relevant, and how to appreciate them, be- tion? And how are we to appreciate it:
cause we have made them for the purpose what are the appropriate modes of appre-
of aesthetic appreciation-and to fulfill ciation and acts of aspect ion? Moreover,
that purpose, this knowledge must be ac- what are the grounds on which we can
cessible. In making an object, we know justifiably answer these questions?
what we make, and thus we know its parts,
its purposes, and what to do with it. In
creating a painting, we know that it ends Some Artistic Approaches to
at its frame, that its colors and lines are Appreciating Nature
aesthetically important, and that we are
to look at it rather than listen to it. More- In regard to art, we know how to answer
over, works of different types have differ- the questions of what and how to appreci-
ent kinds of boundaries and different foci ate, so it seems justifiable to model our
of aesthetic significance and so demand aesthetic appreciation of nature on our
different acts of aspection. Thus in know- aesthetic appreciation of works of art. In-
ing the classification, we know what and deed, various art-based models of appreci-

120
AESTHETIC APPRECIATION OF THE NATURAL ENVIRONMENT

ationhave often been accepted as the basis na's observation marks a distinction be-
fordeciding what and how to aesthetically tween appreciating nature and appreciating
appreciatethe natural environment. the objects of nature. In fact, one under-
One such approach may be called the standing of the Object Model is that when
ObjectModel. Consider our appreciation the objects of nature are appreciated in this
of a nonrepresentational sculpture, for way, they become "ready-mades" or "found
example,a Brancusi, such as Bird in Space art." That is, the natural objects are granted
(1919).We appreciate the actual physical what is called artistic enfranchisement,and
object; the aesthetically relevant features they, like such artifacts as Marcel Duch-
arethe object's sensuous and design qual- amp's urinal, which he enfranchised as a
itiesand certain abstract expressive quali- work called Fountain (1917),become works
ties. Such a sculpture need not relate to of art. 5 In this way, the questions of what
anything outside itself; it is a self- and how to aesthetically appreciate are an-
contained aesthetic unit. The Brancusi swered, but for art rather than for nature;
has no direct representational ties to the the appreciation of nature is lost in the
rest of reality and no relational connec- shuffle. Appreciating a sculpture that once
tions with its immediate surroundings. was driftwood is, therefore, no closer to
Nonetheless, it has significant aesthetic appreciating nature than is appreciating a
qualities: it glistens, has balance and purse that once was a sow's ear.
grace,and expresses flight itself. Clearly, The Object Model does not, however,
wecan aesthetically appreciate objects of have to turn natural objects into art ob-
nature in accordance with the Object jects. It may examine the objects of nature
Model.We can appreciate a rock or a piece simply by actually or imaginatively remov-
of driftwood in the same way we appreci- ing them from their surroundings. We
atea Brancusi: we may actually or imagi- need not appreciate the rock on our man-
natively remove the object from its telpiece as a ready-made sculpture; rather
surroundings and concentrate on its sen- we can appreciate it only as an aesthetically
suous and possible expressive qualities. pleasing physical object. In this case, our
Natural objects often are appreciated in appreciation focuses on the object's sensu-
preciselythis way; think of mantelpieces ous qualities and a few expressive qualities:
littered with rocks and pieces of drift- our rock has a wonderfully smooth and
wood. Moreover, the model fits the fact gracefully curved surface and expresses so-
that natural objects, like nonrepresenta- lidity. Nonetheless, the Object Model re-
tionalsculpture, have no representational mains problematic when removing natural
tiesto the rest of reality. objects from their surroundings. That is,
Nonetheless, in many ways the Object the model is suitable for self-contained art
Modelis not suitable for an aesthetic ap- objects, whose environments of creation or
preciation of nature. Santayana notes the display are not aesthetically relevant. Con-
natural environment's indeterminateness, versely, natural objects are a part of and
and he also observes that nature contains have been formed in their environments of
objects that have determinate forms. But creation by natural forces at work within
when we direct our appreciation specifi- them. Thus, natural objects' environments
callyto them, we no longer have a genuine of creation are aesthetically relevant, and
aestheticappreciation of nature. 4 Santaya- their environments of display are equally

121
NATURE AND AESTHETIC VALUE

relevant, by being either the same as or and its features . Thus, our appreciative
different from their environments of emphasis is on qualities essential to repre-
creation . senting a prospect: the visual qualities re-
To appreciate the extent of the Object lating to line, color, and overall design.
Model's problem, consider our rock again: Such features are central to landscape
on the mantelpiece, it seems gracefully painting and are the focus of the Land-
curved and expressive of solidity, but in its scape Model. By directing our apprecia-
environment of creation , it has more and tion to the artistic and scenic qualities of
different aesthetic qualities-qualities re- line, color, and design, this model encour-
sulting from the connections between it ages perceiving and appreciating nature
and its environment. The rock reflects the as if it were a landscape painting, an im-
forces that shaped and continue to shape it posing prospect to be viewed from a spe-
and displays for aesthetic appreciation its cific position and distance.
place in and its relationships to its envi- Historically, the Landscape Model has
ronment. In addition, it may not express been significant in the aesthetic apprecia-
those qualities , such as solidity, that it ap- tion of nature. 7 It is the direct descendant
pears to express on the mantelpiece. The of the eighteenth-century concept of the
problem for the Object Model is a di- picturesque. Picturesque literally means
lemma: either we remove the object from "picture-like" and suggests a mode of ap-
its environment or we leave it where it is. If preciation that divides the natural world
we remove the object, the model can an- into scenes, each aiming at an ideal dic-
swer the questions of what and how to ap- tated by art, especially landscape paint-
preciate the rock, but this will result in the ing. The concept guided the aesthetic
appreciation of a limited set of aesthetic appreciation of early tourists as they pur-
qualities. But if we do not remove the ob- sued picturesque scenery with the help of
ject, the Object Model will not be suitable the "Claude-glass. " Named for the famous
for much of the appreciation that is possi- landscape painter Claude Lorrain, this
ble. The model also will not be able to an - small, tinted, convex mirror was designed
swer the what and how questions. In either for viewing the landscape as it would ap-
case, the Object Model is a poor paradigm pear in a landscape painting. Thomas
for an appreciation of nature. West's popular guidebook to the Lake
A second art-based approach to aes- District (1778) says of the glass that
thetic appreciation of nature may be called
the Landscap e Model. In one of its senses, where the objects are great and near, it
land scape means a prospect - usually an removes them to a due distance, and shews
imposing prospect-seen from a specific them in the soft colours of nature, and most
standpoint and distance. 6 Landscape regular perspective the eye can perceive, art
painting traditionally represents such teach, or science demonstrate ... to the
prospects, and the Landscape Model is glass is reserved the finished picture, in
closely tied to this genre. In appreciating highest colouring , and just perspectives.8
landscape painting, the focus is typically
not on the actual object, the painting, or In a similar fashion, modern tourists
the represented object-the prospect- frequently show a preference for the Land-
but on the representation of the object scape Model by visiting ((scenic view-

122
AESTHETIC APPRECIATION OF THE NATURAL ENVIRONMENT

points" where the actual space between that the picturesque "simply confirmed
tourist and prescribed "view" constitutes our anthropocentrism by suggesting that
"a due distance" that aids the impression nature exists to please as well as to serve us.
of "soft colours of nature, and the most Our ethics ... have lagged behind our aes-
regular perspective the eye can perceive." thetics. It is an unfortunate lapse which al-
The "regularity" of the perspective is en- lows us to abuse our local environments
hancedby the position of the viewpoint it- and venerate the Alps and the Rockies.""
self. Modern tourists also look for "the The Landscape Model is questionable
finishedpicture, in highest colouring, and also on aesthetic grounds, as it construes
just perspective," whether this is the the environment as if it were a static, es-
"scene"framed and balanced in a camera sentially "two-dimensional" representa-
viewfinder or the result in the form of a tion; it reduces it to a scene or a view. But
color print. Such prints and the "artisti- the natural environment is not a scene,
cally" composed postcard and calendar not a representation, not static, and not
reproductions of the "scene" often receive two dimensional. In short, the model re-
more appreciation than does what they quires appreciating the environment not
"reproduce." Geographer Ronald Rees as what it is and for the qualities it has,
points out that "the taste has been for a but as something it is not and for quali-
view,for scenery, not for landscape in the ties it does not have. The model is un-
original ... meaning of the term, which suited to the actual nature of the object of
denotesour ordinary, everyday surround- appreciation. Consequently it, like the
ings. The average modern sightseer ... is Object Model, not only unduly limits
interested not in natural forms and pro- appreciation-in this case to certain artis-
cesses,but in a prospect." 9 tic and scenic qualities-it also misleads
The Landscape Model's answers to the it. Philosopher Ronald Hepburn puts the
whatand how questions cause a number of point in general terms:
thinkers some uneasiness. The model dic-
tates appreciation of the natural environ- Supposing that a person's aesthetic educa-
ment as if it were a series of landscape tion ... instills in him the attitudes, the
paintings. It requires dividing nature into tactics of approach, the expectations proper
scenes,each to be viewed from a specific to the appreciation of art works only, such a
position by a viewer separated by an ap- person will either pay very little aesthetic
propriate spatial (and emotional?) dis- heed to natural objects or else heed them in
tance. It reduces a walk in the natural the wrong way. He will look-and of course
environment to something like a stroll look in vain-for what can be found and
through an art gallery. Consequently, some enjoyed only in art. 12
people, like the human ecologist Paul
Shepard,find the Landscape Model so mis-
guided that they doubt the wisdom of any
aesthetic approach to nature. 10 Others re- Some Alternative Approaches to
gard the model as ethically and environ- Appreciating Nature
mentally worrisome. For example, after
contending that modern tourists are inter- If traditional art-based approaches to
ested only in prospects, Rees concludes aesthetic appreciation of nature, like the

123
NATURE AND AESTHETIC VALUE

Object Model and the Landscape Model, pher Robert Elliot elaborates this view,
either unduly limit or mislead apprecia- claiming that our appreciative responses
tion, how should we deal with Santaya- to nature do not "count as aesthetic re-
na's indeterminate natural environment? sponses." He holds that a "judgemental el-
How can we correctly decide what and ement in aesthetic evaluation serves to
how to appreciate aesthetically? Perhaps differentiate it from environmental evalu-
we can learn from the failures of the art- ation .... [For] ... [e]valuating works of
based approaches, which limit and mis- art involves explaining them, and judging
lead appreciation largely because they do them, in terms of their author's
not adequately acknowledge the true na- intentions; . .. locating them in some tra-
ture of the object of appreciation. This dition and in some special milieu . . . .
object is our natural environment, both [but] ... Nature is not a work of art." 13
natural and an environment. But in fo- A second alternative to the art-based
cusing on particular natural objects, the approaches to appreciating nature is more
Object Model overlooks the environmen- troubled by the limitations of the Object
tal dimension, and in focusing on artistic Model and concentrates on the environ-
and scenic features, the Landscape Model mental dimension of our natural environ-
downplays the natural dimension . Aware- ment. It argues that traditional art-based
ness of these failures has inspired other approaches, as exemplified by the Object
approaches to appreciating nature that Model and, to a lesser extent, by the Land-
acknowledge that such an appreciation scape Model, presuppose a dichotomy be-
must recognize the true nature of its ob- tween subject and object involving an
ject and cannot simply be assimilated to isolating, distancing, and objectifying
an aesthetic appreciation of art. stance, which is unsuitable for an aes-
One alternative, aware of the problems thetic appreciation not only of nature but
of appreciation governed by the idea of the of art as well. It suggests that this stance
picturesque and underwritten by the wrongly abstracts both natural objects
Landscape Model, is skeptical of aesthetic and appreciators from the environments
approaches to nature in general. Indeed, it in which they properly belong and are ap-
simply denies the possibility of an aes- propriately appreciated. Thus, this posi-
thetic appreciation of nature . This posi- tion proposes replacing abstraction with
tion accepts the traditional account of engagement, distance with immersion,
aesthetic appreciation of art but empha- and objectivity with subjectivity, calling
sizes that nature is natural, not art, and for a participatory aesthetics of nature.
not our creation. It argues that aesthetic One version of this position is termed the
appreciation necessarily involves aesthetic Aesthetics of Engagement and was devel-
evaluation, which judges the object of ap- oped by philosopher Arnold Berleant :
preciation as the achievement of its cre-
ator. Therefore, because nature, unlike art, The boundlessness of the natural world
is not our creation, indeed is not the prod- does not just surround us; it assimilates us.
uct of any designing intellect, our appreci- Not only are we unable to sense absolute
ation of it is not aesthetic. One version of limits in nature; we cannot distance the
this position is called the Human Chau- natural world from ourselves.... [When we
vinistic Aesthetic. Environmental philoso- perceive] environments from within, as it

124
AESTHETIC APPRECIATION OF THE NATURAL ENVIRONMENT

were,looking not at it but being in it, swer offering less guidance than we might
nature ... is transformed into a realm in wish.
whichwe live as participants, not observ-
ers.... The aesthetic mark of all such times
is ... total engagement, a sensory immer- A Natural Environmental Model for
sionin the natural world. 14 Appreciating Nature

By highlighting the natural environ- Despite the problems inherent in the Hu-
ment's natural and environmental dimen- man Chauvinistic Aesthetic and the Aes-
sions, the Human Chauvinistic Aesthetic thetics of Engagement, both positions '
and the Aesthetics of Engagement address emphases on the natural and the environ-
many of the shortcomings of the tradi- mental point toward a paradigm for ap-
tional art-based models. These two ap- preciating nature. This paradigm is
proaches, however, have problems of their exemplified in the following description
own. The Human Chauvinistic Aesthetic by geographer Yi-Fu Tuan:
runs counter to both the orthodox view
that everything is open to aesthetic appre- An adult must learn to be yielding and
ciation and the commonsense idea that at careless like a child if he were to enjoy
least some instances of appreciation of nature polymorphously. He needs to slip
natural things, such as fiery sunsets and into old clothes so that he could feel free to
soaring birds, are paradigmatic cases of stretch out on the hay beside the brook and
aesthetic appreciation. 15 The Aesthetics of bathe in a meld of physical sensations: the
Engagement is problematic as well. First, smell of the hay and of horse dung; the
because at least some of the subject/object warmth of the ground, its hard and soft
dichotomy seems integral to the very na- contours ; the warmth of the sun tempered
ture of aesthetic appreciation, rejecting it by breeze; the tickling of an ant making its
entirely may necessitate rejecting the aes- way up the calf of his leg; the play of
thetic itself, thereby reducing the Aesthet- shifting leaf shadows on his face; the sound
ics of Engagement to a version of the of water over the pebbles and boulders, the
Human Chauvinistic Aesthetic. Second, sound of cicadas and distant traffic. Such an
the Aesthetics of Engagement seems to environment might break all the formal
contain an unacceptable degree of subjec- rules of euphony and aesthetics, substitut-
tivity in its aesthetic appreciation of both ing confusion for order, and yet be wholly
nature and art. 16 The main problem with satisfying.17
both positions is that they do not ade-
quately answer the questions of what and Tuan's characterization of how to ap-
how to aesthetically appreciate nature. To preciate nature accords with the Aesthetic
the what question, the Human Chauvin- of Engagement's answer to what to appre-
istic Aesthetic's answer is "nothing," and ciate, that is, everything . This answer, of
that of the Aesthetics of Engagement is course, is not acceptable. We cannot ap-
"everything." Consequently, about the preciate everything ; our appreciation of
how question, the former view has noth- nature must have limits and emphases
ing more to say, and the latter apparently just as the appreciation of art has. With-
recommends "total immersion," an an- out limits and emphases, our experience

125
NATURE AND AESTHETIC VALUE

of the natural environment would be only much about it. This knowledge, essentially
"a meld of physical sensations" without common sense and scientific knowledge,
any meaning or significance, what philos- is a plausible candidate for playing the role
opher William James characterizes as a in appreciating nature that our knowledge
"blooming buzzing confusion." 18 Such an of art forms, types of works, and artistic
experience would indeed substitute "con- traditions plays in appreciating art. Con-
fusion for order" but, in contrast to what sider again Tuan's example: We experience
is claimed by both Tuan and the Aesthet- a "meld of sensations" -the smell of hay
ics of Engagement, would be neither and of horse dung, the feel of the ant, the
"wholly satisfying" nor aesthetic. It would sound of cicadas and of distant traffic.
be too far removed from aesthetic appre- However, if our response is to be aesthetic
ciation of art to merit the label aesthetic or appreciation rather than just raw experi-
even appreciation. ence, the meld cannot remain a "bloom-
Consider again the case of art: The ing buzzing confusion." Instead, it must
boundaries and foci of aesthetic signifi- become what philosopher John Dewey
cance for works of art are functions of the calls a consummatory experience: one in
type of art of which they are instances: which knowledge and intelligence trans-
paintings end at their frames, and their form raw experience by making it deter-
lines and colors are significant. Our minate, harmonious, and meaningful. 20
knowledge of such matters is based on the For example, we must recognize the smells
fact that works of art are our creations. of hay and horse dung and perhaps distin-
But here we encounter the point empha- guish between them; we must feel the ant
sized by the Human Chauvinistic Aes- at least as an insect rather than as, say, a
thetic: The natural environment is twitch. Such recognizing and distinguish-
natural, not a work of art, not our cre- ing generate foci of aesthetic significance,
ation. Consequently, it has no boundaries natural foci appropriate to the particular
or foci of aesthetic significance offered by natural environment . Likewise, knowl-
our creation, and we do not know what edge of the environment may yield appro-
and how to appreciate in the natural envi- priate boundaries and limits; the sound of
ronment owing to any involvement in its cicadas may be appreciated as a proper
creation. Indeed, nature itself seemingly part of the environment, but the sound of
has no such boundaries or foci. 19 Must the distant traffic excluded, much as we ignore
what and how questions therefore remain coughing in the concert hall.
unanswered? Must nature remain inde- Moreover, common sense and scien-
terminate, promiscuous, and beyond aes- tific knowledge of natural environments
thetic appreciation? are relevant not only to what to appreciate
I suggest not. The fact that the natu- but also to how to appreciate. Tuan's case
ral environment is natural - not our may exemplify a paradigm of nature ap-
creation - does not mean that we can have preciation, something like a general envi-
no knowledge of it. We can discover things ronmental act of aspection. But because
about nature independent of any involve- natural environments differ in type, just
ment in its creation. Even though we did as works of art do, different natural envi-
not create the natural world, we may know ronments require different acts of aspec-

126
AESTHETIC APPRECIATION OF THE NATURAL ENVIRONMENT

tion. And as with the question of what to have a knowledge of different natural en-
appreciate, a knowledge of different par- vironments and their different systems
ticular environments indicates how to ap- and elements in order to appreciate na-
preciate, that is, the appropriate act or acts ture appropriately and aesthetically. Just
of aspection. Ziff tells us to look for con- as the knowledge provided by art critics
tours in the Florentine school, for light in and art historians enables us to aestheti-
a Claude, and for color in a Bonnard and cally appreciate art, that provided by nat-
to survey a Tintoretto and to scan a Bosch. uralists, ecologists, geologists, and
Likewise,we must survey a prairie, look- natural historians equips us to aestheti-
ing at the subtle contours of the land, feel- cally appreciate nature. 22 Thus the natu -
ing the wind blowing across the open ral and environmental sciences are
space, and smelling the mix of prairie central to an appropriate aesthetic appre-
grasses and flowers. But these acts of as- ciation of nature. 23
pection have little place in a dense forest. A position that considers natural and
Here we must examine and scrutinize, in- environmental science to be the key to the
specting the detail of the forest floor, lis- aesthetic appreciation of the natural envi-
tening carefully for the sounds of birds, ronment may be termed the Natural Envi-
and smelling carefully for the scent of ronmental Model. Like the Human
spruce and pine. Similarly, in addition to Chauvinistic Aesthetic and the Aesthetics
characterizing environmental acts of as- of Engagement, this model stresses that
pection in general, Tuan's quotation also the natural environment is both natural
describes the act of aspection suitable for and an environment. Unlike the Object
a particular type of environment, perhaps Model and the Landscape Model, it does
best classified as pastoral. For an appro- not assimilate natural objects to art ob-
priate aesthetic appreciation of nature, as jects or natural environments to scenery.
for that of art, classification, as Ziff says, Unlike the Human Chauvinistic Aesthetic
is of the essence.2 1 and the Aesthetics of Engagement, the
The questions of what and how to aes- Natural Environmental Model does not
thetically appreciate the natural environ- reject the general and traditional struc-
ment thus may be answered in the same ture of the aesthetic appreciation of art as
way as parallel questions about art are. a model for the aesthetic appreciation of
The difference is that with natural envi- the natural world. In fact, it directly ap-
ronments, the relevant knowledge is the plies that structure to nature, making
common sense and scientific knowledge only those adjustments necessary for the
that we have discovered about the envi- nature of the natural environment. In do-
ronments in question. Such knowledge ing so, it avoids the absurdity of deeming
yields appropriate boundaries of appreci- the appreciation of nature to be nonaes-
ation, particular foci of aesthetic signifi- thetic while promoting an aesthetic ap-
cance, and relevant acts of aspection. If preciation of nature for what it is and the
we must have a knowledge of art forms, qualities it has. Thus, it encourages us not
classifications of works, and artistic tra- to, as Hepburn puts it, "either pay very lit-
ditions in order to appreciate art appro- tle aesthetic heed to natural objects or else
priately and aesthetically, then we must heed them in the wrong way," not to

127
NATURE AND AESTHETIC VALUE

"look-and of course look in vain-for tied to the idea of wilderness preservation


what can be found and enjoyed only in and to the appreciation of nature often
art." associated with environmentalism. The
Natural Environmental Model is relevant
to positive aesthetics because the model
Further Ramifications provides the theoretical underpinnings of
this mode of appreciation. When nature
The Natural Environmental Model ac- is aesthetically appreciated in terms of a
knowledges Santayana's assessment of knowledge of the natural and environ-
the natural environment as indetermi- mental sciences, positive aesthetic appre-
nate and promiscuous, so rich in diver- ciation is singularly appropriate. On the
sity, suggestion, and vague stimulus that one hand, pristine nature-nature in its
it must be composed in order to be ap- natural state-is an aesthetic ideal. On
preciated. Moreover, the Natural Envi- the other hand, science increasingly finds,
ronmental Model suggests that to achieve or at least appears to find, qualities such
appropriate aesthetic appreciation or, as as unity, order, and harmony in nature,
Santayana says, to find nature beautiful, and when it is appreciated in light of such
the composition must be in terms of knowledge, nature itself appears even
common sense and scientific knowledge. more beautiful. 25
In addition to answering the central Other ramifications of the Natural En-
problem of the aesthetics of nature, this vironmental Model are more clearly envi-
suggestion has other ramifications. ronmental and ethical. As noted, the
Some of these ramifications concern traditional art-based models and, by im-
what is called applied aesthetics, specifi- plication, other aesthetic approaches, are
cally the popular appreciation of nature frequently condemned as totally anthro-
as practiced not only by tourists but also pocentric, as not only antinatural but also
by each of us in our daily pursuits. As arrogantly disdainful of environments not
noted, such appreciation is frequently conforming to artistic ideals. The source
based on art appreciation models, espe- of these environmental and ethical con-
cially the Landscape Model. The pictur- cerns is that art-based approaches do not
esque, however, does not have a monopoly encourage an appreciation of nature for
on applied aesthetic appreciation but what it is and the qualities it has. Con-
competes with a somewhat different ap- versely, the Natural Environmental Model
proach. This other mode of appreciation bases aesthetic appreciation on a scientific
has grown out of the tradition of such view of what nature is and the qualities it
thinkers as Henry David Thoreau and has. The Natural Environmental Model
achieved its paradigmatic realization in thereby gives the aesthetic appreciation of
the thought of John Muir. For Muir, ev- nature a degree of objectivity that helps re-
erything in the natural world, all nature fute environmental and moral criticisms,
and especially all wild nature, is aestheti- such as that of anthropocentrism. More-
cally beautiful, and ugliness exists only over, the possibility of an objective basis
where nature has been despoiled by hu- for an aesthetic appreciation of nature also
man intrusion. 24 This conception, which holds out the promise of some direct prac-
may be called positive aesthetics, is closely tical relevance in a world increasingly en-

128
AESTHETIC APPRECIATION OF THE NATURAL ENVIRONMENT

gaged in environmental assessment. 26 that expands the traditional conception


Those people making such assessments, of the discipline, which narrowly identi-
although typically not worried about an- fies aesthetics with the philosophy of art.
thropocentrism, are frequently reluctant Instead of simply an aesthetics of art, the
to acknowledge the relevance and impor- result is a more universal aesthetics-an
tance of aesthetic considerations, regard- aesthetics frequently termed environmen-
ing them, at worst, as subjective whims or, tal aesthetics.
at best, as relativistic, transient, and soft- Finally, by initiating a more universal
headed cultural and artistic ideals. Recog- and object-centered aesthetics, the Natural
nizing that an aesthetic appreciation of Environmental Model helps align aesthet-
nature has scientific underpinnings helps ics with other areas of philosophy, such as
dispelsuch doubts. ethics, epistemology, and philosophy of
Another consequence concerns the mind, which are increasingly rejecting ar-
discipline of aesthetics itself. In rejecting chaic, inappropriate models in favor of a
artistic models in favor of a dependence dependence on knowledge relevant to the
on a common sense and scientific knowl- particular phenomena in question. For ex-
edge of nature, the Natural Environmen- ample, environmental aesthetics parallels
talModel provides a blueprint for aesthetic environmental ethics in the latter's rejec-
appreciation in general. This model sug- tion of anthropocentric models for the
gests that an aesthetic appreciation of moral assessment of the natural world and
anything, be it people or pets, farmyards the replacement of such models with para-
or neighborhoods, shoes or shopping digms drawn from the environmental and
malls, must be centered on and driven by natural sciences.
the object of appreciation itself.27 In all In light of these various ramifications,
such cases, what is appropriate is not an it becomes clear that the challenge implicit
imposition of artistic ideals but, rather, in Santayana's remarks-that we confront
appreciation that is dependent on and a natural world that allows great liberty in
guided by knowledge, scientific or other- selecting, emphasizing, and grouping and
wise,that is relevant to the thing in ques- that we must therefore compose it in order
tion.28 This turn away from artistic to appropriately aesthetically experience
preconceptions and toward the true na- it-holds out an invitation not simply to
ture of objects of appreciation points the find the natural world beautiful but also
way to a general aesthetics, an aesthetics to appreciate its true nature.

NOTES

This essay is a substantially modified ver- 2.Paul Ziff, "Reasons in Art Criticism,"
sionof "Appreciation and the Natural Envi- in Philosophical Turnings: Essays in Concep-
ronment," Journal of Aesthetics and Art tual Appreciation (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell
Criticism37 (1979): 267- 76. University Press, 1966), p. 71. I examine
1. George Santayana, The Sense of Beauty: Ziff's notion of appreciation more fully in
Beingthe Outline of an Aesthetic Theory (1896) "Critical Notice of Ziff, Antiaesthetics: An
(NewYork:Collier,1961), p. 99. Appreciation of the Cow with the Subtile

129
NATURE AND AESTHETIC VALUE

Nose," Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 suggests that aesthetic appreciation of nature


(1987):919-33. is enhanced by "realizing" that an object is
3. Ziff, "Reasons in Art Criticism," p. 71. what it is and has the qualities it has (see pp.
4. Santayana, The Sense of Beauty, p. 100. 60-65). For a more substantial version of
5. See Arthur Danto, "The Artworld," Jour- this essay, see Ronald W. Hepburn, "Co n-
nal of Philosophy 61 (1964):571-84. On issues temporary Aesthetics and the Neglect of
about turning objects into art, see the institu- Natural Beauty," in British Analytical Philos-
tional theory of art; the classic account is ophy, ed. Bernard Williams and Alan Monte-
George Dickie, Art and the Aesthetic: An Insti- fiore (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul,
tutional Analysis (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell Uni- 1966); repr. in R. W. Hepburn, Wonder and
versity Press, 1974). Other Essays (Edinburgh: Edinburgh Uni-
6. See Yi-Fu Tuan, Topophilia: A Study of versity Press, 1984).
Environmental Perception, Attitudes, and Val- 13. Robert Elliot, "Faking Nature," Inquiry
ues (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 25 (1982):90. The label is from Don Manni-
1974), pp. 132-33. son, "A Prolegomenon to a Human Chauvin-
7. For a good brief discussion, see Ronald istic Aesthetic," in Environmental Philosophy,
Rees, "The Scenery Cult: Changi ng Land- ed. D. Mannison, M. McRobbie, and R. Rout-
scape Tastes over Three Centuries," Landscape ley (Canberra: Australian National Univer-
19 (1975):39-47. sity, 1980). I examine the Human Chauvinistic
8. Thomas West, Guide to the Lakes (1778), Aesthetic more fully in "Nature and Positive
quoted in J. T. Ogden, "From Spatial to Aes- Aesthetics," Environmental Ethics 6 (1984):s-
thetic Distance in the Eighteenth Century," 34 (editors' note: see selection 13 of this vol-
Journal of the Histor y of Ideas 35 (1974):66-67. ume). Elliot has now rejected this position in
For an introduction to picturesque apprecia- favor of one closer to what is called positive
tion, see Malcolm Andrews, The Search for the aesthetics; see Robert Elliot, Faking Nature:
Picturesque (Stanford, Calif .: Stanford Uni- The Ethics of Environmental Restoration (Lon-
versity Press, 1989). don: Routledge, 1997).
9. Ronald Rees, "The Taste for Mountain 14. Arnold Berleant, "The Aesthetics of Art
Scenery," History Today 25 (1975):)12. and Nature, " in Aesthetics of Environment
10. Paul Shepard, The Tender Carnivore (Philadelphia: Temple University Press , 1992),
and the Sacred Game (New York: Scribner, pp. 169-70 (emphasis in original). See also
1973), pp. 147- 48. Berleant's Living in the Landscape: Toward an
11. Rees, "Mountain Scenery," p. 312. Ethi- Aesthetics of Environment (Lawrence: Univer-
cal concerns are also expressed by Tuan, sity Press of Kansas, 1997); and Aesthetics and
Topophilia, chap. 8; and by R. A. Smith and C. Environment: Variations on a Theme (Alder-
M. Smith, "Aesthetics and Environmenta l shot: Ashgate, 2005). For a somewhat related
Education," Journal of Aesthetic Education 4 position, see Noel Carroll, "O n Being Moved
(1970):125-40. Smith and Smith find "a spe- by Nature : Between Religion and Natural
cial form of arrogance in experiencing nature History," in Landscape, Natural Beauty and
strict ly in the categories of art ." the Arts, ed. S. Kemal and I. Gaskell (Ca m-
12. Ronald W. Hepburn, "Aesthetic Ap- bridge : Cambridge University Press, 1993),
preciation of Nature," in Aesthetics and the pp. 244-66 (editors' note: see selection 11 of
Mod ern World, ed. H. Osborne (London: this volume). I consider this view in "Nature,
Thames & Hudson, 1968), p. 53. Hepburn Aesthetic Appreciation, and Knowledge,"

130
AESTHETIC APPRECIATION OF THE NATURAL ENVIRONMENT

journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53 manac, ed. J. B. Callicott (Madison: Univer-
(1995):393-400. sity of Wisconsin Press, 1987), pp. 157-71. See
15. For a powerful statement of the ortho- also his updated version of this essay in Chris-
doxview, see Paul Ziff, "Anything Viewed," in topher Key Chapp le, ed., EcologicalProspects:
Antiaesthetics:An Appreciation of the Cow Scientific, Religious, and Aesthetic Perspectives
with the Subtile Nose (Dordrecht: Reidel, (Albany : State University of New York Press,
1984),pp. 129-39. 1994), pp. 169-83 (editors' note: see selection 7
16. I discuss problems with the Aesthetics of this volume).
of Engagement in "Aesthetics and Engage- 23. The centrality of scientific knowledge
ment," British Journal of Aesthetics 33 in aesthetic appreciation of nature is chal-
(1993):220-27; and "Beyond the Aesthetic," lenged in some recent essays such as Stan
Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 52 Godlovitch, "Icebreakers: Environmentalism
(1994):239-41. and Natural Aesthetics," Journal of Applied
17.Tuan, Topophilia, p. 96. Philosophy 11 (1994):15-30 (editors' note: see
18. William James, The Principles of Psy- selection 9 of this volume); Emily Brady,
chology(1890) (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard "Imagination and the Aesthetic Appreciation
UniversityPress, 1981), p. 462. of Nature," Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criti-
19. This point suggests further problems cism 56 (1998):139- 47; and Thomas Heyd,
forthe Landscape Model insofar as that model "Aesthetic Appreciation and the Many Stories
encourages formalistic aesthetic appreciation. About Nature," British Journal of Aesthetics 41
If boundaries and foci do not exist in nature (2001):125-37. However, it is also defended;
itself,it is difficult to see how it can have sig- see, for example, Holmes Rolston, "Does Aes-
nificant formal aesthetic properties. I pursue thetic Appreciation of Landscapes Need to Be
this idea in "Formal Qualities and the Natu- Science-Based? " British Journal of Aesthetics
ral Environment," Journal of Aesthetic Educa- 35 (1995):)74-86; and Marcia Eaton, "Fact and
tion13 (1979):99-114. Fiction in the Aesthetic Appreciation of Na-
20. See John Dewey, Art as Experience ture, " Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
(1934) (New York: Putnam, 1958), especially 56 (1998):149 - 56. A number of essays address-
chap.3, "Having an Experience," pp. 35-57. ing this issue are collected in Allen Carlson
21. For an account of the role of classifica- and Arnold Berleant, eds., The Aesthetics of
tion in art appreciation, see Kendall Walton, Natural Environments (Peterborough, Ont.:
"Categories of Art," Philosophical Review 79 Broadview Press, 2004).
(1970):334-67. I develop a Walton-like view 24. John Muir's view is well exemplified in
for nature appreciation in "Nature, Aesthetic his Atlantic Monthly essays collected in Our
Judgment, and Objectivity" Journal of Aes- National Parks (Boston: Houghton Mifflin ,
theticsand Art Criticism 40 (1981):15-27 . 1916). See also works such as his A Thousand-
22. Perhaps the paradigmatic exemplifica- Mile Walk to the Gulf (Boston: Houghton Mif-
tion of aesthetic appreciation enhanced by flin, 1916); and The Mountains of California
natural science is Aldo Leopold's A Sand (New York: Century Company, 1894) (editors'
CountyAlmanac (Oxford: Oxford University note: see selection 4 of this volum e). For an
Press, 1949) (editors' note: see selection 6 of introduction to his aesthetic views, see P. Ter-
this volume). Leopold's aesthetic views are rie, "John Muir on Mount Ritter: A New Wil-
elaborated in J. Baird Callicott, "The Land derness Aesthetic, " Pacific Historian 31
Aesthetic," Companion to A Sand County Al- (1987):135-44.

131
NATURE AND AESTHETIC VALUE

25. I consider positive aesthetics and its re- cultural Landscapes," Journal of Aesthetics
lationship to the rise of science in "Nature and Art Criticism 43 (1985) :301-12; "Existence,
and Positive Aesthetics" (editors' note: for a Location, and Function: The Appreciation of
full discussion of positive aesthetics, see part Architecture," in Philosophy and Architecture,
3 of this volume). ed. M. Mitias (Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1994), pp.
26. I discuss objectivity in appreciation of 141-64; and "On Aesthetically Appreciating
nature in "Nature, Aesthetic Judgment, and Human Environments," Philosophy and Ge-
Objectivity," and "On the Possibility of Quan- ography 4 (2001):9-24.
tifying Scenic Beauty," Landscape Planning 4 28. I develop the idea of an object-centered
(1977):131-72. aesthetics in "Appreciating Art and Appreci-
27. I apply these ideas to other kinds of ating Nature," Landscape, Natural Beauty, and
cases in, for example, "On Appreciating Agri- the Arts, pp. 199-227.

132

Anda mungkin juga menyukai