Anda di halaman 1dari 6

See

discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/11557970

Quantum Discord: A Measure of the


Quantumness of Correlations

Article in Physical Review Letters · February 2002


DOI: 10.1103/PhysRevLett.88.017901 · Source: PubMed

CITATIONS READS

1,856 448

2 authors, including:

H. Ollivier
Manifold
18 PUBLICATIONS 2,539 CITATIONS

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

Modern Quantum Error Correction View project

All content following this page was uploaded by H. Ollivier on 04 August 2016.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


Quantum discord: A measure of the quantumness of correlations

Harold Ollivier and Wojciech H. Zurek


Theoretical Division T-6, MS B288, LANL, Los Alamos, NM 87545.

Two classically identical expressions for the mutual information generally differ when the systems
involved are quantum. This difference defines the quantum discord. It can be used as a measure of
the quantumness of correlations. Separability of the density matrix describing a pair of systems does
not guarantee vanishing of the discord, thus showing that absence of entanglement does not imply
classicality. We relate this to the quantum superposition principle, and consider the vanishing of
discord as a criterion for the preferred effectively classical states of a system, i.e. the pointer states.

PACS numbers: 03.65.Ta, 03.65.Yz, 03.67.-a


arXiv:quant-ph/0105072v3 31 Oct 2001

The original motivation for the pointer states — states Above PiA correspond to the superselection sectors of the
that are monitored by the environment but do not entan- apparatus, e.g. the record states of its pointer (in our ex-
gle with it, and are therefore stable in spite of the open- ample PiA = |ai i hai |). One implication of this equation
ness of the system — comes from the study of quantum is that — once einselection has forced the apparatus to
measurements [1, 2, 3]. When the quantum apparatus A abide by Eq. (3) — its state can be consulted (measured)
interacts with the system S (pre-measurement), the S– in the basis corresponding to the superselection sectors
A pair becomes entangled. The nature of the resulting PiA leaving ρDS,A unchanged [5, 8].
quantum correlations makes it impossible to ascribe any Einselection, Eq. (2), obviously decreases correlations
independent reality to, say, the state of the apparatus [4]. between S and A. Yet, in a good measurement, one-
For, a measurement of different observables on the state to-one correlations between the pointer states of the ap-
of the system will force the apparatus into mutually in- paratus and a corresponding set of system states must
compatible pure quantum states. This is a consequence survive. We shall use two classically equivalent formu-
of the basis ambiguity. It is best exhibited by noting that lae for the mutual information to quantify the quantum
the S–A state after the pre-measurement, and the classical strength of the correlations present in
a joint density matrix ρS,A , and study the difference be-
P
X
|ψS,A i = αi |si i |ai i (1) tween these two as a measure of the quantum excess of
i correlations — the quantum discord — in ρS,A .
Mutual Information — In classical information theory
is typically entangled. One can rewrite it in a differ- [11] the entropy, H(X ), describes
ent basis of, e.g. the system, and one-to-one correlation Pthe ignorance about a
random variable X , H(X ) = − x pX =x Log pX =x . The
with a corresponding set of pure, but not necessarily or- correlation between two random variables X and Y is
thogonal, states of the apparatus will remain. Thus, it measured by the mutual information:
is obviously impossible to maintain that before the mea-
surements the apparatus had a an unknown but real (i.e., J (X : Y) = H(X ) − H(X |Y), (4)
existing independently of the system) quantum state. P
where H(X |Y) = y pY=y H(X |Y = y) is the conditional
Decoherence leads to environment-induced superselec- entropy of X given Y. All the probability distributions
tion (einselection) which singles out the pointer states are derived from the joint one, pX ,Y :
and thus removes quantum excess of correlation respon-
sible for the basis ambiguity. The density matrix of
X X
pX = pX ,Y=y , pY = pX =x,Y (5)
the decohering quantum apparatus loses its off-diagonal y x
terms as a result of the interaction with the environment pX |Y=y = pX ,Y=y /pY=y (Bayes rule) (6)
[5, 6, 7, 8]:
Hence, the mutual information measures the average de-
P P
ρP
S,A = |ψS,A i hψS,A |
crease of entropy on X when Y is found out. Using
X the Bayes rule, Eq. (6), one can show that H(X |Y) =
→ |αi |2 |si i hsi | ⊗ |ai i hai | = ρD
S,A . (2) H(X , Y) − H(Y). This leads to another classically equiv-
i
alent expression for the mutual information:
Above hai | aj i = δi,j following the ideal einselection pro- I(X : Y) = H(X ) + H(Y) − H(X , Y). (7)
cess, which transforms a pure ρP D
S,A into a decohered ρS,A
satisfying the superselection identity [9, 10]: One would like to generalize the concept of mutual in-
formation to quantum systems. One route to this goal,
motivated by discussions of quantum information pro-
X
ρD
S,A = PiA ρD A
S,A Pi . (3)
i cessing, has been put forward [12, 13]. We shall pursue
2

a different strategy, using Eqs. (4) and (7). We start by The quantum discord is asymmetric under the change
defining I and J for a pair of quantum systems. S ↔ A since the definition of the conditional entropy
I — All the ingredients involved in the definition of I H(S|{ΠA j }) involves a measurement on one end (in our
are easily generalized to deal with arbitrary quantum sys- case the apparatus A), that allows the observer to infer
tems by replacing the classical probability distributions the state of S. This typically involves an increase of
by the appropriate density matrices ρS , ρA and ρS,A and entropy. Hence H(S|{ΠA j }) ≥ H(S, A) − H(A), which
the Shannon entropy by the von Neumann entropy, e.g. implies that for any measurement {ΠA j },
H(S) = H(ρS ) = −TrS ρS Log ρS :
δ(S : A){ΠA
j }
≥ 0. (14)
I(S : A) = H(S) + H(A) − H(S, A). (8)
The proofs are postponed to the end of this letter.
In this formula, H(S) + H(A) represents the uncer- We shall be usually concerned about the set {ΠA j } that
tainty of S and A treated separately, and H(S, A) is minimizes the discord given a certain ρS,A . Minimizing
the uncertainty about the combined system described the discord over the possible measurements on A corre-
by ρS,A . However, in contrast with the classical case, sponds to finding the measurement that disturbs least
extracting all information potentially present in a com- the overall quantum state and that, at the same time, al-
bined quantum system described by ρS,A will, in general, lows one to extract the most information about S. Deco-
require a measurement on the combined Hilbert space herence picks out a set of stable states and converts their
HS,A = HS ⊗ HA . The quantum version of I has been possible superpositions into mixtures, Eq. (2). Moreover,
used some years ago to study entanglement [14], and sub- an unread measurement {ΠA j } on the apparatus has an
sequently rediscovered [15]. effect analogous to einselection in the corresponding ba-
J — The generalization of this expression is not as sis through the reduction postulate [1]. Hence it is rather
automatic as for I, since the conditional entropy H(S|A) natural to expect that when the set {ΠA j } corresponds to
requires us to specify the state of S given the state of A. the superselection sectors {PiA } of Eq. (3), there would
Such statement in quantum theory is ambiguous until be no extra increase of entropy:
the to-be-measured set of states A is selected. We focus
on perfect measurements of A defined by a set of one-
X
ρS,A = ΠA A
j ρS,A Πj ⇒ δ(S : A){ΠA j }
= 0. (15)
dimensional projectors {ΠA j }. The label j distinguishes j
different outcomes of this measurement.
The state of S, after the outcome corresponding to ΠA j
Thus, following einselection, the information can be ex-
has been detected, is tracted from S–A with a local measurement on A with-
out disturbing the overall state. The state of S can be
ρS|ΠA
j
= ΠA A A
j ρS,A Πj /TrS,A Πj ρS,A , (9) inferred from the outcome of the measurement on A only.
The converse of Eq. (15) is also true:
with probability pj = TrS,A ΠA j ρS,A . H(ρS|ΠAj
) is the X
missing information about S. The entropies H(ρS|ΠA ), δ(S : A){ΠA
j } = 0 ⇒ ρ S,A = ΠA A
j ρS,A Πj . (16)
j
j
weighted by probabilities, pj , yield to the conditional en-
tropy of S given the complete measurement {ΠA j } on A, Hence, a vanishing discord can be considered as an in-
X dicator of the superselection rule, or — in the case of
H(S|{ΠA
j }) = pj H(ρS|ΠA
j
). (10) interest — its value is a measure of the efficiency of eins-
j election. When δ is large for any set of projectors {ΠA j },
a lot of information is missed and destroyed by any mea-
This leads to the following quantum generalization of J :
surement on the apparatus alone, but when δ is small
J (S : A){ΠA = H(S) − H(S|{ΠA
j }). (11) almost all the information about S that exists in the S–
j }
A correlations is locally recoverable from the state of the
This quantity represents the information gained about apparatus.
the system S as a result of the measurement {ΠAj }.
The quantum discord can be illustrated in a simple
Quantum discord — The two classically identical ex- model of measurement.
√ Let us assume the initial state
pressions for the mutual information, Eqs. (4) and (7), of S is (|0i + |1i)/ 2. The pre-measurement is a c-not
P √
differ in a quantum case [16]. The quantum discord is gate yielding |ψS,A i = (|00i + |11i)/ 2. If |0i and |1i
this difference, of A are pointer states, partial decoherence will suppress
off-diagonal terms of the density matrix:
δ(S : A){ΠA
j }
= I(S : A) − J (S : A){ΠA
j }
(12)
1
= H(A) − H(S, A) + H(S|{ΠA
j }).(13)
ρS,A = (|00i h00| + |11i h11|)
2
z
It depends both on ρS,A and on the projectors {ΠA + (|00i h11| + |11i h00|) , (17)
j }. 2
3

with 0 ≤ z < 1. Fig. 1 shows δ for various values of z reveal all of the information in S–A, i.e. the resulting
and various bases of measurement parametrized by θ, state of the pair will be pure. Moreover this procedure
can be accomplished without perturbing the ρS,A for an-
{cos(θ) |0i + eiφ sin θ |1i , e−iφ sin θ |0i − cos θ |1i }, (18) other observer, a bystande! r not aware of the outcomes.
S
Thus, for each outcome j there exist a set {πj,k } of
with φ = 1rad. Only in the case of complete einselec- conditional one dimensional projectors such that
tion (z = 0) there exist a basis for which discord dis- XX
S
appears. The corresponding basis of measurement is ρS,A = πj,k ΠA A S
j ρS,A Πj πj,k , (21)
{|0i , |1i} (θ = 0), i.e. it must be carried out in the j k
pointer basis.
S
and πj,k ΠA A S
j ρS,A Πj πj,k is pure for any j and k. Above,
S
the sets {πj,k } for different j will not coincide in gen-
S
eral ({πj,k } is a function of j) and do not need to com-
mute. Classical information is locally accessible, and can
be obtained without perturbing the state of the system:
One can interrogate just one part of a composite system
and discover its state while leaving the overall density
matrix (as perceived by observers that do not have ac-
cess to the measurement outcome) unaltered. A general
separable ρS,A does not allow for such insensitivity to
measurements: Information can be extracted from the
apparatus but only at a price of perturbing ρS,A , even
when this density matrix is separable. However, when
discord disappears, such insensitivity (which may be the
defining feature of “classical reality”, as it allowes ac-
quisition of information without perturbation of the un-
derlying state) becomes possible for correlated quantum
systems. This quantum character of separable density
FIG. 1: Discord for the states given in Eq. (17), with the matrices with non zero discord is a consequence of the
measurement basis defined as in Eq. (18). superposition principle for A, since more than one basis
n Eo
(i)
aj for the apparatus is needed in Eq. (20) in order
Classical aspect of quantum correlations — Separabil- j
ity has been often regarded as synonymous of classicality. to warrant a non vanishing discord.
The temptation that leads one to this conclusion starts The difference between separability and vanishing dis-
with an observation that — by definition — a separable cord can be illustrated by a specific example. Fig. 2
density matrix is a mixture of density matrices shows discord for a Werner state ρS,A = 1−z4 1 + z |ψi hψ|

X with |ψi = (|00i + |11i)/ 2. It can be seen that dis-
ρS,A = pi ρiS,A (19) cord is greater than 0 in any basis when z > 0, which
i contrasts with the well-known separability of such states
when z < 1/3.
that have explicit product eigenstates, Conclusion — The quantum discord is a measure of
X (i) (i) E (i) E D (i) D (i) the information that cannot be extracted by the reading
ρiS,A = pj sj aj aj sj (20) of the state of the apparatus (i.e. without joint mea-
j surements). Hence the quantum discord is a good in-
dicator of the quantum nature of the correlations. The
and hence classical correlations. One might have thought
pointer states obtained by minimizing the quantum dis-
that mixing such obviously classical density matrices can-
cord over the possible measurements should coincide with
not bring in anything quantum: After all, it involves only
the ones obtained with the predictability sieve criterion
loss of information — forgetting of the label i in ρiS,A .
[5, 7], hence showing that the accessible information re-
Yet this is not the case. One symptom of the quantum-
mains in the most stable pointer states.
ness of a separable ρS,A with non-zero discord is imme-
diately apparent: Unless there exists a complete set of —
projectors {ΠA j } for which δ(S : A){ΠAj }
= 0, ρS,A is
perturbed by all local measurements. By contrast, when Proposition 1. H(S|{ΠA D D
j }) = H(ρS,A ) − H(ρA ), with
P A A
δ(S : A){ΠA = 0, then the measurement {ΠA j } on A,
ρD
S,A = j Πj ρS,A Πj .
j }
and an appropriate conditional measurement (i.e. con- Proof 1. ρDS,A is block-diagonal. The j-th block equals
ditioned by the outcome of the measurement on A) will pj ρS|ΠA
j
. By doing calculations block by block one has:
4

For measurement purposes, one may adopt

ρS|ΠA
j
= TrA ΠA A
j ρS,A /TrS,A Πj ρS,A ,

Separable Non−separable since all the correlations (quantum as well as classical)


δ between S and the subspace of the apparatus defined by
ΠAj are not observed. Proposition 1 no longer holds, but
using the same techniques we still have δ(S : A){ΠAj }
≥0
P A A
and if δ(S : A){ΠAj }
= 0, then ρ S,A = j j S,A j .
Π ρ Π
For decoherence purposes, one may prefer to define J
as H(S) + H(A)D − H(S, A)D . With this definition,
z Proposition 3 is valid. J now represents the average in-
formation, quantum and classical that remains in the pair
FIG. 2: Value of the discord for Werner states 1−z 1+z |ψi hψ|, S–A after a decoherence process leading to einselection
√ 4
with |ψi = (|00i + |11i)/ 2. Discord does not depend on the of the superselection sectors {ΠA j }.
basis of measurement in this case because both 1 and |ψi are
This research was supported in part by NSA. Pre-
invariant under rotations.
liminary results were presented at the Newton Institute
in July 1999 by W.H.Z., at the Ushuaia PASI in Oc-
H(ρD
P P tober 2000 by H.O., and described in the proceedings
S,A ) = j H(pj ρS|ΠA ) = j pj H(ρS|ΠA ) −
P A
j
D
j
of the 100th anniversary of Planck’s Constant Meeting
j pj Log pj = H(S|{Πj }) − H(ρA ), which completes [16]. Useful conversations with E. Knill, R. Laflamme, B.
the proof.
Schumacher and L. Viola are gratefully acknowledged.
Proposition 2. δ(S : A){ΠA j }
≥ 0.
Note — After completion of this work, we became
Proof 2. This is a direct consequence of the previous aware of a related work by L. Henderson and V. Ve-
proposition and the concavity of H(S, A) − H(A) [17]. dral (quant-ph/0105028).
Proposition 3. δ(S : A){ΠA j }
= 0 ⇔ ρS,A =
P A A
j Πj ρS,A Πj .
Proof 3. Proposition 1 already shows the converse.
To prove the direct implication we will start with ρS,A
[1] J. von Neumann, “Mathematische Grundlagen der Quan-
and {ΠA j }, a complete set of orthogonal projectors, such tenmechanik” Springer Verlag (1932).
that δ(S : A){ΠA j }
= 0. Without loss of generality, [2] J.A. Wheeler, W.H. Zurek, “Quantum Theory and Mea-
we
P A can write the density matrix of S–A as ρS,A = surements” Princeton University Press (1983).
A [3] A. Peres, “Quantum Theory: Methods and Concepts”
Π ρ
j j S,A j Π + additional terms. If we choose {|si i} a
Kluwer Ac. Pub. (1995).
basis of S, and { ak|j }k a basis of the subspace of A de-

[4] W.H. Zurek, Phys. Rev. D 24 (1981), 1516.
fined by ΠA j , the general form of the additional terms in [5] W.H. Zurek, Prog. Theor. Phys. 89 (1993), 281.
the above formula will be c(si , si′ , ak|j , ak′ |j ′ ) |si i hsi′ | ⊗ [6] D. Guilini, E. Joos, C. Kiefer, J. Kupsch, I.-O. Sta-
ak|j ak′ |j ′ with j 6= j ′ . Suppose that one of those co-


matescu, H.D. Zeh, “Decoherence and the Appearance of
efficients is non-zero. By changing the basis {|si i}i , we a Classical World in Quantum Theory”, Springer Verlag,
can suppose i 6= i′ . We introduce now a new density ma- (1996).
trix ρ̂S,A obtained from ρS,A by removing the preceding [7] J.P. Paz, W.H. Zurek, pp. 533-614 in Les Houches
LXXII, Coherent Atomic Matter Waves, R. Kaiser, C.
matrix element and its complex conjugate. This ensures Westbrook, and F. David, Eds., Springer Verlag (2001).
that ρ̂S,A is associated with a physical state. This state [8] W.H. Zurek, quant-ph/0105127, “Decoherence, ein-
satisfies H(ρ̂S,A ) > H(ρS,A ) and H(ρ̂A ) = H(ρA). The selection, and the quantum origins of the classical”, sub-
concavity of H(S, A) − H(A) implies inequalities; mitted to Rev. Mod. Phys.
[9] N. N. Bogolubov, A. A. Logunov, A. I. Oksak, and I. T.
H(ρS,A ) − H(ρA ) < H(ρ̂S,A ) − H(ρ̂A ), Todorov, General Principles of Quantum Field Theory
(Kluver, Dordrecht, 1990).
H(ρ̂S,A ) − H(ρ̂A ) ≤ H(ρD D
S,A ) − H(ρA ). [10] D. Giulini, quant-ph/0010090.
[11] T.M. Cover, J.A. Thomas, “Elements of Information
Then δ(S : A){ΠA j }
< 0, which contradicts our primary Theory” Ed. J. Wiley (1991).
assumption and proves our last result. [12] B. Schumacher, M.A. Nielsen. Phys. Rev. A 54 (1996),
2629.
Remark. We defined J with the help of a measure-
[13] N.J. Cerf, C. Adami, Phys. Rev. Lett, 79 (1997), 5194.
ment associated with one-dimensional projectors. One [14] W.H. Zurek, in Quantum optics, experimental gravita-
can be interested in looking at multi-dimensional pro- tion and measurement theory (1983), 87.
jective measurements. Depending on the context, two [15] S.M. Barnett, S.J.D. Phoenix, Phys. Rev. A 40 (1989),
different generalization can be used. 2404.
5

[16] W.H. Zurek, Ann. Phys. 9 (2000), 855.


[17] A. Wehrl, Rev. Mod. Phys. 50 (1978), 221.

View publication stats

Anda mungkin juga menyukai