Anda di halaman 1dari 16

Ethical Issues in Pediatric

Anesthesiology
DAVID B. WAISEL
5 
Informed Consent Clinical and Academic Practice Issues
The Informed Consent Process Pediatric Research
Special Situations in Pediatric Informed Consent Managing Potential Conflicts of Interest
The Impaired Parent Physician Obligations, Advocacy, and Good Citizenship
End-of-Life Issues The Ethics Consultation Service
Forgoing Potentially Life-sustaining Treatment
Improving Communication in Pediatric Intensive Care Units
Organ Donation after Cardiac Death

CLINICIANS MUST TAKE SERIOUSLY “the experience, perspective, and tion in decision making should increase, depending on both their
power of children.”1 Clinicians should treat every child and family maturity and the consequences involved in the decision.
with the grace and consideration with which they would want School-age children are developing decision-making capacity,
their own child and family treated. Taking the experience of children so anesthesiologists should seek both informed permission from
seriously means involving interested children in developmentally the parent and assent and participatory decision making from the
appropriate decision making. Clinicians should not solicit a child’s child. School-age children are capable of using logic and reason
views without intending to consider them. Pro forma solicitations and are able to define and relate multiple aspects of a situation.
are harmful. Such situations may include whether to sedate a 6-year-old before
Treating every child like your own means taking time to allow an inhalation induction, whether to use an inhalation or intra-
premedication to work, even if it leads to criticism for a delayed venous induction of anesthesia in an 8-year-old, and whether to
anesthesia start time. It means rigorously following sterile practice insert an epidural in a 12-year-old.
protocols for central lines. It means patiently explaining anesthetic Many adolescents older than 14 years of age have the ability
options to the parents as many times as needed. to use abstract thought, apply complex reasoning, foresee outcomes,
Bioethics helps motivated physicians to identify and resolve simultaneously evaluate multiple options, and understand concepts
ethical dilemmas. Solving ethical dilemmas is not solely a matter such as probability. Although some adolescents have cognitive
of being moral. Consider a child with an upper airway respiratory abilities similar to those of adults, adolescents may be hindered
infection. Usually the surgery would be postponed, but suppose by insufficient psychosocial and emotional development and
the child has missed two previous surgical dates because of an they may not have developed a reasonably stable set of values.2
unstable home situation. While the clinician is explaining the Anesthesiologists should try to fulfill the ethical requirements of
risks of proceeding, the mother distractedly requests to proceed consent while obtaining assent. Situations involving these aspects
with surgery because “we’re already here.” The clinician has to include obtaining consent from a 16-year-old for a sedated thoracic
determine what is in the child’s best interest by balancing the epidural placement for a pectus repair.
risks of proceeding with those of not proceeding, the duty to
ensure that the child receives necessary health care, the weight Informed Permission, the Best Interest Standard and the
to be given to the mother’s consent to proceed, and the duty to Harm Threshold Standard
“do no harm.” Mindful clinicians will seek to identify lurking Parents have traditionally acted as the surrogate decision makers
conflicts of interest in considering whether to proceed. for their children, and legally they give consent. However, surrogate
consent does not fulfill the spirit of consent, which is based on
obtaining an individualized autonomous decision from the patient
Informed Consent receiving the treatment. The AAP has suggested that the proper
The American Academy of Pediatrics (AAP) bases pediatric informed role for the surrogate decision maker is to provide informed permis-
consent on assent, informed permission, and the best interest sion.1 Informed permission has the same requirements as informed
standard.1 consent, but it recognizes that the doctrine of informed consent
cannot apply.
THE INFORMED CONSENT PROCESS The best interest standard requires decision makers to select the
Assent: The Role of the Patient objectively best care. It acknowledges that the cornerstone of
Although most children cannot legally consent to medical care, informed consent, the right to self-determination, is inapplicable
children should share in decision making to the extent that their when it is impossible to know or surmise from previous interactions
development permits (Table 5.1). As children grow older, participa- a child’s likely preference. Using this standard requires determining

69
70 A Practice of Anesthesia for Infants and Children

TABLE 5.1 Graduated Involvement of Minors in Medical is one of the “best” options. This harm threshold is a standard
Decision Makinga similar to the one in assessing for child maltreatment. Whether
this concept of harm threshold is a new cognitive approach or is
Age Decision-Making Capacity Techniques already used in determining best interest depends in large part
<6 years None Best interests about how the borders of acceptable decision making are estab-
standard lished; some clinicians may use the harm threshold in determining
6–12 years Developing Informed permission acceptable decision making and others may not.4–8
Informed assent The harm threshold standard needs further clarification. It may
13–18 years Mostly developed Informed assent not help clarify the best interest standard and it may not be useful
Informed permission in court, given the inconsistency in how courts assess cases.9,10
Mature minor Developed, as legally Informed consent Nonetheless, at the very least, it provides another conceptual way
determined by a judge, for a of evaluating whether a treatment is outside acceptable boundaries.
specific decision. Although
particulars vary by state, the Disclosure
mature minor doctrine in
The “reasonable person” standard—the legal standard for most of
general requires adolescents
the United States, Canada, and other countries—requires that the
to be at least 14 years old
and tends to permit information disclosed be sufficient to satisfy a hypothetical reason-
decisions of lesser risk. able person. This standard does not define exactly what information
Emancipated Developed as determined by Informed consent should be given, and it does not take into account the patient’s
minor statutes defining eligible desires and needs. The “subjective person” standard suggests that
situations (e.g., being informed consent should be matched to the wants and needs of
married, in the military, the decision makers. Although this patient-centered consent better
economically independent). fulfills the spirit of informed consent, its greater ambiguity makes
a it difficult to use as a legal standard.
This broad outline should be viewed as a guide. Specific circumstances should be
taken into consideration. Rather than rely on a rote informed consent process, anesthe-
siologists should seek to satisfy the needs of the decision makers
by meeting their information and decision-making needs. Patients
and surrogates differ in the extent to which they prefer to receive
(1) who will make the decision and (2) what is the best care. The information and to participate in decision making.11,12 In general,
difficulties arise in assuming that there is always one best choice, 10% to 15% of patients may prefer less information than their
because if there is, it should not matter who makes the decision. peers. Overall, most patients want some form of shared decision
In our society, acceptable decision making is broadly defined. making.12
Parents capable of participating in the decision-making process Anesthesiologists should inform families about matters that
are the appropriate primary decision makers because of society’s the anesthesiologist feels must be communicated and about options
respect for the concept of the family and the assumption that that affect the perioperative experience (e.g., regional versus general
parents care greatly for their children. Although a child’s preferences anesthesia)13 and then ask whether the decision makers wish to
cannot be known, it is reasonable to assume that because children know more. By being attentive to the words and actions of the
will incorporate some of the parents’ values as they mature, parental decision makers, anesthesiologists can tailor the process. It is rare
values are a good first approximation for the child’s future values. to be found liable for informed consent malpractice issues. The
A few have questioned the presumption that parents are the best standard for being liable is that there is a duty, a breach of that
decision makers.3 Objections center on the legitimacy of the duty, and a harm directly related to the breach of the duty. Liability
parents’ knowledge of the preferences of the child’s future self. in informed consent requires that the information not shared
Although these concerns are theoretically interesting and help would have affected the patient’s choices. Forming a bond with
clinicians understand the complexities of the best interest standard, the parents is more effective in reducing malpractice lawsuits.14
the standard is that parents have extensive leeway in determining Performing patient-centered informed consent often requires
what is in their child’s best interest. communication of the anesthesiologist’s opinion along with an
The best interest of a child can be defined by what choices explanation of the supporting reasons. With this information, the
fall outside the range of acceptable decision making. Criteria to decision makers are better able to determine which anesthetic
make this determination include the extent of harm to the child approach provides the most desired benefits.
from the intervention or its absence, the likelihood of success, Decision makers often overrate the extent of their knowledge
and the overall risk-to-benefit ratio. about risks and benefits.15 We can increase the likelihood of the
The best interest standard can guide treatment among acceptable decision makers having sufficient knowledge by modifying practices.
options and determine the limits of parental decision-making For example, informed consent documents often use poorly format-
authority, but the best interest standard can be indeterminate, ted, dense, incomprehensible text written at too high a reading
particularly for the decision to attempt to limit parental authority. level for most decision makers.16 Straightforward language written
Given the broad reluctance to override parents, limiting parental at an eighth-grade reading level with reader-friendly formatting
authority is a high-stakes decision. permits better understanding and thus better decision making
Some suggest using a harm threshold standard rather than a about risk, benefits, and options.17
best interest standard to determine whether to limit parental Patients may have difficulty understanding quantitative aspects
authority. The standard for whether a decision exceeds the harm of risk. Risks should be presented as absolute data (e.g., occurs
threshold is if a parental decision threatens the health and safety 10% of time) rather than relative data compared with other
of the child, which is a “lower standard” than whether the decision treatments (e.g., decreases the risk by 50%).18,19 Some decision
Ethical Issues in Pediatric Anesthesiology 71

TABLE 5.2 Recommendations for Risk Communication She is now crying in the preoperative area and refusing to cooperate.
to Patients19 Rather than forcibly or surreptitiously sedating her, the anesthesiolo-

1. Consider presenting only the information that is most critical to the


patient’s or parents’ decision making, even at the expense of
gist should discuss her concerns. If she is unable to discuss the
issues, the anesthesiologist should consider removing her from
the area and giving her time to regain composure before read-
5
completeness.
dressing the situation. Simple actions often allow the situation
2. Use language at the eighth-grade level to improve understanding to be resolved. If the withdrawal of assent was in part related to
of written and oral communications.
anxiety, the child may assent to receiving ample premedication
3. Present data using absolute risks and frequencies. before returning to the holding area. Anesthesiologists must obtain
4. Use pictorial recommendations to communicate statistics when her assent before administering the sedation, however, and not
appropriate. simply assume that forceful or surreptitious administration is
5. The order in which risks and benefits are presented may affect risk justified.
perceptions. The last topic presented has more weight in decision
making.
“Doctor, If This Were Your Child, What Would You Do?”
6. Recognize that comparative risk information (e.g., the average Clinicians should respond to requests for advice by using medical
person’s risk) is persuasive as well as informative.
facts to explain how different paths support specific values so
that decision makers can choose the most concordant path.21–23
However, the question, “If this were your child, what would you do?”
makers may understand frequencies better, so it is wise to include can be asked for a number of different reasons, forcing clinicians
both absolute and frequency data. For example, the statement “If to put the question into a broader context. Do not duck this
she has regional anesthesia, she has a 20% chance of postoperative vomiting, question. Not responding to this question may frustrate and confuse
which means 2 of 10 people will have postoperative vomiting, and if she decision makers.
has general anesthesia, she has a 40% chance of postoperative vomiting, For example, parents may be declaring that they are having
which is 4 of 10 people will have postoperative vomiting. That means difficulty comprehending the overwhelming information and need
that 20 more people of 100 will have postoperative vomiting if we use help making a reasonable decision. Perhaps they are actually asking
general anesthesia” is better than “She has a 100% more likely chance what would give their child the best chance of getting better. In
of postoperative vomiting with general anesthesia as compared with regional this situation, clinicians should explain the reasons and values
anesthesia.” Pictorial representations improve understanding. In underlying their personal choice. Parents may be looking for
the above example, a graphic may be a picture of 10 people, with support that they are making the right choice in an untenable
regional anesthesia having 2 people in one color and general situation. Clinicians should answer with their best judgment if
anesthesia having an additional 2 people in a different color, they agree with the family. If they disagree, clinicians should lend
showing the increased risk. support through comments such as “Other parents in the same situation
Risk perceptions may be affected by whether risks or benefits have made the same choice,” or by acknowledging that it is normal
are presented last.19 For example, oncology patients gave more to feel uncertain.22 If the family persists in asking what they should
weight to the last topic discussed, even though risks and benefits do, clinicians may wish to acknowledge that their choice might
were presented in the same conversation.20 Table 5.2 lists recom- have been different. Clinicians should emphasize, however, that
mendations on communications. parental values are more valid than clinician values when choosing
for their own child.
Informed Refusal Parents may be asking for help in making a life-altering decision.
The requirements to achieve an informed refusal of a procedure One approach to this question is to offer a process for answering
are similar to the requirements for informed consent such that the question (e.g., “I would talk with the chaplain”). Clinicians should
decision makers should be substantially well versed about the feel comfortable admitting that they are unable to determine what
risks, benefits, and alternatives before declining. When parents they would do if in the same situation. Honesty reinforces the
refuse what clinicians believe is necessary care for a child who difficulty of the decision for the parents.
cannot participate in the decision making process, clinicians may
invoke the best interest standard or incorporate the harm threshold Disclosure and Apology of Medical Errors
standard. This situation is more complicated when the child Hiding medical errors is indecent and breaches informed consent.24
expresses significant decision-making capacity and refuses nonemer- Fear of consequences, inadequate support, limited trust in the
gent procedures. Anesthesiologists should respect the right of institution, and lack of education prevent physicians from disclosing
children (typically those over the age of 10 years) not to assent and apologizing appropriately.25–28 Forthrightly disclosing medical
to a procedure, and they should not coerce the child to proceed. errors, although upsetting, often strengthens the patient–physician
In children, particularly adolescents, the distinction between relationship.29,30 Learning about a hidden medical error destroys
persuasion and coercion is critical. Persuasion, the act of using trust and rapidly triggers legal action.
argument and reason to influence a patient’s decision, is appropri- Physician apologies or sympathetic comments often are pro-
ate. Coercion, the outright use of a credible threat, manipulation, hibited as legal evidence of wrongdoing, but disclosures of errors
or misleading information, is not. Achieving the child’s assent are permitted as legal evidence.30–32 Apologizing may influence
may necessitate further discussions with the child, parents, and whether patients pursue legal action and whether such action is
other providers, and such discussions may best take place away successful.31,33 Sincere (not pro forma!) apologies and subsequent
from the operating room. redress to prevent future occurrences improves the patient–physician
Consider a 15-year-old who is scheduled for an elective knee relationship, minimizing the likelihood of legal action.
arthroscopy. The day before the procedure, she gave assent and Physicians without expertise in disclosure and apology often
her parents gave informed permission for anesthesia and surgery. botch the process. Disclosure is a process over time. Initial
72 A Practice of Anesthesia for Infants and Children

disclosure should take place as soon as possible after an event not to inform her parents about the pregnancy test.44 Anesthesiolo-
and should center on the medical implications. Do not speculate gists must be careful not to inadvertently inform the parents of
about cause or fault. When disclosing, it is wise to bring along the pregnancy test while postponing anesthesia and surgery. Nor
an appropriate colleague who can help with the disclosure by should anesthesiologists betray the adolescent by saying, “The case
providing psychological support for the patient and family. Soon is postponed. If you want to know why, ask your daughter.” Although
thereafter, a specific, permanent liaison to the family should be such a statement is factually true and within the letter of the law of
identified. The liaison should be available to arrange meetings, confidentially, terse obliqueness scorns the spirit of confidentially.
explain the results of the investigation into the cause of the event, The desire to tell the parents is understandable. But, I would
and describe plans to prevent future events. The liaison should suggest that clinicians who feel that way are too narrowly applying
be trained and experienced in apology and disclosure (e.g., a their own experiences and expectations. Not all parents are wise
colleague in risk management). and gentle, and not all homes are safe and healthy. Confidentiality
An apology expresses regret or sorrow. Sincere apologies fol- statutes specifically address concerns about child abuse in pregnant
lowed by consistent actions are priceless; insincere apologies are adolescents.
costly. It is always appropriate to apologize for the adverse effects The extent to which anesthesiologists should protect the
of an event and although the standard teaching is that physicians adolescent’s confidentiality is debatable. Nonetheless, because
should not assume responsibility for an event before an investiga- the parents have no legal right to that information, I believe that
tion is performed, it seems bizarre to dissemble about clear errors. more active deception, although less desirable, is appropriate if
As an example, after reassuring the parents that their child is necessary. Successful deception avoids initiating diagnostic evalu-
unharmed, I would readily admit that because I had inadvertently ations or treatment and does not unduly worry parents. For
given a muscle relaxant instead of an anticholinesterase, their example, do not attribute the delay to “hearing a new murmur.”
child will require a brief stay in the intensive care unit until ready Vague, unremarkable reasons such as “an oncoming cold” are best.
for tracheal extubation. To evade responsibility (e.g., “Somehow It is rare to condone deception.45,46 Deception should not be
one drug was given when another was intended”) for a clear error undertaken without serious reservations. But, under certain cir-
mocks the apology. cumstances, the obligation to the patient may supersede prohibi-
Different strategies are being tested to improve disclosure and tions on deception. At times, the harms of not deceiving outweigh
apology. An approach called “disclosure, apology, and offer” shows the harms of deceiving.
promise.34 Open disclosure, prompt and fair compensation, and
a vigorous defense of acceptable care leads to a transparency that The Adolescent and Abortion
reduces adversarial relationships, contributes to patient safety, Even though pediatric patients who are pregnant may be statutorily
and curtails legal action and costs.34–36 Success in this program or by practice emancipated, many states require some form of
requires aligning of incentives of the clinician and hospital system. parental involvement, such as parental consent or notification,
Differing incentives, such as in whether to settle or not, lead to before an elective abortion.47 If a state requires parental involve-
distrust and doom the program. ment, the ability of the minor to circumvent this regulation by
seeking relief from a judge, known as judicial bypass, must be
SPECIAL SITUATIONS IN PEDIATRIC INFORMED CONSENT available. Requirements and enforcement of statutes vary from
Confidentially for Adolescents state to state.47,48 The need for parental involvement in a minor’s
The obligation to maintain confidentiality requires clinicians to planned abortion is not always legally straightforward, and it may
protect patient information from unauthorized and unnecessary be best to consult with hospital counsel in determining these
disclosure.37 Confidentiality is necessary for an open flow of issues. Although this is an area in which honorable people disagree,
information.38–40 Clinicians enhance trust by interviewing the note that both the AAP and the American Medical Association
adolescent in private, acknowledging the adolescent’s concerns (AMA) have affirmed these rights.48,49
about confidentiality, and keeping promises. Emancipated and
mature minors have a right to complete confidentiality. For other Children of Jehovah’s Witnesses
adolescents, if maintaining confidentiality entails minimal harm, Jehovah’s Witnesses interpret biblical scripture as prohibiting
clinicians should encourage adolescents to be forthright with transfusion therapy because blood holds the “life force” and anyone
parents but respect their decision not to be. If maintaining who takes blood will be “cut off from his people” and not earn
confidentiality may result in serious harm to the adolescent, clini- eternal salvation.50–52 For adults, it is a “matter of conscience” whether
cians may be ethically justified in notifying the parents. State they accept transfusion products. Adults may refuse potentially
laws vary in their extent of requirements. life-sustaining transfusion therapy because it is assumed they are
making an informed decision about the risks and benefits of
The Pregnant Adolescent transfusion. However, based on the obligations of the state to
Anesthesiologists face confidentially issues when an adolescent protect the interests of incompetent patients, courts have uniformly
has a positive pregnancy test before anesthesia. Given the principles intervened when parents desire to refuse transfusion therapy on
of confidentiality, it is ethically appropriate to inform only the behalf of their children. Based on the mature minor doctrine, older
adolescent.41,42 Because locales may statutorily prohibit sharing adolescents who are able to articulate significant decision-making
pregnancy information with anyone other than the adolescent, capacity and maturity have been permitted to refuse potentially
anesthesiologists must share this information with the adolescent life-sustaining transfusion therapy.53 Most clinicians start considering
without letting the parents know.43 Anesthesiologists should involve this option when the patient is 16, but younger children have been
pediatricians, gynecologists, and social workers with expertise in permitted to refuse potentially life-sustaining transfusion therapy.54
adolescent issues in this discussion. Obtaining informed permission and assent for the care of a
Matters become more complex if the clinicians and adolescent ward of a Jehovah’s Witness should address transfusion therapy.
believe the case should be postponed, and the adolescent chooses Anesthesiologists should clarify which therapy is acceptable.
Ethical Issues in Pediatric Anesthesiology 73

Synthetic colloid solutions, dextran, erythropoietin, desmopressin, THE IMPAIRED PARENT


and preoperative iron are usually acceptable. Note that erythro- Parents may be unable to fulfill surrogate responsibilities because
poietin is available in two forms: lyophilized, and dissolved in
saline with trace concentrations of albumin. Jehovah’s Witnesses
who accept albumin will accept either formulation, whereas those
of acutely impaired judgment, such as being intoxicated.57 Clinicians
have to weigh the benefits of waiting for appropriate legal consent
against what is in the best interest of the child. It may be in the
5
who refuse albumin should be offered the lyophilized formulation. child’s best interest to proceed with a routine procedure in the
Some Jehovah’s Witnesses accept the removal and return of blood situation of an impaired parent who is unable to give legal consent.
in a continuous loop (e.g., cell saver blood). The family should Clinicians may wish to consult legal and risk management col-
understand, however, that in a life-threatening situation, the leagues for guidance.
anesthesiologist will seek a court order authorizing the administra-
tion of life-sustaining blood. When the likelihood of requiring
blood is high or the local judiciary is not very familiar with case
End-of-Life Issues
law for Jehovah’s Witnesses, the anesthesiologist may choose to FORGOING POTENTIALLY LIFE-SUSTAINING TREATMENT
obtain a court order in advance of the operation. Perioperative Limitations on Life-Sustaining Treatment
A common concern is the sudden need for an emergent The concept of limiting potentially life-sustaining medical treatment
transfusion in a healthy child undergoing a low-risk procedure. (LSMT) is the same for children as it is for adults. Decision makers
In emergencies, based on the obligation to protect children, choose to limit LSMT because they do not consider the potential
anesthesiologists should take the legally correct and ethically burdens worth the potential benefits.58,59 The AAP, the American
appropriate action to protect the child by transfusing blood without Society of Anesthesiologists (ASA), and the American College of
a court order. A court order may then be sought if desired. Surgery mandate “required reconsideration” of any limitations
Clinicians may wonder if they should change their transfusion on LSMT before proceeding to the operating room.
triggers for a child of a Jehovah’s Witness. It may be appropriate Although the term “Do Not Resuscitate” (DNR) is commonly
for clinicians to delay transfusion as compared with their usual used, the term “Life-Sustaining Medical Treatment” is becoming
practices in an effort to honor the parents’ preferences and in more common. One purpose of this shift is to emphasize that
recognition of our inadequate knowledge of when to transfuse. desired limitations on medical treatment are continuous rather
Other clinicians, while acknowledging the difficulty in knowing than dichotomous. The term “potentially” is often used to modify
when to transfuse, believe it is appropriate to use their usual LSMT to emphasize the uncertainty about whether a therapy will
transfusion triggers, in the belief that the requirement is to treat be life-sustaining.
this child of a Jehovah’s Witness as you would treat any other Reevaluation of LSMT preferences for the perioperative period
child. starts with clarifying the patient’s goals for the proposed surgery
Decision makers may consider postponing a procedure that and end-of-life care (Table 5.3). Anesthesiologists should involve
can be delayed until the child is of sufficient age and maturity the patient, family, and other clinicians such as surgeons, intensiv-
to decide about transfusion therapy. The complexity is whether ists, and pediatricians in determining what is in the best interest
the delay may increase the risk or decrease the likelihood of a of the child.
good outcome. This decision requires the same balancing act as Benefits of potentially LSMT include an improved quality of
for determining best interest for a child. Relevant factors include life and prolongation of life under certain circumstances. Burdens
the quantitative and qualitative change in risk or benefit. Consider
that it may be easier to wait on a procedure that is purely cosmetic
than on a procedure for which waiting has a small chance of
TABLE 5.3 Components of a Pediatric Perioperative
leading to permanent injury. If individual clinicians choose to
Life-Sustaining Medical Treatment Discussion
honor the wishes of a mature minor, they must ensure the fidelity
of the agreement by making certain that postoperative and on-call • Planned procedure and anticipated benefit to child
clinicians will honor the mature minor’s wishes. • Advantages and opportunities of having specific, identified
clinicians providing therapy for a defined period
Emergency Care • Likelihood of requiring resuscitation
Anesthesiologists should provide necessary emergent care for • Reversibility of likely causes for resuscitation
minors who do not have a parent available to give legal consent.55,56 • Description of potential interventions and their consequences
Emergencies include problems that could cause death, disability, • Chances of successful resuscitation, including improved outcomes
and the increased risk of future complications. of witnessed arrests compared with unwitnessed arrests
The right of an adolescent to refuse emergency care treatment • Ranges of outcomes with and without resuscitation
turns on the adolescent’s decision-making capacity and the resulting • Responses to iatrogenic events
harm from refusal of care. If the harm is significant and the
• Intended and possible venues and types of postoperative care
adolescent’s rationale is decidedly short-term or filled with mis-
• Postoperative timing and mechanisms for reevaluation of the
understanding, it becomes necessary to consider whether the
limitations on life-sustaining medical treatment
adolescent has sufficient decision-making capacity for this decision.
• Establishment of an agreement (which may include a full
In this situation, it may be appropriate to consider what is in the
resuscitation status) through a goal-directed approach
best interest of the adolescent. For example, a 15-year-old football
• Documentation
player with a cervical fracture might refuse emergency stabilization,
stating that he does not want to live life without football. Most Adapted from Truog RD, Waisel DB, Burns JP. DNR in the OR: a goal-directed approach.
would hold that his conclusion overly values short-term implica- Anesthesiology 1999;90:289-295; and Fallat ME, Deshpande JK. Do-not-resuscitate
orders for pediatric patients who require anesthesia and surgery. Pediatrics
tions, especially in light of the suddenness of the injury, and that
2004;114:1686-1692.
he should receive emergency treatment.
74 A Practice of Anesthesia for Infants and Children

include intractable pain and suffering, disability, and events that certain types of iatrogenic arrests should be addressed as part of
cause a decrement in the quality of life, as viewed by the patient.60,61 the perioperative discussion.64
These guidelines help in considering short- and long-term goals The “temporary and reversible” goal-directed perioperative
and putting into appropriate context specific fears such as long-term DNR order can be documented as “The patient desires resuscitative
ventilatory dependency, pain, and suffering. efforts during surgery and in the postanesthesia care unit (PACU) only
Legitimate procedures for a child with limitations on LSMT if the adverse events are believed to be both temporary and reversible, in
include procedures that decrease pain, provide vascular access, the clinical judgment of the attending anesthesiologists and surgeons.”
enable the child to be at home, treat an urgent problem unrelated With the patient’s permission, anesthesiologists may want to
to the primary problem (e.g., appendicitis), or treat a problem include selected family members in the reevaluation discussion
that may be related but is not considered a terminal event (e.g., to enable the best communication of the patient’s preferences.
bowel obstruction). However, seeking these interventions does
not obviate the desire to avoid potential postresuscitation burdens Barriers to Honoring Preferences for Resuscitation
such as need for extensive ventilator support, cognitive deficits, Barriers to honoring limitations center on clinician attitudes, time
or physical limitations. pressures, and inadequate knowledge about policy, law, and
The goal-directed approach for perioperative limitations on ethics.64–71 Although required reconsideration has been accepted
LSMT permits decision makers to guide therapy by prioritizing for more than 20 years, and there has been some improvement,
outcomes rather than procedures. After defining desirable outcomes, anesthesiologists and surgeons still have inadequate knowledge
decision makers ask anesthesiologists to use their clinical judgment and practices about perioperative LSMT.72–74 Deficiencies include
to determine how specific interventions will affect achieving the lack of knowledge about required reconsideration, infrequent
specific goals. Predictions about the success of interventions preoperative determination of the presence of an advance directive,
made at the time of the resuscitation are more accurate than and inadequate willingness to care for patients with perioperative
predictions made preoperatively, when the quality and nature limitations on LSMT.75 On the whole, however, it seems that the
of the problems are unknown. Therapy may be guided by goals extent of knowledge and practices is institution-dependent.
rather than specific procedures (as is done on the ward), because Anesthesiologists may falsely believe that law or hospital policy
during the perioperative period children are cared for by dedicated requires full resuscitation during the perioperative period. Clinicians
anesthesiologists for brief, defined periods. It is helpful to define who act in accordance with statutory requirements are often
a goal-directed approach by discussing the acceptable burdens, explicitly protected from liability when they honor a child’s or
the desirable benefits, and the likelihood of distinct outcomes. family’s refusal of resuscitation. Given the well-established right
Most decision makers choose a goal-directed approach of desiring of children and parents to refuse medical treatment and the paucity
therapy if the interventions and burdens were temporary and of cases finding clinicians liable for honoring limitations on LSMT,
reversible (i.e., if they could return to the present state without the risk of liability for honoring an appropriately documented
suffering too much). perioperative limitation on LSMT is not high and is likely to be
Prior determination of acceptable postoperative LSMT is less less than the risk of not honoring the limitations.
critical in pediatrics, because usually parents are available in the
postoperative period to make decisions regarding therapy. Nonethe- Physicians Orders for Life-Sustaining Treatment
less, when a sufficiently mature child participates in discussions Physician orders for life-sustaining treatment (POLST) were designed
about LSMT, anesthesiologists should ensure that the discussion in part to improve honoring resuscitation preferences and are
incorporates the child’s preferences for postoperative trials of becoming more common in pediatric patients. POLST have two
therapy. The willingness to undergo a trial of therapy indicates a main advantages compared with other forms of advance directives.
belief that the burdens of the trial (e.g., a few days of ventilator POLST have the advantages of being a medical order that is valid
support) may be worth the benefits (e.g., extubation of the trachea) across different locations, including schools. These features will
initially, but at some point, the increasing burdens may not be likely increase compliance with the documented preferences,
worth the decreasing likelihood of the benefits. Flexibly inherent particularly in terms of emergency medical treatment. The POLST
in the goal-directed approach is that it promotes trials of therapy document defines code status and preferences for medical interven-
to evaluate whether said therapy achieves its desired goals. This tions, typically documented as full treatment, trial of treatment,
is particularly important given our ever-changing knowledge about and selective treatment.76 Although clinicians feel that POLST
the outcomes of resuscitation.62 limited unwanted resuscitation and that the declared preferences
A time-limited trial of therapy is “an agreement between clinicians were durable, some clinicians report difficulty in using the form
and a patient/family to use certain medical therapies over a defined period or having it honored across locations.77–81 Research is needed to
to see if the patient’s condition improves or deteriorates according to the help optimize POLST practices.80,82
agreed on clinical outcomes.” 63 The results of a time-limited trial can
help decision makers determine whether to continue therapy or Potentially Inappropriate Interventions
shift to comfort care measures. Knowing the results of a burden- It is more helpful to think about potentially inappropriate interven-
some therapy makes withdrawing a therapy that does not achieve tions instead of futile treatments. An intervention is futile only
the identified goals more ethically stout than simply withholding if it cannot accomplish a physiologic goal. A more common and
the therapy and not knowing what the effects of the therapy difficult dilemma is how to handle potentially inappropriate
would be. interventions. Interventions may be inappropriate when “there is
Iatrogenic problems such as cardiac arrest do not obviate no reasonable expectation that the patient will improve sufficiently to
decisions to limit LSMT.64 To decision makers, the cause of the survive outside the acute care setting, or when there is no reasonable
arrest is irrelevant. Decision makers care about the factors they expectation that the patient’s neurologic function will improve sufficiently
considered in requesting limited resuscitation, including the to allow the patient to perceive the benefits of treatment.” 83 This useful
likelihood of successful resuscitation and physical and mental concept may be less useful to pediatric decision making given
status after the arrest. The benefits of continued therapy after the relatively sparse specific outcome data for the very young.84,85
Ethical Issues in Pediatric Anesthesiology 75

Treatments with small likelihoods of success may be considered TABLE 5.4 Steps for Conflict Resolution of Requests for
inappropriate because of the burden to the child, cost, or uncertain Potentially Inappropriate Treatment in Intensive
benefit. Discussions about inappropriate treatment should bear
in mind the goals of the treatment and the likelihood of achieving
a defined result. When offering the likelihood of a result, clinicians
Care Units86
1. Before initiation of and throughout the formal conflict-resolution
5
procedure, clinicians should enlist expert consultation to aid in
should be clear whether the information used to form the estima-
achieving a negotiated agreement.
tion is based on intuition, clinical experience, or rigorous scientific
2. Surrogate(s) should be given clear notification in writing regarding
studies. Scoring systems that are useful for population predictions
the initiation of the formal conflict-resolution procedure and the
in determining potentially inadvisable care should be considered
steps and timeline to be expected in this process.
as contributory but not determinative for decision making for
3. Clinicians should obtain a second medical opinion to verify the
individuals.
prognosis and the judgment that the requested treatment is
Parents and clinicians may disagree about therapy for a child inappropriate.
near the end of life. Hospitals should have defined processes to
4. There should be case review by an interdisciplinary institutional
help resolve conflict about applying potentially inappropriate committee.
interventions (Table 5.4).86
5. If the committee agrees with the clinicians, then clinicians should
offer the option to seek a willing provider at another institution and
IMPROVING COMMUNICATION IN PEDIATRIC INTENSIVE should facilitate this process.
CARE UNITS 6. If the committee agrees with the clinicians and no willing provider
Pediatric intensivists should emphasize interdisciplinary com- can be found, surrogate(s) should be informed of their right to seek
munication, tailor the communication style to the parents, and case review by an independent appeals body.
maximize meaningful parental participation in the child’s care.87,88 7. a. If the committee or appellate body agrees with the patient or
The goal is to be an empathic professional who establishes compas- surrogate’s request for life-prolonging treatment clinicians
sionate relationships with the child and family by managing should provide these treatments or transfer the patient to a
emotional, informational, and care needs. In almost all conversa- willing provider.
tions, clinicians should explain the meaning of the conversation b. If the committee agrees with the clinicians’ judgment, no
in terms of overall care. willing provider can be found, and the surrogate does not seek
Patient-centered characteristics—such as asking questions, using independent appeal or the appeal affirms the clinicians’
position, clinicians may withhold or withdraw the contested
empathic statements, increasing the amount of parental contribu-
treatments and should provide high-quality palliative care.
tions to the conversation, and focusing on psychosocial and lifestyle
issues as compared with medical issues—improved parent satisfaction From: Bosslet GT, Pope TM, Rubenfeld GD, et al. An official ATS/AACN/ACCP/ESICM/
during family conferences.89 When wanting to convey sympathy SCCM policy statement: responding to requests for potentially inappropriate treatments
in intensive care units. Am J Respir Crit Care Med. 2015;191(11):1318-1330. doi:10.1164/
to patients and families, wish statements, such as “I wish things
rccm.201505-0924ST.
were different” seem effective.90 Table 5.5 lists characteristics of
good communication in the intensive care unit.

TABLE 5.5 Parents’ Desires for Communication in the Intensive Care Units
1. Honest and complete information should be tailored to the parents’ needs and information-receiving preferences. Comprehension of the child’s
potential trajectories permits better participation in care and a greater chance of appropriate end-of-life care.
2. Ready access to staff should include periodic scheduled informal visits to the bedside and the availability of e-mail interactions. The goal is to
provide the parents with easy and frequent opportunities to have their questions answered, with sufficient repetition and clarification of the “big
picture.”
3. To maximize successful communication, clinicians should actively assess the parents’ preferences for communication and decision making. This
includes considering how to relate information to parents when clinicians have different management opinions. Parents frequently recognize that
there are differences between options, and some prefer to hear the range of options, whereas others prefer to hear only the recommended option.
4. Emotional expression and support by staff are critical to parents. To do this successfully, clinicians should adapt their style to parents’ preferences.
Most clinicians should adopt practices that give parents more room to control the conversation, including talking less, listening more, and tolerating
silence as parents gather themselves to continue communicating.
5. Parents respond and benefit from the relational aspects of compassion, mercy, authenticity, and integrity. More colloquially, the relational aspect
is referred to as “being there”—interacting with the parents as a caring person with feelings and emotions. For example, although some clinicians
may believe it is inappropriate to show emotion, parents appreciate compassion and some level of distress at the sharing of bad news, rather than
cold hard professionalism.88
6. Preservation of the integrity of the parent-child relationship means enabling parents to continue in their self-identified and prominent role as
decision maker and protector. Loss of this role harms parents and may impair their ability to participate in decision making for the child.
7. Faith and spiritual matters are highly personal, and parents may feel uncomfortable expressing their faith in an institutional setting. Spiritual matters
should be accepted and integrated into the intensive care unit practice to assist those who benefit from spiritual support.
8. Parents’ lifelong views of these events are profoundly colored by vivid memories and strong feelings about seminal discussions. How difficult
discussions are handled and the quality of the communication among clinicians and families often become the basis for the family’s lifelong
narrative of these events.

Modified from Meyer EC, Ritholz MD, Burns JP, Truog RD. Improving the quality of end-of-life care in the pediatric intensive care unit: parents’ priorities and recommendations.
Pediatrics 2006;117:649-657.
76 A Practice of Anesthesia for Infants and Children

TABLE 5.6 Ethical Issues Surrounding Donation After Cardiac Death (DCD)
Ethical Issue Discussion Points
Should interventions be permitted The burdens from the interventions are not in the best interests of the child. On the other hand, the burdens of
prior to withdrawal of care? the interventions are mostly theoretical and may improve the quality of the transplanted organs.
Should withdrawal of therapy Withdrawing therapy in the operating room may increase the quality of the organs transplanted. Withdrawing
occur in the intensive care unit therapy in the ICU is likely to be less jarring to the family and more consistent with the premise of withdrawing
(ICU) or in the operating room? therapy for the child’s benefit. In addition, it may remove some of the awkwardness that may occur if the child
does not die within the defined interval.
Who should withdraw therapy? To be consistent with the premises of withdrawal of therapy, it should be the same person who would normally
withdraw therapy from the child. Even if the decision is made to withdraw therapy in the operating room, an
anesthesiologist who has not been caring for the child should not be asked to withdraw therapy because of the
physical location of the event.
How long should cessation of Proposed times may be based on the premises of how long it would take to autoresuscitate compared with how
cardiac function exist for a child to long it would take to be resuscitated through medical intervention.
be declared dead?
What are the contents of a good Acceptable interventions before withdrawing therapy
DCD policy? Acceptable locations of withdrawing therapy
Amount of time to wait until death before forgoing procurement
Which individual should withdraw therapy
What to do if the family will not leave after death is declared

ORGAN DONATION AFTER CARDIAC DEATH TABLE 5.7 Federal Classification of Pediatric Research
In organ procurement after a declaration of death through neu-
rologic criteria (i.e., brain death), the child is declared dead before 1. Research not involving greater than minimal risk
a. IRB determines minimal risk
being brought to the operating room. The organs are then retrieved
b. IRB finds and documents that adequate provisions are made for
while total body homeostasis is maintained through mechanical soliciting assent from children and permission from their
ventilation, pharmacologic therapy, and other standard resuscitative parents or guardians
techniques. 2. Research involving greater than minimal risk but presenting the
Concern about the limited availability of organs for transplanta- prospect of direct benefit to the individual subject
tion has resulted in the now widely accepted concept of donation a. IRB justifies the risk by the anticipated benefit to the subjects
after cardiac death (DCD).71,91,92 In DCD the child is not declared b. The relationship of the anticipated benefit to the risk is at least as
dead before being brought to the operating room for organ retrieval. favorable as that presented by available alternative approaches
Instead, after it is determined that therapy should be withdrawn c. Adequate provisions are made for assent and permission
based on a standard benefits and burdens assessment, the child is 3. Research that involves greater than minimal risk and no prospect of
brought to the operating room and therapy is withdrawn. If the direct benefit to the individual subject but is likely to yield
child dies after life-sustaining therapy is withdrawn, he or she is generalizable knowledge about the subject’s disorder or condition
declared dead by cardiac criteria and the organs are retrieved. Ethical a. IRB determines that the risk represents a minor increase over
issues regarding DCD protocols center on whether the protocols minimal risk
b. The intervention or procedure presents experiences to subjects
seriously alter the dying process by shifting decision making away
that are reasonably commensurate with those inherent in their
from the best interest of the dying child and by interfering with the actual or expected medical, dental, psychological, social, or
family’s ability to be with their dying child (Table 5.6). educational situations
c. The intervention or procedure is likely to yield generalizable
Clinical and Academic Practice Issues knowledge . . . which is of vital importance for the understanding
or amelioration of the subject’s disorder or condition
PEDIATRIC RESEARCH d. Adequate provisions are made for assent and permission
The anesthesiologist Henry K. Beecher was one of the first to 4. Research not otherwise approvable, which presents an opportunity
propose that pediatric research had different requirements compared to understand, prevent, or alleviate a serious problem affecting the
with adult research.93 Pediatric research is closely examined because health or welfare of children
children are incapable of consenting to experiments and because Where research is covered by numbers 3 and 4 above and permission is to be
the developing child is at greater risk for long-term harm.94 Federal obtained from parents, both parents must give their permission unless one parent
guidelines give four categories of pediatric research, with each is deceased, unknown, incompetent, or not reasonably available, or when only
ascending category requiring greater scrutiny of the risk-to-benefit one parent has legal responsibility for the care and custody of the child.
IRB, institutional review board.
ratio, especially in research without therapeutic benefit for the From U.S. Department of Human Services: 45 CFR 46 Subpart D. Additional Protections
subject (Table 5.7). Whereas obtaining the assent of the child for Children Involved as Subjects in Research.
whenever possible is important for therapeutic medical procedures,
it is absolutely essential in the context of research, along with the
informed permission of the parents. or during the performance of routine physical or psychological
examinations. Most interpret this to mean the risks encountered
Minimal Risk in daily life by healthy children, such as running in the backyard,
Minimal risks are defined as those risks that are not greater in playing sports, or riding in a car.95–97 A less favored relative
and of themselves than those ordinarily encountered in daily life interpretation uses as a benchmark those risks encountered in the
Ethical Issues in Pediatric Anesthesiology 77

daily lives of children who will be enrolled in the research. In new drugs because physicians tended to prescribe less effective,
other words, if a child were living in a manner that exposed the known medications. Inadequate research into pediatric drugs forced
child to risk (e.g., undergoing repeated general anesthesia), then
it would be acceptable to expose the child up to that level of risk
in a study.
physicians to prescribe drugs in nonstandard ways, such as sprinkled
or crushed tablets. Even when there is some pediatric labeling,
there is scant labeling for children younger than 2 years of age.
5
Individuals are poor at estimating the risk levels of activities In 2009 a survey of a Canadian pediatric tertiary hospital found
and often correlate risk to familiarity, control of the activity, and that even when comparing off-label (see below) use with contem-
reversibility of the potential harms. Institutional review boards porary pediatric references (an unofficial and very liberal interpreta-
may reject low-risk studies because they involve unfamiliar matters tion), 16% of drug administrations during the perioperative period
while approving studies that have excessive risks. were considered off-label. Based on a more traditional standard
of the Canadian Compendium of Pharmaceutical Specialties, 55% of
Minor Increase Over Minimal Risk drugs administered were used off-label.101 Neonatology and pediatric
The pediatric research category that involves “greater than minimal intensive care units are particularly at risk for off-label use. In a
risk and no prospect of direct benefit to the individual subject but is likely study of more than 65,000 patients, drugs that were considered
to yield generalizable knowledge about the subject’s disorder or condition to have high-risk status or high priority for study by the Food
… which is of vital importance” 98 is based on the idea that it is and Drug Administration [FDA] were used off-label in 85% of
acceptable to expose a child to a “minor increase over minimal patients.102 Off-label drugs included dexmedetomidine, dopamine,
risk” under certain conditions. Parsing the regulation may help hydromorphone, lorazepam, and milrinone.
clarify this somewhat unhelpful definition. One suggestion has The following selective history highlights the overall intent to
been that “minor increase” means that the pain, discomfort, or ensure that (1) children get the same benefits of pharmacologic
stress must be transient, reversible, and not severe.99 The condition advances as adults and (2) research is performed in the youngest
of the subject should be used to mean a set of characteristics “that children. Readers should also learn from this history that persistent
an established body of scientific or clinical evidence has shown to negatively advocacy is often required before regulatory change can be suc-
affect children’s health and well-being or to increase the risk of developing cessfully obtained. In 1962 the Kefauver-Harris Amendments
a health problem in the future.” Interpreting “condition” to include (passed after the thalidomide disaster) required that drug companies
“having the potential to have the condition” permits otherwise demonstrate safety and efficacy before marketing a drug. Because
healthy children to participate in research for diseases that they the vast majority of drugs did not undergo pediatric-specific
may develop (e.g., cellulitis). Vital importance implies that the investigation, this requirement actually led to less pediatric labeling,
evidence supporting the relevance of the study should require a with the package insert (drug label) often reading, “Safety and
higher order of proof. efficacy have not been demonstrated for children <12 years,” because of
the expense of getting this information. In 1994 the U.S. FDA
Socioeconomic Concerns and Distribution of Risk began requiring sponsors to explain why pediatric labeling cannot
Socioeconomically disadvantaged children living in urban areas occur but did not require sponsors to perform pediatric studies
may be overrepresented in research studies because urban academic (see Chapter 7).
centers in disadvantaged areas perform the majority of clinical The 1997 FDA Modernization Act and the 1998 Final Rule
research.100 Children living in socioeconomically disadvantaged were legislative initiatives designed to gain more data from drug
areas are often more affected by diseases associated with their companies through pediatric studies in exchange for the benefit
environment, such as asthma or nutritional disorders complicated of an additional 6 months of patent exclusivity. This effort was
by limited access to stocked grocery stores. One could argue further codified with the passage of the Best Pharmaceuticals for
that this unequal burden of risk, primarily manifested by greater Children Act (BPCA) in 2002. With these requirements, the FDA
participation of socioeconomically disadvantaged children in now had the legal power to mandate pediatric studies if a new
research studies, is reasonable because these children are more drug might be used in a substantial number of children, if it
likely to develop these diseases and therefore are more likely to might provide a meaningful therapeutic benefit, or if inadequate
benefit from the research. Most reject that view and believe that labeling could pose significant risks. The pharmaceutical industry
in some sense, socioeconomically advantaged patients gratuitously responded with an explosion of pediatric studies. However, the
gain the benefits of the research without sharing the risks. The exclusivity provision did not encourage study of generic drugs or
disproportionate risk borne by one segment of society compared drugs with insufficient sales. Further, once exclusivity was credited
with another likely breeches the most accepted interpretation of for older pediatric age groups, there was no incentive to conduct
the core ethical value of justice. studies in younger groups.
Socioeconomically disadvantaged families may be more likely In December 2003 the Pediatric Research Equity Act (PREA)
to be influenced by the small gifts offered to research participants. required pediatric studies for all drugs and biologic products with
Aside from compensating for costs (e.g., parking vouchers), gifts a new indication, new dosage form, new route, new dosing regimen,
should not of themselves encourage participation. The problem or new active ingredient. Studies need to evaluate safety, efficacy,
is that gifts that represent a small expression of gratitude for some dosing and administration for a drug intended use for a specific
families may provide an incentive for participation for socioeco- pediatric subpopulation. Studies could be waived if they were
nomically disadvantaged families.100 impracticable, if the therapy would be ineffective or unsafe in
pediatric patients, or if there would be no meaningful therapeutic
Imperative for Pharmacologic Research benefit over existing therapies and the moiety would not be used
Through the mid-1990s, more than 70% of new molecular entities in a substantial number of children.
were without pediatric drug labeling. Inadequate information In 2012 the Food and Drug Administration Safety and Innova-
exposed children to age-specific adverse reactions, ineffective tion Act (FDASIA) made the BPCA and PREA permanent. The
treatment owing to inappropriate dosing, and lack of access to FDASIA initiated new requirements such as a Pediatric Study
78 A Practice of Anesthesia for Infants and Children

Plan, which included an outline of the studies including study TABLE 5.8 Strategies Used by Drug Companies to
objectives, design, statistical approach, age of patients, relevant Influence Physicians
outcomes, and a timeline. An increased focus on the youngest
patients included requiring that neonates be included in studies 1. Teach sales people subtle verbal and nonverbal techniques to
influence physicians.
unless the disease did not affect neonates or studies were not
feasible or safe. The FDASIA offered priority review for therapies 2. Instruct sales people to misdirect and to dissemble when
questioned about possible complications.
for rare pediatric diseases. Through August 2016 the FDA granted
pediatric exclusivity for 217 drugs.103 In 2014 the FDA put in 3. Cherry-pick which data are distributed to physicians.
similar requirements for medical devices intended for use in 4. Prohibit distribution of studies that may criticize the product. (One
children. Other nations have adopted similar regulatory require- strategy is to classify concerning studies as background studies and
then prohibit distribution of background studies.)
ments and incentives to encourage drug research.104,105
5. Seek “opinion leaders” to speak in favor of the product.
MANAGING POTENTIAL CONFLICTS OF INTEREST 6. Continue the well-established gift-giving strategy to subconsciously
A conflict of interest is “a set of conditions in which professional judgment curry favor with the physician and to develop a positive association
about the product and the company.
concerning a primary interest (such as a patient’s welfare or the validity
of research) tends to be unduly influenced by a secondary interest.”106
Because these conditions in an individual are internal, they are
best characterized by describing situations that may create the
potential for conflicts of interest. Focusing on potential conflicts program in the Sunshine Act (section 6002) of the Patient Protection
of interest moves the concept away from attacking an individual’s and Affordable Care Act.113,114 This program “collects information
morals and toward more uniform definitions. Potential conflicts about the payments drug and device companies made to physicians and
of interest may be induced by financial, personal, and professional teaching hospitals for things like travel, research, gifts, speaking fees and
benefits such as prestige, promotion, and personal gratification.107 meals.”115,116 From August 2013 through 2015, the Open Payments
Anesthesiologists should be mindful of these potential conflicts program reported data from 812,000 physician payments valued
and attempt to identify them to better understand the likelihood at more than 5 billion dollars.117 The actual benefits from the
of compromised judgment. Open Payments program are unclear.118–121

Conducting Research Interaction With Industry


Perhaps the most powerful conflict in conducting research is the Interaction with industry affects clinicians’ prescribing behavior,
loss of equipoise that can come from originating and developing often through unconscious feelings of gratitude, obligation, or
an idea. Other sources of conflict related to research center on fellowship.112,122–125 Because clinicians are mostly unaware of the
academic promotion and reputation. Research disclosures do not social dynamic industry is creating, clinicians can legitimately
help identify conflicts of interest. In one study, only 80% of assert they do not consciously adjust their clinical practice, but
physicians disclosed payments related to the research, and only stealthily creating familiarity and good feelings for a product or
50% disclosed payments from the same company but unrelated an individual is a core competency in advertising.
to the product being discussed. Indirect payments were just as Be cynical about advertisements. Clinicians should indepen-
likely to influence behavior as direct payment.108 dently evaluate information supplied by industry because they
In 2009 an anesthesiologist was falsifying data that had encour- commonly overstate benefits and understate risks (Table 5.8).
aged multimodal pain therapy. Concerns of an internal reviewer Risks associated with industry misrepresentation will increase
brought about the internal investigation that found significant as increasing clinician workload decreases time for study. For
irregularities in the research. Major journals retracted articles. The these reasons, it is instructive to look more closely at this problem.
editor of Anesthesia and Analgesia was quoted as saying, “We are Evidence published in the 2000 Vioxx Gastrointestinal Outcomes
left with a large hole in our understanding of this [multimodal pain Research (VIGOR) study indicated that rofecoxib (Vioxx) dramati-
therapy].”109,110 The editor of the journal called the scandal “a cally increased the rate of myocardial infarction in patients. In
tragedy” for the profession, for patients, and for the anesthesiologist 2001 the FDA determined that clinicians should be made aware
involved personally. Given that the anesthesiologist’s studies were of the cardiovascular effects of rofecoxib, and in 2004 it was
“robust” and influential, “the big chunk of what people have based their withdrawn from the market. Congressman Henry Waxman later
[multimodal] protocol on is gone.” It is important to emphasize that wrote the following126:
the anesthesiologist’s coauthors were deceived by him and were
not complicit. If fact, they assisted in assessing the legitimacy of Merck, the manufacturer of Vioxx, . . . has an excellent reputation
within the drug industry and supports many products, such as vaccines,
articles that were not retracted.110
that are medically essential but not very profitable. . . . Yet as we learned,
Conflicts of interest also come from industry support of research. even a company like Merck can direct its sales force to provide clinicians
To be clear, the academic-anesthesia-industry research complex is with a distorted picture of the relevant scientific evidence.
necessary to continue the rapid advancement of science. Rigorous
oversight minimizes these abuses.111 Researchers need to be involved On February 7, 2001 the Arthritis Drugs Advisory Committee
in trial development, must have access to raw data, and must be of the FDA voted unanimously that physicians should be made
able to publish without the company’s authorization. Cozy relation- aware of VIGOR’s cardiovascular results. The next day, Merck sent
ships between powerful members of the local academic community a bulletin to its rofecoxib sales force [which] ordered, “DO
and industry should be examined and brought to light to minimize NOT INITIATE DISCUSSIONS ON THE FDA ARTHRITIS
influence and potential conflicts of interest.112 ADVISORY COMMITTEE . . . OR THE RESULTS OF THE . . .
Financial relationships among physicians, researchers, hospitals VIGOR STUDY.” It advised that if a physician inquired about
and industry are publicly available through the Open Payments VIGOR, the sales representative should indicate that the study
Ethical Issues in Pediatric Anesthesiology 79

showed a gastrointestinal benefit and then say, “I cannot discuss TABLE 5.9 Examples of Obligations of Anesthesiologists to
the study with you.” Participate and Advocate
Merck further instructed representatives to show those doctors
who asked whether rofecoxib caused myocardial infarction a
pamphlet called “The Cardiovascular Card.” This pamphlet,
Obligations of Pediatric Anesthesiologists129–131,133,135–137,152,153
Treat every child with the grace and consideration you would want for
5
prepared by Merck’s marketing department, indicated that rofecoxib your child and family
was associated with 1 8 the mortality from cardiovascular causes Tailor the perioperative experience to the individual
of that found with other antiinflammatory drugs. Respond to problems that may harm children (e.g., impaired
The Cardiovascular Card did not include any data from the colleagues)
VIGOR study. Instead, it presented a pooled analysis of preapproval Practice mindfulness and critical self-reflection
studies, in most of which small doses of rofecoxib were used for Actively engage in continuing medical education
a short period. None of these studies were designed to assess Support advancement of the science
cardiovascular safety. In fact, FDA experts had publicly expressed Participate in quality improvement initiatives such as Wake Up Safe
“serious concerns” about using preapproval studies as evidence of the
Participate in professional organizations such as the Society for
drug’s cardiovascular safety: Pediatric Anesthesia and the American Academy of Pediatrics Section
[B]ut it would be a mistake to restrict the lessons learned to a single on Anesthesiology and Pain Medicine
company. The testimony we heard indicated that Merck’s marketing Prepare future generations through teaching, mentoring, creating
practices may be less aggressive and more ethical than many of its opportunities, and developing systems to enable anesthesiologists to
competitors. fulfill these obligations
Community Advocacy and Participation
Production Pressure Raise public awareness about a health or social issue
Production pressure is “the internal or external pressure on the anesthetist
Participate in public advocacy and lobbying
to keep the operating room schedule moving along speedily.”127 Almost
Work toward eliminating racial disparities in care
half of surveyed anesthesiologists reported seeing what they
Encourage a medical society to act on an issue that concerns the
considered unsafe anesthetic practices in response to this production
public health
pressure.128 As a consequence, anesthesiologists may not want to
Serve in a local organization, political interest group, or political
take the time to allow a child to ask questions about the anesthetic,
organization
to adequately premedicate an anxious child, or to engage the
Topics of particular relevance to pediatric anesthesiologists:
parents in a lengthy discussion about postponing the surgery in
• Pediatric obesity
a child with a cold. Anesthesiologists should be cognizant of their
• Pediatric sedation safety in hospitals and non-hospital facilities
level of skill. For example, the “routine” tonsillectomy may be • Child abuse
beyond some anesthesiologists’ ability in a child with multiple • Health care access
congenital deficits. Anesthesiologists have an obligation to the • Role of subspecialty training in improving care for children
patient and themselves to only provide care that is within their
skills and to recognize when economic and administrative pressures
may induce them to do otherwise. universal standards of patient identification.141 Clinicians should
also participate in the data collection of national and international
PHYSICIAN OBLIGATIONS, ADVOCACY, databases.
AND GOOD CITIZENSHIP Although clinicians may not see the big picture and therefore
An implicit social contract obligates physicians to serve society resent doing “extra” steps, it is vital for clinicians to accept on
beyond direct patient caring. Society enables medical students, faith that participation is good patient care.129 Surreptitiously
physicians in training, and physicians to train, perform research, circumventing policies may harm patients, does not permit
and, perhaps most importantly, learn from and with patients. In remediation of the policy, and weakens the fidelity of the entire
return, society expects pediatric anesthesiologists to “manage all system, encouraging others to “make their own rules.”
things pediatric anesthesia” (Table 5.9).129–134 Clinicians should Clinicians also have an obligation to report potential medical
participate in relevant community advocacy, such as reducing errors. Although the “blame-free” approach is well touted, clinicians
variations in pediatric care secondary to issues like race, insurance perceive significant barriers to honestly reporting near-misses,
status, and language barriers.135–137 hindering improved patient safety. Institutional barriers center
Individual anesthesiologists do not need to fulfill every obliga- on inadequate procedures and lack of trust in the administration.142
tion. “Units” of anesthesiologists, such as private practice groups, When clinicians believe that policies are harmful or unnecessary,
academic departments, and state societies, should fulfill these they are obligated to raise these questions through appropriate
obligations collectively. channels, particularly to address institutional barriers to reporting
patient safety events.
Participating in Patient Safety Efforts
Medical errors come from human mistakes and system flaws.138,139 Treating Suffering
Parents in particular are interested in medical errors. In one study, Cassel described suffering as an intensely personal feeling that
39% of parents felt obligated to be vigilant for medical errors in can be defined as “the state of severe distress associated with events that
their child’s care.140 Clinicians have an obligation to work to threaten the intactness of the person.”143 Suffering should be considered
reduce system flaws, including participating in quality improvement when managing pain, and adequate steps should be taken to find
activities and data collection, following policies meant to improve and alleviate sources of suffering. Factors that contribute to a
care in high-risk situations (e.g., nosocomial infections), and actively child’s suffering include not knowing the origin or meaning of
engaging in policies designed to reduce medical errors, such as the pain, believing that pain is a punishment, and fearing that
80 A Practice of Anesthesia for Infants and Children

the pain will never be relieved. Anesthesiologists minimize suffering interest standard for a neonate, ethicists are more likely to consider
by clearly communicating about these issues with parents and the infant’s interests and the effects on the family. Neonatologists
children and affording children as much control of their care as were influenced by parents’ wishes, but were more likely to consider
possible. only the infant’s interests and were less likely to consider the
effects on the family.151 After consultations, clinicians feel greater
Suspicion of Child Maltreatment satisfaction in managing cases with ethical conflicts, not only
Child maltreatment includes acts of physical abuse, sexual abuse, because of their heightened awareness of the expert consulting
emotional abuse, and neglect.144–146 Anesthesiologists should be services available, but also because of their increased knowledge
particularly sensitive to bruises or burns in the shape of objects, and comfort in dealing with these issues.
injuries to soft tissue areas such as the upper arms, unexplained
mouth and dental injuries, fractures in infants, height and weight
less than the fifth percentile, and injuries that are not explained ANNOTATED REFERENCES
by the history (see Fig. 39.2). Children with physical or mental
Cassel EJ. The nature of suffering and the goals of medicine. N Engl J
handicaps are particularly prone to abuse.147 Anesthesiologists, Med. 1982;306:639-646.
like all physicians, are legally required to report the suspicion of Physicians relieve suffering. Cassel’s 30-year-old treatise is the unparalleled
child abuse or neglect to appropriate authorities. Indeed, in most explanation of suffering.
jurisdictions, a physician can be criminally prosecuted if found Committee on Bioethics, American Academy of Pediatrics. Informed
liable for failing to report suspected child abuse. consent, parental permission, and assent in pediatric practice. Pediatrics.
1995;95:314-317.
THE ETHICS CONSULTATION SERVICE This article is the basis of informed consent for children. Pay particular attention
The ethical dilemmas that occur in the practice of anesthesiology to the introduction, in which Dr. William Bartholome (in abstentia) exhorts
may be difficult for the practitioner to resolve alone. Ethics clinicians to respect “the experience, perspective and power of children”.
Gruen RL, Pearson SD, Brennan TA. Physician-citizens: public roles and
committees and their consulting services act in an advisory role
professional obligations. JAMA. 2004;291:94-98.
to help clinicians, patients, and families amicably resolve ethical Gruen et al. provide a thoughtful perspective on the public and professional obligations
dilemmas. Anesthesiologists may find ethics consultation helpful of physicians. They provide a path on how to fulfill these obligations.
with questions about informed consent, decision-making capacity, Kon AA, Shepard EK, Sederstrom NO, et al. Defining futile and
and resuscitation decisions and in resolving disagreements among potentially inappropriate interventions: a policy statement from the
patients, families, and clinicians. Society of Critical Care Medicine Ethics Committee. Crit Care Med.
Although most ethics consultation services use a small group 2016;44(9):1769-1774. doi:10.1097/CCM.0000000000001965.
(typically three people) to perform consultations, some use the This article elegantly describes the characteristics of potentially inappropriate
entire committee and some use a single individual.148 Physicians, intervention and provides practical advice about implications.
nurses, social workers, chaplains, administrators, and laypeople Lang K, Dupree C, Kon A, Dudinski D. Calling out implicit racial bias
as a harm in pediatric care. Camb Q Healthc Ethics. 2016;25(3):540-552.
serve on ethics committees and perform consultations. Common
doi:10.1017/S0963180116000190.
characteristics of ethics consultation services are that they permit A thorough, readable and nonjudgmental analysis of one of those problems we
anyone to request an ethics consultation; that they require noti- prefer not to discuss—differences in care by race.
fication (not permission) of the patient, parents, and attending Quill TE. “I wish things were different”: expressing wishes in response to
physician prior to the consultation; and that choosing to follow loss, futility, and unrealistic hopes. Ann Intern Med. 2001;135(7):551.
the recommendations is wholly voluntary. Ethics committees are doi:10.7326/0003-4819-135-7-200110020-00022.
also available to consult on policy development and to organize A short paper that changes the way you think about communicating with the
continuing educational programs. patient or family during difficult times. The “wish” statement initiates deeper
For pediatric ethics consultations, the attending physician discussion and conveys empathy and being on the “same side of the fence”
requested the majority of consults, but consult requests were also with the patient and family.
Shafer SL. Tattered threads. Anesth Analg. 2009;108:1361-1363.
commonly received from nurses, social workers, nurse practitioners,
Shafer elegantly articulates the harms of false data.
and families.149 Typical ethical concerns were on end-of-life care, Waxman HA. The lessons of Vioxx: drug safety and sales. N Engl J Med.
goals of care, prognosis, quality of life, parental decision making, 2005;352:2576-2578.
pediatric assent, cultural differences, professional obligations, and Waxman’s recounting of public testimony eviscerates the reassuring murmurings
disagreement among professionals.149,150 Ethics consultations seems of industry.
to work efficiently, reaching consensus promptly and consistently.
The opinions of ethicists may differ from the opinions of A complete reference list can be found online at ExpertConsult.com.
subsets of physicians. For example, when interpreting the best
Ethical Issues in Pediatric Anesthesiology 80.e1

24. Gallagher TH, Studdert D, Levinson W. Disclosing harmful


REFERENCES medical errors to patients. N Engl J Med. 2007;356(26):2713-2719.
1. Informed consent, parental permission, and assent in pediatric practice.
Committee on Bioethics, American Academy of Pediatrics. Pediatrics.
1995;95(2):314-317.
doi:356/26/2713 [pii]10.1056/NEJMra070568.
25. O’Connor E, Coates HM, Yardley IE, Wu AW. Disclosure of patient
safety incidents: a comprehensive review. Int J Qual Health Care.
5
2. Diekema DS. Adolescent refusal of lifesaving treatment: are we asking 2010;22(5):371-379. doi:mzq042 [pii]10.1093/intqhc/mzq042.
the right questions? Adolesc Med State Art Rev. 2011;22(2):213-228. 26. Studdert DM, Piper D, Iedema R. Legal aspects of open disclosure
3. Dare T. Parental rights and medical decisions. Paediatr Anaesth. II: attitudes of health professionals—findings from a national survey.
2009;19(10):947-952. doi:10.1111/j.1460-9592.2009.03094.x. Med J Aust. 2010;193(6):351-355. doi:stu10128_fm [pii].
4. Diekema DS. Revisiting the best interest standard: uses and misuses. 27. Loren DJ, Klein EJ, Garbutt J, et al. Medical error disclosure among
J Clin Ethics. 2011;22(2):128-133. pediatricians: choosing carefully what we might say to parents.
5. Diekema DS. Parental refusals of medical treatment: the harm principle Arch Pediatr Adolesc Med. 2008;162(10):922-927. doi:162/10/922
as threshold for state intervention. Theor Med Bioeth. 2004;25(4):243- [pii]10.1001/archpedi.162.10.922.
264. doi:10.1007/s11017-004-3146-6. 28. Wu AW, Huang IC, Stokes S, Pronovost PJ. Disclosing medical
6. Pope TM. The best interest standard: both guide and limit to medical errors to patients: it’s not what you say, it’s what they hear. J Gen
decision making on behalf of incapacitated patients. J Clin Ethics. Intern Med. 2009;24(9):1012-1017. doi:10.1007/s11606-009-1044-3.
2011;22(2):134-138. 29. Matlow A, Stevens P, Harrison C, Laxer R. Achieving closure
7. de Vos MA, Seeber AA, Gevers SKM, et al. Parents who wish no through disclosure: experience in a pediatric institution. J Pediatr.
further treatment for their child. J Med Ethics. 2015;41(2):195-200. 2004;144(5):559-560. doi:S0022-3476(04)00047-2 [pii]10.1016/j.
doi:10.1136/medethics-2013-101395. jpeds.2004.01.013.
8. Foster C. Harm: as indeterminate as “best interests”, but useful 30. Matlow AG, Moody L, Laxer R, et al. Disclosure of medical error
for triage. J Med Ethics. 2016;42(2):121-122. doi:10.1136/medethics- to parents and paediatric patients: assessment of parents’ attitudes
2015-103209. and influencing factors. Arch Dis Child. 2010;95(4):286-290.
9. Birchley G. The harm threshold and parents’ obligation to doi:adc.2009.163097 [pii]10.1136/adc.2009.163097.
benefit their children. J Med Ethics. 2016;42(2):123-126. doi:10.1136/ 31. Mastroianni AC, Mello MM, Sommer S, et al. The flaws in state
medethics-2015-103283. “apology” and “disclosure” laws dilute their intended impact on
10. Birchley G. Harm is all you need? Best interests and disputes malpractice suits. Health Aff. 2010;29(9):1611-1619. doi:10.1377/
about parental decision-making. J Med Ethics. 2016;42(2):111-115. hlthaff.2009.0134.
doi:10.1136/medethics-2015-102893. 32. Marshall DC, Jackson ME, Hattangadi-Gluth JA. Disclosure of
11. Levinson W, Kao A, Kuby A, Thisted RA. Not all patients want to par- industry payments to physicians an epidemiologic analysis of early data
ticipate in decision making. A national study of public preferences. J Gen from the Open Payments Program. Mayo Clin Proc. 2016;91(1):84-96.
Intern Med. 2005;20(6):531-535. doi:10.1111/j.1525-1497.2005.0088.x. doi:10.1016/j.mayocp.2015.10.016.
12. Deber RB, Kraetschmer N, Urowitz S, Sharpe N. Do people want to 33. Perez B, Didona T. Assessing legislative potential to institute error trans-
be autonomous patients? Preferred roles in treatment decision-making parency: a state comparison of malpractice claims rates. J Healthc Qual.
in several patient populations. Health Expect. 2007;10(3):248-258. 2010;32(3):36-41. doi:JHQ66 [pii]10.1111/j.1945-1474.2009.00066.x.
13. Waisel DB. Let the patient drive the informed consent process: ignore 34. Bell SK, Smulowitz PB, Woodward AC, et al. Disclosure, apology,
legal requirements. Anesth Analg. 2011;113(1):13-15. doi:10.1213/ and offer programs: stakeholders’ views of barriers to and strate-
ANE.0b013e31821bfc1f113/1/13 [pii]. gies for broad implementation. Milbank Q. 2012;90(4):682-705.
14. Stelfox HT, Gandhi TK, Orav EJ, Gustafson ML. The relation of doi:10.1111/j.1468-0009.2012.00679.x.
patient satisfaction with complaints against physicians and malpractice 35. Murtagh L, Gallagher TH, Andrew P, Mello MM. Disclosure-and-
lawsuits. Am J Med. 2005;118(10):1126-1133. resolution programs that include generous compensation offers may
15. Sepucha KR, Fagerlin A, Couper MP, et al. How does feeling informed prompt a complex patient response. Health Aff. 2012;31(12):2681-2689.
relate to being informed? The DECISIONS survey. Med Decis Making. doi:10.1377/hlthaff.2012.0185.
2010;30(5 suppl):77S-84S. doi:10.1177/0272989X10379647. 36. Boothman RC, Imhoff SJ, Campbell DA Jr. Nurturing a culture
16. Tait AR, Teig MK, Voepel-Lewis T. Informed consent for anesthesia: of patient safety and achieving lower malpractice risk through
a review of practice and strategies for optimizing the consent process. disclosure: lessons learned and future directions. Front Health Serv
Can J Anaesth. 2014;61(9):832-842. doi:10.1007/s12630-014-0188-8. Manage. 2012;28(3):13-28.
17. McCaffery KJ, Holmes-Rovner M, Smith SK, et al. Addressing 37. Ford C, English A, Sigman G. Confidential health care for adolescents:
health literacy in patient decision aids. BMC Med Inform Decis Mak. position paper of the Society for Adolescent Medicine. J Adolesc
2013;13(suppl 2):S10. doi:10.1186/1472-6947-13-S2-S10. Health. 2004;35(2):160-167. doi:10.1016/j.jadohealth.2004.03.002.
18. Tait AR, Voepel-Lewis T, Zikmund-Fisher BJ, Fagerlin A. Presenting 38. Gilbert AL, Rickert VI, Aalsma MC. Clinical conversations
research risks and benefits to parents: does format matter? Anesth about health: The impact of confidentiality in preventive ado-
Analg. 2010;111(3):718-723. doi:10.1213/ANE.0b013e3181e8570a. lescent care. J Adolesc Health. 2014;55(5):672-677. doi:10.1016/j.
19. Fagerlin A, Zikmund-Fisher BJ, Ubel PA. Helping patients jadohealth.2014.05.016.
decide: ten steps to better risk communication. J Natl Cancer Inst. 39. Burstein GR, Blythe MJ, Santelli JS, et al. Confidentiality Protec-
2011;103(19):1436-1443. doi:10.1093/jnci/djr318. tions for Adolescents and Young Adults in the Health Care Billing
20. Ubel PA, Smith DM, Zikmund-Fisher BJ, et al. Testing whether and Insurance Claims Process. J Adolesc Health. 2016;58(3):374-377.
decision aids introduce cognitive biases: results of a randomized trial. doi:10.1016/j.jadohealth.2015.12.009.
Patient Educ Couns. 2010;80(2):158-163. doi:10.1016/j.pec.2009.10.021. 40. Rubin SE, McKee MD, Campos G, O’Sullivan LF. Delivery
21. Tucker Edmonds B, McKenzie F, Panoch JE, et al. “Doctor, what of confidential care to adolescent males. J Am Board Fam Med.
would you do?”: physicians’ responses to patient inquiries about 2010;23(6):728-735. doi:10.3122/jabfm.2010.06.100072.
periviable delivery. Patient Educ Couns. 2015;98(1):49-54. doi:10.1016/j. 41. Anonymous. Counseling the adolescent about pregnancy options.
pec.2014.09.014. American Academy of Pediatrics. Committee on Adolescence. Pedi-
22. Kon AA. Answering the question: “Doctor, if this were your child, atrics. 1998;101(5):938-940.
what would you do?” Pediatrics. 2006;118(1):393-397. 42. Mercurio MR. Pediatric obstetrical ethics: medical decision-
23. Truog RD. “Doctor, if this were your child, what would you do”? making by, with, and for pregnant early adolescents. Semin Perinatol.
Pediatrics. 1999;103(1):153-154. 2016;40(4):237-246. doi:10.1053/j.semperi.2015.12.013.
80.e2 A Practice of Anesthesia for Infants and Children

43. Chervenak FA, McCullough LB, Knapp RC, et al. A clinically com- 66. White B, Willmott L, Cartwright C, et al. Knowledge of the law about
prehensive ethical framework for offering and recommending cancer withholding or withdrawing life-sustaining treatment by intensivists
treatment before and during pregnancy. Cancer. 2004;100(2):215-222. and other specialists. Crit Care Resusc. 2016;18(2):109-115. doi:10.5694/
doi:10.1002/cncr.11564. mja13.00217.
44. Moon M. Adolescents’ right to consent to reproductive medical 67. Bruce CR, Liang C, Blumenthal-Barby JS, et al. Barriers and facilitators
care: balancing respect for families with public health goals. Virtual to initiating and completing time-limited trials in critical care. Crit Care
Mentor. 2012;14(10):805-808. doi:10.1001/virtualmentor.2012.14.10. Med. 2015;43(12):2535-2543. doi:10.1097/CCM.0000000000001307.
msoc1-1210. 68. Aslakson R, Curtis JR, Nelson JE. The changing role of palliative
45. Pugh J, Kahane G, Maslen H, Savulescu J. Lay attitudes toward care in the ICU. Crit Care Med. 2014;42(11):2418-2428. doi:10.1097/
deception in medicine: Theoretical considerations and empirical CCM.0000000000000573.
evidence. AJOB Empir Bioeth. 2016;7(1):31-38. doi:10.1080/232945 69. Waisel DB. Unrecognized barriers to perioperative limitations
15.2015.1021494. on potentially life-sustaining medical treatment. J Clin Anesth.
46. Gillon R. Is there an important moral distinction for medical 2014;26(3):171-173. doi:10.1016/j.jclinane.2014.01.003.
ethics between lying and other forms of deception? J Med Ethics. 70. Adams JS. Utilizing evidence-based research and practice to support
1993;19:131-132. the infusion alliance. J Infus Nurs. 2010;33(5):273-277. doi:10.1097/
47. Guttmacher Institute. An Overview of Minors’ Consent Law. https:// NAN.0b013e3181ee037e00129804-201009000-00003 [pii].
www.guttmacher.org/state-policy/explore/overview-minors-consent-law. 71. Sanderson A, Zurakowski D, Wolfe J. Clinician perspectives regarding
Accessed 4 October 2016. the do-not-resuscitate order. JAMA Pediatr. 2013;167(10):954-958.
48. Committee on Adolescence, American Academy of Pediatrics. The doi:10.1001/jamapediatrics.2013.2204.
adolescent’s right to confidential care when considering abortion. 72. Nurok M, Green DST, Chisholm MF, et al. Anesthesiologists’ familiar-
Pediatrics. 1996;97:746-751. ity with the ASA and ACS guidelines on Advance Directives in the
49. Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs, American Medical Association. perioperative setting. J Clin Anesth. 2014;26(3):174-176. doi:10.1016/j.
Mandatory parental consent to abortion. JAMA. 1993;269:82-86. jclinane.2013.11.011.
50. Brydon C. Jehovah’s witnesses. Anaesth Intensive Care Med. 73. Hadler RA, Neuman MD, Raper S, Fleisher LA. Advance directives and
2013;14(2):79-81. doi:10.1016/j.mpaic.2012.11.015. operating: room for improvement? A A Case Rep. 2016;6(7):204-207.
51. Research Guide for Jehovah’s Witnesses for Publications in English. New doi:10.1213/XAA.0000000000000269.
York, New York: Watchtower Bible and Tract Society of New York, 74. Burkle CM, Swetz KM, Armstrong MH, Keegan MT. Patient and
Inc; 2016. doctor attitudes and beliefs concerning perioperative do not resuscitate
52. West JM. Ethical issues in the care of Jehovah’s Witnesses. Curr Opin orders: anesthesiologists’ growing compliance with patient autonomy
Anaesthesiol. 2014;27(2):170-176. doi:10.1097/ACO.0000000000000053. and self determination guidelines. BMC Anesthesiol. 2013;13(1):2.
53. Coleman DL, Rosoff PM. The legal authority of mature minors doi:10.1186/1471-2253-13-2.
to consent to general medical treatment. Pediatrics. 2013;786-793. 75. Redmann AJ, Brasel KJ, Alexander CG, Schwarze ML. Use of advance
doi:10.1542/peds.2012-2470. directives for high-risk operations: a national survey of surgeons. Ann
54. Black C. Boy’s Death Ends Battle Because Of His Religion, Leukemia Surg. 2012;255(3):418-423. doi:10.1097/SLA.0b013e31823b6782.
Patient Dennis Lindberg, 14, Didn’t Want Vital Transfusions; His 76. POLST California. Physician Orders for Life-Sustaining Treatment
Biological Parents Did. A Judge Sided With The Son, Who Died (POLST). EMSA #111 B. https://www.law.cornell.edu/wex/emancipa-
Last Night. Seattle Post-Intelligencer. November 27, 2007. tion_of_minors. Published 2016. Accessed 1 June 2016.
55. Rettig PJ. Can a minor refuse assent for emergency care? Virtual 77. Pedraza SL, Culp S, Falkenstine EC, Moss AH. POST forms more
Mentor. 2012;14(10):763-766. than advance directives associated with out-of-hospital death: insights
56. Sirbaugh PE, Diekema DS, Shaw KN, et al. Policy statement—Consent from a state registry. J Pain Symptom Manage. 2015;doi:10.1016/j.
for emergency medical services for children and adolescents. Pediatrics. jpainsymman.2015.10.003.
2011;128(2):427-433. 78. Hickman SE, Nelson CA, Smith-Howell E, Hammes BJ. Use of the
57. Fraser JJ, McAbee GN. Dealing with the parent whose judgment physician orders for life-sustaining treatment program for patients
is impaired by alcohol or drugs: legal and ethical considerations. being discharged from the hospital to the nursing facility. J Palliat
Pediatrics. 2004;114(3):869-873. doi:10.1542/peds.2004-1234. Med. 2014;17(1):43-49. doi:10.1089/jpm.2013.0097.
58. Truog RD, Waisel DB, Burns JP. DNR in the OR: a goal-directed 79. Moore v. Rees, Second Notice of Supplemental Information, No.
approach. Anesthesiology. 1999;90(1):289-295. 3:06-Cv-00022-KKC; 2006.
59. Fallat ME, Deshpande JK. Do-not-resuscitate orders for pedi- 80. Moore KA, Rubin EB, Halpern SD. The problems with physician
atric patients who require anesthesia and surgery. Pediatrics. orders for life-sustaining treatment. JAMA. 2016;315(3):259-260.
2004;114(6):1686-1692. doi:10.1542/peds.2004-2119. doi:10.1001/jama.2015.17362.
60. Teno JM, Hakim RB, Knaus WA, et al. Preferences for cardiopulmo- 81. Mirarchi FL, Doshi AA, Zerkle SW, Cooney TE. TRIAD VI: how
nary resuscitation: physician-patient agreement and hospital resource well do emergency physicians understand Physicians Orders for Life
use. The SUPPORT Investigators. J Gen Intern Med. 1995;10(4):179-186. Sustaining Treatment (POLST) forms? J Patient Saf. 2015;11(1):1-8.
61. American Academy of Pediatrics, Committee on Bioethics. Guidelines doi:10.1097/pts.0000000000000165.
on forgoing life-sustaining medical treatment. Pediatrics. 1994;93(3): 82. Halpern SD. Toward evidence-based end-of-life care. N Engl J Med.
532-536. 2015;37321(19):2001-2003. doi:10.1056/NEJMp1509664.
62. Olasveengen TM. Challenging our current concept of futility. 83. Kon AA, Shepard EK, Sederstrom NO, et al. Defining Futile and
Resuscitation. 2016;doi:10.1016/j.resuscitation.2016.05.002. Potentially Inappropriate Interventions: A Policy Statement From
63. Quill TE. Time-limited trials near the end of life. JAMA. 2011; the Society of Critical Care Medicine Ethics Committee. Crit Care
306(13):1483. Med. 2016;44(9):1769-1774. doi:10.1097/CCM.0000000000001965.
64. Waisel DB, Simon R, Truog RD, et al. Anesthesiologist manage- 84. Steurer MA, Adams M, Bacchetti P, et al. Swiss medical centres vary
ment of perioperative do-not-resuscitate orders: a simulation-based significantly when it comes to outcomes of neonates with a very
experiment. Simul Healthc. 2009;4(2):70-76. doi:10.1097/SIH.0b013 low gestational age. Acta Paediatr. 2015;104(9):872-879. doi:10.1111/
e31819e137b01266021-200900420-00002 [pii]. apa.13047.
65. Chung GS, Yoon JD, Rasinski KA, Curlin FA. US Physicians’ 85. Serenius F, Sjörs G, Blennow M, et al. EXPRESS study shows
Opinions about Distinctions between Withdrawing and Withhold- significant regional differences in 1-year outcome of extremely preterm
ing Life-Sustaining Treatment. J Relig Health. 2016;55(5):1596-1606. infants in Sweden. Acta Paediatr. 2014;103(1):27-37. doi:10.1111/
doi:10.1007/s10943-015-0171-x. apa.12421.
Ethical Issues in Pediatric Anesthesiology 80.e3

86. Bosslet GT, Pope TM, Rubenfeld GD, et al. An official ATS/AACN/ 107. Irwin RS. The role of conflict of interest in reporting of scientific
ACCP/ESICM/SCCM policy statement: Responding to requests information. Chest. 2009;136(1):253-259. doi:136/1/253 [pii]10.1378/
for potentially inappropriate treatments in intensive care units.
Am J Respir Crit Care Med. 2015;191(11):1318-1330. doi:10.1164/
rccm.201505-0924ST.
chest.09-0890.
108. Okike K, Kocher MS, Wei EX, et al. Accuracy of conflict-of-interest
disclosures reported by physicians. N Engl J Med. 2009;361(15):1466-
5
87. Truog RD, Meyer EC, Burns JP. Toward interventions to improve 1474. doi:361/15/1466 [pii]10.1056/NEJMsa0807160.
end-of-life care in the pediatric intensive care unit. Crit Care Med. 109. Marcus A. Fraud Case Rocks Anesthesiology Community. Anesthesiol
2006;34(11 suppl):S373-S379. News. 2009;35(3).
88. Meyer EC, Ritholz MD, Burns JP, Truog RD. Improving the quality of 110. White PF, Rosow CE, Shafer SL. The Scott Reuben saga: one
end-of-life care in the pediatric intensive care unit: parents’ priorities last retraction. Anesth Analg. 2011;112(3):512-515. doi:112/3/512
and recommendations. Pediatrics. 2006;117(3):649-657. [pii]10.1213/ANE.0b013e318209736f.
89. October TW, Hinds PS, Wang J, et al. Parent satisfaction with 111. Rothman DJ, Chimonas S. Academic medical centers’ conflict of
communication is associated with physician’s patient-centered interest policies. JAMA. 2010;304(20):2294-2295. doi:304/20/2294
communication patterns during family conferences. Pediatr Crit Care [pii]10.1001/jama.2010.1714.
Med. 2016;17(6):490-497. doi:10.1097/PCC.0000000000000719. 112. Lo B. Serving two masters—conflicts of interest in academic medicine.
90. Quill TE, Arnold RM, Platt F. “I wish things were different”: expressing N Engl J Med. 2010;362(8):669-671. doi:362/8/669 [pii]10.1056/
wishes in response to loss, futility, and unrealistic hopes. Ann Intern NEJMp1000213.
Med. 2001;135(7):551. doi:10.7326/0003-4819-135-7-200110020-00022. 113. Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act of 2010, Section 6002.
91. Potts M, Byrne PA, Evans DW. Infant hrart transplantation after cardiac 114. Marshall DC, Jackson ME, Hattangadi-Gluth JA. Disclosure of
death: ethical and Legal problems. J Clin Ethics. 2010;21(3):224-228. Industry Payments to Physicians: An Epidemiologic Analysis of
92. Nandi D, Miyamoto SD, Pietra BA, et al. Donation after circulatory Early Data from the Open Payments Program. Mayo Clin Proc.
death: Current utilization in the United States. J Heart Lung Transplant. 2016;91(1):84-96. doi:10.1016/j.mayocp.2015.10.016.
2016;35(9):1131-1132. doi:10.1016/j.healun.2016.05.027. 115. Department of Health and Human Services, Centers for Medicare and
93. Curran WJ, Beecher HK. Experimentation in children: a reexamination Medicare and Medicaid Services. Annual Report to Congress on the
of legal ethical principles. JAMA. 1969;10:77-83. Open Payments Program; 2016. https://www.cms.gov/OpenPayments/
94. Bos W, Tromp K, Tibboel D, Pinxten W. Ethical aspects of clinical Downloads/Open-Payments-Report-to-Congress.pdf. Accessed 5 June
research with minors. Eur J Pediatr. 2013;172(7):859-866. doi:10.1007/ 2016.
s00431-012-1856-8. 116. Department of Health and Human Services, Centers for Medicare
95. Wendler D, Belsky L, Thompson KM, Emanuel EJ. Quantifying the and Medicare and Medicaid Services. Open Payments. https://
federal minimal risk standard: implications for pediatric research www.cms.gov/openpayments/. Published 2016. Accessed 20 September
without a prospect of direct benefit. JAMA. 2005;294(7):826-832. 2016.
96. Wendler D. Minimal risk in pediatric research as a function of 117. Department of Health and Human Services, Centers for Medicare and
age. Arch Pediatr Adolesc Med. 2009;163(2):115-118. doi:10.1001/ Medicare and Medicaid Services. The Facts About Open Payments
archpediatrics.2008.524. Data. https://openpaymentsdata.cms.gov/summary. Accessed 20
97. Snyder J, Miller CL, Gray G. Relative versus absolute standards for September 2016.
everyday risk in adolescent HIV prevention trials: expanding the 118. Silverman E. Everything you need to know about the Sunshine Act.
debate. Am J Bioeth. 2011;11(6):5-13. doi:10.1080/15265161.2011.5 BMJ. 2013;347:f4704. doi:10.1136/bmj.f4704.
68576. 119. Santhakumar S, Adashi EY. The Physician Payment Sunshine
98. U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. 45 CFR 46 Subpart Act: testing the value of transparency. JAMA. 2015;313(1):23-24.
D. Additional Protection for Children Involved as Subjects in doi:10.1001/jama.2014.15472.
Research. Fed Regist. 2015. 120. Agrawal S, Brennan N, Budetti P. The Sunshine Act—effects on
99. Fisher CB, Kornetsky SZ, Prentice ED. Determining risk in pediatric physicians. N Engl J Med. 2013;368(22):2052-2054. doi:10.1056/
research with no prospect of direct benefit: time for a national NEJMp1305090.
consensus on the interpretation of federal regulations. Am J Bioeth. 121. Toroser D, Robinson M, Gegner J, et al. Systematic review of reports
2007;7(3):5-10. describing potential impact of the Sunshine Act on peer-reviewed
100. Coleman DL. The legal ethics of pediatric research. Duke Law J. medical publications. Curr Med Res Opin. 2016;32(3):547-553. doi:1
2007;57:517-624. 0.1185/03007995.2015.1131151.
101. Doherty DR, Pascuet E, Ni A, et al. Off-label drug use in pediatric 122. Churchill LR. The hegemony of money: commercialism and profes-
anesthesia and intensive care according to official and pediatric refer- sionalism in American medicine. Camb Q Healthc Ethics. 2007;16(4):
ence formularies. Can J Anaesth. 2010;57(12):1078-1088. doi:10.1007/ 407-442.
s12630-010-9395-0. 123. Campbell EG, Rao SR, DesRoches CM, et al. Physician profes-
102. Czaja AS, Reiter PD, Schultz ML, Valuck RJ. Patterns of Off-Label sionalism and changes in physician-industry relationships from 2004
Prescribing in the Pediatric Intensive Care Unit and Prioritizing to 2009. Arch Intern Med. 2010;170(20):1820-1826. doi:170/20/1820
Future Research. J Pediatr Pharmacol Ther. 2015;20(3):186-196. [pii]10.1001/archinternmed.2010.383.
doi:10.5863/1551-6776-20.3.186. 124. Perlis RH, Perlis CS. Physician payments from industry are associ-
103. US Food and Drug Administration. Pediatric Exclusivity Granted. ated with greater Medicare Part D prescribing costs. PLoS ONE.
http://www.fda.gov/downloads/Drugs/DevelopmentApprovalProcess/ 2016;11(5):e0155474. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0155474.
DevelopmentResources/UCM514985.pdf. Published 2016. Accessed 125. Spurling GK, Mansfield PR, Montgomery BD, et al. Information
1 January 2016. from pharmaceutical companies and the quality, quantity, and cost
104. European Medicines Agency. Paediatric Medicines: Overview. of physicians’ prescribing: a systematic review. PLoS Med. 2010;7(10):
http://www.ema.europa.eu/ema/index.jsp?curl=pages/regulation/ doi:10.1371/journal.pmed.1000352.
general/general_content_000023.jsp. Published 2016. Accessed 20 126. Waxman HA. The lessons of Vioxx–drug safety and sales. N Engl
September 2016. J Med. 2005;352(25):2576-2578. doi:352/25/2576 [pii]10.1056/
105. Tsukamoto K, Carroll KA, Onishi T, et al. Improvement of pediatric NEJMp058136.
drug development: regulatory and practical frameworks. Clin Ther. 127. Gaba DM, Fish KJ, Howard SK. Crisis Management in Anesthesiology.
2016;38(3):574-581. doi:10.1016/j.clinthera.2016.01.012. New York: Churchill Livingstone Inc; 1994.
106. Thompson DF. Understanding financial conflicts of interest. N Engl 128. Gaba DM, Howard SK, Jump B, et al. Production pressure in the work
J Med. 1993;329(8):573-576. environment. California anesthesiologists’ attitudes and experiences.
80.e4 A Practice of Anesthesia for Infants and Children

Anesthesiology. 1994;81(2):488-500. http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/ 141. American Academy of Pediatrics, Committee on Drugs and Committee
pubmed/8053599. on Hospital Care. Prevention of medication errors in the pediatric
129. Waisel DB. Nonpatient care obligations of anesthesiologists. Anesthesiol- inpatient setting. Pediatrics. 1998;102(2 Pt 1):428-430.
ogy. 1999;91(4):1152-1158. doi:10.1097/00000542-199910000-00032. 142. Renkema E, Broekhuis M, Ahaus K. Conditions that influence the
130. Gruen RL, Pearson SD, Brennan TA. Physician-citizens–public roles impact of malpractice litigation risk on physicians’ behavior regard-
and professional obligations. JAMA. 2004;291(1):94-98. http://www ing patient safety. BMC Health Serv Res. 2014;14:38. doi:10.1186/
.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/entrez/query.fcgi?cmd=Retrieve&db=PubMed&d 1472-6963-14-38.
opt=Citation&list_uids=14709581. 143. Cassel EJ. The nature of suffering and the goals of medicine. N Engl
131. Gruen RL, Campbell EG, Blumenthal D. Public roles of US physi- J Med. 1982;306:639-646.
cians: community participation, political involvement, and collective 144. Hussey JM, Chang JJ, Kotch JB. Child maltreatment in the United
advocacy. JAMA. 2006;296(20):2467-2475. States: prevalence, risk factors, and adolescent health consequences.
132. Hubinette MM, Ajjawi R, Dharamsi S. Family physician preceptors’ Pediatrics. 2006;118(3):933-942. doi:118/3/933 [pii]10.1542/
conceptualizations of health advocacy. Acad Med. 2014;89(11):1502- peds.2005-2452.
1509. doi:10.1097/ACM.0000000000000479. 145. Flaherty EG, Stirling J, American Academy of Pediatrics. Committee
133. Earnest MA, Wong SL, Federico SG. Perspective: Physician advo- on Child Abuse and Neglect. Clinical report—the pediatrician’s role
cacy: what is it and how do we do it? Acad Med. 2010;85(1):63-67. in child maltreatment prevention. Pediatrics. 2010;126(4):833-841.
doi:10.1097/ACM.0b013e3181c40d40. 146. Raman S, Hodes D. Cultural issues in child maltreatment. J Paediatr
134. Dharamsi S, Ho A, Spadafora SM, Woollard R. The physician as Child Health. 2012;48(1):30-37. doi:10.1111/j.1440-1754.2011.02184.x.
health advocate: translating the quest for social responsibility into 147. Nowak CB. Recognition and prevention of child abuse in the child
medical education and practice. Acad Med. 2011;86(9):1108-1113. with disability. Am J Med Genet C Semin Med Genet. 2015;169(4):293-
doi:10.1097/ACM.0b013e318226b43b. 301. doi:10.1002/ajmg.c.31458.
135. Lang K, Dupree C, Kon A, Dudinski D. Calling out implicit racial bias 148. Kesselheim JC, Johnson J, Joffe S. Ethics consultation in children’s
as a harm in pediatric care. Camb Q Healthc Ethics. 2016;25(3):540-552. hospitals: results from a survey of pediatric clinical ethicists. Pediatrics.
doi:10.1017/S0963180116000190. 2010;125(4):742-746. doi:peds.2009-1813 [pii]10.1542/peds.2009-1813.
136. Mack JW, Paulk ME, Viswanath K, Prigerson HG. Racial disparities 149. Thomas SM, Ford PJ, Weise KL, et al. Not just little adults: a review of
in the outcomes of communication on medical care received near 102 paediatric ethics consultations. Acta Paediatr. 2015;104(5):529-534.
death. Arch Intern Med. 2010;170(17):1533-1540. doi:170/17/1533 doi:10.1111/apa.12940.
[pii]10.1001/archinternmed.2010.322. 150. Johnson L-M, Church CL, Metzger M, Baker JN. Ethics consultation
137. Cummings JR, Ponce NA, Mays VM. Comparing racial/ethnic in pediatrics: long-term experience from a pediatric oncology center.
differences in mental health service use among high-need subpopu- Am J Bioeth. 2016;15(5):3-17. doi:10.1080/15265161.2015.1021965.
lations across clinical and school-based settings. J Adolesc Health. Ethics.
2010;46(6):603-606. doi:10.1016/j.jadohealth.2009.11.221S1054- 151. Lutz T, Lampert A, Hoffmann GF, Ries M. Novel treatments for rare
139X(09)00645-4 [pii]. rheumatologic disorders: analysis of the impact of 30 years of the
138. Kozer E. Medication errors in children. Pediatric Drugs. 2009;11:52-54. US orphan drug act. Orphanet J Rare Dis. 2016;11(1):60. doi:10.1186/
doi:10.2165/0148581-200911010-00017. s13023-016-0443-x.
139. Hardmeier A, Tsourounis C, Moore M, et al. Pediatric medication 152. Hubinette MM, Ajjawi R, Dharamsi S. Family physician preceptors’
administration errors and workflow following implementation conceptualizations of health advocacy. Acad Med. 2014;89(11):1502-
of a bar code medication administration system. J Healthc Qual. 1509. doi:10.1097/ACM.0000000000000479.
2014;36(4):54-61. doi:10.1111/jhq.12071. 153. Dharamsi S, Ho A, Spadafora SM, Woollard R. The physician as
140. Cox ED, Carayon P, Hansen KW, et al. Parent perceptions of children’s health advocate: translating the quest for social responsibility into
hospital safety climate. BMJ Qual Saf. 2013;22(8):664-671. doi:10.1136/ medical education and practice. Acad Med. 2011;86(9):1108-1113.
bmjqs-2012-001727. doi:10.1097/ACM.0b013e318226b43b.

Anda mungkin juga menyukai