Anda di halaman 1dari 6

fHA, xvi (1985)

DID COPERNICUS OWE A DEBT TO ARISTARCHUS?

OWEN GINGERICH,
Harvard-Smithsonian Center for Astrophysics

During Copernicus's lifetime, in the early years ofthe sixteenth century, very little
was known in western Europe of Aristarchus. Our best source for Aristarchus's
heliocentric ideas, the Sand-reckoner of Archimedes, was not published until
1544, the year after Copernicus died.' In our modern era of library catalogues,
reference indices, and data retrieval systems it is easy but anachronistic to imagine
that Copernicus could have consulted a manuscript in Italy when he was
beginning to learn Greek. In fact, Copernicus relied almost entirely on printed
works for his information, and there is only a single case where we know for sure
that he used a manuscript source.? Even the encyclopaedist Giorgio Valla, who
published various translations of Archimedes, did not mention the Sand-reckoner
in his De expetendis et fugiendis rebus opus (Venice, 1501).3
Of course, Copernicus profited indirectly from Aristarchus's work on the sizes
and distances of the Sun and Moon: the basic idea of using the size of the Earth's
shadow as measured during a lunar eclipse was transmitted through Hipparchus
and is found, although in a drastically revised form, in Ptolemy's Almagest, and
the diagram for this method appears in Book IV, Chapter 19 of Copernicus's De
revolutionibus. However, the question of greatest interest is how much
Copernicus might have known directly of Aristarchus, particularly concerning his
heliocentric ideas.
In the autograph manuscript of Copernicus's De revolutionibus, still preserved
at the Jagiellonian Library in Cracow, the name of Aristarchus of Samos appears
six times.' I shall first mention five relatively uninteresting entries in the part of his
manuscript submitted for publication. In three places, Copernicus by mistake
attributes to Aristarchus a value of the obliquity of the ecliptic that should have
been credited to Erathosthenes. The mistake was due to his misinterpretation of
the word "Archusianus" appearing in the 1515 Almagest (1.12, f. 9v), which was
Gerhard of Cremona's attempt to render the Arabic transcription of
Eratosthenes's name.' In a fourth citation Copernicus originally mentioned
Aristarchus in connection with the motion of precession, but before publication
he correctly changed the entry to Aristyllus. The fifth citation includes
Aristarchus in a list of those who believed that the year was exactly 365Y4 days
long, a not very helpful and probably erroneous statement. 6 Thus, the name of
Aristarchus appears only four times in De revolutionibus as it was finally printed
in 1543, and at least three of these are erroneous.
There is, however, a sixth reference to Aristarchus in the manuscript, far and
away the most interesting one because it refers to the Greek astronomer's
cosmology, but it was crossed out before publication. What Copernicus had
written in the passage is as follows:
And if we should admit that the motion of the Sun and Moon could be
demonstrated even if the Earth is fixed, then with respect to the other

0021-8286/85/1601-0037 $2.00 e 1985 Science History Publications Ltd

Downloaded from jha.sagepub.com at Bobst Library, New York University on May 26, 2015
38 Owen Gingerich
wandering bodies there is less agreement. It is credible that for these and
similar causes (and not because of the reasons that Aristotle mentions and
rejects), Philolaus believed in the mobility of the Earth and some even say
that Aristarchus of Samos was of that opinion. But since such things could
not be comprehended except by a keen intellect and continuing diligence,
Plato does not conceal the fact that there were very few philosophers in that
time who mastered the study of celestial motions.'
The foregoing passage says very little about the Aristarchan cosmology. Had
Copernicus known more, he surely would have been happy to mention it, since he
needed all the support that he could muster for his own unorthodox views, and
since he quotes with enthusiasm other possible geokineticists from Antiquity with
less reputable credentials. In a curious way, Copernicus's intellectual heritage is
closely rooted to the island of Samos, but to Pythagoras rather than Aristarchus;
he repeatedly cites the Pythagoreans and he knew full well their geokineticism
because of Aristotle's protests in De cae/o. In order to examine the question of
what debt, if any, Copernicus owed to Aristarchus, we must inquire about the
reasons for this deletion and we must examine in detail what knowledge
Copernicus had about his illustrious Greek predecessor.f
Throughout most of his life, Copernicus worked in comparative isolation on his
astronomical system. By the time he was in his sixties, he had little hope, or
intention, of publishing his voluminous manuscript. However, in the spring of
1539 a young astronomer from Wittenberg arrived, eager to learn more detail of
Copernicus's radical cosmology. Inflamed with enthusiasm for the new system,
Georg Joachim Rheticus urged the ageing Copernicus to put the finishing touches
on his manuscript so that it could be taken to Germany for publication. In this
process a number of editorial changes were made in the manuscript, including the
one that had eliminated the earliest reference to Aristarchus.
Originally, Copernicus had laid out his treatise in seven major sections or
books. The first dealt entirely with cosmology, ending with the fleeting reference
to Aristarchus and with Copernicus's own longer Latin translation of the so-
called "Letter from Lysis", a brief work dealing with Pythagorean philosophy.
The translation may simply have been one of those youthful exercises used by
Copernicus to improve his skill in Greek. In any event, upon second thought
Copernicus decided that the "Letter from Lysis" was not really germane to his
purpose, so the entire section was withdrawn and the original Book II on
mathematical methods was joined directly onto Book I on cosmology.
Various suggestions have been advanced as to why Copernicus eliminated the
"Letter from Lysis" (and therefore also the brief reference to Aristarchus) from his
text, but it seems to me that no elaborate explanation is required. The "Letter
from Lysis", emphasizing the desire of the Pythagoreans to keep their philosophy
secret, may have been appropriate for a manuscript destined to gather dust on the
shelves of the cathedral library, but in a printed treatise it offered an awkward and
largely irrelevant digression. From an editorial viewpoint, it was eminently
sensible to remove the material and to paraphrase some of the ideas in the
introductory preface to the Pope. This is precisely what Copernicus did.?
When Copernicus reworked the omitted material into the dedicatory letter to
Pope Paul III, he mentioned the "Letter from Lysis" in the first paragraph.
However, at a later point where Copernicus mentions his precursors, he by then

Downloaded from jha.sagepub.com at Bobst Library, New York University on May 26, 2015
Copernicus and Aristarchus 39
felt it would be more authoritative to quote his source in the original Greek. Thus
Copernicus set down several Greek sentences from the Opinions of the
philosophers, a work attributed to Plutarch. In translation they read:
Some think that the Earth remains at rest. But Philolaus the Pythagorean
believes that, like the Sun and Moon, it revolves around the Fire in an
oblique circle. Heraclides of Pontus and Ecphantus the Pythagorean make
the Earth move, not in a progressive motion, but like a wheel in a rotation
from west to east about its own centre.tv
That this passage is not really from Plutarch but from a pseudononymous work
by Aetius Amidenus is of no consequence to us here - what matters is that
Copernicus chose to quote this particular paragraph, probably because in the
Latin edition it was conspicuously labelled "concerning the motion of the
Earth".'! Because the name of Aristarchus simply did not appear here, the direct
reference to Copernicus's intellectual ancestor was quite inadvertently omitted. In
fact, Aetius (Pseudo-Plutarch) had actually mentioned Aristarchus a few pages
earlier in his Opinions of the philosophers, but in a place where he discussed
eclipses. The text says: "Aristarchus counts the Sun among the fixed stars; he has
the Earth moving around the ecliptic and therefore by its inclinations he wants the
Sun to be shadowed."12 This vague and confusing passage may well have been the
only hint Copernicus had about Aristarchus as an architect of a heliocentric
system. Had Copernicus been able to search the literature more carefully, he
might have found two other references to Aristarchus in genuine works of
Plutarch, one of which clearly witnessed to the heliocentric idea in Antiquity. In
the Platonic questions, Query VIII, Plutarch writes:
Ought the Earth ... be understood to have been devised not as confined and
at rest, but as turning and whirling about in the way set forth later by
Aristarchus and Seleucus, by the former only as an hypothesis, but by
Seleucus beyond that as a statement of fact?13
In On the face in the orb of the Moon, Plutarch mentions Aristarchus of Samos
three times, twice in connection with his treatise On size and distances, but in the
third as follows:
Thereupon Lucius laughed and said: "Oh, sir,just don't bring suit against us
for impiety as Cleanthes thought that the Greeks ought to charge
Aristarchus the Samian with impiety on the ground that he was disturbing
the hearth of the Universe because he sought to save the phenomena by
assuming that the Heaven is at rest while the Earth is revolving along the
ecliptic and at the same time is rotating about its own axis."14
Had Copernicus known of these references, particularly the latter one, he likely
would have quoted it. But there is not a shred of evidence that Copernicus knew
anything about Aristarchus as a heliocentrist except for the single rather cryptic
passage on eclipses in the Opinions of the philosophers.
How was it that Copernicus even saw the Opinions ofthe philosophers? It was
printed in Greek in Venice in 1509 in the Plutarchi opuscula, a work that also
contained both of the genuine Plutarchian references to Aristarchus's cosmology.
Professor Edward Rosen has assumed that Copernicus consulted this dense and
bulky edition, noting only the passage from the Opinions and overlooking the
other references to Aristarchus.'> There is, however, no firm evidence that

Downloaded from jha.sagepub.com at Bobst Library, New York University on May 26, 2015
40 Owen Gingerich
Copernicus either owned or had access to the 1509 Greek text, nor do we know
how fluent he was in reading Greek. It seems to me more likely that he would have
first found the information in a Latin source, and indeed, a 1516 Latin edition of
the Opinions of the philosophers with numerous convenient subheadings was
available in the library of the cathedral where Copernicus worked. Copernicus
himself wrote: "I first found in Cicero that Hicetas supposed the Earth to move.
Later I also discovered in Plutarch that certain others were of this opinion."16
Perhaps by "later" Copernicus meant "after 1518", when the nine items
including the Latin Pseudo-Plutarch were bound together in the volume owned
by the cathedral library. 17 Because he had the idea for the heliocentric system by
1514 if not earlier, Copernicus would then have read Aetius's Opinions of the
philosophers only after he had firmly and independently grasped the heliocentric
hypothesis.
Much later, when Copernicus was making the final revisions of his De
revolutionibus, he could have sought the original Greek text for the passage he
knew in Latin from the Basel 1531 Greek edition of the Opinions. 18 If this scenario
is correct then Copernicus never saw the genuine Plutarchian references to
Aristarchus.
What other evidence do we have concerning how and where Copernicus arrived
at his heliocentric cosmology? We simply do not know if Copernicus accepted
heliocentrism as an undergraduate in Cracow in the early 1490s, as a graduate
student in Italy between 1496and 1503, or after his subsequent return to Poland.
Nor is there any clear-cut path that led Copernicus to his heliocentric cosmology.
Like Aristarchus's conception nearly two millenia earlier, Copernicus's
cosmology was a great adventure of the mind, a mental construction not forced by
any observations and in fact contrary to the immediate senses.
Space does not permit an examination of the beautiful argument, based on one
of the few extant early manuscript sources from Copernicus, that the Polish
astronomer arrived at his heliocentric system through a Tychonic geo-heliocentric
system.'! If, indeed, Copernicus groped his way to the heliocentric synthesis via an
intermediate geocentric scheme, then it is all the more unlikely that knowledge of
Aristarchus had any practical influence on his work. Copernicus, like most
modern scientists, presents his finished plan and says almost nothing about the
pathway to his discovery. Yet there is no question but that harmonious bonds of
commensurability, linking the phenomena together "as if by a golden chain",
were ultimately persuasive in Copernicus's mind: he liked the idea of placing the
Sun, clearly a unique body among the planets, in a unique central place, and he
was impressed by the rhythmic regularity possible with the heliocentric
arrangement - with Mercury, the fastest planet, revolving nearest the Sun, with
Saturn, the slowest, placed at the farthest position, and with the Earth falling in
the natural sequence between Venus and Mars. The elegance ofthis arrangement
he could not have discovered directly in any possible citations from Aristarchus.
There is no question but that Aristarchus had the priority of the heliocentric idea.
Yet there is no evidence that Copernicus owed him anything. 19 As far as we can tell
both the idea and its justification were found independently by Copernicus.
It is not really the task of the historian of science to assess the comparative
originality of these two scientific giants. The heliocentric cosmology was
convincing neither to the contemporaries of Aristarchus nor to those of

Downloaded from jha.sagepub.com at Bobst Library, New York University on May 26, 2015
Copernicus and Aristarchus 41
Copernicus, but Copernicus had the good luck to be born not only at a time when
science was beginning to reach, so to say, a critical mass, but also at a time when
scientific works were beginning to be printed; therefore his arguments survived
and convinced a later generation of astronomers. For better or for worse,
scientific credit goes generally not so much for the originality of the concept as for
the persuasiveness of the arguments. Thus, Aristarchus will undoubtedly continue
to be remembered as "The Copernicus of Antiquity", rather than Copernicus as
"The Aristarchus of the Renaissance".

REFERENCES
I. The famous passage in the Sand-reckoner reads: "But Aristarchus brought out a book consisting
of certain hypotheses, wherein it appears, as a consequence of the assumptions made, that the
universe is many times greater than the universe just mentioned. His hypotheses are that the
fixed stars and the Sun remain unmoved, that the Earth revolves about the Sun in the
circumference of a circle, the Sun lying in the middle of the orbit, and that the sphere of the
fixed stars, situated about the same centre as the Sun, is so great that the circle in which he
supposes the Earth to revolve bears such a proportion to the distance of the fixed stars as the
centre of the sphere bears to its surface." The translation is from Sir Thomas Heath,
Aristarchus of Samos (Oxford, 1913),302.
2. These are the three observations of Mercury by Bernard Walther, not published until 1544.
3. Even though Valla failed to mention the Sand-reckoner, he did in fact own the oldest and most
complete manuscript of Archimedes, namely Greek manuscript A, which is the source for our
text of the Sand-reckoner. Furthermore, Valla had seen a translation made by Jacobus
Cremonensis around 1450; Jacobus's own copy of the translation went to the Marciana in
Venice in 1468, where it remains today (Marciana f.a.327). A copy of this translation was sent
to Nicholas of Cusa, and Regiomontanus made another copy around 1462 which was the basis
for the printed Basel edition of 1544. I am indebted to Marshall Clagett for these details, found
in his Archimedes in the Middle Ages, iii, part III, The medieval Archimedes in the
Renaissance. 1450-1565 (Philadelphia, 1978), chap. 2.
4. This is established with a complete word-in-context index prepared by Heribert Nobis at the
Copernicus Forschungsstelle in Munich, and with the index and notes in Edward Rosen's
translation, Nicholas Copernicus, On the revolutions (Warsaw-Cracow, 1978).The references
are found in Book III, chaps. 2, 6, and 13.
5. See N. M. Swerdlow and O. Neugebauer, Mathematical astronomy in Copernicus' De
revolutionibus (New York, 1984), n. 1I on p. 133.
6. Probably taken from Censorinus, De die natali liber, chap. 19; this small work appeared in at least
eight collections printed during Copernicus's lifetime.
7. Based on the translation on p. 513 in Owen Gingerich, "From Copernicus to Kepler:
Heliocentrism as model and reality", Proceedings ofthe American Philosophical Society, cxvii
(1973),513-22.
8. This task is rendered much easier by the article and notes of Rosen cited in refs 4 and 15,and by the
review by Byron Emerson Wall, "Anatomy of a precurser, The historiography of Aristarchos of
Sarnos", Studies in the history and philosophy of science, vi (1975), 201-28.
9. I feel that it is unfortunate that the two most recent English translators of Copernicus's book, A.
M. Duncan (1976) and Edward Rosen (1978), have disregarded his decision and have inserted
the cancelled "Letter from Lysis" directly into the text rather than into an appendix.
10. Aetius Amidenus [Pseudo-Plutarch], De placitis philosophorum 111.13; Hermann Diels,
Doxographi Graeci (Stuttgart, 1929); translation from Rosen, On the revolutions, 5.
II. De motione terrae, f. 20v, De philosophorum placitis (Strassburg, 1516); I am indebted to Jerzy
Dobrzycki for access to a microfilm of the Uppsala copy of this rare edition - see below, ref. 17.
12. Ibid. f. 14, Aristarchus solem haerentibus stellis annumerat terram vero circulum solis orbem
versat itaque eius inclinationibus obumbrari solem voluit. The Greek text (from Diels,
Doxographi Graeci, 355) is: 'Apicr'tCLPXO<; 'tOY fjl.lOv'icr'tllcrt /lE'ta 'troy UltI.CLVroV, 'tTtv creYi'iv
K1VE1ltEpt rov Ttl.lCLKOV KUKI.OV KCLt KCL'ta 'ta<; 'tCLU'tll<; i:yKl.icrEl<; crK\(i~EcreCLl rov 3icrKOV.
13. Harold Cherniss (trans.), Plutarch's Moralia, xiii(Loeb Library, Cambridge, Mass., 1976),77,79.
14. Based on Harold Cherniss and William C. Helmbold (trans.), Plutarch's Moralia, xii (Loeb
Library, Cambridge, Mass., 1957), 55.

Downloaded from jha.sagepub.com at Bobst Library, New York University on May 26, 2015
42 Owen Gingerich
15. Edward Rosen, "Aristarchus of Samos and Copernicus", Bulletin of the American Society of
Papyrologists, xv (1978), 85-93, esp. pp. 89-90.
16. Rosen translation, On the revolutions, 4.
17. This collection of short works is still found in the Uppsala University Library - see item 42, p. 380,
in Pawel Czartoryski, "The library of Copernicus", pp. 355-96 in Science and history: Studies in
honor of Edward Rosen (Studio Copernicana, xvi) (Wroclaw, 1978).
18. See Noel M. Swerdlow, 'The derivation and first draft of Copernicus's Planetary theory",
Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, cxvii (1973), 423-512.
19. After I presented this paper in Samos in 1980, Prof. L. Biermann pointed out Eugen Brachvogel's
"Nikolaus Koppernikus und Aristarch von Samos", Zeitschrift fur die Geschichte und
Altertumskunde Ermlands, xxv (1935), 703-67. Brachvogel's conclusions, more
philosophically based, are similar: "Kein Faden, nichts, fuhrt da von Aristarch zu
Koppernikus. Was dieser an der Weite des Himmels erschaute, hat er fur sich allein erspaht."

JOURNAL OF THE BRITISH


ASTRONOMICAL ASSOCIATION

Edited by Colin A. Ronan

The Journal contains papers on observational and


theoretical astronomy, and also regularly includes
papers on the history of astronomy. Recently published
have been Ptolemy's Almagest: Fourteen Centuries of
Neglect by Norriss S. Hetherington and Colin A. Ronan
and Paris Observatory in 1784 - Cassini de Thury's
Legacy to Jean-Dominique Cassini by Ian Howard-Duff.

Published once every two months, each volume


beginning in December. Price £2.75 per issue, from the
British Astronomical Association, Burlington House,
Piccadilly, London, W1V ONL.

Downloaded from jha.sagepub.com at Bobst Library, New York University on May 26, 2015

Anda mungkin juga menyukai