Anda di halaman 1dari 3

Averis, K., & Moran, M. (Eds.). (2010).

Le mensonge: multidisciplinary perspectives


in French studies. Cambridge Scholars Publishing.

Condren, C. (1997). Political Lying. In Satire, Lies and Politics (pp. 111-143).
Palgrave Macmillan, London.

Denery, Dallas G., II. (2015). The Devil Wins: A History of Lying from the Garden
of Eden to the Enlightenment. Princeton: Princeton University Press. pp. xi, 331.
ISBN: 978-0-691-16321-5 (hardback).

Hardin, K. J. Linguistic Approaches to Lying and Deception. In The Oxford Handbook


of Lying.

Levin, I. I. (2005). Sobre la semi�tica de la mentira. Entretextos: Revista


Electr�nica Semestral de Estudios Semi�ticos de la Cultura, (5), 6.

Mecke, J. (Ed.). (2007). Cultures of lying: theories and practice of lying in


society, literature, and film. Galda & Wilch.

Nissan, E. (2008). Epistemic formulae, argument structures, and a narrative on


identity and deception: a formal representation from the AJIT subproject within
AURANGZEB. Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence, 54(4), 293-362.

Pelc, J. (1990). Sur la notion de mensonge, du point de vue de la s�miotique.


Studia Semiotyczne= Etudes S�miotiques, (16-17), 289-297.

Raskin, V. (1986). Semantics of lying. Aspects of language: Studies in honour of


Mario Alinei, 2, 443-469.

Ruch, W. I. L. L. I. B. A. L. D. (1998). Humor measurement tools. W: W. Ruch


(red.), The sense of humor: Explorations of a personality characteristic, 405-412.

Weinrich, H. (2005). The linguistics of lying and other essays. University of


Washington Press.

BASIC
Resumen: El documento considera una mentira como un modelo de comunicaci�n, y luego
se enfoca en el an�lisis de los conceptos de mentiras en el lenguaje y la cultura
serbios. Resulta que la mentira en la creaci�n popular serbia a menudo se
conceptualizaba como una fabricaci�n divertida destinada al entretenimiento.
Adem�s, se registr� el concepto de mentiras como un pronunciamiento perjudicial de
falsedad, motivado por el uso y la obtenci�n de poder. Las mentiras da�inas en las
actuaciones folkl�ricas serbias se relacionan principalmente con el poderoso
"Otro", mientras que los miembros de su propia comunidad generalmente se atribuyen
a una mentira inocente y humor�stica o como un marginado. En la cultura serbia
moderna, la mentira se asocia m�s a menudo con los pol�ticos y los medios de
comunicaci�n como portadores del poder social.

DENERY
Reviewed by:
Edwin D. Craun
Washington and Lee University, Emeritus
craune@wlu.edu
The inevitable question fronts Dallas Denery's The Devil Wins, forming the title to
his introduction: "Is it ever acceptable to lie?" (1). There might be many ways of
writing a history of responses to this insistent question, and this book contains
several of them--and more, for it covers not only lying itself as communicating
something false with an intention to deceive but also flattery, hypocrisy,
dissimulation, concealing the truth, and much more. It is, in short, a history of
deception, not surprising from a historian of ideas whose work has centered on
epistemological uncertainty from his first book, Seeing and Being Seen in the Later
Middle Ages, which read confessionalia and perspectivist optics together. As this
loose grouping and the very phrasing of the question indicate, Denery is not very
interested in the semiotics of lying (What makes an act of speech a lie?) or in
ethical analysis (What is the moral character and gravity of a given lie?).
Instead, bookended by the serpent's words in Eden as interpreted in patristic
exegesis and by Rousseau for whom society itself is the source of deceit, The Devil
Wins sets forth lucidly the arguments of texts that grapple with how human beings
should live in a world full of deception. To counter the common scholarly narrative
contrasting Augustinian-inflected medieval prohibitions of lying with early modern
acceptance of dissimulation, Denery chooses his texts not only from biblical
exegesis, theology, and philosophy, but from conduct books, political treatises,
dialogues about the status of women. Indeed, he writes five separate narrative
histories of lying, each extended from Christian antiquity (never before that, even
where Aristotle and the Stoics might be drawn in) to the eighteenth century, each
focused on a different figure in light of another question: For whom is it
acceptable to lie?: the Devil (not fitting all too well this second question of
"for whom"), God (more properly, "Can God lie?"), human beings in general,
courtiers, and women. While he sets aside the status of fiction (Do poets lie?) and
politics (When is it acceptable for a political leader to lie?), who could complain
that The Devil Wins lacks reach and ambition?

To counter the "popular narrative" of a medieval/early modern divide on lying,


Denery writes a general history. Figures, like St. Bernard or Bernard Mandeville,
are briefly identified--"perhaps the most famous religious figure of the twelfth
century" (4) for the former. The story of the Fall in Eden is told over several
pages. Aphoristic sentences open and close sections. Scholarly debates are ignored;
indeed, scholarship is consigned to brief notes. Well-known texts, like Augustine's
Contra mendacium and Christine de Pizan's Book of the City of Ladies, are
foregrounded. Yet any medievalist is bound to learn a great deal from The Devil
Wins: the great range of texts, unexpected and illuminating pairings (Bernard
Mandeville and the Jansenist theologian Pierre Nicole), Denery's unfailingly
patient exposition, and the increasingly fruitful interchange between his several
histories guarantee this.

Denery's first two chapters, "The Devil," and "God," work from the Gospel and
Paulinian contrast of the Devil's destructive falsehoods and God's creative truth.
The first--dominated by Augustine, Nicholas of Lyra, and Luther--constitutes a
brief history of the faulty exegesis initiated by the serpent. While medieval
exegetes explore the riddles and gaps of the Genesis story of deception and fall,
Luther focuses on the serpent's additions to God's word, tempting Eve to evade the
simple obedience it demands. While for Luther exegetical difference results from
struggles between the Devil's cunning and the one, true, literal meaning, Denery
tellingly uses Acontius to show how that difference could create, in later writers,
suspicion of "any claim to exegetical certainty" (57). "God" sets forth the
tension, running throughout the Middle Ages, between the theologians' just, good,
and omnipotent God and the biblical God who seems, at least, to deceive even the
faithful in specific historical circumstances. While medievals resolve
inconsistencies by developing God's prudence and the limits of human perception,
Luther and Calvin find fraud acceptable if it accomplishes what an unknowable God
wills. In the kind of final twist that makes this book so interesting, Denery
traces how Descartes sets aside the God of the Bible who speaks to, and interacts
with, humans, replacing him with a beneficent God who, far from deceiving us,
invites us to know truth through the natural laws he has established.

"Human Beings" is the heart of this book. Denery traces how tension between
Augustine's absolute prohibition of lying and lies by biblical figures drives
Catholic thinkers down through Pascal as they search for premises to support ways
of explaining those lies. (And I write "Catholic" advisedly for he omits, without
explanation, Reformation writing.) Denery understands how Augustine saw every lie
as a turning from God as truth and the speaker's inner word, although that
ontological approach tempts Denery to scant the importance of consequences in
Augustine's ethics of lying. Even more penetrating is his exposition, first, of
Dominican thinkers for whom just doings with others create another frame for
evaluating lying (that is, a frame other than that of God as truth) and, then, of
Franciscans who develop the primacy of the speaker's intention. Finally, in a
trenchant account of the successors to these scholastics, chiefly Antoninus of
Florence and Navarrus, he shows convincingly that dissimulation may be seen as
virtuous, depending on calculated outcomes and good intentions--a move that renders
licit such devices as the equivocation and mental reservation so deplored by
Pascal.

In his final chapters, Denery turns to two social groups commonly branded as arch-
deceivers in medieval culture: courtiers and women. In the first he challenges the
historiographical account that locates modernity in the early modern court's loss
of confidence in traditional beliefs and institutions. John of Salisbury and
Christine de Pizan, he argues, already advocate practicing a prudent deception that
modifies ethical principles to suit circumstances because only then can the
courtier and court lady fulfill their duties in an undecipherable and treacherous
world. Renaissance conduct books extend the value of strategic lying by presenting
it as so beneficial to the speaker and others that lies actually make civil society
possible. "Women" turns first to the well-trodden ground of "Matheolus" and
Christine de Pizan, of women as born liars, deception rising from their very
bodies, and of a defense of women's constancy and prudence arising from women's own
experience. What may be new for medievalists is how Denery lays out the strategies
of early modern Venetian women writers who expose men as habitual liars in their
very lying about women as congenital liars and in their preoccupation with
adornment, emblematic of their verbal deceptions. Finally, he intertwines courtiers
and women by considering Madame de Scud�ry's salon culture, in which women create
social and political harmony in a competitive world by concealing self-interest
through complaisance and nonchalant conversation.

As I have indicated throughout this review, readers who know well certain texts
will learn little from Denery's three-to-five page expositions of their arguments
about deception. Nevertheless, the sheer generic and chronological range of
material guarantees that any reader will encounter exciting new arguments about
deception, set forth with clarity and analytical rigor (the latter especially as
the book moves on). Moreover, a trenchant conclusion not only synthesizes all the
material but uses Rousseau to argue that the real shift in the history of lying
comes when its beginning lies not in Genesis but in humankind's movement from a
state of nature to socialization. This important book's reach and ambition is amply
vindicated in this conclusion in which the old alternatives--spanning Christian
antiquity, the Middle Ages, the Renaissance, and the early eighteenth century--of
rejecting or accepting a mendacious world yield to a third way: being true to one's
sentiments, even when one lies, as a natural solution to a natural problem.

Anda mungkin juga menyukai