Anda di halaman 1dari 3

doi:10.

1093/brain/awp218 Brain 2009: 132; 2303–2305 | 2303

BRAIN
A JOURNAL OF NEUROLOGY

FROM THE ARCHIVES

The cerebral basis of consciousness. By W. Russell Brain. Brain 1950: 73; 465-479; and The physiological basis of
consciousness. A critical review by Russell Brain. Brain 1958: 81; 426–455.

In his presidential address to the Neurological Section of the Royal


Society of Medicine, delivered in October 1950, Russell Brain
(Fig. 1) aims to ‘make a broad survey of some aspect of
neurology . . . to consider how far the various pieces of the
jigsaw are fitting together, and what kind of picture they are
making. If the action of the nervous system is integrative, it is

Downloaded from brain.oxfordjournals.org by guest on November 4, 2010


doubly desirable that we should try to integrate knowledge of
it’. His topic is consciousness. This exists alongside awareness,
perception and emotion but is necessarily not independent of
these conscious states. What happens in the nervous system
when a conscious state is experienced must therefore be the
basis for studies of consciousness itself. Although their spatial
and temporal patterns of firing may vary, the character of
electrical conduction does not differ materially in pathways that
transmit the impressions of sensation, sight and hearing or any
other afferent impulses. The clue to consciousness lies more in
the fact that focal stimulation of the cerebral cortex can only be
perceived and localized to a specific part—say, the big toe—by
relating that structure to the entire body schema: ‘to perceive a
part of the body as pricked is to perceive it in relationship with the
whole of the rest of the body, pin-pointed as it were upon the
body-image . . . we can appreciate touch without knowing its
whereabouts, but we cannot know a whereabouts that is vacant
of any sensory content’. It follows that electrical activity of the
sensory cortex must simultaneously cause widespread irradiation Figure 1 Walter Russell Brain, first Baron Brain (1895–1966).
of impulses throughout both hemispheres. John Hughlings-Jackson
(1835–1911) has already made the point that the ‘. . . anatomical
substrata of subject-consciousness represent . . . all parts of the ability to remember that he ever possessed a[nother] half of the
body, mainly sensorily, in relation to one another . . . [they] are body’. It follows that, in this situation, the intact cortex has
centres of universal coordination . . . or synthesizing centres’. adjusted and accepts that the half-body of which it is aware is
These cortical centres are no more than nodal points for onward now the whole. Taking forward his argument, Russell Brain reflects
distribution of sensory stimuli. Searching for an anatomical sub- on the observation of William Grey Walter (1910–77) that visual
strate to these nodal points, physiologists have identified area 1 in imagery reproduces electroencephalographic alpha rhythms
the post-central cortex which, other than for the face, has strictly identical to those observed when subjects view a real object,
contralateral representation, and area 2 that registers both sides of indicating that imagination and reality deploy the same neuronal
the body but with a preference for crossed structures. networks. Karl Lashley (1890–1958) has shown that blind animals
These principles are nicely illustrated by the clinical condition of trained to navigate a maze lose their way when the visual cortex is
anosagnosia in which loss of sensation is combined with failure to removed. Following head injury with frontal lobe damage, one of
recognize that the affected part exists at all: ‘we can only miss Russell Brain’s patients with ‘loss of revisualization’ could recognize
something if we remember that we once had it . . . the lesion in people, even after brief acquaintance, but never visualize them;
such cases has destroyed not only the patient’s present awareness nor could he remember details of a building plan (his trade)
of his body-image but also neurones which are essential to his without constant reference to the architect’s plans, or routes

ß The Author (2009). Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of the Guarantors of Brain. All rights reserved.
For Permissions, please email: journals.permissions@oxfordjournals.org
2304 | Brain 2009: 132; 2303–2305 From the Archives

when travelling even though he recognized the landmarks as each in the brainstem either through structural damage or electrical
was passed; and even his dreams were devoid of images despite discharges.
awareness of the narrative. The retention of ‘a propositional Having organized his thoughts on the nature of conscious
memory of things which cannot be visualized . . . [provides] a pre- states, 8 years later Russell Brain feels that he should now tackle
cise experiment on the value of consciousness compared with both its anatomical and physiological bases. Taking forward the
unconscious mechanisms in the visual sphere’. Other work discussion at a symposium from 1954 on ‘Brain mechanisms and
suggests that the ‘centre for revisualization’ is Brodmann area consciousness’ edited by ED Adrian (1889–1977) in which ideas
19 but this is no more than the critical node in the widespread were rehearsed on ‘experienced integration’, ‘dynamic abstrac-
neural network for imagery which is ‘set vibrating in an almost tion’, ‘momentary distributions of patterns’ and ‘cortical electro-
infinite variety of patterns in space and time’. genesis’ as constituents of consciousness, Russell Brain (now editor
The nervous system combines both category-specific (semantic, of Brain) focuses on the role of the brainstem central reticular
in modern parlance) and particular (episodic) memories. Survival— formation. But he has difficulty in defining this anatomical and
say of a mouse encountering a cat—depends on recognizing a physiological entity linked to wakefulness and electroencephalo-
particular class without being distracted by the detailed variations graphic arousal. What impresses Russell Brain is that the reticular
of its individual members: ‘the nervous system has solved formation shows evidence for delayed activation linked to impulses
this . . . [by introducing] plasticity . . . so that [reaction] is not a in ascending brainstem sensory pathways that relay in the thala-
mosaic of all the individual features . . . but a pattern which con- mus en route to the cortex. Barbiturate anaesthetics appear to
disconnect this central processing, and hence awareness and

Downloaded from brain.oxfordjournals.org by guest on November 4, 2010


stitutes an abstraction . . . common to all individuals of the group’.
Small birds recognize a hawk solely from the features of outline arousal, from the crude appreciation of incoming sensations.
and movement. Russell Brain’s suggestion for the process that Transection of the ascending reticular formation results in pro-
longed sleep. Conversely, stimulation of the ascending reticular
abstracts the essential patterns of vision, music and speech, inter
formation leads to desynchronization of the electroencephalogram
alia, is the derivation of perceptual concepts from ‘physiological
and waking. Others consider this view of consciousness, arousal
universals’. But he senses that consciousness must also have
of the ascending reticular formation associated with centripetal
an anatomical basis; and this is less easy to find. Certainly,
sensory stimulation, to be limited and argue for more complex
physiological universals involve the diencephalic nuclei, especially
multi-directional activity as consciousness waxes and wanes:
the thalamus which has rich and widespread reciprocal connec-
‘a slackening of activity of any region of the brain must result in
tions to the cortex. The thalamus may filter impulses and
a lowering of excitatory state in areas or nuclei – including the
distinguish those signals for which localization will eventually be
reticular formation – and so the whole of the synergic structures
needed—sensations referred to an anatomical part—from
are gradually affected. Doubtless ‘‘the functional depression’’ of
experiences that are more generic such as emotions.
the reticular formation . . . plays a predominant, if not always an
In a persuasive passage, Russell Brain argues that consciousness
initial, role in this process of cumulative ‘‘defacilitation’’ ‘.
adjusts automaticity and immediacy by adding space and time
Attempts at tracing the descending pathways that contribute
distance receptors, or delays, into reflex responses. Sir Charles
to consciousness show many inputs to the brainstem; and
Sherrington’s (1857–1952) introduction to the reissue of The
physiological studies suggest that, whatever their origin, these
Integrative Action Of The Nervous System (1947), his last word
act tonically and competitively on the reticular formation:
on the nervous system, makes the point: ‘. . . the brain is always
‘responses to a flashing light recorded from the occipital cortex
the part of the nervous system which is constructed upon and
of the cat were almost abolished when the animal was given fish
evolved upon the ‘‘distance-receptors’’ ‘. Russell Brain extends to smell’ and ‘the arrival of sensory impulses at a specific cortical
this concept to suggest that emotions are the manifestation in area [is] capable of exciting corticofugal impulses which have an
consciousness of the motive power that sustains action in time; inhibitory effect upon the afferent pathways of other sensory
short-term, as in the response to hunger, or lifelong, as in the modalities’. In the same way, perception depends on selecting
commitment to medical research; and, in animals, pouncing on from amongst a plethora of extraneous sensory stimuli in order
prey versus caring for the young. Russell Brain reflects how to focus on a single object or event whilst nevertheless attending
the recall of events requiring a delayed reflex response involves to the many additional components that contribute to an experi-
faithful representation by the cortex of the outside world through ence: ‘attention [uses] the discriminative power of the cortex to
symbolism and imagery. These images may bring aesthetic and focus consciousness upon a certain perceptual experience at any
other pleasurable dividends but primarily they determine response particular moment’.
and action; and they depend on memory. He points out that Sleep differs from the unconsciousness of coma, in that it is
memory is not exclusively a primate attribute: the worker honey- rapidly reversible and can be considered as a generalized with-
bee on returning to the hive indicates to other workers a new drawal of attention; waking involves the cortex in assessing an
source of food by a dance in which ‘the direction of action of afferent input and, if it is judged important, signalling on to the
gravity is symbolic of the direction of incidence of the sun’s rays’. diencephalon with ensuing arousal. In sleep and waking, there is
Finally, does unconsciousness, in which the quantum more than therefore reciprocal inhibition and facilitation of the cortex and
the content is lost, help us to understand consciousness? reticular formation. Sleep inhibits muscle tone and so, in turn,
Everything suggests that consciousness is impaired, to varying reduces afferent stimulatory proprioceptive activity thereby
degrees and with different consequences, when function is altered minimizing sensory disturbance of the slumbering ascending
From the Archives Brain 2009: 132; 2303–2305 | 2305

generating these attacks, the consensus is that a unilateral focus


fires into a more centrally placed (deep) structure—the centrifugal
downward spread mimicking the onset of sleep. This leads Russell
Brain to distinguish features of fits directly attributable to the focal
electrical discharge from those dependent upon ‘epileptic decon-
trol’ in which parts of the nervous system become unruly when
temporarily disconnected from the control of higher centres.
Now, Sir Russell Brain rehearses Sir Henry Head’s (1861–1940)
concept of brain ‘vigilance’, developed to explain why the
response of the nervous system varies with quality and complexity
of the stimulus more than its static amount—such diverse and
varying modes of activity demanding a state of vigilance or
choice in the response to stimulus. According to this analysis,
vigilance is consciousness. Head argued that regional pathology
may detach specific mental activities, such as perception and emo-
Figure 2 Coronal section at the level of the anterior corpora tion, and the psychical functions with which they are associated
quadrigemina showing necrosis involving the tegmentum on from overall activity of the mind, i.e. consciousness. Brain is not
both sides and on the left side (the right in the figure)
impressed and he rationalizes vigilance as an idea that, as his own

Downloaded from brain.oxfordjournals.org by guest on November 4, 2010


extending ventrally to involve the medial one-third of the
last word on neurology, Sir Henry Head had no time to refine or
substantia nigra and the medial one-fourth of the crus Loyez
stain. develop in more detail. Nonetheless, Sir Charles Sherrington did
seem to accept and apply Head’s concept of vigilance.
Satisfied with the concept of consciousness in terms of referen-
reticular formation. It follows that sleep and waking are enabled or cing perception to the body schema, and accepting its anatomical
prevented by behaviours that generally depress or alert the ner- and physiological basis in reciprocal connectivity between the
vous system. For Russell Brain, the existence of a diencephalic cortex and the brainstem reticular formation, Russell Brain wants
hypnagogic centre described by Walter Rudolph Hess to identify the separate contributions of these anatomical struc-
(1881–1973) seems improbable except insofar as the diencephalon tures to consciousness. He distinguishes situations in which there is
relays information conducted reciprocally between the brainstem disorder of the content of consciousness from the underlying state
and the cortex. of attention, vigilance or level of consciousness itself; and he spec-
As a clinician, Russell Brain wants to enhance his analysis of ulates on the nature of referring present experience to the past
consciousness through clinical examples but, curiously, this is and transferring this to a concept of the future, as in memory and
much the least coherent part of his review. W.H., aged 46 imagination, as an integral part of consciousness. Integration is lost
years, lapsed rapidly into a state of parasomnia [a term introduced with unconsciousness; and perceptual, emotional and temporal
by Sir Geoffrey Jefferson (1886–1961) in 1944] with minimal integration are altered in epilepsy. But is consciousness integrated
pyramidal signs and died 11 days later; at autopsy there was primarily in the cortex or the reticular formation and is one
evidence for embolic infarction involving the left thalamus and ‘higher’, in Jacksonian terms, than the other? Both Hughlings-
the brainstem bilaterally down to the junction of the anterior Jackson and Sherrington write of ‘higher’ in terms of most
and posterior corpora quadrigemina (Fig. 2). Self-evidently, this recent in evolutionary terms and synonymous with an expanded
lesion had destroyed the centre for consciousness. But the physiol- cerebral cortex. For them, the cortex is the acme of evolution. It
ogy of consciousness may be better explained by studying created the organ of mind and provides the anatomy of conscious-
reversible coma, whatever its cause. Lesions around the third ven- ness, making man ‘supreme amongst the paragon of animals’. But
tricle induce a state of akinetic mutism; expanding hemisphere Russell Brain is not comfortable with a formulation that elevates
lesions cause coma by compressing the midbrain through the the cortex as the seat of higher function detached from the unity
tentorium (coning); hypothalamic lesions cause restless and of the nervous system or from his preferred integrator of con-
uneasy sleep from which arousal is possible with alterations of sciousness: ‘is there any meaning in asking whether the cortex
temperature and respiratory and cardiovascular rhythms; and or the diencephalon of an artist or a poet . . . is . . . ‘‘higher’’ . . . we
posterior fossa lesions result in coma that best resembles peaceful should . . . conceive of the relationship between these two parts of
sleep. Even more intriguing are paroxysmal disturbances of the brain . . . as an integrative unity . . . such as that represented by
consciousness. On narcolepsy, Russell Brain engages a debate the yin and the yang symbols of Taoism intertwined in their
we have previously rehearsed (see Brain 2008: 131; 2532–5) in self-embracing circle’. As papers in the present issue illustrate
hinting at the difference of view between WA (William) Adie (pages 2531 and 2541), consciousness and unconsciousness
(1886–1935) and (Samuel Alexander) Kinnier Wilson (1878– remain enigmatic; and no more comprehensible to clinicians,
1937), but he does not arbitrate; and he has little to say on scientists and philosophers of the nervous system working now
hallucinations other than those that are associated with disordered than they were for Russell Brain writing in the 1950s.
consciousness. Hughlings-Jackson regarded grand mal and petit
mal seizures as ‘highest level fits’; and although modern electro- Alastair Compston
physiology has implicated the thalamic intralaminar nuclei in Cambridge

Anda mungkin juga menyukai