Anda di halaman 1dari 9

RESEARCH METHODOLOGY: DISCUSSION PAPER –

METHODOLOGY

Concept analysis and the building blocks of theory: misconceptions


regarding theory development
Elisabeth Bergdahl & Carina M. Berter€
o

Accepted for publication 11 March 2016

Correspondence to E. Bergdahl: BERGDAHL E. & BERTERO € C . M . ( 2 0 1 6 ) Concept analysis and the building
e-mail: bergdahl_elisabeth@hotmail.com blocks of theory: misconceptions regarding theory development. Journal of
Advanced Nursing 72(10), 2558–2566. doi: 10.1111/jan.13002
Elisabeth Bergdahl MScN PhD RN
Project Leader/Affiliated Researcher
Research and Development Unit, FOU nu,
Abstract
SLSO, Stockholm, Sweden Aim. The purpose of this article is to discuss the attempts to justify concepts
Faculty of Professional Studies, Nursing analysis as a way to construct theory – a notion often advocated in nursing.
Science, Nord University, Bod€o, Norway Background. The notion that concepts are the building blocks or threads from
which theory is constructed is often repeated. It can be found in many articles
Carina M. Berter€o BSc MScN PhD RNT and well-known textbooks. However, this notion is seldom explained or
Professor
defended. The notion of concepts as building blocks has also been questioned by
Division of Nursing Science, Department of
several authors. However, most of these authors seem to agree to some degree
Medical and Health Sciences, Link€
oping
University, Sweden that concepts are essential components from which theory is built.
Design. Discussion paper.
Data sources. Literature was reviewed to synthesize and debate current
knowledge.
Implications for nursing. Our point is that theory is not built by concepts
analysis or clarification and we will show that this notion has its basis in some
serious misunderstandings. We argue that concept analysis is not a part of sound
scientific method and should be abandoned.
Conclusion. The current methods of concept analysis in nursing have no
foundation in philosophy of science or in language philosophy. The type of
concept analysis performed in nursing is not a way to ‘construct’ theory. Rather,
theories are formed by creative endeavour to propose a solution to a scientific
and/or practical problem. The bottom line is that the current style and form of
concept analysis in nursing should be abandoned in favour of methods in line
with modern theory of science.

Keywords: concept analysis, epistemology, nursing theory, philosophy, research


methods

2558 © 2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd


JAN: RESEARCH METHODOLOGY: DISCUSSION PAPER – METHODOLOGY Concept analysis and the building blocks of theory

analyse some other attempts to justify concept analysis and


Why is this review needed? show that those also are based on misunderstandings. We
• The debate around concept analysis in nursing seems to argue that the misconceptions regarding concepts and the
concern the definition of ‘concepts’ and how to best clarify need for concept analyses argued for by Walker and Avant
them, rather than questioning if concept analysis is a sound (2011), Morse et al. (1996a,b), Morse (2012), Rodgers
scientific endeavour. (1989), Penrod & Hupcey 2005 and Fawcett (2012) can
• The notion of concepts as building blocks of theory is often lead researchers in the wrong direction and limit their abil-
repeated. It can be found in many articles and well-known
ity to create nursing theory, much like other misconceptions
textbooks. However, the statement is seldom explained or
and rhetoric around positivism, the philosophy of science
defended.
(Persson 2009) and phenomenology (Paley 1998, 2005).
• As a scientific discipline nursing science must discard inade-
Our standpoint is that the concept analysis methods com-
quate methods, it has been questioned if concept analysis is
an adequate scientific procedure. monly used in nursing should be abandoned and we will
not suggest any replacement. Instead, we argue for creating
What are the key findings? theories and using qualitative and/or quantitative methods
in combination or separately to test them.
• The theory of concepts as building blocks, or threads, that
builds theory is based on a misunderstanding of philosophy
of science. Background
• Insights from the last decade of modern philosophy show
that the idea of defining all terms and concepts before for- Rodgers (2000) tries to give a philosophical foundation for
mulating a theory results in endless iterations of clarifica- concept development and states that:
tions and cannot produce scientific theory.
In theory development literature, concepts are widely recognized as
• The use of concepts analysis in nursing research has no
the ‘building blocks’ from which theories are constructed. (p. 2)
foundation in the philosophy of science that is often
referred to when advocating concept analysis as a way to If Rodgers had written that it was in nursing theory
construct science. development, her statement would have been correct. In
theory development literature from well-known philoso-
How should the findings be used to influence research/
phers of science, such as Popper (2001), Kuhn (1970),
practice?
Quine (1998) and Toulmin (1972), there is no trace of the
• The type of concept analysis used in nursing science should idea of concepts as building blocks or any discussion of
not be seen as proper scientific work.
concept analysis methods. The closest parallel, which will
• The idea of concepts as building blocks, or threads, from
be discussed below, is the positivist idea of primitive terms
which theory is constructed should be abandoned.
as building blocks to define all other terms.
• There is a need to review the epistemic foundation of nurs-
The notion of concepts as building blocks has been ques-
ing science to embrace a hypothetical deductive view of
science where theory development is seen as a creative tioned by several authors, including Paley (1996), Penrod
endeavour. and Hupcey (2005), Duncan et al. (2007) and Risjord
(2009). However, most of these authors, with the exception
of Paley (1996), seem to agree that concepts are essential
components from which theory is built. The debate seems
Introduction
to concern the definition of ‘concepts’ and how best to clar-
The purpose of this article was to show that the attempts ify them, not so much questioning if theory is actually built
to justify concept analysis (CA) as described in nursing on concepts. Duncan et al. (2007) state that the ‘philosoph-
science (Morse et al. 1996b, Rodgers 2000, Penrod & Hup- ical foundation’ of concepts and its epistemological and
cey 2005, Walker & Avant 2005) are based on misunder- ontological basis are not identified in the different frame-
standing of the philosophy of science. To do this, we will works of concept analysis. Of the aforementioned authors,
discuss the notion of concepts as the building blocks of the- Paley (1996) and Hupcey and Penrod (2005) are those who
ory – a notion often advocated in nursing (Chinn & Jacobs explicitly criticize the notion of concepts as building blocks,
1983, Morse et al. 1996b, Rodgers & Knafl 2000, Walker Paley prefers to see concepts as ‘niches’ in theory and Hup-
& Avant 2005, 2011) and that is used to justify different cey and Penrod see them as knots in a tapestry. For Paley,
approaches of concept analysis. Our standpoint is that con- concepts are defined within the context of a theory. If Paley
cepts are not building blocks of theory. We will also is right, there is no justification to first analysing concepts

© 2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd 2559


E. Bergdahl et al.

and then building theory – in fact concept analysis cannot be found ‘out there’. An underlying assumption by the advo-
seen as an activity in theory creation. When a theory is devel- cates of concept analysis seems to be that there is a
oped, the concepts – or rather terms – are developed and given ‘proper’ definition to be found, at least in a particular
their position in the theory (Paley 1996), this view is consistent context, an idea at odds with findings from the philosophy
with influential philosophers of science (Kuhn 1970, Toulmin of language.
1972, Quine 1998, Popper 2001). Morse et al. (1996b) are aware that many philosophers
A new debate around the legitimacy of concept analysis regard efforts to assess or evaluate concepts as unnecessary
has recently emerged in nursing. Draper (2014) states that: or impossible and they also regard it as ‘remarkable’ that
‘texts on logic ignore concepts in favour of arguments.’ (p.
. . .there is no place for concept analysis in the scholarship of mod-
385). However, since Plato and Aristotle, philosophers and
ern nursing. (p. 1207)
logicians have been concerned with how words in the lan-
To which Morse (2014) adds: guage can ‘point’ to things in the external world and how
they can ‘mean’ something. As Goertz (2012) points out,
Inadequate or insufficient methods of concept analysis must be dis-
the first part of J.S. Mills ‘A System of Logic’ is dedicated
carded and appropriate, productive methods used. (p. 2969)
to this problem. Another logician who carried out ground-
We agree with Morse that inadequate methods must be breaking work on logic and language in the early 20th
discarded. This paper aims to show why the concept analy- century was Gottlieb Frege, who was a driving force behind
sis as method, including approaches suggested by Walker what is often called the ‘linguistic turn’ in philosophy.
and Avant (2011) and Rodgers (1989) does not have any In fact, leading philosophers and logicians, such as
justification in the philosophy of science and cannot be seen Wittgenstein (1922, 1953/2001) and Quine (1998), put
as a proper scientific endeavour. By showing that concepts great effort into investigating how words, terms and con-
are not building blocks of theory or ‘the foundation of our cepts acquire meaning.
discipline’ (Morse 2012, p. 151), we argue that the idea of The meaning of a word, according to Wittgenstein
‘Delineation and description of the anatomy of the concept’ (1953/2001), is connected to the ability to use it in some
(Morse 2012, p. 152) as an activity that is needed before language game. Wittgenstein’s point is that a specific word
theories can be formulated is wrong. The notion we are does not need, nor have, one specific definition since we
going to defend here is in line with Paley’s (1996) view, can use it successfully in language games without defining
that concepts (or terms) as such do not have any specific it. Furthermore, concepts get their meaning through use in
meaning outside the context where they are defined. a language game, i.e. a context (Wittgenstein 1953/2001).
Quine (1998) had a similar view. A parallel is that both
Hempel (1952) and Popper (2001) are clear that a term
Data sources
acquires meaning by its use and definition in a theory and
This discussion is based on some of the most influential those terms are introduced as abbreviations for longer state-
papers in nursing on concept analysis and the notion of ments in a theoretical context.
concepts as building blocks of nursing science. The roots A term is just an abbreviation that can be used instead of
of this notion are traced and the influential philosophy of a longer sentence is also true for everyday language use. To
science is used to problematize the idea of concepts as analyse what ‘puppy’ means, is to analyse the sentence or
building blocks of theory and the types of concept analysis proposition ‘a young dog’. ‘Puppy’ is shorthand for the
most often seen in nursing science. statement ‘a young dog’. To get a clearer understanding,
we might also need to understand and investigate the defini-
tion of ‘young’ and ‘dog’. We will then find that a dog is a
Discussion
mammal, but all of this does not really give a clearer
understanding of what a person means when uttering the
Is concept analysis a good idea?
word ‘puppy’ or what ‘puppy’ means to that particular
Intuitively, trying to find the ‘correct’ definition of all con- language user.
cepts or terms and then combine these into a theory seems Furthermore, Quine (1998) concludes that we have an
like a good idea. Certainly, good theorists make sure they indeterminacy of translation; there are several correct ways
define the terms they use in a theory or hypothesis, but to translate a word or a sentence into another language. It
usually these definitions are stipulated by the theorists; the seems that Morse et al. (1996b) also misunderstand that in
terms are explicated in the theory by the theorists, not logic, as exemplified above, a term is usually seen as defined

2560 © 2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd


JAN: RESEARCH METHODOLOGY: DISCUSSION PAPER – METHODOLOGY Concept analysis and the building blocks of theory

by a statement and therefore a concept/term can be under- For example, Toulmin (1972) shows that some concepts
stood by analysing the statement defining the term. One are invented and are not abstracted from reality at all.
philosopher of science well versed in logic, Karl Popper Toulmin (1972) uses the example of particle physics. Sub-
(2011), also quite clearly explains why we should not start atomic particles were invented by theorists in a creative
out by defining terms/concepts: endeavour to solve a scientific problem, not by observation.
Later, the validity of these conceptualizations (theories) was
For a definition cannot establish the meaning of a term any more
deductively tested against reality. The idea (conception) of
than a logical derivation can establish the truth of a statement;
‘atoms’ has gone through tremendous changes throughout
both can only shift this problem back. The derivation shifts the
the history of physics, as have many ideas or concepts in all
problem of truth back to the premises, the definition shifts the
sciences, but these changes are not a problem to scientists.
problem of meaning back to the defining terms (i.e., the terms that
Scientific endeavours cannot start with concept clarification
make up the defining formula). But these, for many reasons, are
and move towards theories: it is the other way around.
likely to be just as vague and confusing as the terms we started
First, theories are proposed and in the formulation of the
with; and in any case, we should have to go on to define them in
theory the needed concepts are given a definition, which
turn; which leads to new terms which too must be defined. And so
can be unique for a given theory (c.f. Popper 2011). In fact,
on, to infinity. (p. 276)
most philosophers of science since the early 20th century
Many concept analyses in nursing are quite good exam- separated the creation of theory from theory justification
ples of the issue Popper (2011) presents: the defining attri- (Putnam 1992, p193). Theory creation is seen as a creative,
butes are on a higher level of abstraction than the concept artistic, endeavour and theory justification and testing is
that is supposed to be defined. Examples can be found in seen as more like a craft.
the most important books on concept analysis, such as The lesson we should learn from the philosophy of lan-
Rodgers (1989), or Cowles and Rodgers (2000), which guage and science is that the ‘true’ meaning of a term or
analyses the ‘concept’ of grief and finds that it has five attri- ‘concept’, cannot be found and that the effort to find
butes: dynamic, process, individualized, pervasive and nor- such meanings is an endless and fruitless endeavour (c.f.
mative. Each of these attributes is at least as complex and Paley 1996).
undefined as grief. In any attempt to find a definition, be it
in the form of dictionary definition or with a set of ‘at-
How concepts became building blocks
tributes’, ‘properties’ or ‘dimensions’ (Fawcett 2012), the
attributes and definition will contain other concepts that Most authors in nursing who state that concepts are build-
are undefined that lead to the next analysis and so on. In ing blocks do not argue their case; they merely use a refer-
this way, an endless stream of analysis can be published ence to justify this idea. For example, Morse et al. (1996b)
without actually adding any proper knowledge to the refers to Chinn and Jacobs (1983) and the first edition of
discipline. their book Theory and Nursing: A Systematic Approach. In
In social science, there are a few theorists (Collier and this edition, Chinn and Jacobs just state it as a fact, without
Levitsky 1997, Sartori 2009, Goertz 2012) that have gone reference or explanation. Interestingly, in later editions of
deeper into the problem of concepts and the possibility to this book (Chinn and Kramer 1991), there is no mention of
use them in qualitative studies. In this context, the main concepts as building blocks. Another source of the notion
focus is to avoid conceptual stretching and to create a con- of concepts as building blocks is Walker and Avant; they
ceptual system that can aid empirical research. And, again, state this notion as fact and it appears in the 1995, 2005
it is important to remember that the created conceptual and 2011 editions of their book Strategies for Theory Con-
classification system is a classification of what these con- struction in Nursing. Walker and Avant use a reference, i.e.
cepts are, not what causes something or what the effects of Hardy (1974), as a source of the notion of concepts as
something are. The conceptual classification system allows building blocks of theory. It is therefore of interest to see
us to investigate causes and effects but the causes and how Hardy (1974) refers to ‘primitive terms’ as primary
effects are not a part of the definition. building blocks of theory:
The greatest problem might be that many concept analy-
. . .the primitive terms (or concepts) are primary building blocks of
ses are made without investigating whether there is a con-
theories from which new terms are defined. (p. 101)
ceptual problem, the first step Wilson recommends for
students so they do not waste time conducting a conceptual Hardy also refers to Hempel (1952) in stating that the
analysis when there is no conceptual problem. ‘derived terms’ are built on ‘primitive terms’. To clarify this

© 2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd 2561


E. Bergdahl et al.

statement and why it is not correct to justify the ‘building constitute virtually two different aspects of the same procedure.
block’ dogma using Hempel, we need to see what Hempel (pp. 1–2)
actually writes in Fundamentals of Concept Formation in
Hempel himself advocates a deductive view of theory
Empirical Science in 1952. First of all, Hempel never states
where the terms acquire meaning by being seen as knots in
that primitive terms have been seen as the building blocks
a ‘complex spatial network’ (Hempel 1952, p. 36) where
of ‘defined terms’. The expression ‘derived terms’ is not
the threads are their theoretical definitions that are funda-
used by Hempel (1952) at all. Hempel explains:
mental and derivative hypothesis of the network.
Thus the vocabulary of a theory falls into two classes, the defined When Hardy (1974) sets ‘concepts’ in parentheses after
terms, i.e. those which are introduced by definition in terms of ‘primitive terms’, it can be seen as a mistake. Readers that
other expressions of the vocabulary and the so-called primitive are not familiar with Hempel’s work can interpret this as
terms, or primitives, by means of which all other terms of the theo- Hempel seeing ‘primitive terms’ and ‘concepts’ as syn-
retical vocabulary are ultimately defined. (p. 15) onyms, which is not at all consistent with Hempel’s use of
these two terms. In other words, the notion of ‘concepts as
Primitive terms are a positivist idea and are supposed to
building blocks of theory’, which is still advocated widely
be applicable to those terms that could be defined by direct
in nursing science, seems to be based on a misunderstand-
correlation with an empirical observation, often called ‘ob-
ing or mistake by Hardy (1974) and the notion does not
servation terms’ (Hempel 1952). Defined terms are made of
have support in Hempel or any theory of science we know
several primitive terms – linguistic labels on possible direct
of outside nursing. Nor is there any argument to support
sense data or empirical observation according to Hempel
the notion of ‘building blocks’ in the writing of Walker and
(1952). So in some ways, Hempel could be said to describe
Avant, Morse or any of the other proponents of the view
and criticize, how the logical positivists saw scientific theo-
that concepts need to be analysed before theory can be cre-
ries as built on terms (or at least containing terms), but not
ated.
necessarily concepts and where defined terms can be
The conclusion has to be that the notion of concepts as
reduced to primitive terms. Hempel regarded the distinction
building blocks is not supported by the references to
between defined and primitive terms as deeply problematic.
Walker and Avant or Chinn and Jacobs; nor is the reference
Hempel does not have an inductive view of science and
that Walker and Avant (1995, 2005, 2011) give to Hardy a
points out those concepts, which he regards as ‘theoretical
support for that notion. On the contrary, Hempel – who is
constructs’, are invented:
referred to by Hardy (1974) – has a view of concepts as
Guided by his knowledge of observational data, the scientist has to defined within theory.
invent a set of concepts, theoretical constructs, which lack immedi-
ate experiential significance, a system of hypotheses couched in
Concepts as building blocks in grounded theory
terms of them and an interpretation for the resulting theoretical
network; and all this in a manner which will establish explana- Another source of this notion can be found in Straussian
tory and predictive connections between the data or direct grounded theory, where it is declared that ‘concepts that
observation. (p. 37) are the building blocks of theory’ (Strauss & Corbin 1998,
p. 13). In the analysis phase of the method, categories are
This is a very different view of concepts to the plethora
developed and these form the concepts of the theory that is
of definitions offered by nursing theorists. Hempel even
created with grounded theory as a tool. However, Strauss
points out those concepts may lack ‘experiential signifi-
and Corbin (1998) make an effort to point out that con-
cance’, again a sharp contrast to the notion of concepts as
cepts are contextual and that the same phenomena may get
inductive building blocks. Hempel (1952) advocates a view
different labels in different theories.
of science where theories could be formulated by invented
There are several similarities between the way that
concepts used as descriptions of a possible phenomenon,
Strauss and Corbin express themselves and how theories
often not yet observed by empirical science but put forward
are regarded in post-positivistic philosophy of science; all
as a hypothesis. Hempel further sees concept and theory
theory is regarded as provisional and subject to change
formation as closely related or aspects of the same activity:
when confronted with new data. In grounded theory, the
This analysis will lead to a close examination of the function of finding is ‘theoretical constructs’, which is in agreement
concepts in scientific theories and will show that concept formation with Hempel’s (1952) idea that theory is invented. Strauss
and theory formation in science are so closely interrelated as to and Corbin (1998) seem to have a conception of concepts

2562 © 2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd


JAN: RESEARCH METHODOLOGY: DISCUSSION PAPER – METHODOLOGY Concept analysis and the building blocks of theory

and theory as being contextual and provisional, which is in Hemple (1966) offers a different concept-theory analogy in his
contrast with the way Morse et al. (1996b) and Morse work in natural science, describing concepts as the ‘knots in a net-
(2012) views concepts and theory. work of systematic interrelationships (p. 94).’ (Hupcey & Penrod
2005)

Short analysis of Wilson’s ‘Thinking with Concepts’ They only quote a part of Hempel’s sentence; in its com-
Wilson wrote Thinking with Concepts (1963) as an aid to plete form it is as follows:
high school students to prepare for university and be able Thus, the concepts of science are the knots in a network of system-
to grasp how words (concepts) are used in ordinary lan- atic interrelationships in which laws and theoretical principles form
guage and academic texts. (c.f. Hupcey & Penrod 2005). the threads. (Hempel 1966, p. 94)
Wilson was heavily influenced by the Oxford and Cam-
bridge language philosophy of that time; in particular, there What Penrod and Hupcey do is to substitute blocks with
was a heavy influence from Wittgenstein’s ‘philosophical strand and wall with tapestry but ultimately they keep the
investigations’ and the then debate and development of same view, that concepts build well integrated supported
Wittgenstein’s thoughts in Oxford and Cambridge. The theory. Penrod and Hupcey (2005) do however acknowl-
book was not intended to be used in theory development edge that ‘. . .concepts cannot be analysed irrespective of
and the method described is not a scientific method. This is their theoretical frame.’ (p 199), but they believe, without
evident when Walker and Avant (2011) try to develop Wil- support from Hempel or other philosophy of science, that
son’s text into some sort of scientific method. We believe it is possible ‘to tie and retie the conceptual knots to form
the method could be used in a literature review, but as used a stronger, more coherent tapestry of nursing theory’ (pp.
in nursing currently it is only contributing to increased frus- 199–200). By stating this, they disregard that a particular
tration and confusion and is not in any way advancing term can have very different definitions in different theo-
science. ries that are all part of nursing science. Trying to create
When we look at Wilson’s (1963) examples, we also see an understating of ‘concepts’ by tying and retying terms/
that the techniques are mainly used for two purposes: ana- concepts from different theories does not seem to be a fea-
lysing rather long and complex texts and answering ques- sible way to create knowledge. In fact, the tapestry anal-
tions such as ‘Is astrology a science?’ There is no attempt ogy is no better than the building block analogy in our
to give one clear answer and definition of ‘concepts’ with opinion.
attributes or antecedents. It is worth noting that Wilson There are also some misconceptions in the foundation
does not give any example that resembles the concept anal- for concept development that Rodgers claims to find in
yses that in nursing are said to be ‘Wilsonian’. the philosophy of Toulmin. Rodgers claims that ‘Toulmin
It can also be noted that the only thing that Walker and failed to define the term concept. . .’ (Rodgers 2000, p.
Avant have in common with Wilson (1963) is the idea to 28). This statement is untrue in two ways. First, Toulmin
describe typical cases and also extend them to contrary and (1972) clearly states that, like many other terms or con-
borderline cases. None of the other five steps of Walker cepts, the term ‘concept’ might not need a comprehensive
and Avant have anything in common with Wilson. definition since scientists use it without problems. Second,
As we see it, all approaches derived from Wilson lack in the case of the term ‘concept’, Toulmin does give a def-
foundation in scientific methods and should not be seen as inition of concepts, albeit in the form of a question, as
methods suitable to provide a foundation for research to be follows:
published in peer-reviewed scientific journals. What are the skills or traditions, the activities, procedures or
instruments of Man0 s intellectual life and imagination – in a word
Further misunderstandings and attempts to justify the concepts – through which that human understanding is
concept analysis achieved and expressed? (p. 11)

Penrod and Hupcey abandon the building block analogy in Toulmin’s definition of concepts is clearly very different
their two papers from 2005; instead they adopt a tapestry than something that is ‘. . .cognitive in nature and com-
analogy. Interestingly, they refer to Hempel, whose name prised of attributes abstracted from reality, expressed in
they misspell as ‘Hemple’, where they see concepts as the some form. . .’ (Rodgers 2000, p33) or ‘. . .abstractions
strand or threads that build the tapestry. They quote expressed in some way’ (Rodgers 1989, p. 78). To analyse
Hempel to give emphasis to their argument: ‘concepts’ of the sort Toulmin speaks of, the strategies

© 2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd 2563


E. Bergdahl et al.

proposed by Rodgers are clearly not applicable. An impor- misinterpretation of these areas. If analysis of language use,
tant consequence is that the alleged support Rodgers claims terms and conceptualization is needed, this should not be
to find in the writings of Toulmin is not at all a support for done by junior nursing scholars in their thesis work, other
Rodgers evolutionary view of concept analysis. Instead, we than as a step in the needed background research. If such
can see that Toulmin is rather close to Hempel (1952) in an analysis is to be published as an academic paper, it
that he sees concepts and theories development as virtually should either be done by senior nursing researchers with
the same activity. sound competence in semiotics and language philosophy, or
It is also very hard to understand how Wittgenstein’s be done together with specialists from these fields. When
‘family resemblance’ ideas for natural language are applica- we want to analyse what theorists and researchers have
ble for analysis of scientific terms or concepts. In fact, it published on a particular subject, a literature review can be
seems that Rodgers is guilty of ‘the language-in-use fallacy’ performed, just as Draper (2014) suggests, or a meta-synth-
mentioned by Sartori (2009). Furthermore, all inductive esis might be applicable.
methods of concept analysis are automatically guilty of this We agree with Beckwith et al. (2008) that there is:
fallacy. The argument is that science is a practice of con-
. . . little evidence to show that the CA (concept analysis) frame-
structing a more exact language to describe some aspect of
works discussed add rigour to our research or facilitate deep
reality; therefore, to quote or refer to Wittgenstein (1953/
enough understanding of concepts to enable and justify the theory
2001) theories regarding ordinary language when discussing
developments which they underpin. (p. 1840)
scientific language is to interpret Wittgenstein out of con-
text (c.f. Sartori 2009). In our view, the underlying problem is that the idea
Fawcett (2012) regards herself as a post-positivist, but that the proper definition or essence of a concept/term can
post-positivist philosophers such as Popper or Hempel be found or that a meaning can be revealed through any
would not, as we have seen, conduct concept analysis as sort of concept analysis is flawed. Important concepts will
advocated in nursing and they would also object to the always be ambiguous and have several uses even in a dis-
notion of the essence of a phenomenon, which is central to cipline. This is not a problem since concepts are not the
Fawcett’s (2012) definition of concepts as: ‘building blocks of science’, nor do they ‘form the founda-
tion of our discipline’, nor are they ‘threads in a tapestry’.
. . .a label, expressed as a word or phrase that summarizes the
Rather, science is built on hypotheses that are systemati-
essence of a phenomenon.
cally tested and then rejected, modified or tentatively
Fawcett (2012) regards the result of a concept analysis as accepted, not on concepts. In our view, nursing theory, as
a middle-range theory: with all theories, starts with ideas that are formulated in a
hypothetical manner. There is no formula or strict method
. . .which should be linked explicitly with the conceptual model that
to be found for theory creation, no more than there is a
guided the analysis.
formula on how to write books, be a great painter or
The statement above repeats the view that concept analy- compose music. In our view, all theories should start as
sis could be a way to construct theory, a view that is not creative interpretations of some aspect or reality, the the-
supported be post-positivist or other philosophies of ory is regarded as true when it has been rigorously tested.
science. The only difference is that Fawcett thinks that a What we find perplexing is the willingness by many quali-
concept analysis is of more value if it is confined to a con- tative method theorists to emphasize almost mechanical
ceptual model. structure that should generate or construct theory. For us,
the way forward is to open up for creative and free think-
ing in formulating theories, conjectures and that the future
Implications for nursing – a way forward?
of qualitative methods is depending on clarifications of
From time to time, there is a need to analyse the way lan- how qualitative methods contribute both to creative for-
guage is used in a professional academic discipline. One mulation of theory and to rigorous testing of theory. In
might then perform an analysis of existing knowledge and this discussion, there is a need to question many of the
clarify how terms are used in the discipline and what the foundation of our discipline to ensure that nursing ontol-
most important theories and ideas are. However, the ogy and epistemology is well grounded. The most impor-
methods used in nursing regarding concept analysis men- tant lesson that should be learnt is that, as a scientific
tioned in this paper have no foundation in theory of science discipline, we need to retain and value critical thinking
nor in language philosophy; rather it is built on the and creative ideas.

2564 © 2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd


JAN: RESEARCH METHODOLOGY: DISCUSSION PAPER – METHODOLOGY Concept analysis and the building blocks of theory

Conclusion • drafting the article or revising it critically for important


intellectual content.
We have shown that the attempts to justify concept analysis
as a way to construct theory lack sound foundation in the
philosophy of science and are to a large extent argued for
References
with some serious misinterpretations of the philosophy of Beckwith S., Dickinson A. & Kendall S. (2008) The “con” of
science. Although Rodgers (2000), Penrod and Hupcey concept analysis: a discussion paper which explores and critiques
(2005) and Fawcett (2012) do not use the building block the ontological focus, reliability and antecedents of concept
analysis frameworks. International Journal of Nursing Studies
analogy, they nevertheless share the same view, that theory
45, 1831–1841.
is constructed from concepts and as a consequence, concept Chinn P.L. & Jacobs M.K. (1983) Theory and Nursing: A
analysis and development is a vital part of theory construc- Systematic Approach. Mosby, St Louis, Missouri.
tion. It seems as if authors that are critical towards the Chinn P.L. & Kramer M.K. (1991) Theory and Nursing: A
building block analogy still cling to the notion that con- Systematic Approach. Mosby Yearbook, St Louis, Missouri.
cepts build theory, but when they try to justify that notion Collier D. & Levitsky S. (1997) Democracy with Adjectives,
Conceptual innovation in comparative Research. World Politics
by referring to philosophers of science that are against term
49(3), 430–451.
and concept clarifications and the notion that one can gen- Cowles K.V. & Rodgers B.L. (2000) The concept of grief: an
erate theory, the lack of foundation for the concept clarifi- evolutionary perspective. In Concept Development in Nursing,
cation notion becomes obvious. 2nd edn (Rodgers B.L. & Knafl K.A., eds), Saunders,
As we have shown, the type of concept analysis per- Philadelphia, Pennsylvania, pp. 119–128.
Draper P. (2014) A critique of concept analysis. Journal of
formed in nursing is not a way to ‘construct’ theory; theo-
Advanced Nursing 70(6), 1207–1208.
ries are formed by creative endeavour to propose a solution Duncan C., Cloutier J.D. & Bailey P.H. (2007) Concept analysis:
to a scientific and/or practical problem. The focus on con- the importance of differentiating the ontological focus. Journal
cept development and analysis also cripples theory develop- of Advanced Nursing 58(3), 293–300.
ment and empirical research, both quantitative and even Fawcett J. (2012) Thoughts on concept analysis: multiple approaches,
more so qualitative research. It is important that we aban- one result. Nursing Science Quarterly 25(3), 285–287.
Goertz G. (2012) Social Science Concepts. A User Guide. Princeton
don this concept focus and start to create and test theories
University Press, Princeton, USA.
instead. To get an overview on a specific subject existing lit- Hardy M.E. (1974) Theories: components, development,
erature reviews and knowledge synthesises methods are suf- evaluation. Nursing Research 23(2), 100–107.
ficient. The bottom line is that concept analysis in nursing Hempel C.G. (1952) Fundamentals of Concept Formation in
should be abandoned in favour of sound scientific methods Empirical Science. International Encyclopedia of Unified
Sciences, Vol. 2, No. 7. The University of Chicago Press,
in line with modern theory of science.
Chicago, Illinois.
Hempel C.G. (1966) Philosophy of Natural Science. Prentice-Hall,
Englewood Cliffs, NJ.
Funding
Hupcey J.E. & Penrod J. (2005) Concept analysis examining the
This research received no specific grant from any funding state of the art. Research and Theory for Nursing Practice: An
agency in the public, commercial, or not-for-profit sectors. International Journal 19(2), 197–208.
Kuhn T. (1970) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd edn.
University of Chicago Press, Chicago, Illinois.
Conflict of interest Morse J.M. (2012) Introducing the first Global Congress for
Qualitative Health Research: what are we? What will we do and
No conflict of interest has been declared by the authors. why? Qualitative Health Research 22(2), 147–156.
Morse J.M. (2014) The baby and the bathwater. Journal of
Advanced Nursing 70(12), 2969.
Author contributions Morse J.M., Hupcey J.C., Mitcham C. & Lenz E.R. (1996a)
Concept analysis in nursing research: a critical appraisal.
All authors have agreed on the final version and meet at Scholarly Inquiry for Nursing Practice: An International Journal
least one of the following criteria [recommended by the 10(3), 253–277.
ICMJE (http://www.icmje.org/recommendations/)]: Morse J.M., Mitcham C., Hupcey J.E. & Tas on M.C. (1996b)
Criteria for concept evaluation. Journal of Advanced Nursing 24
• substantial contributions to conception and design, (2), 385–390.
acquisition of data, or analysis and interpretation of Paley J. (1996) How not to clarify concepts in nursing. Journal of
data; Advanced Nursing 24(2), 572–578.

© 2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd 2565


E. Bergdahl et al.

Paley J. (1998) Misinterpretive phenomenology: Heidegger, ontology Rodgers B.L. & Knafl K.A. (2000) Introduction to concept
and nursing. Journal of Advanced Nursing 27(4), 817–824. development. In Concept Development in Nursing, 2nd edn
Paley J. (2005) Phenomenology as rhetoric. Nursing Inquiry 12(2), (Rodgers B.L. & Knafl K.A., eds). Saunders, Philadelphia,
106–116. Pennsylvania, pp. 1–6.
Penrod J. & Hupcey J.E. (2005) Enhancing methodological clarity: Sartori G. (2009) Guidelines for concept analysis. In Concepts and
principle-based concept analysis. Journal of Advanced Nursing Method in Social Science (Collier D., Gerring J., eds), Routledge,
50(4), 403–409. New York, pp. 269–288.
Persson J. (2009) Misconceptions of positivism and five unnecessary Strauss A. & Corbin J. (1998) Basics of Qualitative Research. Sage
science theoretic mistakes they bring in their train: a discussion Publications, Thousand Oaks, California.
paper. International Journal of Nursing Studies 47(5), 651–661. Toulmin S. (1972) Human Understanding: the Collective Use and
Popper K. (2001) The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Routledge, Evolution of Concepts. Princeton University Press, Princeton,
London. New Jersey.
Popper K. (2011) Open Society and Its Enemies. Routledge, London. Walker L.O. & Avant K.C. (1995) Strategies for Theory Construction
Putnam H. (1992) Renewing Philosophy. Harvard University Press, in Nursing. Appleton & Lange, Norwalk, Connecticut.
London, UK. Walker L.O. & Avant K.C. (2005) Strategies for Theory
Quine W.V.O. (1998) From Stimulus to Science. Harvard Construction in Nursing, 4th edn. Pearson Prentice Hall, Upper
University Press, Cambridge. Saddle River, NJ.
Risjord M. (2009) Rethinking concept analysis. Journal of Walker L.O. & Avant K.C. (2011) Strategies for Theory
Advanced Nursing 65(3), 684–691. Construction in Nursing, 5th edn. Pearson Prentice Hall, Upper
Rodgers B.L. (1989) Concepts, analysis and the development of Saddle River, NJ.
nursing knowledge: the evolutionary cycle. Journal of Advanced Wilson J. (1963) Thinking with Concepts. Cambridge University
Nursing 14(4), 330–335. Press, Cambridge.
Rodgers B.L. (2000). Philosophical foundations of concept Wittgenstein L. (1922) Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Kegan
development. In Concept Development in Nursing, 2nd edn Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co., LTD, London.
(Rodgers B.L. & Knafl K.A., eds), Saunders, Philadelphia, Wittgenstein L. (1953/2001) Philosophical Investigations. Blackwell
Pennsylvania, pp. 7–37. Publishing, Oxford.

The Journal of Advanced Nursing (JAN) is an international, peer-reviewed, scientific journal. JAN contributes to the advancement of
evidence-based nursing, midwifery and health care by disseminating high quality research and scholarship of contemporary relevance
and with potential to advance knowledge for practice, education, management or policy. JAN publishes research reviews, original
research reports and methodological and theoretical papers.

For further information, please visit JAN on the Wiley Online Library website: www.wileyonlinelibrary.com/journal/jan

Reasons to publish your work in JAN:

• High-impact forum: the world’s most cited nursing journal, with an Impact Factor of 1917 – ranked 8/114 in the 2015 ISI Jour-
nal Citation Reports © (Nursing (Social Science)).
• Most read nursing journal in the world: over 3 million articles downloaded online per year and accessible in over 10,000 libraries
worldwide (including over 3,500 in developing countries with free or low cost access).
• Fast and easy online submission: online submission at http://mc.manuscriptcentral.com/jan.
• Positive publishing experience: rapid double-blind peer review with constructive feedback.
• Rapid online publication in five weeks: average time from final manuscript arriving in production to online publication.
• Online Open: the option to pay to make your article freely and openly accessible to non-subscribers upon publication on Wiley
Online Library, as well as the option to deposit the article in your own or your funding agency’s preferred archive (e.g. PubMed).

2566 © 2016 John Wiley & Sons Ltd

Anda mungkin juga menyukai