Anda di halaman 1dari 3

Conspiracy theories

by Neil Van Leeuwen

I attended a talk about conspiracy theories at the end of July. That talk has played on my
mind since, especially given the recent banning of Alex Jones, that prominent purveyor of
conspiracy theories, from Apple, Facebook, YouTube, and Spotify. The speaker at the talk
was Jan-Willem van Prooijen from the Vrije Universiteit (VU) Amsterdam. He’s an expert
both on the psychology behind conspiracy theories and on the psychology of moral
punishment, and he offered substantial insights into why people would be taken in by the
bizarre rantings of someone like Jones.

Van Prooijen uses the acronym CUES to abbreviate his framework for understanding
conspiracy theories. Conspiracy theories are Consequential (their existence can make
momentous differences in people’s lives, affecting things like whether they get needed
medicine), Universal (they emerge in nearly every observed society and time), Emotional
(they emerge from System 1 emotional and intuitive processes), and Social (they typically
posit conspiracies among members of a perceived dominant group, where the conspiracies
are designed to ensure continued domination).
Though all that made sense, one thing still puzzled me about the talk.
At one point, van Prooijen began talking about the flat earther conspiracy theory, which has
so many adherents that there are conferences dedicated to “research” on the flatness of the
earth—and to the massive conspiracy designed to convince us it’s round.
The puzzle came with this parenthetical comment:
“You might think these people don’t think about things. But they do! They have an answer
for everything. You’ll find this if you argue with a flat earther.”
He illustrated his point. Explain to a flat earther that there are satellite photos of the round
earth. Those are from NASA. NASA’s not trustworthy! Point out that people like Magellan
sailed around the world. Of course a government history curriculum would say that! Point
out that you can see the curvature of the earth from the window of an airplane. The airplane
windows were designed to make it look curved!
So a typical flat earther has a system of cohesive (albeit bizarre) thoughts that capture the
implications of their theory. The same holds true, mutatis mutandis, for conspiracy theorists
of other stripes: in many (maybe most) cases, conspiracy theorists embrace the strange
entailments of their central views. Now here’s what’s weird: embracing entailments of one’s
views is supposed to be a hallmark of rational thought. So what is it doing nestled amongst
a bizarre and arguably irrational web of conspiracy theoretic beliefs?
Connoisseurs of philosophy of science will here recognize the lurking ghost of the Quine-
Duhem problem: any empirical hypothesis can be treated as consistent with the known
observations, as long as the “right” auxiliary assumptions are also embraced. And many
conspiracy theorists are, if van Prooijen is right, adept at embracing the “right” auxiliary
assumptions.
Connoisseurs of British humor will recognize a parallel to the famous Monty Python parrot
sketch, in which the pet shop owner maintains that a dead parrot is in fact alive in the face
of all contrary evidence (it’s resting! it’s stunned! it’s probably pining for the fjords!). Again,
just keep making the “right” auxiliary assumptions…
In any case, there appears to be a whiff of rationality in the typical conspiracy theorist’s
thought, since they recognize the need to embrace the implied consequences of what they
believe.
But not only is it common sense that at least a great many conspiracy theories are irrational
(such as the flat earther conspiracy theory); there are also empirical data that suggest that
conspiracy theories flourish in the absence of rational thought.
Viren Swami and colleagues, for example, published a paper in 2014 showing that belief in
conspiracy theories is associated with lower scores in analytic thinking. That means—at a
rough pass—that the sort of mental processing often called System 2 (conscious effortful
reasoning) is dissociated with acceptance of conspiracy theories.
So does conspiracy theoretic ideation involve conscious reasoning or not? And how does
intuition and emotion play into this (the E in CUES)?
I think the resolution of this puzzle is that conspiracy theoretic ideation first involves an
initial intuition or suspicion that is the product of emotional, automatic processing (feeling
oppressed or lacking in control appears to be partly behind the initial conspiracy theoretic
impulses). But conspiracy theoretic ideation second involves a great deal of quasi-rational
thinking that works out how things would be if the initial intuition were accurate. And
people like Jones purvey ideas that validate the suspicious intuition and give a template for
the downstream quasi-rational thinking—so many people gobble those ideas up.
The problem with people who accept outlandish conspiracy theories is thus not lack of
thinking. It’s lack of thinking that would override one’s initial intuitions. So when those
initial dark intuitions are strong enough (they are out to get us!), one ends up with not
merely a suspicion but a whole cluster of culturally scaffolded ideas that would (i) seem to
make sense of the intuition and (ii) arm it against refutation.
This view is consistent with the methods that many researchers have used to measure
analytic cognitive style. Good tests for analytic cognitive style assess whether people use
conscious thought to override intuitive responses. Consider the following classic problem:
A bat and a ball cost $1.10.
The bat costs one dollar more than the ball.
How much is the ball?

Almost everyone has the fast intuitive response ten cents. That, of course, is wrong, but
people (including ones good at math) have this intuition anyway. So the measure of analytic
cognitive style is whether people override their initial intuitions to give reasoned answers,
like five cents [corret answer]. (y=1.10-x and y=x-1)
It’s thus possible to score low in tests of analytic thinking, despite the fact that one does a
lot of conscious “reasoning”—as long as that conscious “reasoning” doesn’t go against the
initial intuitions one has. Otherwise put, being low in analytic cognitive style doesn’t mean
that one doesn’t think consciously, it just means that one’s conscious thinking seldom goes
against what one intuits: post-intuition thinking is more like a one-way street.
And this, I think, is exactly what happens with conspiracy theorists (by which I mean here
people who are actually taken in by the conspiracy theories, as opposed to those who
propagate them mendaciously or as part of a prank). Their initial conspiracy theoretic
intuitions (they’re covering up the truth!) are powerful. And even more importantly, those
intuitions aren’t overridden, despite their outlandishness, among people who have a lower
analytic cognitive style. Such conspiracy theorists do think a lot; they just do so in ways that
only cohere with their initial, suspicious emotional/intuitive responses.
It’s hard to know where this leaves us when it comes to combating outlandish conspiracy
theories. Banning Alex Jones is a good start, but that just leaves a vacuum in the minds of
suspicious people with low analytic cognitive styles for some other pernicious purveyor to
exploit. So perhaps it’s worth attempting to nip the initial conspiracy theoretic intuitions in
the bud. That, anyway, is more crucial than refuting the post hoc “reasoning,” since by that
point many conspiracy theorists have already thought of the objections you’ll bring to their
views.
But how on earth might one do that—i.e., nip the initial intuitions? That’s the topic of the
next blog!

Anda mungkin juga menyukai