Anda di halaman 1dari 142

Lukag Novak • Daniel D.

Novotny
Prokop Sousedik • David Svoboda (Eds.)
CONTEMPORARY SCHOLASTICISM
EDITED BY
Edward Feser • Edmund Runggaldier
Metaphysics:
ADVISORY BOARD
Aristotelian, Scholastic,
Brain Davies, Fortham University, U.S.A.
Christian Kanzian, University of Innsbruck, Austria Analytic
Gyula Klima, Fordham University, U.S.A.
David S. Oderberg, University of Reading, U.K.
Eleonore Stump, Saint Louis University, U.S.A.

Band 1 / Volume 1

Published in Cooperation with

Studia Neoaristotelica
A Journal of Analytical Scholasticism ontos
verlag
Bibliographic information published by Die Deutsche Bibliothek
Die Deutsche Bibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliographie;
detailed bibliographic data is available in the Internet at http://dnb ddb.de

North and South America by CONTENTS


Transaction Books

11!
transaction
Rutgers University
Piscataway, NJ 08854-8042
trans@transactionpub.com
Preface 5

CATEGORIES AND BEYOND


United Kingdom, Ire, Iceland, Turkey, Malta, Portugal by
Gazelle Books Services Limited Peter van Inwagen
White Cross Mills What is an Ontological Category? 11
Hightown
LANCASTER, LAI 4XS Daniel D. Novotny
sales@gazellebooks.co.uk Scholastic Debates about Beings of Reason
and Contemporary Analytical Metaphysics 25

Livraison pour Ia France et Ia Belgique: METAPHYSICAL STUCTURE


Librairie Philosophique J.Vrin
Michael J. Loux
6, place de la Sorbonne ; F-75005 PARIS
Tel. +33 (0)1 43 54 03 47 ; Fax +33 (0)1 43 54 48 18 What Is Constituent Ontology? 43
www.vrin.fr
Anne Siebels Peterson
Elemental Transformation in Aristotle:
Three Dilemmas for the Traditional Account 59
Ross Inman
Essential Dependence, Truthmaking, and Mereology: Then and Now 73
©2012 ontos verlag
P.O. Box 15 41, D-63133 Heusenstamm SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT
www.ontosverlag.com
E. J. Lowe
ISBN 978-3-86838-146-7 Essence and Ontology 93
2012 Lukcig Novak
No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in retrieval systems or transmitted
An Aristotelian Argument Against Bare Particulars 113
in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise
without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the Prokop Souseak & David Svoboda
purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use of the purchaser of the work The Ontology of Number: Is Number an Accident? 123
Printed on acid-free paper
ISO-Norm 970-6
FSC-certified (Forest Stewardship Council)
This hardcover binding meets the International Library standard

Printed in Germany
by CPI buch bucher.de

4 (,(0A 32-0 3
CONTENTS

EXISTENCE
Edward Feser
Existential Inertia 143 I PREFACE
Gyula Klima
Aquinas vs. Buridan on Essence and Existence,
and the Commensurability of Paradigms 169 Just like any other philosophical discipline, metaphysics has a history and a
present. It flourished in the classical and mediaeval period, gradually declined in
the modern period and almost ceased to exist in the first half of the 20'h century.
MODALITIES Its present is characterised by a revival of some traditional speculative topics,
Edmund Runggaldier SJ which has been taking place within analytical philosophy since the 1960s.
The fact that the current renewal of interest in metaphysics occurs in the
Potentiality in Scholasticism (potentiae)
and the Contemporary Debate on "Powers" 185 context of analytical philosophy is somewhat surprising. Analytical philosophy
has been deeply influenced by logical positivism with its strong anti-meta-
David Peroutka OCD physical orientation. Its proponents saw the task and future of philosophy in
Dispositional Necessity and Ontological Possibility 195 the ontologically neutral analysis of scientific or natural language - not in
Mark Faller metaphysical speculations. Many were convinced that the progress of mankind,
The Optimal and the Necessary in Leibniz' Mathematical Framing which they wished to assist, requires various obstacles to be cleared out of the
209 way. Metaphysics was considered to be one such intellectual obstacle.
of the Compossible How are we to understand, then, that the philosophical discipline, which the
older analytical philosophers stood so radically against, has reappeared within
PREDICATION the intellectual context of this very anti-metaphysical current? This question
Uwe Meixner does not seem to be satisfactorily answered yet, neither in socio-psychological
229 terms nor in purely philosophical ones: answering it may require a time interval
The Interpretation(s) of Predication
which has not elapsed yet. One of the causes is most probably to be sought in the
Stanislav Sousedlk analytical philosophy itself. With time, its development came to cast doubt on
Towards a Thomistic Theory of Predication 247 some of the anti-metaphysical points of departure. In this respect, for instance,
Wittgenstein's criticism of private languages, which problematised Cartesian
subjectivism, or Kripke's systematisation of modal logic, which facilitated a re-
Authors 257
turn to the previously rejected topic of modalities, ought to be mentioned.' The
General Index 263 renewed interest in these and similar topics advanced the revival of metaphysical
investigations.
Index of Persons 281
Of course, there are as yet many authors who reject metaphysics, as well
as some of its presuppositions, such as modal logic.' They consider analytical
metaphysics to be one of the many delusions of our time. Perhaps they think of
contemporary metaphysicians as of the prodigal son who has left his home and
LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN, Philosophical Investigations, trans!. G. E. M. Anscombe (Oxford:
Basil Blackwell, 1963); SAUL KRIPKE, "Semantical Considerations on Modal Logic", Acta Philo-
sophica Fennica 16 (1963): 83-99.
In the 20th century modal concepts were subjected to criticism especially by WILLARD VAN
ORMAN QUINE, see his "Two Dogmas of Empiricism", in From a Logical Point of View (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1954); or his Word and Object (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1960).

4 5
PREFACE PREFACE

wilfully violates the morality impressed on him by his parents. The prodigal son The section on metaphysical structure is closely connected to the previous one
should return home in order not to perish in a world full of delusion and hazard. in dealing with the most general ontological problems. In the first article, Michael
The editors of this publication are teachers of philosophy at Czech theological Loux contrasts two fundamentally distinct approaches to explaining the mould
faculties. In the controversy between contemporary analytical metaphysics of "familiar particulars": the "Aristotelian" or "constituent" strategy, and the
and its opponents they side with the renewal of speculative thinking. We are "Platonic" or "relational" strategy. Loux seeks first to clarify the dichotomy by
interested not only in the current debate but also in earlier discussions taking distinguishing it from the dispute over the nature of universals, and then proceeds
place within the tradition of Christian Aristotelism (the so-called First and Second to analyse the "constituent" approach and point out its various problems. In the
Scholasticism). Historical research has often led us to the remarkable observation following contribution Anne Siebels Peterson explores the Aristotelian notion of
that older scholastic discussions are in many respects similar to current debates. "prime matter" as the substratum of elemental transformation with no essence
This naturally induced in us the effort to enhance contemporary metaphysical of its own; she exposes certain conflicts between the theory of prime matter and
thinking by the treasures of the Aristotelian-scholastic past. Contemporary meta- other doctrines commonly ascribed to Aristotle. The concluding contribution of
physical speculation could thereby gain not only new stimuli and inspiration this section is by Ross Inman. It focuses on the notion of "essential dependence"
for solving challenging philosophical problems but also firm grounding in the and tries to show how scholastic analyses of this notion (especially those under-
intellectual history of the Western world. In this we are not entirely original taken by Duns Scotus) can help to remedy a certain void in contemporary ana-
but can follow up on the already existing tradition of Analytical Thomism. How- lytical discussions regarding the topic of truthmaking.
ever, unlike the proponents of Analytical Thomism we are inspired not only by The third section comprises three contributions related in some way or other
the legacy of Thomas Aquinas but also seek advice from the technically more to the problems of substance and accident. E. J. Lowe opens the section with the
elaborate Thomistic, Scotistic, and other traditions of Second Scholasticism, article "Essence and ontology", in which he tries to show how by combining a neo-
which have not been thoroughly researched yet. The endeavour of Renaissance Aristotelian account of essence with a neo-Aristotelian "four-category ontology"
and Baroque scholastic authors at technical refinement makes them intrinsically of individual substances, modes, substantial universals, and property universals,
related to the analytical tradition. a thoroughgoing metaphysical foundation for modal truths can be provided.
We are honoured that several outstanding proponents of contemporary ana- Lukag Novak continues in a similar vein by presenting an "Aristotelian" argument
lytical metaphysics as well as prominent specialists in the history of scholastic against the theory of the so-called "bare particulars", thus providing a defence of
philosophy have appreciated our idea of relating the traditional and the new an essentialist account of substances and accidents. Prokop Sousedik and David
metaphysics and accepted the invitation to the conference Metaphysics: Aristo- Svoboda, who jointly authored the concluding contribution of this section, pose
telian, Scholastic, Analytic (Prague, the Czech Republic, June 30 - July 3, 2010). This the question whether number is an accident. By way of an answer they develop a
publication is the fruit of this conference. It contains both historical and syste- neo-Aristotelian theory of number which attempts to steer a middle way between
matic contributions. We have grouped them according to their topic to form six "the Scylla of Aristotelian naturalism" and "the Charybdis of Platonic idealism".
sections titled Categories and Beyond, Metaphysical Structure, Substance and Accident, The fourth section is devoted to existence. In his article Edward Feser criticises,
Existence, Modalities, and Predication. from a broadly Aristotelian-Thomistic standpoint, the doctrine of existential
The first section, dealing with categories (and what is beyond), is devoted to inertia, contrasting it with the doctrine of divine conservation. In the other
the problem of ontological classification in general. It opens with the article by article of this section, Gyula Klima takes the comparison of two different accounts
Peter van Inwagen who explores the notion of ontological category such that it of the relation between essence and existence, namely those of Aquinas and
may be utilised in defining ontology. Inwagen proposes that "ontology proper" (as Buridan, as a point of departure for some more general thoughts concerning the
opposed to meta-ontology) is an attempt to set out a satisfactory list of ontological possibility of cross-paradigm argumentation.
categories. In the second article, Daniel D. Novotny broadens the scope of enquiry The subject of the penultimate section is the modality and its metaphysi-
by focusing on the problem of the ontological status of the so-called "beings of cal grounding. In the first contribution, Edmund Runggaldier reconstructs the
reason": entities or pseudo-entities beyond the confines of reality proper. In his scholastic theory of potentiality which draws an important distinction between
approach he fruitfully combines the contributions of scholastic and analytical subjective and objective potencies. He shows how these two kinds of potencies
thinkers, thus implicitly providing a positive answer to his concluding question allow for two complementary accounts of modalities, of which the first corre-
whether contemporary analytical metaphysics can draw some inspiration from sponds more to the "common sense" perception of modalities while the other
scholastic debates. approximates to modern possible-world semantics. In a further development of

6 7
PREFACE

the topic, David Peroutka combines the contemporary and Aristotelian analysis
of "powers" or "potencies" to explain the necessity of causal nexus and the
grounding of possibility in active and passive causal capabilities. The concluding
contribution by Mark Faller focuses on Leibniz's understanding of necessity and
possibility. Working in quite a broad context, Faller tries to develop a unified
reading of Leibniz and praises him for his realist view of the nature of truth and
SECTION I
its corresponding reality.
The topic of the final section is predication in a metaphysical perspective. Uwe
Meixner provides an historical survey of various interpretations of predication
and its metaphysical basis. He defends the view that Frege, despite some deficits
in his conception, was the first to bring the philosophy of predication on the
CATEGORIES
right track, and proposes his own Frege-inspired theory. On the contrary, Sta-
nislav Sousedik in the closing contribution defends a pre-Fregean notion of pre-
dication and presents a theory of his own, conceived as a modern recasting of the
AND BEYOND
Thom istic, metaphysically grounded identity theory of predication.
We would like to thank all the participants of the Prague conference for their
contributions, especially to the authors of the papers published in this book.
It was an honour and pleasure to work with them. Special thanks belongs to
our language editor and proofreader Svetla Jarogova, who has spared us many
errors and substantially contributed to the quality of the text. For any remaining
mistakes and shortcomings we take, of course, full responsibility. We are also
grateful to Rafael Huntelmann of Ontos Verlag for his interest in this volume
and his patience with our work on it. We are also obliged to express our gratitude
to His Grace, Right Reverend Michael Josef Pojezdnyr, O.Praem., the Abbot of the
Strahov Monastery, for generously providing the historical premises of the mo-
nastery for the conference. We are further indebted to the Dean of the Catholic
Theological Faculty of the Charles University Prague, Spectabilis ThDr. Prokop
Bra and to the Director of the Institute of Philosophy of the Academy of Sciences
of the Czech Republic, PhDr. Pavel Baran, CSc., for the sympathy with which they
accepted patronage of the conference. The conference was organised by the
Catholic Theological Faculty of the Charles University together with the Institute
of Philosophy of the Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic.
The conference proceedings are being published with the financial support
of the Grant Agency of the Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic, Grant
No. IAA908280801 "Metaphysics in contemporary analytical philosophy and its
relations to the metaphysics of modern Aristotelianism".
Stanislav Sousedik
David Svoboda, Prokop Sousedik
Daniel D. Novotny, Lukcig Novak

8
WHAT IS AN ONTOLOGICAL CATEGORY?
Peter van Inwagen

ABSTRACT heCT
ITn RtA pa
In the author examines the concept of a natural class, and proposes a definition
of "ontological category" in terms of that concept. Say that a class is "large" if its membership
comprises a significant proportion of the things that there are. Say that a class is "high" if it is
a proper subclass of no natural class. Then a natural class is a primary ontological category if and
only if (a) there are large natural classes, and (b) it is a high class. (Secondary, tertiary, etc.,
ontological categories are defined by an extension of this definition.) The author defends the
definition, considers various ways in which it might be modified, and applies it to the problem
of constructing a taxonomy of ontologies.

As names of divisions of philosophy go, "ontology" is a rather new word. Al-


though it is older than that terminological parvenu "epistemology", it is much
newer than "metaphysics" or "ethics" or "logic" - and, of course, it is much newer
than "philosophy". But the word is as hard to define as any of her elder sisters.
within analytical philosophy,' one finds three understandings of the word "onto-
logy" - or, if you like, three conceptions of ontology.'
One of them, the use of the word by Bergmann and his school, is that ontology
is the study of the ontological structure of objects. I reject this conception of
ontology. I reject it as provincial, as the identification of a kingdom with one of
its provinces. (In my view - I defend this view in an unpublished companion piece
to this paper entitled "Relational vs. Constituent Ontologies" - that province is
uninhabited. But I do not reject the Bergmanian conception of ontology on that
ground alone: I contend that it is a provincial conception even if objects do have
ontological structures.)
There is, secondly, what I will call the "bare Quinean" conception of ontology.
Quine has famously called the question "What is there?" "the ontological

' For a discussion of the existential-phenomenological conception of ontology, see my


essay, "Being, Existence, and Ontological Commitment", in Metametaphysics: New Essays on the
Foundations of Ontology, ed. David J. Chalmers, David Manley, and Ryan Wasserman (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2009), 472-506.
2 This count - three conceptions of ontology - is problematical, owing to the fact that many

analytical philosophers who have made important contributions to ontology (on anyone's
conception of ontology) have not given an explicit statement of what they take ontology to
be. Perhaps I should say: Within analytical philosophy, one finds three potential or implicit or
tacit understandings of ontology (see note 3).

CATEGORIES AND BEYOND • 11


Peter van Inwagen Peter van Inwagen
WHAT IS AN ONTOLOGICAL CATEGORY? WHAT IS AN ONTOLOGICAL CATEGORY?

question", and one might incautiously infer from this label that he conceives of will indeed insist that it would be a mistake to try to provide such an account
ontology as the attempt to answer the ontological question. But neither Quine owing to the fact that those words are no more than expressions of the subjective
nor anyone else would regard just any answer to the ontological question as reactions of various philosophers to the degree of generality exhibited by various
the kind of answer a discipline called ontology might be expected to provide. existential theses.'
Quine himself has observed that one correct answer to the ontological question The third conception of ontology - it is the conception I favour - rests on the
is "Everything" - and we certainly do not need to turn to any science or discipline conviction that the notion of a "general" or "abstract" or "systematic" answer to
to satisfy ourselves that that answer is correct. Another sort of correct answer the ontological question can be given an objective sense. The third conception
might well be of the following form: a very long - no doubt infinite - conjunction rests on the conviction that there are ontological categories and that it is the
of existential quantifications on "low-level" predicates, a conjunction that would business of ontology to provide answers to the ontological question in terms of a
perhaps read in part "... and there are bananas and there are electron neutrinos specification of the ontological categories. I will attempt to give an account of the
and there are protein molecules and there are locomotives ... and there are colours concept on which this conception of ontology rests, the concept of an ontological
and there are political parties and there are nontrivial zeros of the Riemann zeta category.
function...". (Perhaps its final conjunct - if a sentence comprising infinitely many * * *

conjuncts can have a final conjunct - would be: "and there is nothing else".) If the I begin with the idea of a natural class. One of the assumptions on which
only answers (other than answers that involve the "everything trick", answers the third conception of ontology rests is that natural classes are real. By this
like "Everything" and "Locomotives and everything else") that can be given I do not necessarily mean that there are objects called "natural classes", for an
to the ontological question are those provided by the investigative techniques ontologian (why is there no such word?) may well deny that there are classes of
native to everyday life and the special sciences, then all answers to the ontological any description." Indeed, anyone who did deny the existence of classes would ipso
question may well be of that sort. But if there is a philosophical discipline called facto be engaged in ontology. What I mean by saying that there are natural classes
ontology, it will attempt to give an answer to the ontological question that is in is a consequence of the thesis that there are natural - non-conventional - lines
some sense more general, more abstract, more systematic than a long conjunction of division among things. This assumption was famously rejected by Hobbes,
of existential quantifications on low-level predicates. And the "bare Quinean" and, following him, by Locke and the other empiricists. As Locke says (in the
will agree with this statement: on the bare Quinean conception of ontology, concluding passage of Chapter 3 of Book III of the Essay),
ontology is the discipline whose business it is to provide an abstract or general
Recapitulation. - To conclude: This is that which in short I would say, viz., that all
or systematic answer to the ontological question - answers that are less abstract
the great business of genera and species, and their essences, amounts to no more
and more informative than "Everything" and less informative and more abstract but this, that men making abstract ideas, and settling them in their minds, with
than "long list" answers. names annexed to them, do thereby enable themselves to consider things, and
The bare Quinean will, however, be happy to regard the ideas expressed by discourse of them, as it were in bundles, for the easier and readier improvement
the words "general", "abstract", and "systematic" as entirely subjective. On the
bare Quinean conception of ontology, it is the business of the practitioners of
3 I have not said that Quine or anyone else is a bare Quinean. I suspect, however, that
ontology to produce and defend answers to the ontological question that - as
Quine would at the very least find bare Quineanism an attractive formulation of the nature
one might say - strike them and their peers as "general" and "abstract" and of ontology (see note 2).
"systematic", answers that it seems appropriate to them to apply those terms to. ' The "classes" that figure in this essay are - or are if they really exist - much more
If, for example, I say that there are abstract objects or sets or temporal parts like biological taxa than they are like sets. Like taxa, and unlike sets, they can change their
of persisting objects, the bare Quineans will almost certainly recognise this as membership with the passage of time and the membership of a class in one possible world
an assertion of the kind that characterises ontology. But if I say that there are may not even overlap its membership in another. Like taxa, and unlike sets, moreover, they
bananas or protein molecules or solutions to Einstein's field equations that are may have "borderline members" (if there is something that is neither determinately a cat
without physical interest, these assertions will almost certainly seen by the bare nor determinately a non-cat, that does not prevent "cat" from being a natural class). But
I am not seriously asserting that there really are things that have the properties I have
Quineans as having a place in ontology only as examples that illustrate some ascribed to classes. I issue this promissory note: I could - the result would be rather awkward,
much more general existential thesis or as premises of some argument for some I concede - eliminate the apparent reference to and quantification over classes in the sequel by
much more general existential thesis. And they will offer no account of what it paraphrase. In my view, the only substantive philosophical issue raised by my talk of "natural
is for an existential thesis to be "much more general" than these theses. They classes" is whether there are real lines of division among things.

12 • CATEGORIES AND BEYOND CATEGORIES AND BEYOND • 13


Peter van Inwagen Peter van Inwagen
WHAT IS AN ONTOLOGICAL CATEGORY? WHAT IS AN ONTOLOGICAL CATEGORY?

and communication of their knowledge, which would advance but slowly, were their For any class, if its boundary marks a real division among things, then either that
words and thoughts confined only to particulars. class or its complement is a natural class - but not necessarily both.

I am not wholly convinced that what Locke says in this "recapitulation" is If you ask me, "In such a case, how do we determine which of two given
consistent with everything he says in the Essay (or even with everything he says complementary classes are natural classes?", I'm afraid I do not have any very
in Chapter 3 of Book III), but, whether it will do as an unqualified statement of informative answer. I could try this: The ones with "sufficient internal unity". It
Locke's views or not, it is a good statement of the point of view whose rejection does seem obvious to me that if the boundary between a class and its complement
is one of the assumptions on which the third conception of ontology rests. (From marks a real division among things, at least one of the two must exhibit sufficient
this point on, when I ascribe features to "ontology", I shall be speaking from the internal unity for it to be called a natural class. If this thesis is granted, the
point of view of the third conception - my own conception.) According to this existence of natural classes follows from the existence of real divisions among
anti-Lockean philosophy of classification, some classes of things - a minuscule things. Nevertheless, the concept of "natural class" cannot be defined solely in
proportion of them, if classes are anything like as numerous as sets - correspond terms the concept "real division." We must also appeal to the concept of "sufficient
to real divisions among things: in each case, the real division between the things internal unity" if we are to provide a full explanation of "natural class". (Or, at any
that are members of that set and those that are not.' To say that there are rate, we must appeal to some concept other than "real division") One might in fact
real divisions among things implies the existence of natural classes,' but this contend that, if we really have the concept "sufficient internal unity", we could
statement does not say enough to settle the question of what natural classes use it to define the concept "real division among things". (Suppose a class exhibits
there are - not even to settle it in the rather abstract and uninformative way "sufficient internal unity"; suppose its union with no unit class other than its unit
I want to settle it in this initial discussion of the natural classes. To show you what subclasses has this feature; then it is plausible to suppose that its boundary marks
I mean by this statement, I'm going to ask you to consider two questions about a real division among things.) Why, then, have I assigned such a fundamental
the relation between the concepts "real division among things" and the concept role to "real division" in my exposition of the concept "natural class"? Because,
"natural class". first, it seems to me that "real division" is a far easier idea to grasp than the idea
I shall introduce the first of these two questions by the following example. "exhibits sufficient internal unity". And because, secondly, in most interesting
Suppose that the line that marks the division between horses and non-horses cases in which the boundary between two complementary classes marks a real
is one of those real lines of division among things. Does it follow that "horse" division among things, it will be simply evident that - whatever internal unity
is a natural class? Before you answer, consider this question: Does it follow that may be - either one of them exhibits vastly more internal unity than the other or
"non-horse" is a natural class? That "non-horse" is a natural class certainly does they both exhibit an approximately equal (and very high) degree of internal unity.
not seem to be a thesis that should be true by definition. But the boundary of that Now the second question about the relation between "real division" and
class marks a real division among things. At any rate, it does if the boundary of "natural class". Consider the universal class, the class of all things.' Is it a natural
"horse" marks a real division among things, since the two classes have the same class? I propose to leave this an open question - to provide an account of "natural
boundary. We therefore do not want to say that a class is a natural class given class" that leaves it an open question.8 Does what I have said have any implications
only that its boundary marks a real division among things. for this question? The only relevant implication of what we have said is this: if the
I think that the following statement is a more plausible candidate for what we boundary of the universal class marks a real division among things, then either
want to say about the relation between "real division" and "natural class": the universal class or the empty class is a natural class. Well, what is the boundary
of the universal class? In one sense, it has no boundary - not if boundaries divide
5 Real divisions need not be sharp divisions. If one divides the world into things that
are determinately cats, things that are determinately not cats and things that are neither
determinately cats nor determinately non-cats, one may have thereby have marked a real ' Even those who are realists about classes will be well advised to treat the universal class
division among things. as a virtual class - that is to treat apparent reference to it as a mere - and dispensable - matter
6 Or, to speak more carefully (see note 4), it implies that those who have no objection to of speaking.
affirming the existence of classes should regard some of those classes as natural classes. And 8 Suppose that Meinong was wrong and that one name for the universal class is "being".
even nominalists who believe in real divisions among things may find it useful to speak as if Aristotle held that "being" was not a category. On the account of "ontological category" I shall
those divisions marked the boundaries of natural classes. (Such nominalists will presumably propose - and given that Meinong was wrong -, "being" will be a category if it is a natural
be able to eliminate, at least in principle, apparent reference to and apparent quantification class. I do not want to give an account of "natural class" that will imply either the truth or
over natural classes from their discourse.) the falsity of Aristotle's thesis.

14 • CATEGORIES AND BEYOND CATEGORIES AND BEYOND • 15


Peter van Inwagen Peter van Inwagen
WHAT IS AN ONTOLOGICAL CATEGORY? WHAT IS AN ONTOLOGICAL CATEGORY?

things from other things. But we might not insist that a boundary must divide proportion of the things that there are are bosons or fermions. We might, for
things. (Suppose the universe is finite in extent; adopt a relational theory of space. example, imagine that she supposes that, for any xs, the mereological sum of
Isn't it reasonable to say that in that case the universe has a boundary, a boundary the xs exists, and that among these sums are to be found atoms and molecules
that nothing is outside?) and cats and locomotives and galaxies and most of the tangible or visible things
The simplest way to leave it an open question whether the universal class is a that we unreflectively believe in. (And, of course, Alice believes that there are
natural class is to stipulate that it has no boundary (in which case our principle a vast number of convoluted gerrymanders most of which are not - considered
says nothing about whether it is a natural class). We say, that is, that a class has a individually - possible objects of human thought.) The class of cats, Alice con-
boundary if (and only if) both that class and its complement are non-empty. Those tends, is not a natural class: the vague and imperfect boundary we have drawn
who want to say that the universal class is a natural class - or that it is not - must around the cats is a mere product of convention and fails to reflect a real division
defend their thesis on some ground that does not involve the properties of its among things, unlike the boundary we have drawn around the bosons. And the
boundary (perhaps on the ground of its "internal unity" or lack thereof). It will same goes for the locomotives and the galaxies. (Of course most classes of sums
be observed that, in virtue of this stipulation, we have left it an open question are cognitively inaccessible to us, but, says Alice, if, per impossibile, we were to
whether the empty class is a natural class. I hereby stipulate that the empty draw boundaries around any of these classes, those boundaries would be merely
class is not a natural class - but for no profound reason; whether the empty class conventional - and with a vengeance.) And, of course, she maintains that the
is a natural class seems to be one of those "don't care" questions, one of those class of things that are neither bosons nor fermions is, as one might say, radically
questions that can properly be settled by stipulation, and stipulating that it is not deficient in internal unity and is not a natural class.
a natural class will simplify some of my definitions and the statements of some If Alice is right, ontology is, again, like astrology: a science that rests on a
of my theses. false assumption. For one of the assumptions on which ontology rests is this:
Are there any natural classes? Well, it seems plausible to suppose so. The class that membership in the natural classes is not restricted to any such minuscule
of electrons is a plausible candidate for the office "natural class" - as plausible proportion of the things that there are as Alice supposes it to be.
a candidate as there could be, in my view. (The boundary between electrons It is an assumption of ontology that there indeed are natural classes whose
and non-electrons is certainly a plausible candidate for the office "boundary membership comprises a really significant proportion of the things that there
that marks a real division among things", and it seems evident that the class of are. I am acutely aware that the idea of a class whose membership comprises
electrons exhibits vastly more internal unity than the class of non-electrons.) The a really significant proportion of the things that there are is an idea that it is
class of horses (members of the species Equus caballus) would be a rather more hard to give any precise sense to. But it does not seem to me to be an obviously
controversial but still reasonably plausible example. meaningless or entirely vacuous idea. Take our friend Alice. In her view there
Whether there are natural classes or not, it is one of the assumptions of are certainly a lot more things - even a lot more concrete things - than there
ontology that there are. (If there are no natural classes, ontology is like astrology: are things that are members of some natural class. If, for example, there are
a science that rests on a false assumption.) It is, moreover, one of the assumptions 10 exp 80 bosons and fermions, then there are 2 exp (10 exp 80) - 1 things
of ontology that, although some pairs of natural classes may have non-empty (abstractions aside): there are 10 exp 80 things that belong to some natural class
intersections otherwise than by one's being a subclass of the other, there are and ((2 exp (10 exp 80) - 1) - 10 exp 80 things that belong to no natural class, and
nested sequences of natural classes - sequences ordered by the subclass relation. the latter number is inconceivably larger than the former. (The ratio of the latter
The class of electrons, the class of leptons, and the class of fermions provide a to the former can be described this way. Think of the number that is expressed
plausible example of such a sequence. The class of horses, the class of mammals, by a "1" followed by eighty zeros. The ratio of the number of things that belong
and the class of chordates would (again) be a rather more controversial but still to no natural class to the number of things that belong to some natural class
reasonably plausible example. is a number that can be expressed by a "1" followed by - approximately - one-
One could, however, affirm the existence of natural classes and of nested third that many zeros.) Or if the number of bosons and fermions is denumerably
sequences of natural classes without involving oneself in ontology - or in any infinite, then the number of (concrete) things that belong to no natural class is
other part of philosophy. Suppose, for example, that Alice maintains that the indenumerably infinite.
largest natural classes are the class of bosons and the class of fermions and that There are various ways in which there might be natural classes whose mem-
every natural class is a subclass of one of these two non-overlapping classes. bership comprised "a really significant proportion of the things that there are".
And suppose that she also maintains that (in some sense) only a very small

16 • CATEGORIES AND BEYOND CATEGORIES AND BEYOND • 17


Peter van Inwagen
! Peter van Inwagen
WHAT IS AN ONTOLOGICAL CATEGORY? WHAT IS AN ONTOLOGICAL CATEGORY?

(Let us call such a class "large".) One of them is this: the universal class is a natural a -matter-of-convention classification. But remember that the highest links in the
class - for the membership of a class is certainly a "significant proportion" of itself. great chains of classification are primary ontological categories only if primary
Here is another way. It may be that, although the class of all things, the uni- ontological categories exist - just as the highest buildings are skyscrapers only if
versal class, is not a natural class, it is the union of a small number of natural skyscrapers exist. If our friend Alice is right about what natural classes there are,
classes. (A "small" number would be a number like 2 or 6 or 19. And what do the highest natural classes are not primary ontological categories. (If she is right,
I mean by "a number like"? You may well ask. But if you want a definition of "small the highest natural class, the class of elementary particles, is not an ontological
number", I offer the following. A number n is small in just this case: if a class is category, since there are no large natural classes.) Her world corresponds, in the
the union of n subclasses, the membership at least one of them must comprise a analogy, to a world in which the highest buildings are three stories high: highest
really significant proportion of the membership of that class.) buildings but no skyscrapers.
And here is a third. Say that a natural class is "high" if is not a proper subclass Having defined "primary ontological category", we may proceed to define
of any natural class. At least one high natural class is large - although some things "secondary ontological category", "tertiary ontological category", and so on, by
belong to no natural class. (Suppose, for example, that God exists and that a vast repeated applications of essentially the same device. We say that x is a natural
number of creatures exist and that everything is either God or a creature. Suppose subclass ofy if x is a subclass of y and x is a natural class. We say that x is a large
that God belongs to no natural class - and hence that the universal class is not a subclass ofy if x is a subclass ofy and x comprises a significant proportion of the
natural class - and that the class of creatures is a natural class.) members ofy. We say that x is a high subclass ofy if x is a natural proper subclass
Note that the assumption we are considering, that there are large natural of y and is a proper subclass of no natural proper subclass of y. Then, a natural
classes, leaves open the possibility that that there are high natural classes that are class x is a secondary ontological category if
not large. Our assumption is, for example, consistent with the following threefold There is a primary ontological category y such that
thesis: everything is either a substance or (exclusive) an attribute; "substance"
and "attribute" are both natural classes and every natural class is a subclass of - y has large natural proper subclasses
one or the other; there are finitely many substances and too many attributes to - x is a high subclass ofy.
be numbered even by a transfinite number. In this case, "substance" is a high And so for tertiary ontological category, quaternary ontological category, ....
class, despite the fact that only an insignificant proportion of the things that And, finally, an ontological category (simpliciter)10 is a class that, for some /7, is
there are are substances. an n-ary ontological category."
We may now define "ontological category". Let us say, first, that a natural class
x is a primary ontological category just in the case that '° In formulating this definition of "ontological category", I have assumed that every
- there are large natural classes sequence of natural classes ordered by the proper-subclass relation has a first member. (If
this were not so, there might be large natural classes but no high natural classes - and hence
- x is a high natural class. no primary ontological categories and hence no ontological categories of any order. But it is
Consider for example the case presented in the previous paragraph. In this at least plausible to suppose that any large natural class is an ontological category, and even
more plausible to suppose that if there are large natural classes, some of them are ontological
case "substance" and "attribute" are high natural classes and are in fact the high categories.) This is a consequence of the stronger statement that every such sequence is finite.
natural classes. And there are large natural classes - the class of attributes if no I see no reason to question either of these theses.
other. "Substance" and "attribute are therefore primary ontological categories - " Note that this definition allows ontological categories to overlap. Suppose that every-
and are the primary ontological categories.' thing is either an A or a B, that A and B are natural classes, and that neither is a proper subclass
The primary ontological categories are the highest links in the great chains of any natural class. Then A and B are primary ontological categories. But nothing we have
of classification - the great chains of non-arbitrary classification, of not-merely- said implies that A and B do not overlap. (Cf. n. 9). Suppose further that they do overlap and
that their intersection is a natural class that is not a proper subclass of any natural class.
Then their intersection is also a primary ontological category. Or suppose that A and B do not
9 Note that the definition does not rule out overlapping primary ontological categories. overlap, and that A can be partitioned into two subclasses C and D, each of which is a natural
Suppose, for example, that Phoebe maintains that "abstract" and "concrete" are the primary class and that B can be partitioned into two subclasses E and F, each of which is a natural class.
ontological categories. She may consistently go on to maintain that the proposition that Suppose that the union of C and E is a natural class that is a proper subclass of no natural class.
Socrates was a philosopher is abstract (in virtue of being a proposition) and concrete (in virtue Then the union of C and E is a primary ontological category that overlaps both the primary
of having a certain concrete object, Socrates, as an ontological constituent). categories A and B and the secondary categories C and E.

18 • CATEGORIES AND BEYOND CATEGORIES AND BEYOND • 19


7
Peter van Inwagen Peter van Inwagen
WHAT IS AN ONTOLOGICAL CATEGORY? WHAT IS AN ONTOLOGICAL CATEGORY?

One might wonder whether this account of "ontological category" has the the lowest ontological categories are the quaternary categories. (Someone might
consequence that this concept is "entirely subjective" - and thus wonder whether be happy to suppose that "you'd have to get down into the twenties" before
the account of ontology that I am proposing in the end reduces to the "bare things you were calling ontological categories became objectionably dependent
Quinean" conception of ontology. It is certainly true that the account depends on the contingencies of history.) This idea is, obviously, attended by all manner
essentially on certain vague terms. (For example, "the membership of x comprises of difficulties, but there is no point in trying to solve them, because there are
a significant proportion of the membership ofy".) I would contend, however, that imaginable cases of "modally fragile" primary and secondary categories. Con-
the vague is not the same as the subjective. For example, "delicious" is a subjective sider, for example, Bertram, who, like Alice, believes that the highest natural
term, in contrast to "edible" and "nutritious", which are merely vague. I would classes are "boson" and "fermion". But - unlike Alice - Bertram is a mereological
also point out that there can be perfectly clear cases of objects that fall under nihilist (and a nominalist to boot): he believes that everything is either a boson
vague terms, and that this account, when applied to a particular metaphysic may or a fermion. By the above definition, then it follows from these beliefs of his
yield determinate answers to the question, "What, according to that metaphysic, that "boson" and "fermion" are primary ontological categories. So far forth, this
are the ontological categories?" It may be obvious, for example, that according to might not be objectionable. But suppose Bertram also believes that the physical
Albert's metaphysic, there are no secondary ontological categories, since all his economy of most possible worlds is radically different from the physical economy
primary categories have infinitely many members and all other natural classes of the actual world. Suppose he believes that there are non-arbitrary measures
have only finitely many members - which entails that none of Albert's primary of the sizes many sets of possible worlds (the measure of the whole of logical
categories have large natural subsets. space being 1), and that the measure of the set of worlds that contains bosons
Assuming that the "subjectivity" worry has been adequately answered, is the and fermions is [insert here a decimal point and a string of sixty zeros]13 - or
above account of "ontological category" satisfactory? I am inclined to think that believes that the measure is infinitesimal or even O. In that case, I think it would
this account is incomplete. I am inclined to think that there should be a further be just wrong to say that it follows from his beliefs that "boson" and "fermion"
condition on what an "ontological category" is, a modal condition. I think this are ontological categories. It seems to me to be wrong to call a natural class an
because what I have so far said allows ontological categories to be rather fragile, ontological category if it exists in "hardly any" possible worlds.
modally speaking, much more fragile than I'm comfortable with their being. One I am inclined to think, therefore, that the account of "ontological category"
kind of example that makes me uneasy is this: it is consistent with this account that I have given needs to be supplemented by a clause to the effect that an onto-
that the natural class "dog" (let's assume that this is a natural class) turn out to logical category must in some sense be "modally robust" - but almost certainly
be, oh, let's say, a 23-ary ontological category. And this result seems wrong to not so robust that an ontological category must, by definition, exist in all possible
me - and not because I have anything against either dogs or allowing the science worlds. I leave for another occasion the problem of spelling out what this means
of biology to have implications for ontology. It seems wrong to me because the - and the question whether my modal scruples as regards ontological categories
fact that there is such a natural class as "dog" is - no doubt - radically contingent. are justified.
Very small changes in the world of a hundred million years ago - changes local Let us now return to the concept of ontology. Ontology, as I see ontology,
to the surface of the earth - would have resulted in there never having been any rests on the following assumption: there are ontological categories. We may, in
such class. And it seems evident to me that a satisfactory account of "ontological fact, define ontology as the discipline whose business is to specify the ontological
category" should not allow the list of ontological categories to be dependent on categories. Remember that the empty set or class is not to count as a natural class,
the contingencies of history to that extent. But to what extent might the list be a and it is therefore true by definition that all ontological categories are non-empty.
matter of contingency? I do not want to say that an ontological category must be, To specify the ontological categories is therefore to make an existential statement
by definition, necessarily existent (that is, represented in every possible world). - even if one regards the categories themselves as virtual classes and thus as
If some school of metaphysicians proposes "contingent thing" as an ontological not really "there". If for example, one says that "substance" is an ontological
category, I do not think that that proposal should commit them to the proposition category, this statement implies that there are substances. The goal of ontology
that there are, of necessity, contingent things - although it should commit them is to provide an answer to the ontological question in the form of a specification
to the proposition that, of necessity, if there are contingent things they form or I of the ontological categories.
constitute an ontological category. It is a commonplace that the word "ontology" is used both as a mass term
The example I have said makes me uneasy might be "handled" by some sort and a count-noun. When it is used as a mass term, it denotes a certain discipline,
of restriction on the "n" in "n-ary ontological category" - say, by insisting that a certain sub-field of philosophy or of metaphysics - just that discipline that

20 • CATEGORIES AND BEYOND CATEGORIES AND BEYOND • 21


Peter van Inwagen Peter van Inwagen
WHAT IS AN ONTOLOGICAL CATEGORY? WHAT IS AN ONTOLOGICAL CATEGORY?

I have been attempting to give an account of. When it is used as a count-noun, it two categories "the existent" and "the (concrete but) non-existent", and the
is used to refer to certain philosophically interesting answers to the ontological category "the abstract" divides into the two categories "the subsistent" and "the
question. If my account of ontology is right, an ontology is a specification of the (abstract but) non-subsistent". The union of the existent and the subsistent is
ontological categories. itself an ontological category, the category of Sein, and the complement of that
I briefly show how this account of "ontology" fares when it is applied to category is a category, the category Nichtsein.15 If Sosein is not a natural class, then
two very different ontologies. My first example is the ontology I myself favour. the abstract, the concrete, Sein, and Nichtsein are primary categories and the
According to this ontology, there are two primary categories, substance and re- categories that pertain to existence and subsistence are secondary categories.
lation. (Unless the universal class is a natural class, in which case it is the primary Let me now say something to connect the definition of ontology I have given
category, and substance and relation are the two secondary categories. I have no with an ancient and important definition of ontology.
firm opinion about whether the universal class - I suppose the best name for it The definition I am thinking of derives from one of Aristotle's definitions of
would be "being" if it is thought of as a category - is a natural class and therefore "first philosophy" in Metaphysics: Ontology is the science of being as such or being
a category. qua being. In my view, this Aristotelian definition of ontology is, if not entirely
The category "relation" subsumes propositions (0-adic relations) and attributes satisfactory, not wholly wrong either. I would defend this position as follows.
(monadic relations). The universal class, the class of all things, is either the class of all beings - the
The category "substance" goes by two other names, "concrete thing" and class whose membership is just exactly the things that there are -, or else it is
"individual (thing)"." Similarly, the category "relation" is also called "abstract the class that comprises both all beings and all non-beings. (Or, as a Meinon-
thing" and "universal". It is not my position that that, e.g., "substance" and gian might prefer to say, the universal class, the "realm" of Sosein, comprises
"individual" are synonymous. Although I say that all substances are individual two non-overlapping realms, the realm of being and the realm of non-being.)
things and all individual things are substances, I regard this as a substantive In the former case, being is what is common to the members of all ontological
thesis, one of the component propositions of my ontology that requires a philo- categories, and, if there is something common to all the ontological categories,
sophical defence. And the same goes for the pairs "substance" and "concrete it seems plausible to say that a science or discipline whose business is to specify
thing", "concrete thing" and "particular", "relation" and "abstract thing", the ontological categories should have as one of its first orders of business to say
"abstract thing" and "universal", and "universal" and "relation". I contend only what this "something" is. In the latter case, being and non-being are the two of
that the extensions of each pair are the same." the highest ontological categories (perhaps Sosein is the highest category) and,
My second example is the Meinongian ontology.'" The universal class, the if there is such a category as non-being, the task of explaining what being is and
class of "objects" or the realm of Sosein divides into the two ontological categories the task of explaining what non-being is can be divorced from each other only
the concrete and the abstract (I do not mean to imply that those two terms are by an act of severe abstraction: if those tasks are in any sense "two", they must
actually used by Meinongians). The category "the concrete" divides into the nevertheless be seen as two sub-tasks of one task. If I reject the Aristotelian
definition of ontology, it is not because I deny that the question "What is being?"
is one of the questions that ontology must answer. I reject it because I deny that
12 Or "particular (thing)". As I use the words, "individual" and "particular" are synonyms.
(Some writers give different senses to these two words.) I use "thing" as the most general it is the primary ontological question, the question that defines the business of
count-noun: everything is a thing; "every thing" and "everything" are synonyms; a "thing" ontology.
is anything that can be the referent of a pronoun. I use such words as "object", "entity" and A word on terminology. In other discussions of ontology, I've said that onto-
"item" in the same sense. logy divides into meta-ontology and ontology proper. Ontology proper, I said, is
13 One possible "version" of the ontology called "austere nominalism" raises a problem for the investigation of what there is, and meta-ontology addresses the two questions,
my account of ontology. This is the version I have in mind: there are only concrete particulars; What does "there is" mean? and What methods should be employed in the in-
there are no high natural classes: neither "concrete particular" nor any other large class is vestigation of what there is? But here I have defined ontology as the discipline that
a natural class. This version of austere nominalism seems clearly to be "an ontology" but it
implies that there are no ontological categories.
attempts to specify the ontological categories. Does this definition not identify
ontology (ontology simpliciter) with "ontology proper"? My earlier characteri-
" Meinongians will no doubt object to my use of the terms "the Meinongian ontology"
and "ontological category" in my description of their position - since, of course "to on" means
"being". They will insist that providing an answer to the question, "What is there?" is only one 's Assuming that "the concrete", "the abstract", "the existent", "the subsistent", "the
small part of their project. Well, let them find their own terminology. This is mine. non-existent", "the non-subsistent", Sein, and Nichtsein are all natural classes.

22 • CATEGORIES AND BEYOND CATEGORIES AND BEYOND • 23


Peter van Inwagen
WHAT IS AN ONTOLOGICAL CATEGORY?

sation of ontology and the present characterisation can be reconciled if we adopt


I
a sufficiently liberal understanding of "specify the ontological categories": to
specify the ontological categories is not merely to set out a list of categories;
specifying the ontological categories also involves explaining the concept of an SCHOLASTIC DEBATES ABOUT BEINGS OF REASON
ontological category and describing the relations between the categories and AND CONTEMPORARY ANALYTICAL METAPHYSICS
attempting to answer any philosophical questions that may arise in the course of
doing this. One of these philosophical questions will be the question of the nature Daniel D. Novotny
of being - which is essentially the question, What is it for a category to be non-
empty? (So, at any rate, we anti-Meinongians say. I leave it to the Meinongians to
explain in terms they find satisfactory what it is for a category to be non-empty.)
We may say then that "ontology proper" is the attempt to set out a satisfactory list ABSTRACT
of ontological categories; everything else in ontology belongs to meta-ontology. Prima facie it would seem that the traditional scholastic debates about entia rationis ("beings
of reason") may be easily brought into dialogue with debates about nonexistent objects in
contemporary analytical metaphysics. It turns out, however, that the scholastic debates about
beings of reason are placed within a very different ontological framework or paradigm, so
that bringing scholastic and analytical authors into common discussion about this topic is not
trivial. In this paper I make the first step toward establishing such discussion by describing
the ontological framework presupposed by the scholastic debates about beings of reason, and
by identifying the roles that beings of reason were supposed to play in it.

1. INTRODUCTION
One of the main tasks of metaphysics - as it was conceived by Aristotle -
is to provide a list of categories of what exists.' Late scholastic authors of the
Renaissance and Baroque periods, however, were increasingly preoccupied not
just with what exists but also with what does not exist.' The most important and
well-known label with which these late scholastic discussions are associated is 'ens
rationis', literally "being of reason".3 Prima facie it would seem that the traditional

' This is, of course, an oversimplification and a bold claim, see e.g. JORGE J. E. GRACIA,
Metaphysics and Its Task: The Search for the Categorial Foundation of Knowledge (Albany, NY: SUNY
Press, 1999); ROBERT A. DELFINO, ed., What are We to Understand Gracia to Mean: Realist Challenges
to Metaphysical Neutralism (Amsterdam and New York: Rodopi, 2006); and VAN INWAGEN's contri-
bution in this volume.
2 For an introduction into these scholastic discussions see, e.g., JOHN P. DOYLE, "Suarez on

Beings of Reason and Truth (First part)", Vivarium 25 (1987): 47-75; "Suarez on Beings of Reason
and Truth (Second part)", Vivarium 26 (1988): 51-72; DANIEL D. NOVOTNt "Prolegomena to a
Study of Beings of Reason in Post-Suarezian Scholasticism, 1600 -1650", Studia Neoaristotelica
3, no. 2 (2006): 117-141.
' Henceforth in this paper, for the sake of simplicity, whenever I shall speak about scho-
lasticism I shall mean "scholasticism of the Renaissance and especially Baroque period", to wit,
scholasticism of the seventeenth century. Baroque scholastic culture and discussions differed
in many ways from the scholasticism of the Middle Ages and the Renaissance. See DANIEL D.
NOVOTNt "In Defense of Baroque Scholasticism", Studia Neoaristotelica 6, no. 2 (2009): 209-233.

24 • CATEGORIES AND BEYOND CATEGORIES AND BEYOND • 25


Daniel D. Novotny Daniel D. Novotny
SCHOLASTIC DEBATES ABOUT BEINGS OF REASON SCHOLASTIC DEBATES ABOUT BEINGS OF REASON

scholastic debates about beings of reason may be easily brought into dialogue
with the current work on nonexistent objects in analytical metaphysics.4 It turns
out, however, that the scholastic debates about beings of reason are placed within Actual 4 Things in the
strict sense
a very different ontological framework or paradigm, so that bringing scholastic
and analytical authors into common discussion on this topic is not trivial. In this Possible
paper I make the first step toward establishing such discussion by (1) providing a Merely- Possible
description of the framework presupposed by the scholastic debates about beings Possible things
of reason, and (2) identifying the roles that beings of reason were supposed to
Being
play in it.
Second inten-
Positive 4 tions and other
2. THE ONTOLOGICAL FRAMEWORK OF SCHOLASTIC DEBATES relations of
reason
Let me start with a scheme (see the opposite page) attempting to classify Impossible
into "super-categories" whatever non-existing items one might encounter in Integral* Negations, pri-
scholastic works. Negative 4 vations, self-
incompatibles
At the very left of our scheme we see the term 'item'. By this term I mean
anything to which one can refer and of which one can say that "it is (in some
sense) there" (datur) - regardless of such issues as to whether it exists or whether Non-Being
Object*
it is real. (The asterisk next to this and some other super-categories indicates Para-
that it is a term that scholastic authors themselves did not use but that is useful Being
to have for our talk about their views). For comparison, in analytical philosophy Extrinsic
Bertrand Russell tried to capture this broad meaning of 'item' by the term term':5 Being
Item Accidental
Whatever may be an object of thought, or may occur in any true or false pro-
position, or can be counted as one, I call a term. This, then, is the widest word in
the philosophical vocabulary. I shall use as synonymous with it the words unit,
individual, and entity. The first two emphasise the fact that every term has being,
i.e. is in some sense. A man, a moment, a number, a class, a relation, a chimaera, or
anything else that can be mentioned, is sure to be a term...
Objective*
And Peter Strawson, to take another example, also acknowledged the possibi-
lity to have such a "widest word in philosophical vocabulary":'
Anything whatever can be introduced into discussion by means of a singular,
definitely identifying substantival expression... Since anything whatever can be
identifyingly referred to, being a possible object of identifying reference does not Items are divided into objects and objectives by which I mean things and
distinguish any class or type of items or entities from any other. propositions/states-of-affairs, respectively.' Let me expand a bit. Etymologically,
the word 'object' means "thrown in the way"; a stone, for instance, could be an
' For an overview of these debates see, e.g., MARIA REICHER, "Nonexistent Objects", The object. The stone is something that catches our attention and hence it becomes
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2010 Edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta, (http://plato.stanford.
edu/archives/fal12010/entries/nonexistent-objects/). 7 The division and the terminology is inspired by Alexius Meinong. What I call 'item'
5 BERTRAND RUSSELL, The Principles of Mathematics, (http://fair-use.org/bertrand-russell/ Meinong calls 'Gegenstand'. He then divides it into Objekt and Objektiv. See ALEXIUS MEINONG,
the-principles-of-mathematics/) (1" ed. Cambridge: At the University Press, 1903; rd ed. 1938), Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandstheorie and Psychologie (Leipzig: J. A. Barth, 1904), 6; translated
§47. in RODERICK M. CHISHOLM, Realism and the Background of Phenomenology (New York: The Free
6 PETER F. STRAWSON, Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics (New York: Routledge, Press, 1960), 80. See also JOHN N. FINDLAY, Meinong's theory of objects and values, 2"d ed. (Aldershot:
1959, repr. 2005), 137. Ashgate Publishing (Gregg revivals), 1995), 60-69 (1" ed. 1933).

26 • CATEGORIES AND BEYOND CATEGORIES AND BEYOND • 27


Daniel D. Novotny
SCHOLASTIC DEBATES ABOUT BEINGS OF REASON I Daniel D. Novotny
SCHOLASTIC DEBATES ABOUT BEINGS OF REASON

an object of perception and thought. But the expression 'object of thought', as Then we get to the division of beings into possible in the broad sense and
A. N. Prior points out, is ambiguous:8 impossible (impossibilia). Broadly possible beings are divided into actual (entia
The phrase 'object of thought' may be used in two very different ways. An object of
actu, vera entia) and merely possible (possibilia). Actual beings, i.e. beings in the
thought may be (1) what we think, or (2) what we think about; e.g. if we think that narrowest sense of the word, make up the world/reality of the scholastics." They
grass is green, (1) what we think is that grass is green, and (2) what we think about is are ontologically prior to everything else. Beings divide into substances, such as
grass. 'Objects of thought' ... are sometimes called 'propositions, not in the sense of people, animals, plants, or stones, and their various accidents, and are typically
sentences, but in the sense of what sentences mean.... What we think, may be false; and classified into nine structured groups, called 'categories'. Merely possible beings
what we think about may be non-existent. These are quite different defects, though were enormously controversial among the scholastics."
philosophers have sometimes slipped into treating them as if they were the same.
Finally, we get to the impossible beings, i.e. beings that cannot exist in actual
Some analytical philosophers consider Prior's propositions to be primary reality. These, according to the common default scholastic assumption, are mind-
truthmakers, corresponding or failing to correspond to facts or obtaining states- dependent and hence they are called `entia rationis'. As I have already said, this
of-affairs as truthmakers. These distinctions within the "genus" of objectives, expression means literally "beings of reason" although there are at least three
however, need not concern us at this point, because Baroque scholastics paid other translations of this term in use: 'mental being' (Gracia), `rationate being'
virtually no attention to them - at least in the context of beings of reason.° For (Schmidt), and 'intentional being' (Sousedik). I use 'being of reason' not only
them, the world is the totality of things and not of facts (pace Wittgenstein)." because it is the most common (Doyle, Cantetis), but also because its oddity high-
Next comes the division into accidental objects (per accidens, loosely united lights the fact that we speak about a kind of item taken from within a specifically
objects, aggregates) and integral objects (per se, "innerly integrated", tightly/ scholastic context."
naturally united objects). Accidental objects include artefacts, heaps, or any kind
of arbitrary wholes.
The following division, the division of integral objects, is of crucial importance,
because many scholastic authors simply identify integral (per se) objects with Leptotatos (Vigevani: Typis Episcopalibus, apud Camillum Conradam, 1681), diss. 2, pars 2,
beings (entia). There are, however, texts in which, for instance, Francisco Suarez a. 1, concl. 5, 96a; cf. Daniel D. Novotny, "Ens rationis in Caramuel's Leptotatos (1681)", in Juan
acknowledges the categories of non-beings and extrinsic beings. These, for the caramuel Lobkowitz, the Last Scholastic Polymath, ed. Petr Dvoi-ak and Jacob Schmutz (Praha:
lack of a better term, I call "para-beings", a term I have made up but which cap- Filosofia, 2008), 71-84.
tures the idea of a category of objects parasitic on beings in the strict sense." '2 This world/reality has material and non-material "regions". Angels, for instance, belong
to the non-material region and human beings are peculiar hybrids of the two worlds (they
have a non-material "part"). God has a sui generis ontological status: Everything, whether
8 ARTHUR N. PRIOR, Objects of Thought, ed. Peter Geach and Anthony Kenny (Oxford: Claren- material or non-material, depends on God both for the beginning and for the continuation of
don Press, 1971), 3-4. its existence (cf. E. FESER'S contribution to this volume).
9 There were some exceptions, see DANIEL D. NOVOTNY, "The Historical Non-Significance "3 There are several studies of the late scholastic views on merely possibles, e.g.: JEFFREY
of Suarez's Theory of Beings of Reason: A Lesson From Hurtado", in Metaphysics of Francisco CoomBs, "The Possibility of Created Entities in Seventeenth-Century Scotism", The Philosophical
Sucirez (1548-1617): Disputationes metaphysicae in their systematic and historical context, ed. Daniel Quarterly 43 (1993): 447-459; STANISLAV SOUSEDIK, "Der Streit um den wahren Sinn der Sco-
Heider, Lukag Novak, and David Svoboda (Prague, forthcoming), ch. 9. There is an evidence tischen Possibilienlehre", in John Duns Scotus: Metaphysics and Ethics, ed. Ludger Honnefelder,
that propositions and states-of-affairs (under the heading 'complexe significabile' - 'something Rega Wood, Mechtild Dreyer (Leiden: Brill, 1996), 191-204; TOBIAS HOFFMANN, Creatura intellecta:
signifiable in a complex way') were discussed in different contexts by Renaissance scholastics, see Die Ideen und Possibilien bei Duns Scotus mit Ausblick auf Franz von Mayronis, Poncius und Mastrius
GABRIEL Nuc HELMANS, Late-Scholastic and Humanist Theories of the Proposition (Oxford, New York: (Munster: Aschendorff, 2002).
North Holland Publishing Company, 1980). I prefer Meinong's term 'objective' to the medieval " JORGE J. E. GRACIA, "Suarez's Conception of Metaphysics: A Step in the Direction of
term 'complexe significabile' for two reasons. First, Meinong's term highlights the correlation Mentalism?", American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 65 (1991): 287-309; ROBERT W. SCHMIDT,
between objectives and objects, and second, it is neutral with respect to the question whether "The translation of terms like Ens rationis", The Modern Schoolman 41 (1963): 73-75; STANISLAV
objectives are mental constructs or not. The term 'complexe significabile' or 'complexly signifiable' SOUSED1K, "P0MySlna jsoucna (entia rationis) v aristotelske tradici 17. stoletr, Filozofick); easo-
may seem to imply that it is something mental. pis 52 (2004): 533-544; JOHN P. DOYLE, "Suarez on Beings of Reason and Truth (First part)";
'' Cf. LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (New York: Cosimo, Inc., 1922, BERNARDO CANTEFIS , "Suarez on Beings of Reason: What Kind of Being (entia) are Beings of
repr. 2009), 29, prop. 1.1. Reason, and What Kind of Being (esse) Do they Have?", American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly
" The term is mine but it is inspired by Caramuel's 'Ttaqovta', see IOANNES CARAMUEL, 77 (2003): 171-187.

28 • CATEGORIES AND BEYOND CATEGORIES AND BEYOND • 29


Daniel D. Novotny Daniel D. Novotny
SCHOLASTIC DEBATES ABOUT BEINGS OF REASON SCHOLASTIC DEBATES ABOUT BEINGS OF REASON

Now the surprising fact: Suarez and most other Baroque scholastics considered contain explicit contradictions." Although many later Baroque authors reduced
merely possible beings to be real and hence they were not classified as beings of impossible beings to self-contradictory objects, this is not a trivial move. For
reason. This fact is often overlooked. Nicholas Rescher, for instance, writes:" Suarez and other scholastics there seem to be objects that cannot exist in actual
With regard to non-existents, the medieval mainstream thus sought to effect a com- reality but still, they are not self-contradictory (for instance, the universal human
promise. On the one hand, their lack of reality, of actual existence, deprived non- being or blindness).
entities of a self-sustaining ontological footing and made them into mind-artifacts, So far for the explanation of the above given schematic classification of scho-
entia rationis. On the other hand, their footing in the mind of God endowed them with lastic super-categories. Before we go on to the second part of my paper, let me
a certain objectivity and quasi-reality that precluded them from being mere flatus make three clarificatory notes about this classification.
vocis fictions, mere verbalisms that represent creatures of human fancy'6
Hence, using non-scholastic terminology, beings of reason might be best Note 1: Classifications and natural classes
described as intentional or mind-dependent impossible objects. This mind-de- The classification of super-categories (if I am right) provides an overview of
pendency of beings of reason, however, is more precisely characterised by the various strange ontological items one can encounter in scholastic texts. But why
scholastics as merely objective mind-dependency. This sort of mind-dependency did the scholastics themselves not formulate such a classification? I can only
is contrasted by them with subjective mind-dependency, which is a real relation speculate. First of all, many elements of the classification I give were controversial
of dependency of the mental accidents, such as sensations, emotions, thoughts, among them. Not all scholastics agreed, for instance, that extrinsic beings or
and volitions, on the mind. There are two sorts of objective mind-dependency. non-beings were in some sense real and hence a special "genus" of items. Hence,
(1) Suppose there is a person p who apprehends a real being x. In this case x is since there was no agreement on these issues, they did not feel the need to provide
not merely objectively in the intellect of p, for x also has its own real being in an explicit classification of the items they talked about. Secondly, the hesitancy
itself. (2) Suppose there is a person p who apprehends x and x has no other being to formulate such a classification might be due to their assumption that "good"
besides the being it has in the intellect of p. In this case x is merely objectively in concepts must delimit natural classes (members of which are at least analogically
the intellect of p. It is only in this last sense of 'mind-dependency' that the word related). And since there is no natural class, for instance, of existing and non-
`ens rationis' is appropriately used.'7 existing beings, the two should not be lumped under one label. Today, however,
Impossible beings (beings of reason, necessarily mind-dependent beings) we feel free to draw such classifications, provided that we keep in mind that some
divide into negative beings (entia negativa) and positive beings (entia positiva). The of the "fields" of our classification may represent just arbitrarily united classes.
former are further divided into negations (negationes) and privations (privationes), The fact that x and y belong to a class C does not imply that x and y share some
and the latter are identified with relations of reason (relationes rationis). Impossible common (intrinsic) feature. Later Baroque scholastics seem to go in this direction
beings should be understood as objects for which it is impossible to exist in in that they started to acknowledge "extrinsic thinkability", i.e. the possibility of
actual reality and hence they need to be distinguished from what I call "self- subsuming x and y under a common concept, without implying that they share
contradictory beings", which are objects, such as square-circles or goat-stags, that anything intrinsically in common - except for the extrinsic feature of belonging
to the same class. The notion of extrinsic thinkability gave rise to the idea that
RESCHER, Imagining Irreality, 362. there are supertranscendental terms, such as 'thinkable' or 'something', which
16 ANTONIO MILLAN-PUELLES (see The Theory of the Pure Object, trans. and ed. by Jorge
are applicable both to real and non-real objects.'9
Garcia-Gomez, Heidelberg: Universitatsverlag C. Winter, 1996) does not make the same his-
torical mistake, although for systematic reasons he agrees with Rescher's view that mere
possibles are non-real. Even some contemporary Thomists argue that for systematic reasons
the traditional thesis about the reality of the possibles is inconsistent with other tenets of
scholastic ontology, see, e.g., NORRIS W. CLARKE: "What is Really Real?", in Progress in Philosophy.
Philosophical Studies in Honor of Rev. Doctor Charles A. Hart, ed. by J. A. McWilliams (Milwaukee, Milian-Puelles calls these "paradoxical quiddities" or "openly paradoxical beings"
1955). (MILLAN-PUELLES, The Theory of the Pure Object).
17 Note that in contemporary usage the words objective/subjective are used in exactly the 19 It is also noteworthy that Baroque scholastic authors in Catholic lands, with some

reversed sense. The term 'objective' means real and mind-independent, whereas 'subjective' exceptions, did not use graphs in their philosophical and theological works. One of the reasons
means apparent and mind-dependent. How this reversal of meaning happened is still an might be that they wished to avoid associations with the infamous ex-Catholic Petrus Ramus
untold story of the history of philosophy. (1515-1572) and his movement (Ramism) that was using them extensively.

30 • CATEGORIES AND BEYOND I CATEGORIES AND BEYOND • 31


Daniel D. Novotny
SCHOLASTIC DEBATES ABOUT BEINGS OF REASON
I Daniel D. Novotny
SCHOLASTIC DEBATES ABOUT BEINGS OF REASON

Note 2: Existence and being 3. THE ROLES OF BEINGS OF REASON IN SCHOLASTIC DEBATES
One of the presuppositions of any classification of non-existing items is the Having classified non-existing items discussed by the scholastics into super-
distinction between the meanings of 'there is' and 'exists'. Many analytical philo- categories and identified the position of beings of reason within the classification,
sophers, notably those in the Frege-Quine tradition, like to treat the expres- let us take a look now at the roles they were supposed to play in scholastic ontology.
sion 'there is' with metaphysical seriousness. In their view 'there is' and 'exists' Why did the scholastic authors feel the need to talk about them? They used them
are synonymous - they both have "ontological import". The scholastics would to address various philosophical puzzles, most conspicuously the problem of non-
disagree."' According to them one needs to make a distinction between 'there being/intentionality. Hence we start with the latter issue (3.1) and then discuss
is' (datur, "is given"), which is meant to be as neutral and broad as possible, and several other problems related to beings of reason (3.2).
narrower predicates, such as 'exists', which express a first-order non-trivial
feature of individuals." 3.1 The problem of non-being/intentionality
Thought and language direct our attention to various sorts of objects that
Note 3: Categories and transcendentals either clearly do not exist or whose existence is questionable. This fact is the main
There is another group of terms one may encounter in scholastic texts, the source of the problem (or the family of problems) addressed first by Parmenides
so-called transcendentals (one, true, good, etc.) that apply to every being. Beside and discussed by philosophers ever since. From one point of view, the problem
these there are also other terms, such as actual/potential, real/nonreal, perhaps concerns non-being including questions such as, What is the status of non-being?
whole/part, one/many, etc. that apply to beings from various categories but Is it in some sense real and mind-independent? What belongs to its domain: past,
not to everything. Although one could perhaps subsume these trans-categorial future, potential, merely possible, impossible, fictitious, and so on? From another
terms (and whatever they express) under item, it is more convenient and closer point of view, the problem concerns intentionality and intentional being. The
to scholastic usage of the words to keep the super-categories and the super- pertinent questions in this case include: What is an intentional object, if any?
transcendentals separately, not to include them in the same classification. To Does a category of intentional objects help to explain our thinking of and about
put the difference between the two in a rather simplistic way one could say that non-being?
the aim of the categories and super-categories is a general division of what there Several basic strategies have been used to deal with the problem of non-being.
is and is not, whereas the aim of the transcendentals and super-transcendentals First, however, we need to note that the problem of non-being divides into the
is a general characterisation of what there is and is not." problem of non-existing objects and the problem of negative facts (also referred
to as negative truths). The question whether there are negative facts is more
2° Cf. Klima's distinction between soft and hard ontological commitments in pre-Ock- fundamental than the question whether there are non-existing objects. Indeed,
hamist philosophy. For Aquinas beings of reason are "objects of thought and signification that negative facts are sometimes taken as evidence that there are non-existing
are required by a certain kind of semantics but undesirable as objects simpliciter in ontology". objects but not vice versa. And it is possible to hold that there are negative facts
GYULA KLIMA "The Changing Role of Entia rationis in Mediaeval Semantics and Ontology: and no non-existing objects, but not vice versa."
A Comparative Study with a Reconstruction", Synthese 96 (1993): 25.
2 ' In the latter part of the twentieth century some analytical philosophers came to defend
the distinction as well. For instance, TERENCE PARSONS (Nonexistent Objects, New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1980) constructed a logic distinguishing the existence predicate (`El') from in die Ontologie (Darmstadt: WBG, 2004), 22-29. For an introduction into transcendentals in
the quantifier ('3'). Another way of dealing with the distinction was developed by GRAHAM Baroque scholasticism, see, e.g., JORGE J. E. GRACIA and DANIEL D. NOVOTNt "Fundamentals
PRIEST (Towards Non-Being: The Logic and Metaphysics of Intentionality, Oxford University Press, in Suarez's Metaphysics: Transcendenta Is and Categories", in Interpreting Sucirez: A Collection of
2005), who treats 'there is' and 'exists' synonymously but interprets them as ontologically Critical Essays, ed. Daniel Schwartz (Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press, 2012), 19-38.
neutral. Still, to acknowledge that existence is a property of individuals as such does not " At this point one might wonder whether there is a distinction between negative objects
imply that it is a non-trivial property. For instance, PETER VAN INWAGEN in Metaphysics, Third and non-existent objects. This question is posed by MEINONG, Ober Annahmen (Leipzig: J. A.
Edition (Philadelphia, PA: Westview, 2009, 277-292) argues that existence is a trivial property Barth, 1902), 7ff. Examples of putative negative objects that Meinong gives include nothing,
of individuals (amounting to self-identity). For more on existence "as one of the deep topics immortal, infinite, A without B, not-A. In the end Meinong rejects negative objects as distinct
in philosophy, if not the deepest", see WILLIAM F. VALLICELLA, A Paradigm Theory of Existence from non-existing objects which I agree with because I do not see any difference between
(Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2002). the two: non-redness of an apple is just non-existent redness of it, immortality of the soul is
" The traditional idea of transcendentals is one that does not seem to have emerged so just the non-existent capacity-to-die of the soul, etc. For Meinong's arguments, see FINDLAY,
far as a topic in analytical metaphysics. With some exceptions: cf. UWE MEIXNER, Einfiihrung Meinong's theory of objects and values, 81-89.

32 • CATEGORIES AND BEYOND CATEGORIES AND BEYOND • 33


Daniel D. Novotny Daniel D. Novotny,
SCHOLASTIC DEBATES ABOUT BEINGS OF REASON SCHOLASTIC DEBATES ABOUT BEINGS OF REASON

With respect to non-being one may adopt views of various sorts. The most [T]he pure object stands beyond being and non-being; both alike are external to
radical one holds that there are no negative facts, and consequently no non- it. Whether an object is or not, makes no difference to what the object is. The pure
existing objects. A less radical view acknowledges negative facts, but rejects object is said to be aulgerseiend or to have Aufgersein: it lies 'outside'. What the object
is ... consists in a number of determinations of so-being.... [S]uch determinations are
non-existing objects. The least radical position acknowledges both. These views genuinely possessed by an object whether it exists or not ... [T]his does not mean that
might be further subdivided according to the account they give of negative facts any objects are exempt from being or non-being; the law of excluded middle lays it
and of non-existing objects. down that every object necessarily stands in a fact of being or a fact of non-being....
With respect to non-existing objects, drawing on Meinong and Findlay, I would [but] being and non-being have nothing to do with the object as object."
distinguish three accounts: Intentional, Quasi-Being, and Ausser-Being Views.24
This view and its distinctive thesis was dubbed by Ernst Mally 'The Principle
The Intentional View explains non-existing objects in terms of mind-made, of the Independence of So-being from Being'. It has been the main source of the
intentional being. Quine ascribes a version of the Intentional View to (the fictional
attraction to Meinong in contemporary philosophy."
philosopher) McX and dismisses it as a deception "by the crudest and most
The scholastics usually accepted the Intentional View: non-existent objects
flagrant counterfeit". Quine asks, what can be more dissimilar and unlike than, are immanent to (=staying within) our mental/intentional activity and they
for instance, Pegasus, an alleged non-existing object, and the Pegasus-idea, the
"exist" only as long as somebody actually thinks about them." For the most part,
intentional object? If it comes to real objects, Quine contends, such as Parthenon
however, this was the view that was simply assumed and not argued for because
and the Parthenon-idea, we would never be deceived, but when it comes to
no alternative was seriously entertained by them."
Pegasus, somehow, confusion sets in." Meinong also rejects the Intentional View
for "with regard to an innumerable multitude of non-existent objects it may be
3.2 Other problems
the case that no one thinks of them or needs to think of them".26 Although beings of reason have to do primarily with non-being and intentional
The Quasi-Being View explains non-existing objects in terms of some peculiar
being, the scholastics used the theory of beings of reason for various other
sort of being that pertains to everything. Every object, whether existing or not,
purposes, two of which stand out. First, to account for higher-order predicates
whether non-existing contingently or necessarily, has it. As early Russell puts it
("second intentions").34 Second, to account for self-contradictory objects, such as
"being is a general attribute of everything, and to mention anything is to show
square-circles or chimeras." (The standard view was that the latter are reducible
that it is".27 Meinong suggests calling this sort of being 'quasi-being' for it has no
to negative beings of reason.)
contrary and thus it is a very unusual sort of being. Quine ascribes a version of the
Quasi-Being View to Wyman and dismisses it for it offends his "aesthetic ... taste " FINDLAY, Meinong's theory of objects and values, 49.
for desert landscapes", and is to him "a breeding ground of disorderly elements" " RICHARD RouTLEY (Exploring Meinong's Jungle and Beyond, Canberra: Australian National
in the case of unactualised possibles and even of contradictions in the case of University, 1980), for instance, takes up Meinong's ideas to develop so-called noneism that
unactualisable impossibles.28 In the end, Meinong also rejects the Quasi-Being posits (1) there are non-existent objects, (2) these objects have no existence, being, or what-
View, although for some time he was, as he says, tempted by it.29 have-you. The main principle of noneism, which amounts to Mally's Independence Principle,
The Ausser-Being View is Meinong's own child, although in a different context is the so-called Characterisation Principle: An object has (only those?) properties that it is
characterised as having.
an analogy to it might be seen in Aquinas's notion of natura absoluta (something
" We can think of it this way: Let us take, for instance, the proposition "The apple is not
which is neither one nor many, neither individual nor universal). Findlay sum-
red". This proposition is true in virtue of the real/mind-independent fact that the apple is
marises the Ausser-Being View as follows: not red. This fact involves a non-existent object, namely the apple's non-redness, which is,
however, not real but purely intentional: the apple's non-existent redness "exists" only as long
as somebody actually thinks about it.
24 See FINDLAY, Meinong's theory of objects and values, 42-58.
" There were exceptions: some scholastics seem to come close to a version of Quasi-Being
25 WILLARD VAN ORMAN QUINE, "On what there is", Review of Metaphysics 2, no. 5 (1948); View according to which beings of reason have a peculiar type of (essential) being, which is
reprinted in From a Logical Point of View: Nine Logico-Philosophical Essays, (Cambridge, MA; London, in some sense mind-independent.
England: Harvard University Press, 1980), 2.
26 FINDLAY, Meinong's theory of objects and values, 45. " For an excellent study of second intentions in late scholasticism, see LARRY HICKMAN,
Modern Theories of Higher Level Predicates: Second Intentions in the Neuzeit (Munchen: Phi losophia
27 RUSSELL, The Principles of Mathematics, 449. Verlag, 1980).
" QUINE, "On what there is", 2-5. " Jennifer Ashworth distinguishes between literary and logical definition of 'chimera' in
29 FINDLAY, Meinong's theory of objects and values, 48. the late fifteenth and early sixteenth century scholastics: "References fin the literary definition]

34 • CATEGORIES AND BEYOND CATEGORIES AND BEYOND • 35


Daniel D. Novotny Daniel D. Novotny
SCHOLASTIC DEBATES ABOUT BEINGS OF REASON SCHOLASTIC DEBATES ABOUT BEINGS OF REASON

Several kinds of questions were addressed with respect to beings of reason in (9) Ontologically Suspicious Items I: abstract entities (universals, sets, num-
standard philosophical works in seventeenth-century scholasticism. The issues bers, etc.)
can be divided into three areas: (10) Ontologically Suspicious Items II: extrinsic properties, logical, semantic, social
Nature: What is a being of reason? Do beings of reason exist? Are they to be relations, etc.
identified with extrinsic denominations? Why do we construct beings of (11) Methodology: fictionalism, ontological commitments, paraphrases
reason? In what sense do beings of reason exist? Is there a sense of 'being' The scholastics have much to say about all of these matters, with the exception
which is common to real beings and beings of reason? Is there a science that of (7), which is astonishing, given the extent and detail of Baroque scholastic
studies beings of reason? works." In the treatises on beings of reason the scholastics were concerned
Causes: What mental powers are involved in conceiving beings of reason? Intellect, ma inly with (1), (3), (5), (10), and (11), although some authors discussed (8). The
will, sense, imagination? remaining issues, i.e. (2), (4), (6), and (9) were extensively treated elsewhere, but
Division: What is the division of beings of reason? (negation, privation, relation, ...) not under the heading 'beings of reason'.37
What is a negation? What is a privation? What is a relation of reason?
4. CONCLUSION
various "additional" issues, which perhaps could be subsumed under the
heading 'nature', were also treated. For instance: motivation (Why do we need Thus I have finished a brief description of the ontological framework pre-
beings of reason?) and methodology (Does the study of beings of reason belong supposed by the scholastic debates about beings of reason. First I provided a list of
to the domain of logic or metaphysics?). Scholastic authors of the seventeenth super-categories of various non-existing items one might encounter in scholastics
century did not care much for semantic problems (the meaning of being-of-reason works of the Baroque era. Then I identified the roles that the most important of
terms, the truth-value of sentences with such terms, etc.). these items, namely beings of reason, were supposed to play in scholastic onto-
For a comparison, contemporary philosophers seem to discuss the following logy. In this paper I have not tried to say whether the scholastic approach to
issues related to beings of reason: perennial issues of non-being, intentionality and other related issues makes sense
for us today or not. My aim was more modest: to take the first step toward making
(1) Non-being (in thought): non-existent objects, negative facts scholastic discussions and concerns somewhat more intelligible to contemporary
(2) Non-being (in perception): vacuum, holes analytical metaphysicians. Whether contemporary analytical metaphysics can be
(3) Intentionality: mental objects, objects of thoughts, semantic content inspired or challenged by these scholastic debates or whether these debates have
(4) Modality I: possible (i.e. contingently non-existing) objects merely historical value remains at this point an open question."
(5) Modality II: impossible (i.e. necessarily non-existing) objects
(6) Temporality: past or future (i.e. now non-existing) objects
(7) Fictitiousness: texts, objects of literary fictions
(8) Fallibility: objects of errors, mis-representations, illusions
36 An explanation for this strange neglect might be the assumption that literary fiction
describes possible entities and possible worlds and hence there are no special questions about
were made to such diverse sources as Ovid, Virgil, Lucian, and the Koran, and the consensus of opinion
literary fiction that would not be dealt with in the discussion of possibility.
was that a chimera is a monster formed out of parts of other animals having, on one account, the head
3' Some of these topics in scholasticism have already been treated in secondary literature;
of a lion, the torso of a girl, and the tail of a dragon. This was said to be impossible. ... [For] chimera was
thought of not as a mere hybrid, but as something which had the essences of all the creatures which for possibility, see note 13; for vacuum, see EDWARD GRANT, Much Ado About Nothing: Theories
entered into it, and it was for that reason that it was thought to be an impossible object. ... One of the of space and vacuum from the Middle Ages to the Scientific Revolution (Cambridge: Cambridge
important features of this definition of "chimera" is ... [that it] is not thought of as a mere aggregate, University Press, 1981); for temporality, see JACOB ScHmwTZ, "Juan Caramuel on the Year
a random assemblage of different parts. If the term "chimera" is to refer, it must refer to some one thing. 2000: Time and Possible Worlds in Early-Modern Scholasticism", in The Medieval Concept of Time.
... The logician's definition of "chimera", which stems from Buridan, was considerably less picturesque ... Studies on the Scholastic Debate and Its Reception in Early Modern Philosophy, ed. Pasquale Porro
for it said merely that a chimera is a being composed of parts which cannot be put together, or which it is (Leiden, New York, Köln: Brill 2001), 399-434.
impossible to put together" -JENNIFER E. ASHWORTH, "Chimeras and Imaginary Objects: A Study 38 The work on this paper received support from the Czech Science Foundation (grant

in the Post-Medieval Theory of Signification", Vivarium 15 (1977): 63. no.13401/n/P°20).

36 • CATEGORIES AND BEYOND CATEGORIES AND BEYOND • 37


Daniel D. Novotny Daniel D. Novotny
SCHOLASTIC DEBATES ABOUT BEINGS OF REASON SCHOLASTIC DEBATES ABOUT BEINGS OF REASON
BIBLIOGRAPHY KLIMA, GYULA. "The Changing Role of Entia rationis in Mediaeval Semantics and Ontology:
A Comparative Study with a Reconstruction". Synthese 96 (1993): 25-58.
ASHWORTH, JENNIFER E. "Chimeras and Imaginary Objects: A Study in the Post-Medieval
Theory of Signification". Vivarium 15, 1977. MEINONG, ALEXIUS. Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandstheorie und Psychologie. Leipzig: J. A.
CANTEIZIS, BERNARDO: "Suarez on Beings of Reason: What Kind of Being (entia) are Beings Boba er tr hA,n1n9a0h4m.
of Reason, and What Kind of Being (esse) Do they Have?" American Catholic Philosophical en. Leipzig: J. A. Barth, 1902.
Quarterly 77 (2003): 171-187. MEIXNER, UWE. Einfiihrung in die Ontologie. Darmstadt: WBG, 2004.
CARAMUEL Y LosRowIcz, IoANNEs. Leptotatos. Vigevani: Typis Episcopalibus, apud Camil- MILLAN-PUELLES, ANTONIO. The Theory of the Pure Object. Translated and edited by Jorge
lum Conradam, 1681. Garcfa-G6mez. Heidelberg: Universitatsverlag C. Winter, 1996.
CHISHOLM, RODERICK M., ed. Realism and the Background of Phenomenology. New York: The Novomt DANIEL D. "The Historical Non-Significance of Suarez's Theory of Beings
Free Press, 1960. of Reason: A Lesson From Hurtado". In Metaphysics of Francisco Sucirez (1548-1617):
CLARKE, NORRIS W.: "What is Really Real?" In Progress in Philosophy. Philosophical Studies Disputationes metaphysicae in their systematic and historical context, edited by Daniel
in Honor of Rev. Doctor Charles A. Hart, edited by J. A. McWilliams, 61-90. Milwaukee: Heider, Lukag Novak, David Svoboda (forthcoming).
Bruce, 1955. -"In Defense of Baroque Scholasticism". Studia Neoaristotelica 6, no. 2 (2009): 209-233.
Comm, JEFFREY. "The Possibility of Created Entities in Seventeenth-Century Scotism", - "Ens rationis in Caramuel's Leptotatos (1681)". In Juan Caramuel Lobkowitz, the Last Scho-
The Philosophical Quarterly 43 (1993): 447-459. lastic Polymath, edited by Petr Dvorik and Jacob Schmutz, 71-84. Praha: Filosofia, 2008.
DELFINO, ROBERT A., ed. What are We to Understand Gracia to Mean: Realist Challenges to -"Prolegomena to a Study of Beings of Reason in Post-Suarezian Scholasticism, 1600-
Metaphysical Neutralism. Amsterdam, New York: Rodopi, 2006. 1650". Studia Neoaristotelica 3, no. 2 (2006): 117-141.
DOYLE, JOHN P. "Suarez on Beings of Reason and Truth (First part)". Vivarium 25 (1987): NUCHELMANS, GABRIEL. Late-Scholastic and Humanist Theories of the Proposition. Oxford, New
47-75. York: North Holland Publishing Company, 1980.
- "Suarez on Beings of Reason and Truth (Second part)". Vivarium 26 (1988): 51-72. PARSONS, TERENCE. Nonexistent Objects. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1980.
FESER, EDWARD. "Existential Inertia". In Metaphysics: Aristotelian, Scholastic, Analytic, edited PRIEST, GRAHAM. Towards Non-Being: The Logic and Metaphysics of Intentionality. Oxford:
by L. Novak, D. D. Novotny, P. Sousedfk, D. Svoboda, 143-168. Ontos Verlag, 2012. Oxford University Press, 2005.
FINDLAY, JOHN N. Meinong's theory of objects and values. Second edition. Aldershot: Ashgate PRIOR, ARTHUR N. Objects of Thought. Edited by Peter Geach and Anthony Kenny. Oxford:
Publishing (Gregg Revivals) 1995. Clarendon Press, 1971.
GRACIA, JORGE J. E. Metaphysics and Its Task: The Search for the Categorial Foundation of Know- QUINE, WILLARD VAN ORMAN. "On what there is". Review of Metaphysics 2, no. 5 (1948): 21-38.
ledge. Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 1999. Reprinted in From a Logical Point of View: Nine Logico-Philosophical Essays. Cambridge, MA;
- "Suarez's Conception of Metaphysics: A Step in the Direction of Mentalism?" American London, England: Harvard University Press, 1980), 1-19.
Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 65, no. 3 (1991): 287-309. REICHER, MARIA. "Nonexistent Objects", in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall
GRACIA, JORGE J. E. and NOVOTNt DANIEL D. "Fundamentals in Suarez's Metaphysics: 2010 Edition), edited by Edward N. Zalta, (http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fal12010/
Transcendentals and Categories". In Interpreting Sucirez: A Collection of Critical Essays, entries/nonexistent-objects!).
edited by Daniel Schwartz, 19-38. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press, 2012. RESCHER, NICHOLAS. Imagining Irreality: A Study of Unreal Possibilities. Chicago, IL: Open
GRANT, EDWARD. Much Ado About Nothing: Theories of space and vacuum from the Middle Ages Court, 2003.
to the Scientific Revolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981. ROUTLEY, RICHARD. Exploring Meinong's Jungle and Beyond. Canberra: Australian National
HICKMAN, LARRY: Modern Theories of Higher Level Predicates: Second Intentions in the Neuzeit. University, 1980.
Munchen: Philosophia Verlag, 1980. RUSSELL, BERTRAND. The Principles of Mathematics, (http://fair-use.org/bertrand-russell/
HOFFMANN, TOBIAS. Creatura intellecta: Die Ideen und Possibilien bei Duns Scotus mit Ausblick the-principles-of-mathematics!). First edition Cambridge: At the University Press,
auf Franz von Mayronis, Poncius und Mastrius. Munster: Aschendorff, 2002. 1903. Second edition 1938.
INWAGEN, PETER VAN. Metaphysics. Third edition. Philadelphia, PA: Westview, 2009. SCHMIDT, ROBERT W. "The translation of terms like Ens rationis". The Modern Schoolman 41
(1963): 73-75.
- "What is Ontological Category?" In Metaphysics: Aristotelian, Scholastic, Analytic, edited
by L. Novak, D. D. Novotny, P. Sousedfk, D. Svoboda, 11-24. Ontos Verlag, 2012.

38 • CATEGORIES AND BEYOND CATEGORIES AND BEYOND • 39


Daniel D. Novotny
SCHOLASTIC DEBATES ABOUT BEINGS OF REASON

SCHMUTZ, JACOB. "Juan Caramuel on the Year 2000: Time and Possible Worlds in Early-
Modern Scholasticism". In The Medieval Concept of Time. Studies on the Scholastic Debate
and Its Reception in Early Modern Philosophy, edited by Pasquale Porro, 399-434. Leiden,
New York, Köln: Brill, 2001.
STRAWSON, PETER F. Individuals. An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics. New York: Routledge,
1959, repr. 2005.
SECTION II
SOUSEDIK, STANISLAV. "Pomyslna jsoucna (entia rationis) v aristotelske tradici 17. stoletf".
FilozofickY easopis 52 (2004): 533-544.
— "Der Streit urn den wahren Sinn der Scotischen Possibilienlehre", in John Duns Scotus:
Metaphysics and Ethics, ed. Ludger Honnefelder, Rega Wood, Mechtild Dreyer (Leiden:
Brill, 1996), 191-204.
METAPHYSICAL
VALLICELLA, WILLIAM F. A Paradigm Theory of Existence. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Pub-
lishers, 2002.
WITTGENSTEIN, LUDWIG. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (New York: Cosimo, Inc., 1922, repr.
STRUCTURE
2009).

40 • CATEGORIES AND BEYOND


WHAT IS CONSTITUENT ONTOLOGY?
Michael J. Loux

ABSTRACT
This article focuses on one style of ontological explanation - what the author calls the
constituent strategy. Very roughly, a proponent of the constituent approach attempts to
explain the character of a familiar particular by way of underived sources of character that
function as something like parts, components or constituents of the particular. Then, the
author examines some contemporary versions of the constituent approach and considers
objections frequently raised against them. The claim is that these accounts are unable to
accommodate certain facts: (1) that familiar particulars persist through change; (2) that
familiar particulars have some of their properties essentially and others merely contingently;
(3) that familiar particulars are concrete individuals; and (4) that numerically diverse parti-
culars can have all and only the same properties.

A Icentral focus of metaphysical concern is what Russell calls the character


PART
of familiar particulars,' that is, the fact that individual material objects, plants,
animals, and human beings possess properties, fall under kinds, and enter into
relations. This talk of possessing properties, falling under kinds, and entering
into relations is supposed to be prephilosophical discourse; it is supposed to be
the sort of talk we engage in outside the philosophy seminar room. But there is
a metaphysical project to which this sort of talk is supposed to give rise - that of
providing a theoretical account of the individual facts making up what Russell
calls the character of ordinary objects.
The project is, of course, a very old one. By the time of Plato and Aristotle,
the general structure of the project is pretty well worked out. Its underlying
assumption is that familiar particulars have this or that form of character deri-
vatively. As Aristotle puts it, an ordinary object has a given form of character
kae allo (in virtue of something else).2 So ordinary objects derive their character
from other things, and the objects from which they derive their character are or
include things that have their own distinctive forms of character nonderivatively

1 B. RUSSELL, Problems of philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1912), 92.


2 ARISTOTLE, Metaphysics VII, 6, 1031 b 13.

METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 43
Michael J. Loux Michael J. Loux
WHAT IS CONSTITUENT ONTOLOGY? WHAT IS CONSTITUENT ONTOLOGY?

or, as Aristotle again puts it, kath' hauto (in their own right).' The metaphysical and nonrelational hookups is likely to arouse suspicions. At least, it arouses
project is just that of telling the proper story about how this character derivation Wolterstorff's suspicions; and while himself a defender of the nonimmanentist
works itself out. strategy, he insists that any regress to which the strategy might give rise is
Aristotle tells us that there two different and opposed stories we can tell , no nvicious.6Second, it is not as though what Wolterstorff calls the constituent
here." According to the first, the underived sources of character are things that strategy does without relations in its account of familiar particulars. On that
exist, as he puts it, "apart from" or "in separation from" the sensible particulars strategy, the various items that count as constituents of a familiar particular
whose character they underwrite; and a sensible particular has a given form of are related (or, if one prefers, tied) to one another in ways that help explain the
character by entering into some sort of tie or connexion to the appropriate bearer structure and nature of the whole they make up; and obviously defenders of
of underived character. On the second story, the privileged bearers of character that strategy must concede that a whole or composite stands in something like
are immanent in familiar sensible particulars, immanent in the sense of being mereological relations to the underived sources of character that count as its
something like parts, components, or ingredients of familiar particulars, and a constituents. Neither sort of relation or tie is the kind of relation or tie at work
familiar particular has the various forms of character it does because it has the in what Wolterstorff calls his relational strategy, but they are relations or ties
appropriate underived bearers of character as parts, components, or ingredients. nonetheless.
So there are supposed to be two different strategies for explaining the facts It is easy to give examples of the two strategies to which Aristotle and Wolters-
making up the phenomenon of character. Those strategies differ in their accounts torff call our attention. Although the later Russell (the Russell of Inquiry into Mea-
of familiar particulars. Defenders of Aristotle's second strategy attribute to ning and Truth and Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits) endorses an immanentist
ordinary objects something like a mereological structure, a mereological struc- or constituent approach, the Russell of The Problems of Philosophy seems inclined to
ture over and above their commonsense mereological structure. As they see it, a relational account of character. He tells us that where familiar particulars agree
ordinary objects are composites or wholes made up of parts or components other in character, "they all participate in a common nature or essence", and he insists
than their familiar parts or components, and the claim is that it is in virtue of that the nature in question "cannot itself exist in the world of sense". Indeed,
what we can call its metaphysical parts that a familiar object has the character it exists "nowhere and nowhen".' Russell, of course, is not alone. Among recent
it does. Defenders of Aristotle's first strategy, by contrast, deny that familiar ontologists, P. F. Strawson, Roderick Chisholm, and Alvin Plantinga all seem to
particulars have this sort of metaphysical structure. They restrict the parts of favour a relational account;$ and, as I have already mentioned, Wolterstorff himself
ordinary object to their commonsense parts. Nonetheless, they insist that ordi- does as well. On the other hand, it is difficult to understand the metaphysical
nary objects stand in a variety of significant nonmereological connexions or ties discussions of Locke, Berkeley, or Hume without construing them as exercises in
to things that have character kath hauto or nonderivatively; and they tell us that constituent ontology; and more recent proponents of the constituent approach
in virtue of doing so those objects have whatever character they do. include, besides the later Russell, Gustav Bergmann, David Armstrong, Hector
In discussing the metaphysical project of character explanation, Nicholas Castarieda, and, most recently, Laurie Pau1.9 But, of course, these examples of
Wolterstorff identifies the two strategies we meet in Aristotle. He dubs them the relational and constituents ontologists aren't the ones that initially come to mind.
`relational' and `constituent' approaches.' I will stick with Wolterstorff's labels,
but a couple of cautionary notes are in order. First, proponents of Aristotle's first
strategy are, by and large, uncomfortable talking of relations here. As they see 6 N. WOLTERSTORFF, On Universals (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1973), 101-104.
it, talk of the relations into which an object enters is talk about its character; 7 RUSSELL, Problems of Philosophy, 92.
but, then, they worry that the appeal to relations in the account of character will s See P. F. STRAwsoN, Individuals (London: Methuen, 1959), chapters 5 and 6; R. CHISHOLM,
be regressive. Accordingly, they speak of the nonrelational ties, connexions, or "Properties and States of Affairs Intentionally Considered", in Person and Object (La Salle, IL:
nexus between ordinary objects and the transcendent sources of character. The Open Court, 1976); and A. PLANTINGA, The Nature of Necessity (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1974).
suggestion that there is a metaphysically significant contrast between relational
9 See B. RUSSELL, An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth (London: Allen and Unwin, 1940);
B. RUSSELL, Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits (London: Allen and Unwin, 1948); G. BERGMANN,
3 Ibid. Realism. A critique of Brentano and Meinong (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1967);
See Met. III, 1,996 a 15; ibid. 3,998 a 21-23; ibid. XII, 6,1080 a 37-13'. H. CAsTA&EDA, "Thinking and the Structure of the World", Philosophia 4 (1974): 3-40; D. ARM-
See N. WOLTERSTORFF, "Bergmann's Constituent Ontology", Nous 4 (1970): 109-134; and STRONG, A World of States of Affairs (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997); L. PAUL,
"Divine Simplicity", Philosophical Perspectives 5 (1991): 531-552. "Logical Parts", Nous 36 (2002): 578-596; and L. PAUL, "Logical Parts", Nous 36 (2002): 578-596.

44 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 45


Michael J. Loux Michael j. Loux
WHAT IS CONSTITUENT ONTOLOGY? WHAT IS CONSTITUENT ONTOLOGY?

The paradigms of the two approaches are found in the work of their two great u niversals. Nor is it the case that accepting the existence of uninstantiated
sources - Plato and Aristotle. u niversals makes one a relationist. It is rather supposing that for a thing to
While appropriate, the mention, in this context, of Aristotle and Plato can instantiate a universal is for it to enter into some sui generis nonmerelogical tie
lead us to misunderstand the opposition between our two strategies. We tend to or connexion (participation, say, or exemplification) to an underived source of
associate the labels 'Platonism' and 'Aristotelianism' with two opposed views in character. One can concede the existence of uninstantiated universals without
the debate over universals, the contrast being that between metaphysical theories entertaining that supposition. But not only can a constituent ontologist reject
that reject and those that endorse what is called the Principle of Instantiation, the Principle of Instantiation; it is also possible for a relational metaphysician to
the claim that necessarily every universal is instantiated. But our opposition is endorse the Principle of Instantiation and deny the possibility of uninstantiated
not restricted to views about universals. One can deny the existence of universals universals. Consider a metaphysician who couples a relational account where
altogether and still count as a relational or constituent ontologist. Certainly, universals are transcendent sources of character with a general doctrine of self-
contemporary trope theorists want to construe themselves as constituent theo- predication for universals. We are often told that the middle Plato, at least, was a
rists, but they typically deny that there are such things as universals; at least, philosopher who held precisely that combination of views.
they typically deny that among the ontologically fundamental items there are In any case, it is a mistake to identify our opposition with an opposition over
such things as universals. If we understand tropes in the standard way, then we the nature of universals. Another mistake here is to suppose that the two strate-
will agree that trope theorists endorse the reality of properties or attributes; but gies Aristotle and Wolterstorff point to are mutually exclusive and collectively
note: one can endorse either of our two ontological strategies while denying that exhaustive. In fact, they are neither. There are treatments of character that are
there are properties or attributes, even when understood trope-theoretically as neither relational nor constituent. I am thinking of the views of what I have
particulars. Aristotle gives examples here. He characterises Plato's successor, elsewhere called austere nominalists. They reject the assumption underlying our
Speusippus, as a relationist who construes numbers as separated substances target project, insisting that we take the facts expressed by our prephilosophical
responsible for the character of familiar sensibles,i° and Aristotle takes the character ascriptions to be metaphysically primitive. The Quine of "On What
theories of his materialist predecessors, both those who endorse a gunk ontology There Is" is one obvious example." Furthermore, a genuinely substantive account
and those who believe in physical simples, as exercises in constituent ontology." of those same facts can instantiate both of our strategies. Consider a theory
Presumably, we are to understand these early materialists as construing the that construes tropes as constituents of familiar objects responsible for their
relevant material constituents as prior to any properties they might induce. character, but takes those tropes themselves to be instantiations of what we
But even when we restrict ourselves to philosophers who accept the existence might call trope types, where those types are, as Aristotle puts it, "separate from"
of universals, it is not as though the Principle of Instantiation is what divides familiar sensible particulars. But notice: such a theory manages to exemplify both
relational and constituent theorists. It is true that constituent ontologists re- strategies only because it is a two step theory. At each stage of explanation, the
gularly deny the possibility of uninstantiated universals. Think of Aristotle, ontologist must choose between the two explanatory strategies.
Bergmann, and Armstrong." It is likewise true that relational ontologists typically
insist on the existence of uninstantiated or possibly uninstantiated universals. PART II
But neither pairing is mandatory. If one thinks that constituent ontologists must So there is a genuine opposition here. The philosopher seeking a substantive
accept the Principle of Instantiation, then one is likely confusing the existence explanation of the character of familiar particulars seems forced to choose be-
and instantiation of a universal. Constituent ontologists are committed to holding tween some version of the immanentist or constituent strategy and some version
that for a first order universal to be instantiated is for it to be a constituent in of the relational strategy. When he points to the two strategies, Wolterstorff tells
some familiar particular; but that commitment does not preclude uninstantiated us that the latter is currently the dominant approach. He is, I think, correct in
this. Over the whole history of metaphysics, the constituent approach is arguably
I° See Met. XIII, 6, loso b 15-16, for what is almost certainly a reference to Speusippus. the more popular; but in recent years, the relational approach has occupied
" See, for example, Met. III, 3, 998 a 30-31, where Empedocles functions as a stand-in for centre stage. Its influence is felt in virtually every compartment of contemporary
all the materialists. philosophy, where talk of exemplifying properties contingently or necessarily,
12 See ARISTOTLE, Categoriae, 11, 14 b 7-14; G. Bergmann, Realism. A critique of Brentano and

Meinong (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1967), 43 and 88; D. Armstrong, Universals " See W. V. 0. Quine, "On What There Is", in From a Logical Point of View (Cambridge, MA:
(Boulder, CO: Westview, 1989) 75-82. Harvard University Press, 1954), 10ff.

46 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 47


Michael 3. Loux Michael 3. Loux
WHAT IS CONSTITUENT ONTOLOGY? WHAT IS CONSTITUENT ONTOLOGY?

possibly or actually provides the accepted framework for the formulation of just gives the wrong result by holding that at least one person is an abstract entity, or
about any philosophical issue. it forces us to hold an independently controversial claim - atheism. And atheism
As we have seen, there are constituent theorists actively at work on the isn't the only controversial claim associated with the revised criterion. The
current metaphysical scene, but not only are they in the minority; their efforts account works for finite mental substances only if they really do have temporal
are typically viewed with puzzlement or suspicion, if not downright distain. One
P'arts. but presentists, philosophers who insist that only what exists now or in
seldom meets with an explicit statement of the grounds of the prejudice here, the present is real, will deny that there are such things as temporal parts. So the
But if probed, contemporary metaphysicians will suggest that the constituent account works only if some form of four dimensionalism is true.
approach is, at bottom, incoherent. Its central claim, they will say, embodies But there is a further difficulty, one that arises for both ways of drawing the
something like a category mistake. The claim is that the items that have character distinction. Properties, we may assume, are abstract entities. Unfortunately,
nonderivatively are components or parts of familiar particulars. Those items, many constituent ontologists will insist that the properties constitutive of a
however, are abstract entities. Familiar particulars, by contract, are concrete familiar particular have a spatial location: they are where the particular is."
objects; and, we are told, no concrete object can be composed of or made out of And these same constituent ontologists will typically go on and say that a single
abstract entities. property can wholly and completely occupy more than one spatial location at a
More than anything else, I think, this line of thinking explains why contem- time - indeed, as many locations as the familiar particulars it goes to constitute.
porary metaphysicians have been so ready to endorse the relational approach. Of course, the relationists who want to accuse constituent theorists of a category
To endorse the opposing immanentist or constituent approach, the thinking mistake will deny that properties have spatial location; but if the issue of spatial
goes, is to make the category mistake just set out: it is to endorse the incoherent location is one that, in general, divides constituent and relational ontologists, the
idea that abstract entities can be parts, ingredients, or components of concrete assumption that properties have no spatial location can hardly play a role in an
particulars. But as influential as this line of argument may be, it is not altogether argument designed to adjudicate between the two approaches.
convincing. It is just not clear that the distinction between abstract and concrete In any case, the contrast between abstract and concrete is problematic. Some
will bear the weight the line of argument assigns it. For the objection at work philosophers respond to the problems by resorting to lists or inventories. As
here to succeed, we need some principled way of drawing the distinction so that Peter van Inwagen suggests, the motivating theme is much like that Strawson
the things philosophers want to call abstract turn out abstract and those they and Grice expressed with regard to the analytic/synthetic distinction." Even if
want to call concrete turn out concrete. We need, that is, criteria that give the we cannot identify criteria for drawing it, the distinction gets vindicated by the
right results; but, further, those criteria must be such that by reflecting on them fact that we tend to agree about which items fall under the respective headings.
we can see why a concrete entity cannot have abstract entities as components Properties, propositions, and relations are all abstract; whereas, persons, plants,
or constituents. animals, and atoms are all concrete. I have sympathy with this move. Nonetheless,
But what are the criteria here? We might suppose that an entity is concrete iff I cannot resist pointing out that there is less agreement about the classification
it has a spatial location and that it is abstract iff it is not concrete." One difficulty than sanguine philosophers might have us believe. Trope theorists, for example,
is that this way of drawing the distinction either gives the wrong results or disagree about whether tropes are abstract or concrete; but most trope theorists
presupposes controversial philosophical claims that are independent of the issues want to deny that, in the final analysis, there is anything besides tropes." Likewise,
at hand. Traditional dualists tell us that minds are nonspatial beings; but, then, metaphysicians disagree about the status of events: some think they are concrete;
our criteria force us to hold either that individual minds are abstract entities or others, abstract.'9 Still, there are ontologists who insist that events exhaust the
that materialism is true. One might try to repair things by saying that an object
is concrete iff it either has a spatial location or is made up of temporal parts and 16 See, for example, A. DONAGON, "Universals and Metaphysical Realism", Monist 47 (1963):
abstract iff not concrete.15 Minds have temporal parts, don't they? But do they all? 211-247.
Orthodox theists will certainly deny this; but, then, the revised criterion either '7 See P. VAN INWAGEN, "A Theory of Properties", Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 1 (2005):
107-138.
14 See P. SIMONS, "Particulars in Particular Clothing", Philosophy and Phenomenological 18 D. C. WILLIAMS, "Elements of Being". Part One. Review of Metaphysics 7 (1953): 3-18; and P.
Research 54 (1994): 553-575 for this sort of criterion. SIMONS, "Particulars in Particular Clothing", Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (1994):
's See E. J. LOWE, "The Metaphysics of Abstract Objects", Journal of Philosophy 92 (1995): 553-575 take opposing sides on the status of tropes.
509-524; and chapter 10 of E. J. LOWE, The Possibility of Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University 19 See, for example, D. DAVIDSON, "Events as Particulars". Nous 4 (1970): 25-31; and R. M.

Press, 1998) for an account along these lines. CHISHOLM, Person and Object (La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1976) for this opposition.

48 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 49


Michael J. Loux Michael J. Loux
WHAT IS CONSTITUENT ONTOLOGY? WHAT IS CONSTITUENT ONTOLOGY?

inventory of what there is. Again, we are all familiar with the claim that states of it is. Hence, the idea at work in talk about the substantial or metaphysical parts of
affairs or facts are the ultimate realities; nonetheless, there is disagreement about a thing is that each such part involves or induces a form of being that is less than
whether such things are abstract or concrete.2° Let us assume, however, that such or a component of the overall form of being displayed by the whole thing. While
disagreements can be resolved and that there is a genuine distinction here, one Aristotle would concede that the commonsense parts of a thing are one and all
given by the traditional inventories. A difficulty remains. Once we acquiesce in material, he would insist that its substantial or metaphysical parts can include
the Strawson/Grice strategy, we are left without any account of just what makes an item that is not properly material at all.
a thing abstract or concrete; and in the absence of that sort of account, we lack Unlike Aristotle (who is a presentist), David Lewis uses a temporal parts
the resources for showing why it should be problematic to think that concrete framework as the backdrop for his characterisation of what I am calling the con-
entities are composed of or constituted by abstract entities. stituent approach and speaks of nonspatiotemporal parts; and while he thinks
At this point, the objector will likely retrench and make one kind of concrete that the spatiotemporal parts of a material object are every bit as material as
entity - material particulars - the focus of the objection. The parts of a material the object itself, he takes it to be a defining feature of the constituent approach
particular, the revised objection will go, are one and all material; but only at the that nonmaterial things like properties can count as the nonspatiotemporal
risk of a category mistake can we suppose that things like properties are material or metaphysical parts of a material object." Lewis, of course, does not himself
objects. Constituent ontologists, however, want to claim that the properties of a favour a constituent approach to character. Indeed, he denies that we need to
material particular count as its components or constituents, so we once again get give a substantive account (whether of the relational or constituent variety) of
the conclusion that constituent ontologists are guilty of some sort of category the phenomenon; but he recognises that constituent ontology does not, from the
mistake. very start of the project, harbor a category mistake.
As we have noted, it is not quite accurate to say that all constituent onto- And the idea that there is a contrast between the commonsense material
logists want to make the properties of a material particular its constituents;" parts of a thing and its metaphysical parts or constituents is shared by every
nonetheless, many do. But none of those who do will find the revised objection practitioner of the constituent strategy;" nor is it any accident that this is so.
any better than the original. The difficulty, they will claim, is that the revised Recall that the proponent of this strategy makes the constituents of a thing
objection mistakenly identifies the constituents of a material particular with its responsible for its overall character; but its commonsense mereological structure
commonsense parts. Constituent ontologists, however, are anxious to distinguish is just one aspect of that character. And not just the arrangement of a thing's
the two; and while conceding that the latter must be material, they will deny that commonsense parts is due to a thing's constituents. Constituent ontologists will
this is true of the former. As early as Aristotle, we meet with this distinction. He say that the intrinsic nature of the parts themselves is due to the constituents of
distinguishes between "the parts that measure a thing according to quantity" the whole, or they will say that those parts have constituents of their own that
and "the parts of which its substance is composed" (1034 b 33-35). The former are account for their nature. In either case, we have the result that, in the story the
the commonsense parts of a thing; the latter, its constituents or what we might constituent ontologist tells, constituents or metaphysical parts turn out to be
call its metaphysical parts. Now, parts of both sorts are less than, fall short of the prior to commonsense material parts.
wholes they compose; but Aristotle is telling us that the two sorts of parts fall We may concede that the distinction serves to answer the revised objection,
short in different ways. Each of the commonsense parts of a thing is spatially less but if we are to take the constituent approach seriously, we will want to know
than the thing: the primary place each occupies is a proper part of the primary more about constitution. As a start, we can identify its formal properties. If we
place occupied by the whole. Accordingly, the part can be used to provide a spatial restrict ourselves to what might be called the proper constituents of a thing, we
measure of the whole, so that we can speak of the whole as being so many feet long, can agree that the relation of constituent to whole is irreflexive, asymmetrical,
so many cubits wide, or so many hands high. Aristotle's talk about the substance and transitive. Functionally, it is a relation of composition, so it might be tempting
of a thing, by contrast, is talk about its being what it is, its being the kind of thing to identify it with other more familiar composition relations, but the temptation
should be resisted. It is not the relation tying the members of a set to the set:
2° CHISHOLM, Person and Object, and ARMSTRONG, A World of States of Affairs, hold opposed
views on the status of states of affairs. 22 See D. LEWIS, "New Work for a Theory of Universals", Australasian Journal of Philosophy
21 Another exception is Aristotle who denies that the accidents predicated of a substance 61 (1983): 343-377.
are among its constituents. They are constituents of the associated coincidentals, but they are 23 See, for example, L. A. PAUL, "Logical Parts", Nous 36 (2002): 578-596, where we find talk

not predicated of them. See M. J. Loux, Metaphysics, 3rd ed. (London: Routledge, 2006). of "qualitative" or "logical parts".

50 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 51


y--
Michael J. Loux Michael J. Loux
WHAT IS CONSTITUENT ONTOLOGY? WHAT IS CONSTITUENT ONTOLOGY?

familiar particulars aren't sets. Nor is it the relation tying properties to the I have dubbed Constituent Essentialism, is a framework principle for this style
conjunctive property whose conjuncts they are. Many constituent ontologists of metaphysical explanation. On this view, all there is to a familiar particular
refuse to restrict the constituents of familiar particulars to their properties; is its constituents; but, then, it should be impossible for numerically diverse
and even those that do accept the restriction will typically deny that familiar objects to be made up of identical constituents identically arranged. I will call
particulars are themselves properties, whether molecular or atomic. More plau- this claim the Principle of Constituent Identity and will formulate it as the claim
sible is the suggestion that the constituent/whole relation is a case of the relation that necessarily, for any objects, x and y, if x and y have all and only the same
of composition at work in what is properly called mereology, the logic of parts constituents in precisely the same order, x and y are identical.
and wholes; but even this suggestion has its problems. The relation in question
(called summing or fusion) is just too generous; and in this respect it agrees PART III
with both set-theoretical composition and the composition involved in property Towards characterising the concept of constitution at work in immanentist
conjunction. In all three cases, if it is possible for a given plurality of objects to theories, I have said that the relation of constituent to whole is a compositional
compose the relevant whole, then the plurality does compose it. Not so in the case relation that is irreflexive, asymmetrical, and transitive. Furthermore, I have said
of the objects constituting a familiar particular. It is possible for those objects to that while the constituents of a thing only contingently constitute it, the thing
exist without constituting the particular: they play their constitutional role only has its constituents in the appropriate order both necessarily and uniquely. This
contingently, and constituent ontologists routinely take this fact to underlie the characterisation is very general. The concept of constitution I have delineated
contingency of the constituted particular. is one ontologists of quite different stripes will be comfortable making the
Now, some constituent ontologists will claim that we can supplement the centrepiece of their disparate theoretical frameworks. But that is how it should be.
concept of fusion with restrictions which ensure that the only composites are Theories as different as Berkeley's phenomenalism and Aristotle's hylomorphism
those we meet in the case of actually existing ordinary objects.24 But whether count as constituent ontologies. In our own day, the constituent strategy has
they endorse a thoroughly mereological interpretation of the constituent/whole taken three main forms. There are (1) theories that construe a familiar parti-
relation, constituent ontologists will agree that if a plurality of objects, a ... n, cular as a bundle of compresent, but repeatable properties, the properties we
constitutes a particular, x, then it does so only contingently. Nonetheless, they will prephilosophically associate with the particular;" (2) theories that posit, in addi-
also agree that the resulting whole, x, has necessarily the property of having all tion to the repeatable properties making up a thing, a categorically different kind
and only a ... n as constituents. Call this claim Constituent Essentialism. It needs of constituent, a constituent that serves as subject, possessor, or bearer of those
to be distinguished from what is called Mereological Essentialism, the claim that properties;" and (3) theories that restrict the constituents of a familiar object to
a thing has each of its commonsense parts necessarily. It is plausible to think nonrepeatable properties or what have become known as tropes!'
that constituent ontologists are free to disagree about the latter claim; but what Now, I have argued that attempts by relationists to show the enterprise of
I have called Constituent Essentialism is something like a framework principle constituent ontology incoherent fail. But even those who would deny that the
for constituent ontologists. They hold that familiar particulars are nothing but enterprise is fatally flawed from the start find problems in the various theories
composites of their constituents; but, then, it is difficult to understand how that make up the recent history of constituent ontology. To set the stage for
a constituent ontologist could hold that it is possible for a particular to have the discussions that will follow, let me close by reminding you of some of these
constituents other than those it does. Given a different group of constituents, problems.
we would have the existence of a different composite and, therefore, a different Persistence through change has been thought to present problems for con-
familiar particular. stituent theorists. Where a thing changes, the argument goes, there is a variation
So it is a structural fact about constituent ontologies, first, that the items in the properties associated with the thing. Constituent theorists, however,
constituting a given particular do so only contingently and, second, that the construe the properties associated with a thing as its constituents; but, then
particular has the constituents it does necessarily. Constituents ontologists will
typically add that it has those constituents uniquely; or, at least, they will add 25 See CASTAREDA, "Thinking and the Structure of the World"; L. A. PAUL, "The Context of
that it has uniquely the property of having just those constituents in just the Essence", Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82 (2004): 170-184; and PAUL, "Logical Parts".
order in which they are found there; and they will claim that this, like the claim 26 See BERGMANN, Realism, and ARMSTRONG, A World of States of Affairs.
27 See WILLLIAMS, "Elements of Being", SIMONS, "Particulars in Particular Clothing", and

24 See again PAUL, "Logical parts". K. CAMPBELL, Abstract Particulars (Oxford: Blackwell, 1990).

52 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 53


Michael.). Loux Michael 3. Loux
WHAT IS CONSTITUENT ONTOLOGY? WHAT IS CONSTITUENT ONTOLOGY?

they are committed to denying that the composite emerging from a change is perhaps, we should say that the two colour tropes were there beforehand. The
numerically identical with the composite that entered the change. Persistence, difficulty, of course, is that I could go on and cut each of the two new sections of
however, requires identity, so we get the conclusion that constituent ontologists the original desk top in two. So were there really four rather than just two colour
cannot accommodate our prephilosophical belief that ordinary objects persist tropes there before the first division? It is not clear that any answer we might
through change. give here is satisfactory.
What underlies the problem here is, of course, constituent ontologists' corn. Defenders of theories of the first sort I mentioned tell us that familiar parti-
mitment to what I have called Constituent Essentialism. It is because they take culars are bundles of repeatable properties. On their theory, the "materials" out
a composite to have its constituents necessarily that they must deny identity of which a familiar particular is composed are one and all properties, but what
through change. But not only does that doctrine preclude identity through they compose is an individual that has those properties, what we might call a
change; it seems as well to make it impossible for constituent ontologists to do propertied individual. But they owe us an explanation of just how we are supposed
justice to the distinction between the properties essential to a familiar particular to get the propertied individual from "materials" that are restricted to properties.
and those that are merely contingent. All the properties of a thing appear to turn How is it that we get a cp-er, a thing that is cp, from the property cp-ness? The
out essential on the constituent approach. response, doubtless, will be that individuals arise out of the agglomeration of
Two comments here. First, although closely related, the two problems are properties. We begin, so to speak, with one property, add another, add still an-
different. The first bears on variation and persistence through time; the second, other, and what ultimately emerges is an individual having all those properties.
on variation and persistence through what we might call the modal dimension. But why should we suppose that agglomeration yields the multi-propertied indi-
The second problem concerns the various ways a particular could have been other- vidual? Why not suppose instead that what results from the agglomeration is, say,
wise; for the formulation of that problem it is not required that the particular just the conjunctive property whose conjuncts are all the various properties that
realise the relevant possibilities by actually undergoing a change. In any case, have been agglomerated?"
the actual practice of constituent ontologists implies that the two problems are And there is a more familiar problem that dogs traditional bundle theorists.
different. Where they deal with both, constituent ontologists deal with them in They tell us that a thing's character hinges on its repeatable properties. Those
different ways.28 properties are its constituents. They further tell us that different familiar parti-
Second, while conceding that our second problem may arise for both bundle culars can share a given form of character and that where this happens a single
theorists and trope theorists, one might deny that the same holds for substratum property is a constituent of the numerically different particulars. As constituent
theorists. After all, do they not tell us that the ultimate bearers of properties are ontologists, however, they are committed to what I have called the Principle of
particulars that are bare or thin? Yes, but our second problem bears not on the Constituent Identity. But, then, they are committed to some strong version of the
relationship between a substratum and the properties compresent with it, but Identity of Indiscernibles, the principle that necessarily if an object, a, and an
on the relationship between the whole familiar particular and the properties object, b, have all and only the same properties, a is numerically identical with
that constitute it. For the substratum theorist, no less than the bundle or trope b. The difficulty, of course, is that there appear to be counterexamples to the
theorist, that relationship is governed by Constituent Essentialism. appropriate version of that principle."
So our first two problems would seem to create difficulties for all three forms Substratum theorists appeal to the apparent counterexamples in defence
of constituent ontology. But each of the different patterns faces problems of its of their own version of the constituent approach." They argue that what the
own. Trope theorists, for example, face problems about the individuation of items possibility of diverse, but qualitatively indiscernible objects shows is that each
from their favoured category." Although they speak freely and almost casually ordinary object has a constituent that is idiosyncratic to a single composite
about this or that trope, the fact is that it is not altogether clear just what a trope and that functions as the literal possessor of the properties that enter into
is. Take the colour of the desk top on which I am now writing. Presumably, it is the composite. But, they insist that only constituents that have no properties
a single discrete trope. But what happens when I cut the desk top in two? Do I essentially are suited to play the diversifying role here. So we get the doctrine of
thereby bring two colour tropes into existence? If I do, then what was beforehand
not a trope now is one; but how can what was not a trope become one? Well, 30 To my knowledge, the only bundle theorist who explicitly responds to this problem is
CASTAREDA, "Thinking and the Structure of the World".
28 See, for example, PAUL, "Logical Parts", and "The context of Essence". '' See, for example, M. BLACK, "The Identity of Indiscernibles", Mind 61 (1952): 153-164.
29 These problems are clearly presented in CAMPBELL, Abstract Particulars, chapter 6. 32 See, for example, E. B. ALLAIRE, "Bare Particulars", Philosophical Studies 14 (1963): 1-8.

54 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 55


Michael J. Loux Michael J. Loux
WHAT IS CONSTITUENT ONTOLOGY? WHAT IS CONSTITUENT ONTOLOGY?

the bare or thin particular; and most philosophers think that there are serious pLANTINGA, ALVIN. The Nature of Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1974.
problems attaching to that doctrine." VINE, WILLARD VAN ORMAN. From a Logical Point of View. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univer-
So even if there is no single a priori objection that shows the constituent pro- sity Press, 1954.
ject to be doomed from the start, there are problems aplenty for constituent RUSSELL, BERTRAND. An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth. London: Allen and Unwin, 1940.
ontologists. If they are to convince us of the viability of their project, they need Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits. London: Allen and Unwin, 1948.
to address there problems. Let's see how they fare.
problems of Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1912.
SIDER, THEODORE. "Bare Particulars". Philosophical Perspectives 20 (2006): 387-397.
SIMONS, PETER. "Particulars in Particular Clothing". Philosophy and Phenomenological Re-
BIBLIOGRAPHY search 54 (1994): 553-575.
ALLAIRE, EDWIN B. "Bare Particulars". Philosophical Studies 14 (1963): 1-8. STRAWSON, PETER FREDERICK. Individuals. London: Methuen, 1959.

ARISTOTLE. The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation. Edited by J. Barnes, WILLIAMS, DONALD C. "Elements of Being". Part One. Review of Metaphysics 7 (1953): 3-18.
2 vols. Bollingen Series. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1984. WOLTERSTORFF, NICHOLAS. "Bergmann's Constituent Ontology". Nous 4 (1970): 109-134.
ARMSTRONG, DAVID. A World of States of Affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, -On Universals. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1973.
1997. -"Divine Simplicity". Philosophical Perspectives 5 (1991): 531-552.
- Universals. Boulder, CO: Westview, 1989.
BERGMANN, GUSTAV. Realism. A critique of Brentano and Meinong. Madison: University of
Wisconsin Press, 1967.
BLACK, MAx. "The Identity of Indiscernibles". Mind 61 (1952): 153-164.
CAMPBELL, KEITH. Abstract Particulars. Oxford: Blackwell, 1990.
CASTAREDA, HECTOR-NERI. "Thinking and the Structure of the World". Philosophia 4 (1974):
3-40.
CHISHOLM, RODERICK M. Person and Object. La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1976.
- On Metaphysics. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1989.
DAVIDSON, DONALD. "Events as Particulars". Nous 4 (1970): 25-31.
DONAGON, ALAN. "Universals and Metaphysical Realism". Monist 47 (1963): 211-247.
INWAGEN, PETER VAN. "A Theory of Properties". Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 1 (2005):
107-138.
LEWIS, DAVID. "New Work for a Theory of Universals". Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61
(1983): 343-377.
Loux, MICHAEL J. Metaphysics. Third edition. London: Routledge, 2006.
- "Aristotle's Constituent Ontology". Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 2 (2007): 207-250.
LOWE, E. J. "The Metaphysics of Abstract Objects".Journal of Philosophy 92 (1995): 509-524.
- The Possibility of Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998.
PAUL, LAURIE A. "Logical Parts". Nous 36 (2002): 578-596.
- "The Context of Essence". Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82 (2004): 170-184.

" I discuss this issue in my Metaphysics, chapter 3. For a reply, see T. SIDER, "Bare Parti-
culars", Philosophical Perspectives 20 (2006): 387-397.

56 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 57


1
ELEMENTAL TRANSFORMATION IN ARISTOTLE:
THREE DILEMMAS FOR THE TRADITIONAL ACCOUNT
Anne Siebels Peterson

ABSTRACT
According to the traditionally held interpretation of many texts in Aristotle, that which
plays the role of substratum for elemental transformation is a matter with no essence of its
own, prime matter. I argue that the traditional account of elemental transformation, in its
appeal to prime matter, conflicts with three doctrines which many commentators would take
Aristotle himself to endorse. First, it conflicts with that variety of essentialism according
to which everything that exists has an essence which marks it out as what it is. Second, it
conflicts with actualism. And third, it conflicts with the view that Aristotle's four elements
are to be understood in accordance with that version of the constituent ontological strategy
according to which one constituent of a whole serves as subject and the other as predicate.
I argue that these three conflicts are such that satisfactory resolutions of them would involve
controversial metaphysical commitments not usually associated with the traditional account.
My aim is not to undermine the traditional account, but rather to show that it should not
be regarded as a general framework that can be shared by many widely variant accounts
of elemental transformation and of the place of prime matter in Aristotle's ontology. The
traditional account is far more theory-laden than it is often taken to be.

1. INTRODUCTION
According to the traditional account of elemental transformation in Aristotle,
prime matter is that substratum common to the four elements (fire, air, earth, and
water) and paired, in each case, with a different pair of the elemental contraries.
Furthermore, in any case of transformation between two elements, prime matter
serves as a pre-existent and persistent substratum. As C. J. F. Williams puts it:
It is not heat or cold - the abstract qualities - which change into each other, but
the single underlying nature which takes on now one, now the other, of the pair of
contraries. Again we have something which remains when one element changes into
another, i.e. prime matter.'
Thus, in the transformation of water into fire, the contraries that characterise
water (the cold and the wet) are replaced by the contraries that characterise

' C. J. F. WILLIAMS, Aristotle's De Generatione et Corruptione (New York: Oxford University


Press, 1982), 213.

METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 59
Anne Siebels Peterson Anne Siebels Peterson
ELEMENTAL TRANSFORMATION IN ARISTOTLE ELEMENTAL TRANSFORMATION IN ARISTOTLE

fire (the hot and the dry); but the same prime matter persists throughout as what prime matter is in virtue of itself.' Prime matter is essenceless.6 As David
the substratum of both the pre-existent and the generated element in turn. The Bostock writes, prime matter is for Aristotle "all things potentially, which is just
traditional account's insistence on a persistent substratum in any case of trans.. another way of saying that there is nothing which it has to be."7 H. M. Robinson
formation derives from its adherence to the claim that a persistent substratum describes prime matter as:
is necessary in order to free any case of coming to be from the Parmenidea n ... a bare 'stuff, lacking all positive determinations, which is the matter of the ele-
argument, given at Physics I, 8, 191 a 25-34,2 for the incoherence of coming to be? ments and which makes elemental change possible. This prime matter is nothing but
The argument I want to make is that the traditional account's notion of prime a potentiality which can exist only as actualised in some determinate matter - i.e.
matter as a persistent substratum for elemental transformation conflicts with in one of the elements - and which is what persists when one contrariety is replaced
the following three metaphysical doctrines also often associated with Aristotle: by another and the identity of an element changes.8
a certain variety of essentialism, actualism, and the view that the four elements
It is this thesis that the persistent substratum for elemental transformation
are to be understood according to a certain variety of the constituent ontological is, in virtue of itself, pure potentiality - that it is essenceless - that spells trouble
strategy. for the traditional account with respect to the three doctrines just mentioned.9
2. PRIME MATTER: A PROBLEMATIC DOCTRINE
Since the same aspect of the traditional account's notion of prime matter
is the source of its conflict with each of these doctrines, it will be important to
have a grasp on what this problematic aspect is. Prime matter is posited by the
5 On the other hand, we can say what it is to be for each of the four elements. To be fire
traditional account as the substratum for the elements, which are endowed with
is to be prime matter that is hot and dry; to be air is to be prime matter that is hot and wet;
the lowest-level essences there are (after all, if there were any lower-level essences, etc., employing the model of Metaphysics VIII, 2, 1043a1-28. Here I am sensitive to the fact
the things endowed with those essences would be the true elements). As Friedrich that the elements are probably not supposed to be full-fledged substances, as Metaphysics
Solmsen puts it, "There are no bodies or substances in Aristotle's physical system VII, 16, 1040b8-9 affirms: "for none of them is one, but they are like a heap before it is fused by heat
that could be regarded as more primitive and simple than the elements; if there and some one thing is made out of the bits." Still, we can say what something is, according to the
is anything at all of this description, it can only have 'potential' reality."4 Prime model of VIII, 2, even if that thing is not a full-fledged substance; Aristotle tells us this at
matter, on the traditional account, is, in virtue of itself, pure potentiality. We Metaphysics VIII, 2, 1043 a3-7. We do this by giving a form-matter predication: "E.g. if we had
to define a threshold, we should say 'wood or stone in such and such a position, and a house we should
can say what prime matter happens to be (hot and wet, cold and dry, etc.), as the
define as 'bricks and timbers in such and such a position'."
man happens to be musical; or we can say what prime matter is potentially (fire,
6 Indeed, it seems that Aristotle would not accept a view according to which the substratum
earth, air, or water), as flesh is potentially some kind of animal; but, since it is the for the elements is some kind of stuff that does have an essence, rather than essenceless prime
substratum for the things with the lowest-level essences there are, we cannot say matter - for then there would no longer be four elements, but only one. The four elements
would not be genuine elements, because they would not be at the lowest level of the hierarchy
All references to Aristotle's work are taken from the Complete Works of Aristotle, ed. of being - they would be composites made up of the one true element, their substratum. And
J. Barnes. (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1984). Aristotle finds strict monism of this variety utterly objectionable, though he also finds strict
' The point, according to proponents of the traditional account, is that if nothing of the pluralism objectionable - his view is supposed to balance somehow between these extremes
terminus a quo (that which pre-exists the case of coming-to-be), a, persists in the terminus ad (see On Generation and Corruption II, 7, 334a22-334b8); but the argument to this effect lies beyond
quem (the thing that comes to be), b, then we have a case of a's being annihilated and replaced by the scope of this paper. For Aristotle's arguments against strict monism, see, for example, On
b rather than a case of a's genuinely coming-to-be (or in the case of elemental transformation, Generation and Corruption 1, 1, 314b1-5 and II, 7, 334b2-8.
being transformed into) b. Just as, in the case of the man's coming to be musical, described ' DAVID BosTocx, Space, Time, Matter, and Form: Essays on Aristotle's Physics (Oxford University
at Physics 1, 7, 189b34-190a21, we must have the very man who was unmusical persisting as Press, 2006), 34.
8
the subject for the predication of the accident musicality, so in the case of substantial change H. M. RoB1NsoN, "Prime Matter in Aristotle", Phronesis 19 (1974): 168.
we must have something of the terminus a quo persisting as the substratum of the terminus ad 9 There have been many proposed emendations to the traditional account, which may or
quem. See, e.g., MICHAEL Loux, "Aristotle and Parmenides: An Interpretation of Physics A.8", may not harbor a satisfactory response to the difficulties I will lay out. I will consider a few
Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 8 (1992): 302-308. of these views throughout the paper, although to focus on them would take me too far afield
FRIEDRICH SOLMSEN, "Aristotle and Prime Matter: A Reply to Hugh R. King", Journal of from my main aim here, which is to explore some difficulties that arise for the traditional
the History of Ideas 19 (1958): 245. account as it stands.

60 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 61


Anne Siebels Peterson Anne Siebels Peterson
ELEMENTAL TRANSFORMATION IN ARISTOTLE ELEMENTAL TRANSFORMATION IN ARISTOTLE

3. PRIME MATTER AND ARISTOTELIAN ESSENTIALISM


numerical identity. Hence, to say that prime matter, which lacks any essence, is
Consider first that variety of essentialism according to which every genuine subject to claims about numerical identity is to say that there is a genuine being
being is such that, among those properties which belong to it necessarily, one with no essence at all. But that contradicts Aristotelian essentialism.
property marks it out as what it is, endowing it with an essence." In other words, I am sympathetic with the hope that a proponent of the traditional account
for any x, if x lacks an essence, then x is not a genuine being. I will refer to this view might circumvent this conflict with Aristotelian essentialism by focusing on the
as Aristotelian essentialism." At first glance, it might seem that there is no trouble fact that prime matter is not supposed to be a full-fledged being, and maintaining
here for the proponent of the traditional account of elemental transformation that it is therefore not subject to being parcelled out into numerically identical or
who wants to retain Aristotelian essentialism, as long as the proponent of that distinct parcels, and therefore is not subject to claims about numerical identity
account does not hold that prime matter is a genuine being. But it is not clear that or distinctness. But this move alone would not free the traditional account
the proponent of the traditional account can make this move. The trouble arises from difficulty. For the question would become, what is the criterion for the
from the traditional account's thesis that in any case of elemental transformation, persistence of prime matter throughout a case of elemental transformation, if
the prime matter of the pre-existent element must persist as the substratum of not that of numerical identity throughout the transformation? If we give up
the newly generated element. In order for the prime matter of the pre-existent air on the idea that prime matter is subject to claims about numerical identity, do
to count as genuinely persistent, it would seem, it must be identical to the prime we not thereby give up on the idea that it can genuinely persist? Alternatively,
matter of the generated fire in the strictest sense, that of numerical identity we might see the problem in terms of numerical distinctness, since giving up
(sameness in any more generic sense, i:e. in species or genus, would not guarantee numerical identity as a concept that applies to prime matter requires giving up
that anything has persisted)." However - and here is where the conflict with numerical distinctness as a concept that applies to it as well. And without the
Aristotelian essentialism arises - only genuine beings are subject to claims about idea that the prime matter of numerically distinct elements is itself numerically
distinct, it would come out trivially true that the prime matter involved in
'° See Categories 5, 2b31-35: "For if one is to say of the individual man what he is, it will be in place any given transformation persists; for that prime matter would not be distinct
to give the species or the genus (though more informative to give man than animal); but to give any of the from any other prime matter, and so it could only fail to persist if all the prime
other things would be out of place - for example, to say white or runs or anything like that." matter there is failed to persist. But surely the traditional account's thesis that
" This variety of essentialism contrasts, for example, with that defended in ALVIN PLAN- there must be a persistent substratum for any case of elemental transformation
TINGA, "Actual ism and Possible Worlds", in Essays in the Metaphysics of Modality, ed. M. Davidson is not supposed to be a triviality. So we have a dilemma: given the usual way
(New York: Oxford University Press, 2003), 111-114.
of understanding persistence, in terms of numerical identity, the traditional
I2 See FRANK LEWIS, "What's the Matter with Prime Matter?" in Oxford Studies in Ancient
account conflicts with Aristotelian essentialism. Perhaps a view could be devised
Philosophy 34, ed. Sedley (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008), 137: He argues that the
substrata of a pre-existent element and of a generated element count as the same persistent which provides a criterion for persistence of prime matter without appealing
matter because they share the property of "being prime matter". I find this view unsatisfactory, to numerical identity and of distinctness of prime matter without appealing to
because the persistence of a property does not guarantee the persistence of what has that numerical distinctness. Such a view would obviate this dilemma. Or perhaps we
property; we have no guarantee, on this view, that the same prime matter has persisted. The might, as Bostock argues, be able to do without a universally applicable criterion
prime matter of the pre-existent element might share the property of being prime matter for the persistence of matter." However, if I am right that the traditional account
with the prime matter of the generated element even if the prime matter of the pre-existent
element is destroyed in the course of the transformation. For an argument that the persistence
of generic physical properties of prime matter is sufficient to guarantee its persistence, see 13 See BOSTOCK, Space, Time, Matter, and Form: Essays in Aristotle's Physics, 44: According to
THEODORE SCALTSAS, Substances and Universals in Aristotle's Metaphysics (New York: Cornell Aristotle's theory, Bostock argues, "the appropriate criterion of identity for matter is left open. It is
University Press, 1994), 25: "If there is no kind of matter that survives radical transformation, how constrained...but not in a way which tells us how to apply it in all cases." It is constrained, he thinks, by
can one claim that it is matter that is surviving at all? The answer to this question is that, although the Aristotle's thesis that "The same matter is always conserved, which is to say: If we take any boundary
particular physical properties do not remain the same, there are generic physical properties that do." which is not crossed by matter over a certain period, then the matter inside that boundary will be the
On this view, because the pre-existent matter in a case of elemental transformation is (say) same matter all through the period. Thus, within such a boundary, new matter is never created, or old
hot, while the matter of the generated element is cold, we do not have the same kind of matter matter destroyed, either 'out of or into nothing' or by 'increasing or decreasing' the quantity of matter
(since these do not share the same specific properties); but we do have the same matter, because already there." But this constraint could not allow us to determine whether we have the same
both will always have the same generic properties of being thermal, hydral, spatial, and causal matter; to say that it could would be circular, as Bostock points out on the same page. For we
(26-27). But this view faces the same problem that undermines Lewis's view: the persistence could only establish that a certain boundary is not crossed by matter over a period of time if we
of a property does not guarantee the persistence of what has that property. already know that the matter inside the boundary is the same matter throughout the period.

62 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 63


Anne Siebels Peterson Anne Siebels Peterson
ELEMENTAL TRANSFORMATION IN ARISTOTLE ELEMENTAL TRANSFORMATION IN ARISTOTLE

must adhere to some such view in order to cohere with Aristotelian essentialism, affirmation that prime matter serves as the substratum of each of the elements
then it is far more theory-laden than many appeals to it would like to recognise, and persists throughout each case of elemental transformation, despite the
and because of this it will not be able to serve in the way in which it is often fact that it is, in itself, pure potentiality, the traditional account conflicts with
used: as a general framework employed by many widely variant accounts of the actualism.
specifics of elemental transformation with different understandings of precisely It is not clear to me that there is any way for the traditional account to avoid
where prime matter fits into Aristotle's ontology. Rather, to accept the traditional this conflict without significant modification. To summarise my argument: If the
account of elemental transformation will require one either to reject Aristotelian traditional account holds that prime matter, taken by itself, is pure potentiality,
essentialism or to accept an understanding of elemental transformation with and that prime matter, taken by itself, is the substratum for the elements, it
significant theoretical commitments - one that can explain the persistence of follows that pure potentiality is the substratum for the elements. But then given
prime matter without appealing to its numerical identity. actualism, it follows that the substratum for the elements does not exist. In order
to avoid this conflict, the proponent of the traditional account would have to
4. PRIME MATTER AND ACTUALISM argue that prime matter can be an existent substratum for an element despite the
A second doctrine with which the traditional account conflicts is actualism, fact that, taken by itself (that is, taken in abstraction from the element for which
the view that something must actually be to be at all.'" Although, according to it serves as substratum), it does not exist. It is not, on the face of it, clear how such
the traditional account, prime matter will always have some actuality - it will an argument would go - if the traditional account is committed to such a view,
always be either actually hot and dry, actually hot and wet, actually cold and dry; it would be at the very least a controversial addition to that account, rendering
or actually cold and wet - it can only have these properties accidentally. Taken it more theory-laden than it is often taken to be and not nearly as susceptible for
by itself, apart from any merely accidental properties, prime matter will lack use as a general framework as it is often taken to be. But without such an addition,
any actuality whatsoever - it will be pure potentiality. But then given actualism, the traditional account is at odds with actualism.
prime matter, taken by itself, does not exist. But prime matter, taken by itself, There is a second way in which we can show that the traditional account
is just what the traditional account appeals to as the substratum of each of the conflicts with actualism. According to the traditional account, prime matter
elements. If, taken by itself, it does not exist, then neither the pre-existent nor the derives its only actual features from the very predication of a pair of contraries
generated element in a case of elemental transformation even has a substratum. for which it is supposed to serve as subject: hot and dry, hot and wet, cold and dry,
And if these do not even have a substratum, then it follows, trivially, that they do or cold and wet. But then given actualism, which implies that existence comes
not share a substratum - that is, it follows, contrary to the traditional account, only with actuality, it follows that prime matter derives its very existence from
that there is no persistent substratum for elemental transformation.3 Thus, in its the predication for which it serves as subject. In other words, it follows that the
subject for this predication is an entity yielded by this predication; the subject of
With regard to the aim of this paper, the point to note here is this: If a view like Bostock's, the predication is ontologically dependent upon the predication, not vice versa.
according to which there is no determinate criterion of persistence for prime matter, is the There are, of course, predications for which this result would not be objection-
best that can be done as far as understanding prime matter's persistence goes, then this would able - specifically, predications which are such that if they were to cease to hold,
be a significant theoretical commitment; but given my argument, the traditional account their subjects would thereby cease to exist. Consider, for instance, the predication
could not maintain Aristotelian essentialism without making it. holding between a substance-kind and one of its members: if a certain horse
14 There is support for thinking that this too is a doctrine endorsed by Aristotle. For were to cease to have the corresponding substance-kind predicated of it, that
example, Aristotle writes at Metaphysics IX, 3, 1047b 1-2: "For of non-existent things some exist
potentially; but they do not exist, because they do not exist in fulfilment". See also Metaphysics XIV, 2,
horse would cease to exist. In this case it seems correct to say that the horse is
1089 a 28-29: "the false is said not to be and so is the potential". ontologically dependent upon the predication of its substance-kind for which it
'5 Aristotle himself brings up what looks to be precisely this difficulty in a passage which, serves as subject. In the case of prime matter, however, we have something that
like the two passages just given, takes actualism as a premise, in On Generation and Corruption is supposed to persist when the predication for which it serves as subject ceases
I, 3, 317b 23-29: "For if a substantial thing comes-to-be, it is clear that there will be (not actually, but to obtain and a new pair of contraries comes to be predicated of it. (Otherwise it
potentially) a substance, out of which its coming-to-be will proceed and into which the thing that is
passing-away will necessarily change. Then will any predicate belonging to the remaining categories a determinate being, is capable of separate existence; and in addition that coming-to-be proceeds out of
attach actually to this? In other words, will that which is only potentially a 'this' (which only potentially nothing pre-existing." Without actualism as a premise, Aristotle could not make this inference
is), while without qualification it is not a 'this' (i.e. is not), possess, e.g., any determinate size or quality that if the pre-existent entity possesses no actual characteristics but only potentialities, then
or position? For if it possesses none, but all of them potentially, the result is that a being, which is not coming to be proceeds ex nihilo.

64 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 65


Anne Siebels Peterson Anne Siebels Peterson
ELEMENTAL TRANSFORMATION IN ARISTOTLE ELEMENTAL TRANSFORMATION IN ARISTOTLE

could not serve as the persistent substratum for elemental transformation.) This direction as well, by holding that prime matter is contingently ontologically
implies that prime matter must, in every case, be able to exist independently of dependent on a certain pair of contraries, we lose this as a feature distinctive of
the predication for which it serves as subject. And this result conflicts with the u niversals in Aristotle.
previous result that prime matter is ontologically dependent upon the predication
of contraries for which it serves as subject. So although the counterintuitive 5. PRIME MATTER AND ARISTOTELIAN CONSTITUENT ONTOLOGY
result that the subject for a predication is ontologically dependent upon that Thirdly, the traditional account conflicts with that variety of the constituent
predication may not be a difficulty for the predication that holds between a sub- ntological strategy according to which a whole that comes to be and passes
o
stance-kind and one of its members, it does seem to be a difficulty for the pre- away is a predicative entity, of which one constituent serves as subject and the
dication that holds between prime matter and a pair of contraries, since prime other as predicate.P I will refer to this view as Aristotelian constituent ontology."
matter is supposed to be able to exist independently of those contraries. Since This conflict is perhaps the most troubling of the three; for the thesis that the
it is the premise of actualism that leads the proponent of the traditional ac- elements, which come to be and pass away by being transformed into each other,
count to this result, we have another manifestation of the conflict between the are predicative entities in which prime matter serves as the subject for the
traditional account and actualism. Given actualism, prime matter is ontologically predication of a pair of contraries is often included as a part of the traditional
dependent upon the contraries for which it serves as subject, but given certain c To t.
account.
modal properties ascribed to it by the traditional account (e.g., being able to The conflict between the traditional account and Aristotelian constituent
survive apart from those contraries), it does not seem that it can be ontologically arises with respect to the question of how a new pair of contraries
ontology
dependent upon them. could come to be predicated of some prime matter which is already the subject
One might respond that this conflict can be solved by adopting a weaker for a different pair of contraries, as in elemental transformation. We can bring
notion of ontological dependency as the sense in which prime matter depends this conflict into focus by considering the following reductio which a sceptic might
on those contraries for which it serves as subject - a notion of ontological depen- bring against the thesis that a form or accident F could come to be predicated of
dency as a contingent relation." Then we could hold that prime matter only a substratum s: Assume that F did genuinely come to be predicated of s. Then before
happens to be ontologically dependent on that pair of contraries for which it this predication came to hold, s must have been non-F. But then we are committed
serves as subject - it could become ontologically dependent on a different pair to the conclusion that the non-F served as the subject for the predication of F, and
of contraries, which is precisely what happens when elemental transformation this is absurd. For F could never come to be predicated of the non-F.19
occurs. With a notion of ontological dependency as a contingent relation, we could In certain cases - for example, the coming to be of the musical man as described
then say, without conflict, that prime matter is ontologically dependent upon in Physics I, 7 - Aristotle has a ready way out of this argument. Although the
whatever pair of contraries for which it serves as subject; nonetheless, it could subject for the coming to be of the musical man, s, was indeed unmusical before
exist independently of that pair of contraries (as long as it is the subject for some it came to be musical, s was also a man. And indeed, according to Aristotelian
other pair of contraries). Of course, if such a move were made, it would face the essentialism, "man" provides the most proper characterisation of what s is,
same difficulties we have already seen: it would render the traditional account since it is the substance-kind under which s falls.20 "Unmusical," since it picks
far more theory-laden and not susceptible for use as a general framework. And
there is another factor to consider. Adopting this weaker sense of ontological
dependency in this case would blur the line between subject and predicate in " This relationship between subject and predicate is supposed to be metaphysical, not
Aristotle in a way that may be undesirable. It is a special feature of Aristotelian merely linguistic.
universals, which occupy the predicate position, that they obey the principle of 18 in contrast, contemporary bundle theories, though versions of constituent ontology,
do not involve the claim that a predicative tie holds between the constituents of a whole.
instantiation - they cannot exist unless some particular thing instantiates them,
According to these theories (at least for the most part), the constituents of a whole are all of
but they could have been instantiated by different things than they in fact are the same categorical form, all universals, so they are united not by way of predication but in
instantiated by. Here we have ontological dependency understood as a contingent some other way.
relation running from predicate to subject. If we allow it to run in the other '9 As Aristotle tells us at Physics I, 7, 190b32-33: "it is impossible for the contraries to be acted
on by each other."
16 If we want to save the term "ontological dependency" for relations that hold necessarily, " Aristotle continues at Physics I, 7, 190b33-38: "But this difficulty also is solved by the fact that
we can substitute some other name for the relation I am about to describe. what underlies is different from the contraries; for it is itself not a contrary. The principles therefore are,

66 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 67


Anne Siebels Peterson Anne Siebels Peterson
ELEMENTAL TRANSFORMATION IN ARISTOTLE ELEMENTAL TRANSFORMATION IN ARISTOTLE

out a merely accidental property of s, is a characterisation subordinate to and from water, since both features of water (cold and wet) conflict with those of fire.
entirely trumped by "man." We are thus wholly justified in holding that the proper In none of the three possible scenarios for the coming to be of fire, then, can we
description of this predication's coming to hold refers not to musicality coming find a feature of the pre-existent prime matter which provides us with a reply to
to be predicated of "the unmusical" or "the unmusical man," but to musicality the sceptic's reductio by trumping any problematic features of that prime matter,
coming to be predicated of "the man."2' And this predication can coherently in the way that "man" trumps "musical" in the description of the subject for the
come to hold. So in describing this case of coming to be, we have justification for predication that yields the musical man." The best description of prime matter
excising the problematic reference to unmusicality altogether. (whether as the substratum of air, earth, or water) that we can give is one which
The analogous way out of the sceptic's reductio is unavailable, however, for includes a feature (cold, wet, or both) that disallows that prime matter from
the case of elemental transformation as understood by the traditional account. , eanndli kd reyt.
hot
okgsh
becoltmloin
Consider as an example the coming to be of fire, the element characterised by the the case of prime matter's coming to have the hot and dry
hot and dry. If fire comes to be from air (the element characterised by the hot and predicated of it must, in the end, be characterised as a case in which the non-F
wet), then the prime matter which serves as the subject for this transformation comes to be F, where F is one of the contraries and non-F the opposed contrary.
will start out as the substratum of air, and hence as hot and wet. Here the sceptic's For prime matter has no features which can trump those features that belong to it
reductio will conclude that hot and wet prime matter cannot coherently come to accidentally; the best characterisation of it must retain both accidental features."
serve as the subject for the predication of the hot and dry; for the wet and the dry But this is incoherent. And analogous reasoning will hold for the coming to be of
are opposed contraries, as are musical and unmusical. Hot and wet prime matter, any of the three elements other than fire. We thus have a conflict between the
on account of its being wet, could never come to have the dry predicated of it, traditional account and the thesis that prime matter can come to serve as the
just as the unmusical man, on account of his being unmusical, could never come subject for the predication of a pair of contraries that yields an element, since the
to have musicality predicated of him. best characterisation of prime matter will always involve at least one contrary
In this case, Aristotle cannot respond, as he could for the case of the musical opposed to one of the contraries it is supposed to take on in any given case of
man, that there is an unproblematic characterisation of the prime matter of coming to be. This conflict threatens the traditional account's ability to hold that
air that trumps the problematic characterisation of it as hot and wet. There is we can give an Aristotelian constituent analysis of the elements, according to
no justification for simply excising "wet" from the characterisation of the air's which they have a predicative structure.
prime matter and characterising this transformation as a case in which hot prime How could one who wishes to adhere to both the traditional account and to an
matter comes to have the hot and dry predicated of it, because "hot" is no more Aristotelian constituent analysis of the elements respond to this dilemma? One
privileged in the characterisation of the prime matter than "wet" is (while "man" could not, it seems, respond by arguing that the whole problematic does not apply
was a more privileged characterisation of the man than "unmusical"). Both "hot" in the case of elemental transformation; for Aristotle himself seems to consider
and "wet" are accidental features of the substratum for this change, and hence it at On Generation and Corruption I, 6, 322 b 15-22:
equally privileged in its characterisation. And of course, since prime matter is The hot thing, e.g., would not be cooled and the cold thing in turn be warmed; for
essenceless, there is no feature of it which trumps both "hot" and "wet" - we heat and cold do not change reciprocally into one another, but what changes (it is
cannot excise the reference to both. Another way of putting the problem is as clear) is the substratum. Hence, whenever there is action and passion between things,
follows: how can essenceless prime matter play the role assigned to the subject that which underlies them must be a single something.
in Physics I, 7, given that in any case it will always have some contrary predicated
Indeed, he seems to think that he has it resolved for the case of elemental
of it that opposes one it is supposed to take on?
transformation. But if this substratum is prime matter as traditionally under-
Analogous reasoning will hold for fire's coming to be from earth, since the
stood, it is far from clear how it is supposed to solve the dilemma at hand, given
prime matter of earth is cold and dry, the former of which conflicts with the
hotness of fire. And things are even simpler in the case of fire's coming to be 22 Indeed, things do not look hopeful; for what we need to find is a characterisation of

this prime matter that trumps any accidental features, given that its problematic features
in a way, not more in number than the contraries, but as it were two; nor yet precisely two, since there in every case belong to it accidentally. But prime matter has no essence, according to the
is a difference of being, but three. For to be man is different from to be unmusical, and to be unformed traditional account.
from to be bronze." 23 In the case of the man becoming musical, on the other hand, one of the substratum's

2 ' For further discussion of the proper characterisation of the coming to be of Aristotle's actual features (namely, being a man) was both unproblematic with respect to his becoming
musical man, see Loux, "Aristotle and Parmenides", 303-306. musical and was privileged over his problematic features.

68 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 69


lr
Anne Siebels Peterson Anne Siebels Peterson
ELEMENTAL TRANSFORMATION IN ARISTOTLE ELEMENTAL TRANSFORMATION IN ARISTOTLE

that it is best characterised only by the very contraries which are the source of of the elements even has a substratum, and so a fortiori that substratum cannot
the problem.24 In order to reply one who wants to retain the traditional account's ersist throughout a case of elemental transformation as the traditional account
thesis that prime matter is indeed essenceless would have to lay out some view requires.
P According to another way of bringing out the conflict, if actualism
according to which prime matter can serve as a subject despite the fact that it is true then prime matter is ontologically dependent upon the predication of
is best characterised only by the very contraries which are the source of the contraries for which it serves as subject; but this seems problematic, given that,
problem. Once again, this shows the traditional account to require more theo- according to the traditional account, it is supposed to be able to persist through
retical commitments than it is usually taken to require. Until any such com- the loss of one or both of those contraries. And third, it conflicts with the view
mitments have been laid out and shown to yield a coherent view, it is not clear that Aristotle's four elements are to be understood according to that version
that the traditional account can maintain Aristotelian constituent ontology. of the constituent ontological strategy according to which one constituent of
a whole serves as subject and the other as predicate. It is not clear how prime
6. CONCLUSION matter is supposed to be able to come to have a new pair of contraries predicated
In summary, I have argued that the traditional account of elemental trans- of it, when, according to the traditional account, the best characterisation of it
formation in Aristotle conflicts with three doctrines. First, it conflicts with that will always involve some contrary opposed to at least one of the contraries it is
variety of essentialism according to which everything that exists has an essence supposed to take on.
which marks it out as what it is. This conflict arises from the traditional account's Some might conclude that we should give up on one or more of Aristotelian
thesis that the same essenceless prime matter must persist throughout any case essentialism, actualism, and Aristotelian constituent ontology rather than go
of elemental transformation. Second, it conflicts with actualism. This conflict can down the pathways required to find a solution to these dilemmas. But perhaps
be brought out in two ways. According to one way of bringing out the conflict, responses can be found which are less problematic than the rejection of any of
if actualism is true then prime matter, taken in abstraction from the element these three doctrines would be. In some cases more than others, one can see,
for which it serves as substratum, does not exist; but then it seems that none however vaguely, what direction a response on the part of the traditional account
might take. For example, one might respond to the conflict with Aristotelian es-
24 For a view which departs from the traditional account in that it sees the matter shared sentialism by relaxing the constraint on what it would be for prime matter to per-
by the four elements as having certain essential properties, see SHELDON COHEN, "Aristotle's sist. In the case of the dilemma that given actualism, it seems that the elements do
Doctrine of the Material Substrate", The Philosophical Review 93 (1984): 172-178. Cohen argues not even have a substratum, or the dilemma that given Aristotelian constituent
that "Aristotle does posit a common matter for the four elements, but this does not commit him to prime ontology, prime matter must in any case of elemental transformation come to
matter. The common matter of the four elements is not prime - that is, it is not bare or characterless...
It is per se neither hot nor cold, fluid nor solid, light nor heavy.... But if it does not possess any of these
have predicated of it at least one contrary at odds with one of the contraries that
characteristics per se, it does not follow that it possesses no characteristics per se. In fact, that it is serves in the best characterisation of it, it is not so clear what direction a response
potentially light and heavy, and that at any given time it will be either light or heavy, can themselves might take. But suppose that the traditional account can be made to cohere with
be taken to specify a per se characteristic." Cohen's view is an interesting modification of the these three doctrines - suppose satisfactory responses to be devisable. Since
traditional account. His view may avoid the third difficulty I have articulated - however, they will no doubt involve controversial metaphysical theses, we are still left
it would have to be shown that one of the essential properties that he attributes to prime with the result that the traditional account is far more theory-laden than it is
matter counts as privileged above all the others in the requisite way. Perhaps his view could,
often taken to be. Hence, it cannot be so easily employed as a general framework
in addition, be argued to avoid the difficulties regarding essentialism and actualism. (I am,
however, sceptical of whether it could. For not just any predicate we can truly ascribe to that can be shared by variant accounts of elemental transformation and of the
something corresponds to a metaphysical essence or accident on Aristotle's view; moreover, place of prime matter in Aristotle's sublunary realm. Moreover, we are left with
if Cohen's view does succeed in endowing prime matter with an essence and an actuality, then the result that more work needs to be done before the traditional account can be
it entails that the notions of essence and actuality for something in the sublunary realm can appealed to as a coherent and justified framework for understanding elemental
be cut asunder from the notion of form - for prime matter is, in virtue of itself, formless.) I transformation - at least if Aristotelian essentialism, actualism, and Aristotelian
do not here have the space for an adequate consideration of whether his view could avoid constituent ontology are to be maintained. Thus, even if it can somehow be made
these difficulties. Still, if it could do so that would not undercut the aim of this paper, which
is to show that the traditional account of prime matter faces these three difficulties, and that
to cohere with these three doctrines, the traditional account commits one to far
the available pathways away from them which do not involve modification of the traditional more than one might think from the way in which it is often laid out.
account (as Cohen's does) involve significant theoretical commitments not usually associated
with the traditional account.

70 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 71


Anne Siebels Peterson
ELEMENTAL TRANSFORMATION IN ARISTOTLE

BIBLIOGRAPHY
ARISTOTLE. Complete Works of Aristotle. Ed. J. Barnes. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press, 1984.
BOSTOCK, DAVID. "Aristotle's Theory of Matter". In Space, Time, Matter, and Form: Essays in ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE,
Aristotle's Physics, 30-46. Oxford University Press, 2006. TRUTHMAKING, AND MEREOLOGY:
COHEN, SHELDON. "Aristotle's Doctrine of the Material Substrate". The Philosophical Review THEN AND NOW
93 (1984): 171-194.
Lewis, FRANK. "What's the Matter with Prime Matter?" In Oxford Studies in Ancient Philo- Ross Inman
sophy 34, ed. Sedley, 123-146. New York: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Loux, MICHAEL J. "Aristotle and Parmenides: An Interpretation of Physics A.8". Proceedings
of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 8 (1992): 302-308.
ABSTRACT
PLANTINGA, ALVIN. "Actualism and Possible Worlds". In Essays in the Metaphysics of Modality,
One notable area in analytic metaphysics that has seen a revival of Aristotelian and scho-
ed. M. Davidson, 102-121. New York: Oxford University Press, 2003.
lastic inspired metaphysics is the return to a more robust construal of the notion of essence,
ROBINSON, H. M. "Prime Matter in Aristotle". Phronesis 19 (1974): 168-188. what some have labelled "real" or "serious" essentialism. It is only recently, however, that this
SCALTSAS, THEODORE. Substances and Universals in Aristotle's Metaphysics. New York: Cornell more robust notion of essence has been implemented into the debate on truthmaking, mainly
University Press, 1994. by the work of E. J. Lowe. The first part of the paper sets out to explore the scholastic roots
of essential dependence as well as an account of truthmaking for accidental predications in
SOLMSEN, FRIEDRICH. "Aristotle and Prime Matter: A Reply to Hugh R. King".Journal of the terms of accidents. Along the way, the author examines the dialectical role the possibility of
History of Ideas 19 (1958): 243-252. separated accidents in the Eucharist play with respect to developing a scholastic account of
WILLIAMS, C. J. F. Aristotle's De Generatione et Corruptione. New York: Oxford University truthmaking as essential dependence. In conclusion the author utilises Aquinas's hylomorphic
Press, 1982. ontology to suggest a new way forward for an essentialist account of truthmaking.

1. INTRODUCTION
One notable area in analytic metaphysics that has seen a revival of Aristotelian
and scholastic inspired metaphysics is the return to a more robust construal of
the notion essence, what some have labelled "real" or "serious" essentialism.'
However, it is only recently that this more robust notion of essence has been
implemented into the debate on truthmaking, mainly by the work of E. J. Lowe.
The first part of the paper sets out to explore the scholastic roots of essential
dependence as well as an account of truthmaking for accidental predications in
terms of accidents. Along the way, I examine the dialectical role the possibility of
separated accidents in the Eucharist play with respect to developing a scholastic
account of truthmaking as essential dependence. I conclude by utilising Aquinas's
hylomorphic ontology to suggest a new way forward for an essentialist account
of truthmaking.

I See D. ODERBERG, Real Essentialism (London: Routledge, 2007) and E. J. LOWE, "Two Notions
of Being: Entity and Essence", in Royal institute of Philosophy Supplement, 62 (2008): 23-24.

72 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 73


Ross Inman Ross Inman
ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE, TRUTHMAKING, AND MEREOLOGY: THEN AND NOW ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE, TRUTHMAKING, AND MEREOLOGY: THEN AND Now

2. CONTEMPORARY TRUTHMAKING AND ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE That is, if x is the truthmaker for (p), then, necessarily, if x exists then (p)T. In
Let us, then, begin by explicating the current discussion surrounding the this way, the existence of x is said to necessitate (A. For our purposes here, let us
notion of truthmaking, with an emphasis on the notion of essential dependence? assume the truth of TNec, together with the rather contentious thesis that TNec,
The fundamental insight driving the commitment to truthmakers is that truth in some form or other, is both necessary and sufficient for truthmaking.' If so,
is determined by reality. To say that something determines some particular truth we then get the following explication of the notion of the truthmaking relation:
is to say that it is the ontological ground of that truth; its existence explains why
that truth is true. Consider the singular existential proposition that e exists, (TM) Truthmaker: TM(x, (p)) = E!x A ❑(E!x -->(p)T)
(e exists), and suppose that (e exists) is true. Now, intuitively, it is e itself that is
the truthmaker for (e exists) that is, e determines the truth of (e exists). We can In words: x is a truthmaker for (p) if and only if x exists and it is necessary that
call this relationship between e and (e exists) the relation of truthmaking, TM if x exists, then (p) is true.
henceforth, and represent "e is the truthmaker for (e exists)" as TM(e, (e exists))? Many truthmaker advocates are of the opinion that the modality operative
With this in mind, let us formulate what I will call the truthmaker principle in the above formulation of TM is to be construed as metaphysical necessity (as
(TMP) as follows:4 opposed to logical or physical necessity) such that, at the very least, (p)T meta-
physically depends on the existence of x. Several truthmaker theorists, however,
(TMP) Truthmaker Principle: (p)T = E!x A TM(x, (p))5 have expressed doubts as to whether or not standard conceptions of metaphysical
necessitation - where the existence of the truthmaking entity is necessary for
That is, (p) is true ((p), henceforth) if and only if there exists something, x, the truth in question - is fine-grained enough to capture the sort of dependence
that stands in the truthmaking relation to (p). While there are many important that obtains between a true proposition and its truthmaker(s).8
questions regarding the notion of truthmaking operative in TMP (like the status One such contemporary truthmaker theorist is E. J. Lowe.9 Following closely
of truthmaker maximalism, i.e. whether every truth has a truthmaker), I limit the influential work of Kit Fine regarding the shortcomings of modal construals
my discussion here to the status of truthmaker necessitarianism; whether the re- of essence, Lowe questions the adequacy of standard accounts of metaphysical
lation of truthmaking (TM) carries modal import such that the existence of the necessitation in its ability to capture the dependence operative in TM.'9 Lowe
truthmaker necessitates (p)T. critiques modal construals of TM that rely on what he calls "rigid-existential
The proponent of truthmaker necessitarianism claims that if x is the truth- dependence", which can be formulated as follows:
maker for (p) in some world W, then x is the truthmaker for (p) not only in W but
in every possible world in which x exists. Most truthmaker theorists agree that (RD) x depends rigidly ony 'clef D(E!X E!y)"
truthmakers necessitate the propositions they make true.6 We can formulate
truthmaker necessitarianism as follows: As a construal of metaphysical dependence in terms of modality and existence,
RD states that x depends ony just in case it is necessary thaty exists if x exists. As
(TNec) Truthmaker Necessitarianism: TM(x, (p)) —> ❑(E!x —> (p)T) an example of RD, Lowe cites the dependence of a boundary or a hole on its host or
that of a heap of stones upon the individual stones that it contains. A boundary,
thus, rigidly necessitates the existence of its host in that it exists only if its host
For an excellent introduction to the contemporary debate on truthmaking see GONZALO
RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA, "Truthmakers", Philosophy Compass 1, no. 2 (2006): 186 -200. ' Thanks to Jeffrey Brower for conversation on this point.
' I take it for granted that TM is a relation. For a denial of this assumption, see JOSEPH The plural here denotes the fact that TM can be a many-one relation.
MELIA, ."Truthmaking without Truthmakers" in Truthmakers: The Contemporary Debate, ed. H. 9 See E. J. LOWE, "An Essentialist Approach to Truthmaking", in Truth and Truthmaking
Beebee and Julian Dodd, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005, 67-84. What's more, for our (Acumen Press, 2008), 201-217; and The Four Category Ontology (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
purposes in this paper I will generally assume that truthmaking is a cross-categorial relation 2006), 192-210.
that obtains between propositions (truthbearers) and entities in the world. 1° KIT FINE, "Essence and Modality", in Philosophical Perspectives 8: Logic and Language, ed.
' I use the existence predicate 'E!x' ex exists) as shorthand for `3y(x = y)'. James E. Tomberlin (Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview, 1994), 1-16.
My quantifiers are to be taken as universal unless otherwise noted. " Alternatively, -‘0(EN A -.Ely), i.e. x cannot exist unlessy exists. RD also goes by the name
Though JosH PARSONS is a notable exception, see his "There is No `Truthmaker' Argument 'weak foundation' in PETER SIMONS, Parts: A Study in Ontology (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
Against Nominalism", Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77, no. 3: 325-334. 1987), 295.

74 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 75


Ross Inman Ross Inman
ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE, TRUTHMAKING, AND MEREOLOGY: THEN AND Now ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE, TRUTHMAKING, AND MEREOLOGY: THEN AND Now
exists. According to an understanding of TM along the lines of RD, (p)T rigidly (ED) x essentially depends on y =de f There is a function f such that it is
depends on the existence of x such that it is necessarily the case that (A. only if part of the essence of x that x is f(y)."
x exists. It is in this sense that x is said to rigidly necessitate (p)T.
Lowe contends that a modal construal of TM in terms of RD leads to some rather One particular example of ED would be the relationship between Socrates and
untoward consequences, what we might generally dub the objection from irrele- his singleton {Socrates}, the set whose sole member is Socrates. Now, according
vance. Fundamentally, an RD reading of TM suggests that every true proposition to ED, {Socrates} essentially depends on Socrates precisely because it is of the
rigidly depends on necessary beings. Again, recall that x is a truthmaker for some essence - the very identity - of {Socrates} that it be the singleton set of Socrates,
proposition (p), say (Socrates is pale), if and only if x exists and it is necessarily that is, to be the value of the singleton-set-of function, where Socrates serves as
the case that if x exists, then (Socrates is pale) is true. But suppose that x is a rtdn
esmcceeon
Leargument.
epen
dthe u not.
necessary being, say the number 7, and thus exists in every possible world. If the Let consider how ED might serve to elucidate the species of metaphysical
number 7 exists in every possible world, then it, ipso facto, exists in the world in operative in TM. It is precisely in virtue of the fact that ED is more
which (Socrates is pale) is true. It follows from this that (Socrates is pale) rigidly fine-grained than RD that the former is able to sidestep the objection from
depends for its truth on the number 7 and, consequently, the latter is what makes irrelevance. Recall that an RD reading of TM stated that x is the truthmaker
the former true." But this seems implausible as the existence of the number 7 for (Socrates is pale) if and only if x exists and rigidly necessitates the truth of
is wholly irrelevant regarding whether or not (Socrates is pale) is true. Though (Socrates is pale), thereby allowing the unintuitive notion that every true pro-
(Socrates is pale) may well necessarily imply the existence of the number 7, one is position is rigidly necessitated, and thus made true, by some necessary being (the
hesitant to make the further claim that therefore the number 7 is the truthmaker number 7). On a more fine-grained ED reading of TM, however, such an inference is
for (Socrates is pale). unwarranted on the grounds that it is not part of the essence of (Socrates is pale)
In light of this, Lowe contends that to say that x metaphysically necessitates that it be true only if the number 7 exists. While (Socrates is pale) might be rigidly
(A- is not merely to espouse the view that x exists in every world in which (p),, i.e. necessitated by the number 7, it is not essentially necessitated by it in the sense
that x is necessary for (p)T. Rather, metaphysical necessitation is better expressed that (Socrates is pale) does not depend for what it is - its very identity - on the
by the fact that the non-existence of x is necessary for the falsehood of p.13 Alternatively, existence of the number 7." Consequently, as one cannot infer from the existence
for x to be the ontological ground for (p)T is for x's non-existence to be necessary of a necessary being (number 7) that everything is essentially dependent upon it,
for the falsehood of (p). Consequently, Lowe claims that RD fails to adequately the objection from irrelevance is avoided, thereby making essential dependence
construe the modal dependence operative in TM. a welcome candidate for the species of metaphysical necessity operative in TM.
Lowe maintains that the failure of RD to capture the relevant notion of In the case of accidental predications, an ED reading of TM proves to be fruitful.
metaphysical necessitation in TM does not entail that all species of metaphysical Take, for instance, an accidental predication of the form (x is F), where the mode
dependence are therefore inadequate to do so. In the place of RD, Lowe puts F-ness is predicated of a substance x. On Lowe's four-category ontology, F-ness
forward a relation - essential dependence - that he takes to entail rigid existential essentially depends on x as well as the universal F (F-ness being a particularised
dependence, but is not entailed by it. That is, every case of essential dependence instance of F). That is, it is part of the essence of F-ness that it (i) characterise
is a case of rigid-existential dependence, but not the converse.'" As such, essential or inhere in x and (ii) be an instance of F. Since F-ness is essentially dependent
dependence is more fine-grained than rigid-existential dependence and thus is on these two entities, it follows, according to Lowe, that the existence of F-ness
better suited to capture the notion that (p)T metaphysically depends on x. Lowe essentially necessitates x's being F and thus the truth of the proposition (x is F).
states the notion of essential dependence as follows: In other words, the existence of F-ness suffices to secure the existence of x, F, x's
'2 For an early statement of this sort of worry, see SIMONS, Parts, 295. 15 More generally, 3R(1=1„Rxy): for some relation R, x is essentially related by that relation to
13 LOWE, The Four-Category Ontology, 202. y. I should note that Lowe takes identity dependence to be a species of essential dependence,
" It should be noted that Lowe in "Two Notions of Being" takes the notion of essence to though I do not think this affects what I say here. For an extensive treatment of different
be primitive and does not reify essences. Rather, Lowe takes the locution "the essence of x" ti of ontological dependence see FABRICE CORREIA, Existential Dependence and Cognate
to denote "what x is, or what it is to be x". Further, Lowe states the fact that essential (identity) Notions (Philosophia
(Philosophia Verlag, 2005).
dependence entails rigid existential dependence as follows: "that if one entity depends for its 16 Although, as David Oderberg suggests in Real Essentialism, the number 7 is a virtual part

identity upon another, then the former could not have existed without the latter" - LOWE, The Four- of the essence of (Socrates is pale) in so far as the latter, an existing entity, is essentially self-
Category Ontology, 35. identical and thus has as a (virtual) part of its essence being distinct from the number 7.

76 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 77


Ross Inman Ross Inman
ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE, TRUTHMAKING, AND MEREOLOGY: THEN AND NOW ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE, TRUTHMAKING, AND MEREOLOGY: THEN AND NOW

being F, and therefore the truth of the proposition (x is F). As a result, F-ness is said labelling it "essential order" and proceeds to explicate two distinct varieties
to metaphysically necessitate the truth of (x is F) in the right sort of way, thereby of essential order: the order of eminence and the order of dependence.19 The order
satisfying TM. of eminence pertains to the notion of perfection; x is eminently ordered with
respect toy if x's perfection (of essence) exceeds the perfection ofy, and is thereby
3. SCHOLASTIC ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE said to be prior to y in the order of eminence. The order of dependence, on the
In spite of this recent turn to essence in the contemporary literature on other hand, involves the notion of priority and posteriority with respect to the
truthmaking, there has been little exploration of the historical roots of the formal essence or nature of the two relata involved; "the dependent is said to be posterior
concept of essential dependence as it pertains to the notion of truthmaking whereas that on which it depends is prior".20
broadly conceived. My aim in this section is to explore the scholastic roots of Here it is crucial to note that Scotus maintains that the relata of essential
the notion of essential dependence as developed in the work of Duns Scotus. In ordering relations are essences (i.e. forms). Again, in the context of the hypostatic
section 4, I proceed to examine the relationship between Scotus's understanding union, Scotus explicitly endorses the notion that the relata of essential ordering
of essential order with his account of truthmaking for accidental predications relations are essences, "As for the case at hand, the personal or hypostatic entity
in terms of accidents. I then show how his account fails to satisfy the modal has no essential priority in respect to creatures, for an essential order obtains per
constraints on TM in light of his commitment to the possibility of separated se only between essences (in contrast to hypostatic entities), since it is forms (i.e.
accidents in the Eucharist as well as the objection from irrelevance outlined essences) that are like numbers"." In short, the order is one of essential dependence
above. I conclude with a brief examination of a scholastic account of truthmaking in so far as the priority or posteriority stems from the nature or essence of the
for accidental predications that does satisfy the modal constraints of TM and thus s
entity squestion.
presents itself as a viable option for contemporary truthmaker theorists. further suggests that essential ordering relations imply a sort of exis-
tential dependence of the posterior on that which is prior, "the prior according to
3.1. Scotus on essential order nature and essence can exist without the posterior but the reverse is not true"."
The notion of one entity depending on another for its existence and/or essence He continues,
has a formidable history in the Aristotelian tradition. Let us begin, then, with And this I understand as follows. Even though the prior should produce the posterior
an examination of Scotus's understanding of dependence, as displayed in his necessarily and consequently could not exist without it, it would not be because the
philosophical theology and substance-accident ontology. prior requires the posterior for its own existence, but it is rather the other way about.
In the context of the metaphysics of the Incarnation, Scotus contends that the For even assuming that posterior did not exist, the existence of the prior would
not entail a contradiction. But the converse is not true, for the posterior needs the
union that takes place between the Word, the second person of the Trinity, and prior. This need we can call dependence, so that we can say that anything which is
the human nature of Christ (i.e. the hypostatic union) is a "union of order."" After essentially posterior [in this way] depends necessarily upon what is prior but not vice
considering and rejecting two other kinds of unity that might obtain between the versa, even should the posterior at times proceed from it necessarily."
Word and the human nature of Christ, Scotus states,
Following Aristotle, Scotus maintains that if x is essentially posterior to y,
All that remains therefore is the third type, namely, a union of order. The order, then x depends on y for its existence. He states that if x is essentially ordered to
however, is that of the posterior to the prior. The Word obviously is not posterior
y, then x's existence "needs" or "requires" y's existence, i.e. it is impossible that x
to [human] nature; hence it is the other way around. The nature is posterior with
respect to the Word and thus dependent on him.'s exist without y's existing.

For Scotus, then, the Word is ordered with respect to the human nature of
Christ in such a way that the latter is posterior to, and thus dependent on, the 19 JOHN DUNS SCOTUS, De Primo Principio [DPP] 1.6.
former. 20 DPP 1.8.
Scotus's most developed treatment of the notion of dependence is found in 21 Quodl. q. 19, n. 19. However, it should be noted that Scotus does, at times, allow for a wider
his De Primo Principio. There, he elucidates the notion of posteriority and priority, variety of relata in essential ordering relations. See Quodl. 19., a. 2, n. 30 where he distinguishes
different conceptions of essential dependence by their different relata.
17 JOHN DUNS SCOTUS, Quaestiones Quodlibetales [Quodl.], q. 19, n. 2. al DPP 1.8.
'8 Ibid., n. 5. 21 DPP 1.8.

78 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 79


Ross Inman Ross Inman
ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE, TRUTHMAKING, AND MEREOLOGY: THEN AND NOW ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE, TRUTHMAKING, AND MEREOLOGY: THEN AND NOW

Here, however, we must proceed with caution. The claim that x is existentially Asymmetry: "In any essential order a circle is impossible.""
dependent on y admits of two readings, each differing in its respective scope. 0 0(x,y) —• -00(y,x)
We have already encountered the strong variety of existential dependence in
Lowe's explication of rigid-existential dependence (RD) above. Recall that this Transitivity: "What is not subsequent to the prior
stronger notion stated that necessarily, x exists only if y exists, E(E!x —• E!y), is not subsequent to the posterior"28
where 'y' denotes some particular entity such that necessarily, x exists only if
that particular y exists. While rigid-existential dependence captures the notion (00(x,y) A pay,z)) ---, (00(x,z))
of an entity's existence requiring the existence of a particular entity, the weaker
Consequently, what emerges from our above discussion of Scotus's conception
reading captures the notion of an entity's existence requiring the existence of
of dependence is a partial ordering relation that obtains between essences that
an object of a particular sort. As such, the weaker reading states that necessarily,
x exists only if F exists, where 'F' is a general term denoting some instance of the is governed by the axioms of irreflexivity, asymmetry, and transitivity. Though
essential order is commonly understood within the context of distinguishing
class of Fs. Thus, on this weak reading, x cannot exist unless something is an F, i.e.
Ei(E!x —• E!y A Fy). Let us follow Lowe once more and label this weak variety of per se and per accidens causal series, Scotus takes essential ordering relations to
be commonplace, especially as it pertains to his substance-accident ontology." In
existential dependence "non-rigid existential dependence".
attempting to distinguish essential order from any sort of causal dependence, he
In the passage above it is not clear as to which notion of existential depen-
suggests that essential order "can be shown somehow in [the relation of] subject
dence Scotus takes essential order to entail. For now, let us just say that if an
and accident."" What's more, referring again to the essential order that obtains in
entity is essentially ordered to another entity, then the former is existentially
the hypostatic union, Scotus notes that the human nature of Christ is dependent
dependent on the latter in some sense or other (understood in a wide enough sense
on the Word such that the latter sustains the former in existence and, further,
to capture both rigid and non-rigid existential dependence).
that this sustenance is "maximally similar to that of an accident by its subject"."
Let us, then, formulate Scotus's conception of essential order using our sen-
But how exactly does Scotus conceive of the relation between a substance
tential operator 'Clx' to stand for 'it is part of the essence of x':
and its accidents? The issue, as we will see shortly, is complicated given his com-
mitment to the Eucharistic doctrine that upon consecration the accidents of the
(E0): x is essentially ordered toy = El x (E!x ---• E!y)24
bread and the wine remain in existence, even though their underlying substance
That is, x is essentially ordered toy if and only if x is essentially such that it ceases to exist." Let us turn, then, to examine Scotus's notion of E0 as applied to
exists only if y exists. Michael Gorman has pointed out that Scotus puts forward his understanding of the relation between a substance and its accidents with an
several formal features that govern E0 in De Primo Principio 2: irreflexivity, asym- eye on the prospects of its application to the notion of truthmaking below.
metry, and transitivity." Using "Elo" to stand for "essentially ordered", Scotus Scotus operates out of an Aristotelian ontology where substances are the
maintains that E0 is governed by the following axioms: fundamental units of being and accidents are taken to inhere in substances. By an
accident "inhering" in a substance, Scotus means to convey either: (i) the actual
Irreflexivity: "Nothing whatever is essentially ordered to itself."26 union of an existing accident with its existing subject as a kind of act with the
potential or (ii) the dependence of the accident upon the substance, where the
-(00(x,x))

27 DPP 2.4.
28 DPP 2.6.
24 Scotus defines "of the essence of x" (what I am referring to in EO above as "part of the
29 DPP 1.
essence of x such that") as "that which is included per se in the quidditative concept of x and " Ord. III, dist. 1, q. 1, n. 3, as cited in RICHARD CROSS, The Metaphysics of the Incarnation:
therefore, is posited in the essential notion of its quiddity, and not as something added." See Thomas Aquinas to Duns Scotus (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002), 123.
JOHN DUNS SCOTUS, Quaestiones super libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelis [In Met.] VII, q. 1. " Ord. III, dist. 1, q. 4, n. 2, as cited in CROSS, ibid.
25 MICHAEL GORMAN, "Ontological Priority and John Duns Scotus", in The Philosophical " For an excellent treatment of the Eucharist and its role in scholastic metaphysics, see
Quarterly 43 (173) (1993): 460-471. MARILYN MCCORD ADAMS "Aristotle and the Sacrament of the Altar: A Crisis in Medieval
26 DPP 2.2. Theology", Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 17 (1991): 195-249.

80 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 81


Ross Inman Ross Inman
ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE, TRUTHMAKING, AND MEREOLOGY: THEN AND Now ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE, TRUTHMAKING, AND MEREOLOGY: THEN AND NOW

substance is essentially prior and the accident is naturally posterior." Regarding One apparent implication of Scotus's metaphysics of the Eucharist for his
(0, we can say that if x inheres in y then x actualises some potency in y, call this su bstance-accident ontology (and for his view of truthmaking as we will see
`inherence,' as it underscores the fact that x informs y in such a way that y's s hortly)
is that while an accident may be naturally ordered to substance, it is not
passive potency (to be x) is actualised by x. Concerning (ii), if x inheres iny, then essen tially ordered (posterior) to it." The reasoning here is straightforward. In
x is dependent on y for its continued existence, call this 'inherence,' (to be read so far as it is metaphysically possible for an accident to exist without actually
in the broadest terms to include rigid and non-rigid existential dependence). By inheringp in a substance" it follows that it is not part of its essence to actually
claiming that accidents are "naturally posterior" to substances, Scotus means inhere, in a substance and, ipso facto, is not essentially ordered to it. This reasoning
that "the natural entity of these [accidents] is through substance"." That is, it relies on Scotus's earlier contention that that which is essentially ordered is
is the natural order of things that accidents depend on substances as external, existentially dependent (in either the rigid or non-rigid sense) on that which is
efficient causes of their continued existence. prior." Here I interpret Scotus as espousing the view that that which is essentially
Furthermore, Scotus is clear that inherence,, is more fundamental than in. ordered to another must actually depend for its existence on that which is prior,
herenceA in so far as an accident's (natural) dependence on substance serves i.e. it must actually inhere, in either its particular host substance or some substance
as the ground for its capacity to actualise some potency in its substance. If an or other.4° Consequently, Scotus's adherence to the metaphysical possibility of an
accident, F-ness, is to actualise some potency in Socrates (inherence„), to be pale accident existing without actually inhering, in either the strong or weak sense
for instance, then there must be a sense in which F-ness depends on Socrates (i.e. implies that accidents are not, strictly speaking, essentially ordered to substance.
inherence,) as opposed to Crito, say. At the same time, however, Scotus does speak as though accidents, in the
Scotus further distinguishes two ways an accident may inhere simpliciter normal order of things, actually inhered„ in a substance. In fact, he is of the opi-
(i.e. inhere, or inhered in a substance: actual inherence and aptitudinal inherence 35 nion that accidents are (naturally) sustained in existence by their host substances
Heavily influenced by the Eucharistic doctrine concerning separated accidents in such a way that the latter is "the end term of the dependence of the actual
(i.e. accidents that no longer depend on their host substance for their sustained existence of an assumed nature".4' Elsewhere, he refers to this dependence rela-
existence), Scotus argues that while it is not of the essence of an accident to tion as the substance communicating its existence to the accident 42
actually inhere simpliciter in a substance (as is the case with separated accidents In adhering to the possibility of separated accidents together with the fact that
present in the Eucharist), it is of the essence of an accident that it aptitutidinally accidents do at times actually inhere, in their host substances, Scotus appears to
inhere simpliciter in a substance (the separated accidents are such that they be affirming the seemingly implausible thesis that being existentially dependent is
naturally tend to inhere in a substance, though it is not part of their essence that a contingent affair. In fact, Scotus says just this when he states:
they actually do so)." Hence, the aptitude or disposition to inhere, and inhere, in
a substance is part of the essence (what Scotus calls the "quidditative concept")
of an accident, irrespective of whether or not it actually does so. Consequently, 37 See Quodl. q. 19, n. 13. Also, as Richard Cross has shown, Scotus does provide independent

we have the following classification of accidental inherence: philosophical argumentation in support of the thesis that accidents are not essentially ordered
to their host substances. See his The Physics of Duns Scotus (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
INHERENCE
1998), 100.
ACTUAL APTITUDINAL " Something Scotus explicitly affirms, "the natural entity of these [accidents] is through sub-
stance; they can [however] exist without substance with an aptitude for a subject" — In Met. VII, q. 4,
INHERENCEA INHERENCE(' INHERENCE,, INHERENCE(' n. 2). The implication here is that an accident may exist without actually inhering (simpliciter)
in a substance, though it cannot exist without having the aptitude to inhere in a substance.
Quodl. q. 19, n. 13; In Met. VII, q. 1, n. 9. However Scotus intends the modal import of 39 DPP 1.8.

'natural' here, I understand it to be (at the very least) weaker than metaphysical necessity I° Further evidence for this reading is found in his using the notions of actual inherence()
(broad logical necessity) as construed by contemporary philosophers. See CROSS, The Meta- and essential order interchangeably (In Met. VII, q. 1, n. 9) and then, shortly after, stating
physics of the Incarnation, 104 for more on Scotus's view of accidents being naturally posterior explicitly that it is not of the essence of an accident that it actually inhere() (ibid., n. 12) in
to substances. a substance.
31 In Met. VII, q. 4, n. 2. 41 Ord. III, dist. 1, q. 5, n. 8, as cited in CROSS, The Metaphysics of the Incarnation.
" See In Met. VII, q. 1, n. 10; and Quodl. q. 19, n. 24. 42 Ord. III, dist. 1, q. 5, n. 8, as cited in CRoSS, The Metaphysics of the Incarnation; Quodl. q. 19,

'6 In Met. VII, q. 1, n. 12. n. 23.

82 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 83


Ross Inman Ross Inman
ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE, TRUTHMAKING, AND MEREOLOGY: THEN AND Now ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE, TRUTHMAKING, AND MEREOLOGY: THEN AND NOW

We show this thirdly as follows: An accident can have the mode of substance [i.e. it Medieval philosophers customarily defined something's whiteness, heaviness, exis-
can exist without inhering in a substance], although not perfectly in the sense that tence, manhood, or colour, as that by which it was white, was heavy, existed, was a
it would be repugnant for it to depend on a subject, but in some analogous way man, or was coloured... this 'by which' is to be elucidated in terms of truthmaking."
viz., insofar as it does not actually depend; this is seen in the case of a separated
accident." For both Scotus and Aquinas, substances are "made to be" by their accidents in
a qualified sense; accidents are said to actualise some potency in their substances,
The way in which an accident has the mode of substance in the Eucharist is thereby causing substances to be in some particular manner.
that it enjoys independent existence. Be that as it may, separated accidents remain In particular, Aquinas speaks of an accident being related to a substance as act
as accidents in so far as they retain their aptitude to actually inhered in a substance to potency and that "a subject, in virtue of an accident, is in certain ways" and that
(substances do not have this feature). Nonetheless, it remains that the view has "whiteness makes a potentially white human being actually white ... non-essential
the rather untoward consequence that being existentially dependent is a contingent forms make it [substance] actually exist in various non-essential modes"." What's
matter." I must, at this point, leave these interpretive niceties to those with a more, he states that, "Snow is 'white' by reason of its whiteness"." Consequently,
more detailed knowledge of the issues surrounding Scotus's ontology of accidents. Aquinas emphasises the role of accidents in a substance's coming to be modified
As a result, we have seen that Scotus relies on a conception of essential in a particular manner (although we will see shortly that his account does not
dependence (i.e. essential order) that is governed by (i) the notion of priority and appeal to accidents alone).
posteriority between essences (ii) the existential dependence of the posterior on As for Scotus, the actualisation of passive potency in a substance by an acci-
the prior (in some sense or other) and (iii) the axioms of irreflexivity, asymmetry, dent is, as we have already seen, embodied in his notion of inherenceA. Scotus,
and transitivity. Let us turn, then, to discuss several scholastic conceptions of like Aquinas before him, argued that Socrates is white "by the existence of a
truthmaking for accidental predications and their relation to the notion of essen- white thing".5° Following Richard Cross (2002), I take this feature of accidents to
tial dependence (order). be what Scotus elsewhere calls their ability to confer existence denominatively on
their respective substances." Consequently, both Scotus and Aquinas were of the
4. SCHOLASTIC TRUTHMAKING AND ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE opinion that Socrates' potency for being white is actualised by the inhering of
Though the scholastics did not express the notion of truthmaking in precisely the accident whiteness.
the same terms as we do today, the idea is not without witness in the Aristotelian However, both of these thinkers differed as to the details concerning the
tradition 45 In fact, both Scotus and Aquinas, with Aristotle, adopt the fundamental truthmaking role for accidents. To get clear on this, let us represent their views
intuition behind the notion of truthmaking: the dependence of truth on being." regarding the multifaceted relationship between an accident and its substance
As John Fox has noted, as follows:

43 Quodl. q. 19, n. 84. (A) For any accident F-ness and any substance x in which F-ness inheres,
" One rather contentious way out of this would be to suggest that while it appears that (1) F-ness existentially depends on x, either actually or aptitudinally.
being rigidly existentially dependent is non-contingent, being non-rigidly existentially dependent
might be a contingent feature of an entity (as it is a weaker dependence relation). That is, (2) F-ness actualises x's potency to be F.52
a non-rigidly dependent entity can fail to be dependent as such and yet exist nonetheless. For (3) F-ness is a truthmaker, such that (x is F) is true."
an excellent historical treatment of the scholastic debate concerning the view that accidents
have various modes of existence (modus essendi), see ROBERT PASNAU, Metaphysical Themes " Fox, "Truthmaker", 190.
1274-1689 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011). " Summa theologiae [STh] I, q. 3. a. 6 and De principiis naturae 1, respectively.
" For ARISTOTLE, see especially Categories 14 b 16-23. For a defence of the thesis that " STh III, q. 77, a. 1, ad 4.
the scholastics utilised a truthmaking theory of predication see JOHN Fox, "Truthmaker",
50 Ord III, dist. 6, q. 1, n. 6, as cited by CROSS ibid.
Australasian Journal of Philosophy 65 (1987): 188-207; JEFFERY BROWER, "Simplicity and Aseity",
The Oxford Handbook to Philosophical Theology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009); TIM PAWL, 5' CROSS, ibid., 125, n. 21. See also Ord. III, q. 6, a. 1, n. 6, as cited by CROSS ibid., and In Met.

A Thomistic Account of Truthmakers for Modal Truths (doctoral dissertation, St. Louis University, VII, q. 1, n. 10.
2008); and CROSS, The Metaphysics of the Incarnation. 52 As with (1), F-ness may either actually or aptitudinally actualise x's potency to be F. Since
46 For AQUINAS see his Quaestiones Disputatae de Veritate [QDV], q. 1, a. 2, ad 3; ibid. ad 1. For both Scotus and Aquinas appear to ignore an accident's having the aptitude to actualise x's
SCOTUS see Ord III, dist. 6., q. 1, n. 6; Reportata Parisiensia III, dist. 1, q. 2, n. 5, as cited in CROSS, potency to be F, I focus here on an accidents actually doing so.
The Metaphysics of the Incarnation. " Ord. I, dist. 8, pars 1, q. 4, n. 213-214, adapted from CROSS, ibid., 34.

84 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 85


Ross Inman Ross Inman
ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE, TRUTHMAKING, AND MEREOLOGY: THEN AND Now ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE, TRUTHMAKING, AND MEREOLOGY: THEN AND Now

Both Scotus and Aquinas were committed to (1) and (2) regarding the rela- cla im that essential order entails existential dependence in some sense or other.
tionship between an accident and its host substance.54 However, they differ as Un fortunately, we can no longer remain neutral on this matter as the tenability
to how (1) and (2) bear on (3), that is, the truthmaking role of accidents. Here, of Scotus's proposal of truthmaking in terms of (1) heavily depends on whether or
I consider Scotus's account of truthmaking for accidental predications and pro, not he understands an accident to be rigidly or non-rigidly existentially depen-
ceed to Aquinas's more detailed account in the final section. seae substance.
denTtoon
we construe (1) in terms of non-rigid existential depen-
4.1 Scotus's account of truthmaking dence and thus explicate (3) as F-ness non-rigidly depending on x. On this account,
In general, Scotus construes (3) in terms of (1). In fact, Scotus is quite adamant the existence of F-ness does not, strictly speaking, necessitate the truth of (x is F),
that (3) can be understood without reference to (2). He states: say, Socrates' being F. Rather, at most, the existence of F-ness necessitates that
You will object: how is something formally wise by wisdom unless [wisdom] is some x is F, not that this particular, viz. Socrates, is F. On this reading, the existence
its form? I reply: a body is animate denominatively (as it were), because the soul of F-ness could just as easily necessitate the truth of (Glaucon is F). Consequently,
is its form. A human being is said to be animate essentially, and not (as it were) interpreting (1) in terms of non-rigid existential dependence is not strong enough
denominatively, because the soul belongs to him or her as a part. So being of a cer- to capture the modal force operative in TM.
tain sort because of something does not require that the thing [paleness] is a form The same fate awaits an interpretation of (1) in terms of rigid-existential
informing something [Socrates], because a form [paleness] is not a form informing dependence. As was previously demonstrated, this species of metaphysical de-
the whole, even though [the whole] is said to be of a certain sort because of it."
pendence does not appear to be fine-grained enough to capture the notion of
Thus, paleness need not actualise some passive potency in Socrates in or- truthmaking, hence the objection from irrelevance we met in section II. As Lowe
der to serve as the truthmaker for (Socrates is pale). Rather, Scotus was of the (2006) has pointed out, "a truthmaker is not, or not merely, something whose
opinion that the truthmaking role for accidents is best construed in terms of existence is necessary for the truth of a proposition but something whose non-
(1); it is in virtue of a substance x's possessing an accidental form F-ness via existence is necessary for its falsehood.""
actual inherencep that it is true that (x is F), i.e. F-ness is the truthmaker for the Lastly, we might underscore here the implications of Scotus's metaphysics of
accidental predication (x is F). As Marilyn McCord Adams notes, the Eucharist for his account of truthmaking in terms of (1). If separated accidents
Scotus declares that ontological dependence of a broad sense property thing on
are metaphysically possible, then there could be instances where the F-ness (the
a subject is sufficient for characterization. Even if whiteness did not actualise a po- whiteness of the bread) of x exists and yet the accidental predication (x is F) ((the
tency in Socrates, Socrates would be the subject on which the whiteness ontologically bread is white)) is false given that x ceases to exist altogether. Yet this undermines
depended and that would be enough to make it true that Socrates is white." the fact that truthmakers are said to metaphysically necessitate their truths.
Consequently, in so far as we place any stock in the objection from irrelevance
Scotus's explication of truthmaking in terms of (1) instead of (2) is ultimately
and thereby require the modal force of truthmaking to be stronger than that of
tied to his view that inherencei, is more fundamental than inherence„ in so far as
rigid-existential dependence, it appears that we must bid farewell to a scholastic
an accident's actualising some passive potency in a substance requires that the
account of truthmaking for accidental predications in terms of accidents alone.
accident depend on that very substance for its existence.
Given the earlier line of reasoning in section 2 above, however, it appears that 4.2 Hylomorphic truthmakers
this proposal is inadequate to secure the requisite modal strength contemporary I want to conclude by briefly unpacking an alternative essential dependence
philosophers commonly ascribe to the relation of truthmaking. Recall our ear-
account of truthmaking for accidental predications, one that finds its roots in
lier attempt to construe existential dependence (and hence inherence,,) in the the hylomorphic ontology of Thomas Aquinas. Aquinas's hylomorphic account,
broadest possible terms in order to allow for either a strong or weak reading I believe, has much to offer the contemporary truthmaker theorist as it provides
(i.e. rigid or non-rigid respectively) in light of the ambiguity latent in Scotus's a novel alternative to tropes and states of affairs as truthmakers for accidental
predications.
" For AQUINAS, see 5Th III, q. 77, a. 1, ad. 2. Though at times Aquinas speaks as though accidents alone serve as truth-
" Ord. I, dist. 8, pars 1, q. 4, n. 213-214, adapted from CROSS, ibid. makers for accidental predications in virtue of satisfying (2) above, he clearly
56 MARYLYN MCCORD ADAMS, Christ and Horrors (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2006), 126. 57 LowE, The Four-Category Ontology, 202.

86 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 87


Ross Inman Ross Inman
ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE, TRUTHMAKING, AND MEREOLOGY: THEN AND NOW ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE, TRUTHMAKING, AND MEREOLOGY: THEN AND Now

states that it is the combining of an accident and its host substance that serves as toward a hylomorphic ontology and whose aesthetic sensibilities are not offended
the truthmaker for accidental predications. Aquinas is clear that, "when I say by including what Gareth Matthews has famously dubbed 'kooky objects' in their
"Man is white," the cause of the truth of this enunciation is the combining of 6° Nevertheless, I take Aquinas's hylomorphic account of truthmaking
whiteness with the subject".58 Elsewhere, he makes the same point, albeit more t:
° :t el°ygeYt.another example of how a hylomorphic ontology is remarkably fecund
subtly, "But the reasoning by which the affirmative enunciation, 'Man is worthy,' in its application to contemporary issues in metaphysics and thus deserves to be
is true, i.e., by some worthy man existing, is the same as the reasoning by which taken seriously as a viable metaphysic of material objects.
`Man is shameful' is true, i.e., by a shameful man existing".59
For Aquinas, the result of the combining of seatedness and Socrates is a nu_
merically distinct hylomorphic compound, seated-Socrates (what he calls an
BIBLIOGRAPHY
"accidental being" generally), whose matter is Socrates and accidental form is
seatedness. And, it is the existence of this numerically distinct accidental being, ADAMS, MARILYN McCofto. "Aristotle and the Sacrament of the Altar: A Crisis in Medieval
seated-Socrates, which is said to ground the truth of the accidental predication Theology". Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume (1991): 195-249.
(Socrates is seated). As a result, Aquinas is of the opinion that what enters into — Christ and Horrors. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006.
the truthmaking relation for accidental predications are not accidents alone (pace AQUINAS, THOMAS. Translated by Fathers of the English Dominican Province. London:
Scotus), but rather a distinct mereologically complex entity that is composed of Burns, Oates, and Washbourne 1912-36. Reprint, New York: Benziger Brothers 1947-48.
an accident and a substance. Reprint, New York: Christian Classics, 1981.
How does Aquinas's hylomorphic proposal fair as an explication of the truth- — Questiones Disputatae de Veritate: The Disputed Questions on Truth. Translated by Robert
makers for accidental predications? For one, accidental beings have the requi- W. Mulligan, SJ. Chicago: Henry Regnery Co., 1952.
site modal features such that their existence essentially (as opposed to rigidly)
— Sententia super Metaphysicam: Commentary on the Metaphysics of Aristotle. Translated by
necessitates the existence of each of their proper parts (in our example of seated- J. P. Rowan. Chicago: Regnery, 1964.
Socrates, the substance Socrates and the accidental form seatedness), thereby
— Sententia super Peri hermenias: Aristotle on Interpretation: Commentary by St. Thomas and
avoiding the objection from irrelevance.
Cajetan. Translated by J. T. Oesterle. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1962.
To help bring out the modal features of accidental beings qua hylomorphic
compounds, we can represent the essential and ontological priority of the parts —De Principiis Naturae: On the Principles of Nature. Translated by Timothy McDermott. In
Aquinas: Selected Philosophical Writings. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.
of these compounds as being governed by the following mereological principle:
necessarily, if any object x is part of an accidental being, y, then, it is part of the ARISTOTLE. The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation. Edited by J. Barnes.
essence of y that if y exists then x is a part of y. As an accidental being, seated- 2 vols. Bollingen Series. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1984.
Socrates exists and is what it is in virtue of the existence and essence of its proper BROWER, JEFFREY. "Simplicity and Aseity". The Oxford Handbook to Philosophical Theology.
parts, Socrates and seatedness. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009.
It is precisely because accidental beings exhibit these modal features that CORREIA, FABRICS. Existential Dependence and Cognate Notions. Philosophia Verlag, 2005.
the existence of seated-Socrates is said to essentially necessitate Socrates' being CROSS, RICHARD. The Metaphysics of the Incarnation: Thomas Aquinas to Duns Scotus. New York:
seated and not merely the co-existence of two, unrelated entities: Socrates and Oxford University Press, 2002.
seatedness. In so far as the essence of seated-Socrates - its very identity - involves — The Physics of Duns Scotus. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998.
reference to Socrates as modified by his inhering mode of seatedness, it follows that FINE, KIT. "Essence and Modality". In Philosophical Perspectives 8: Logic and Language, edited
the existence of seated-Socrates essentially necessitates Socrates' being seated by James E. Tomberlin, 1-16. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview, 1994.
and, ipso facto, the accidental truth of (Socrates is seated). Fox, JOHN. "Truthmaker". Australasian Journal of Philosophy 65 (1987): 188-207.
Aquinas's hylomorphic account of truthmaking for accidental predications
GORMAN, MICHAEL. "Ontological Priority and John Duns Scotus". The Philosophical Quarterly
will most likely find favour with those who are already favourably disposed 43 [173] (1993): 460-471.

58 THOMAS AQUINAS, Commentary on the Metaphysics of Aristotle IX, lect. 11, n. 1898. I owe
this and the following reference to PAWL, Thomistic Account of Truthmakers. 60 GARETH MATHEWS, "Accidental Unities", in Language and Logos, ed. M. Schofield and
59 THOMAS AQUINAS, Sententia super Peri hermenias I, lect. 11, n. 10. M. Nussbaum (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982).

88 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE • 89


Ross Inman
ESSENTIAL DEPENDENCE, TRUTHMAKING, AND MEREOLOGY: THEN AND Now

LOWE, E. J. The Four-Category Ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.


— "Two Notions of Being: Entity and Essence". Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 62
(2008): 23-48. D01:10.1017/51358246108000568.
LOWE, E. J. and RAM!, A. Truth and Truthmaking. Acumen Press, 2008.
MATTHEWS, GARETH. "Accidental Unities". In Language and Logos, edited by M. Schofield
SECTION III
and M. Nussbaum, 223-240. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982.
MELIA, JOSEPH. "Truthmaking Without Truthmakers". In Truthmakers: The Contemporary
Debate, edited by H. Beebee & J. Dodd, 67-84. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005.
ODERBERG, DAVID. Real Essentialism. London: Routledge, 2007.
PARSONS, JOSH. "There is No "Truthmaker" Argument Against Nominalism". Australasian
SUBSTANCE
Journal of Philosophy 77, no. 3 (1999): 325-334.
PASNAU, ROBERT. Metaphysical Themes 1274-1689. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011.
PAWL, TIM. A Thomistic Account of Truthmakers for Modal Truths. Doctoral dissertation, St
&
Louis University, 2008.
ScoTus, JOHN DUNS. Quaestiones Quodlibetales: God and Creatures: The Quodlibetal Questions,
Translated with an introduction, notes and glossary by Felix Alluntis and Allan B,
ACCIDENT
Wolter. Washington, D. C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1975.
— Quaestiones super libros Metaphysicorum A ristotelis: Questions on the Metaphysics of Aristotle
by John Duns Scotus. Edited by Girard J. Etzkorn and Allan B. Wolter OFM. St. Bona-
venture, NY: The Franciscan Institute, 1997-1998.
— De Primo Principio: John Duns Scotus, A Treatise on God as First Principle. Edited by Allan
B. Wolter. 2nd edition, revised with a commentary. Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press,
1983.
SIMONS, PETER. Parts: A Study in Ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987.

90 • METAPHYSICAL STRUCTURE
ESSENCE AND ONTOLOGY
E, J. Lowe

ABSTRACT
The aim of this paper is to show how, by combining a neo-Aristotelian account of essence
with a neo-Aristotelian four-category ontology (of individual substances, modes, substantial
universals, and property universals), a thoroughgoing metaphysical foundation for modal
truths can be provided - one which avoids any appeal to 'possible worlds' and which renders
modal truths objective, mind-independent, and yet also knowable.

1. ONTOLOGY
In Aristotle's mature ontological system, as presented in the Metaphysics, indi-
vidual substances are taken to be combinations of matter and form, with each
such substance being constituted by a particular parcel of matter embodying,
or organised by, a certain form. For example, an individual house has as its im-
mediate matter some bricks, mortar and timber, which are organised in a certain
distinctive way fit to serve the functions of a human dwelling. Similarly, an indi-
vidual horse has as its immediate matter some flesh, blood and bones, which are
organised in a certain distinctive way fit to sustain a certain kind of life, that
of a herbivorous quadruped. In each case, the 'matter' in question is not, or not
purely, 'prime' matter, but is already 'informed' in certain distinctive ways which
makes it suitable to receive the form of a house or a horse. Thus, bricks, mortar
and timber would not be matter suitable to receive the form of a horse, but at best
that of something like a statue of a horse. According to this view, the matter and
form of an individual substance are each 'incomplete' entities, completed by each
other in their union in that substance. But its form is essential to the substance,
unlike its matter, in the following sense: an individual house, say, cannot lose the
form of house without thereby ceasing to be, whereas - while it must always have
matter of an appropriate kind so long as it continues to be - it need not always
have the same matter of that kind. Individual bricks and timbers in a house may
be replaced without destroying the house - indeed, this may be the only way to
preserve a certain house - but once its bricks and timbers cease to be organised
in the form of a house, the house necessarily ceases to be.
Clearly, according to this hylomorphic Aristotelian picture, an individual
substance is a 'combination' of matter and form in a sense which rules out our

SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 93


E. J. Lowe E. J. Lowe
ESSENCE AND ONTOLOGY ESSENCE AND ONTOLOGY

thinking of its matter and form as being parts of the substance, at least in the these properties are 'cleterminables' rather than 'determinates', such as colour in
normal sense of 'part'. Here it might be objected that, for example, a brick in a the case of Dobbin, and then it is necessary that the substance should possess
house is a part of it in this familiar sense, and yet belongs to the 'matter' of the some determinate feature falling under the relevant determinable, but contingent
house: so can't we at least say that the matter of a house is a 'part' of it in this which feature this is. Such contingent determinate features are the substance's
sense? Not easily: for even if we were to concede that a brick is literally a part of accidents, which can obviously change over time compatibly with the continued
the house, all the matter of the house, considered collectively, can hardly be so existence of the substance. The overall picture, even in this relatively simplified
regarded. For the house coincides with its matter as a whole and hence, it appears, version of it, is quite complex, with an individual substance portrayed as having
that matter could not qualify as a proper part of house, as the brick might. Nor, a rich and in some respects temporally inconstant constituent structure of form,
however, can the matter qualify as an improper part of the house, in the standard matter, properties, and accidents, with form and properties remaining constant
sense, since that would make it identical with the house: and yet the house is while matter and accidents are subject to change.
clearly not identical with its matter, not least because its matter can change Hylomorphism certainly has many attractive aspects. But its core difficulty
while it persists. Equally, on the hylomorphist view, the house's form cannot be lies in its central doctrine - that every concrete object, or more precisely every
regarded as a part, either proper or improper, of the house, in the standard sense concrete individual substance, is a 'combination' of matter and form. For what,
of 'part'. Nothing forbids the hylomorphist from saying that, in some other sense really, are we to understand by 'combination' in this sense? Clearly, we are not
of the term, the matter and form of an individual substance are 'parts' of it, but supposed to think that combination in this sense just is, or is the result of,
saying this would at least not be very helpful, since it would invite confusion. It a 'putting together' of two mutually independent things, since matter and form
is better just to say that the matter and form are constituents, but not parts, of are supposed to be 'incomplete' items which complete each other in the substance
the substance. The key point is that, on this view, individual substances exhibit that combines them. Now, certainly, when some concrete things - such as some
`internal' ontological complexity, being combinations of 'incomplete' entities that bricks, timbers and quantities of mortar - are put together to make a new concrete
are completed by each other in the substance. object, such as a house, those things have to put together in the right sort of way,
So far, I have spoken a lot about forms, but not much about features, and how they not just haphazardly. But does this entitle us to suppose that the completed house
might be accommodated by the approach now under discussion. Very roughly, I is some sort of 'combination' of the things that have been put together and the way in
think that the answer should run somewhat as follows. The form of a substance which they have been put together? The challenge that the hylomorphist presents
constitutes its essence - what it is, its 'quiddity' - whereas its features, or 'qualities', us with is to explain why, if we do not say something like this, we are entitled to
are how it is. A horse is what Dobbin is, for example. If Dobbin is white, however, suppose that a new individual substance is brought into being. One presumption
that is partly how he is - a way that he is. I say 'partly' only to acknowledge that behind that challenge would seem to be that a substance can't simply be a so-
there are many other ways Dobbin is besides being white - such as being heavy called mereological sum of other substances - and with this I can agree, at least if
- and by no means intend to imply that Dobbin's whiteness is a part of Dobbin. by a `mereological sum' we mean an entity whose identity is determined solely
However, Dobbin's whiteness might nonetheless be thought to be a constituent of by the identities of its 'summands', rather as the identity of a set is determined
Dobbin, on this view, distinct from his form, which is equinity. And this might solely by the identities of its members. I agree that only when other substances
be maintained whether one thought of Dobbin's whiteness as being a particular have been put together in the right sort of way does a new substance of a certain
whiteness peculiar to him, or just the universal whiteness that he shares with kind come into being, the way in question depending on the kind in question.
other white substances. But how, then, are a substance's features related to its Moreover, I have no objection to the 'reification' of 'ways', understood as features
form? Some of its features, it seems, are necessitated by its form - such as warm- or forms, provided that we do not treat ways as substances - so here too I am in
bloodedness in the case of Dobbin - and these may be called, in the strictest agreement with the hylomorphist. Reification is not the same as hypostatisation,
sense of the term, the substance's properties. Other of its features, however, are but is merely the acknowledgement of some putative entity's real existence. What
`accidental', such as Dobbin's whiteness, which may therefore be denominated one I do not understand is what it means to say that the completed house's form - the
of his accidents. Even so, although Dobbin's whiteness is accidental, that Dobbin way in which its 'matter' is organised - is an 'incomplete' constituent of the house
has some colour is necessitated by his form and is thus essential to him. So we which 'combines' together with that equally 'incomplete' matter to constitute
arrive at the following picture: an individual substance possesses a certain form, the house, a complete substance. The words that particularly mystify me in
which constitutes its essence, from which 'flow' by necessity certain features of this sort of account are 'incomplete', 'combine' and 'constitute'. It's not that I do
the substance, which are its properties in the strictest sense of the term. Some of not understand these words perfectly well as they are commonly used in other

94 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 95


E. J. Lowe E. J. Lowe
ESSENCE AND ONTOLOGY ESSENCE AND ONTOLOGY

contexts, just that I do not understand their technical use in the hylomorphic 'matter' in this sense is not, as the hylomorphist takes it to be, some 'incomplete'
theory and, equally importantly, why a need should be felt for this use of such constituent of the atom that is completed by the atom's 'form'. In fact, I would
terms. prefer to abandon the term 'matter' altogether, as modern physics has done, at
If I could understand the supposed need to say something like this, then I would least as a fundamental theoretical term. Thus, although modern scientists talk,
make every possible effort to grasp the technical terminology. So let us remind for instance, of 'condensed matter physics', fundamental particle physicists do
ourselves why, allegedly, there is indeed such a need. As was just mentioned, the not nowadays speak of protons and electrons as having, or being composed of,
need supposedly arises in order to meet the challenge of explaining how a new matter - although they might happily speak of them as being 'packets of energy'
substance is brought into existence. The suggestion seems to be that, unless we and certainly as possessing mass.
can see the new substance as being a combination of items neither of which can The hylomorphist ontology described above is inspired by Aristotle, as modi-
exist independently of the other in just such a combination, rather than as merely fied perhaps by later thinkers such as Aquinas. But the basis of another kind of
being composed of other independently existing things each possessing their ontology can also be traced to Aristotle, this time to the Aristotle of his presumed
own features, we shall be unable to justify the judgement that a new concrete early work, the Categories.' The kind of ontology that I now have in mind is one
object - an 'addition of being' - really has been brought into existence, rather than whose key notions are briefly sketched in the opening passages of that work, be-
some previously existing things merely being rearranged. Put in this way, the fore the classificatory divisions commonly known as the Aristotelian 'categories'
supposed problem is one that is familiar from recent debates in metaphysics. Here, are set out later in the treatise. In those opening passages, Aristotle articulates
though, I would urge that some types of 'rearrangement' are ontologically more a fourfold ontological scheme in terms of the two technical notions of 'being said
weighty than others. When a free proton and a free electron are 'rearranged' of a subject' and 'being in a subject'. Primary substances - what we have hitherto
by increasing the distance between them from one mile to two miles, there is been calling 'individual' substances - are described as being neither said of a sub-
no reason at all to suppose that a new concrete object is brought into existence. ject nor in a subject. Secondary substances - the species and genera to which primary
But when they are 'rearranged' so that the electron is captured by the proton substances belong - are described as being said of a subject but not in a subject.
and occupies an orbital around it, then indeed we have a new concrete object of That leaves two other classes of items: those that are both said of a subject and in
a very different kind: a hydrogen atom. This object has certain features, notably a subject, and those that are not said of a subject but are in a subject. Since these
certain powers, which are quite different from those of protons and electrons and two classes receive no official names and have been variously denominated over
quite different, too, from those of a mereological sum of a free proton and a free the centuries, I propose to call them, respectively, attributes and modes. It seems
electron. In the newly created hydrogen atom, the proton remains exactly what that secondary substances and attributes are conceived to be different types of
it was before, just a proton, and the electron remains just an electron. A new form universal, while primary substances and modes are conceived to be different types
is instantiated - one that is possessed neither by the proton nor by the electron of particular. Since the Aristotelian terminology of 'being said of and 'being in'
- namely, the form of a hydrogen atom. This form is the form of the newly created is perhaps less than fully perspicuous, with the former suggesting a linguistic
object, the atom, not that of the proton or the electron, nor even of the pair of relation and the latter seemingly having only a metaphorical sense, I prefer to use
them. The form does not, in any sense that I can understand, 'combine' with the a different terminology: that of instantiation and characterisation. Thus, I say that
proton and the electron so as to constitute, together with them, the atom. The attributes and modes are characterising entities, whereas primary and secondary
only things that do any 'combining' are the proton and the electron, when the former substances are characterisable entities. And I say that secondary substances and
captures the latter and the latter occupies an orbital around the former. And attributes are instantiable entities, whereas primary substances and modes are
the only things that constitute the atom are, again, the proton and the electron, instantiating entities. These terminological niceties, which though necessary are
which are its parts, in the perfectly familiar sense of 'part'. So, as can be seen, I am apt to prove confusing, are most conveniently laid out in diagrammatic form,
perfectly happy to describe the case of the newly created hydrogen atom in terms using the familiar device known as the Ontological Square. I present it below.'
of 'combination' and 'constitution', and indeed in terms of 'form'. It's just that I do
not need, and do not understand, the 'logical grammar' of the hylomorphist who
uses these terms in his own distinctively technical fashion. Furthermore, I have ' See ARISTOTLE, Categories and De Interpretatione, trans. J. L. Ackrill (Oxford: Oxford
no serious need for the hylomorphist's category of matter. I might be prepared to University Press, 1963).
say that the 'matter' of the hydrogen atom is or consists of its proton and electron, For a much fuller account, see my The Four-Category Ontology: A Metaphysical Foundation for
but just in the sense that these are its parts and serve to compose it. But the atom's Natural Science (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006).

96 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 97


E.J. Lowe E. J. Lowe
ESSENCE AND ONTOLOGY ESSENCE AND ONTOLOGY

In my own version of the Ontological Square, I prefer to use the terms 'object' as a head and limbs, but in no sense is he a 'combination' of anything material
and 'kind' in place of the more cumbersome 'primary substance' and 'secondary a nd the universal form in question. What I am saying, then, is that individual
substance'. I also include a 'diagonal' relationship between objects and attributes, objects or primary substances are nothing other than particular forms, or form-
which is distinct from both instantiation and characterisation, calling this, as particulars - particular instances of universal forms, in precisely the same sense
seems appropriate, exemplification. Here is my version: in which modes (or 'tropes', as they are now often called) are particular instances
of a ttributes. A crucial question that now arises is whether the four-category
ontology is, like the hylomorphic ontology, a constituent ontology or whether,
characterised by rather, it is a relational ontology.' The answer that I want to defend is that it is neither
- and that this is very much to its credit. At first sight, it might seem that the four-
category ontology must be a relational ontology, since the Ontological Square
instantiated by exemplified by instantiated by apparently depicts three relations supposedly holding between entities in different
categories of the system: the instantiation relation between objects and kinds and
between modes and attributes, the characterisation relation between attributes and
kinds and between modes and objects, and the exemplification relation between
characterised by objects and attributes. However, if the system includes such relations amongst
the entities whose existence it acknowledges, those entities must find a place in
one or other of the system's four fundamental categories. There seem to be only
I call the four classes of entities depicted here ontological categories, albeit with two that could possibly house them: the category of attributes and the category
a cautionary note that these are not to be confused with, even though they are not of modes. That is to say, the relations in question would have to be categorised as
unrelated to, Aristotle's own list of 'categories' later in his treatise. More precisely, being either relational attributes or relational modes. In fact, they would have to be
I regard these four as the fundamental ontological categories, allowing that within classified in both of these ways, in the following sense: since the theory maintains
each there may be various sub-categories, sub-sub-categories, and so on. that every attribute is instantiated by modes and that every mode instantiates
How exactly are the two 'Aristotelian' systems of ontology related to one an attribute - because to this extent, at least, the theory is 'immanentist' where
another? Unsurprisingly, they overlap in many respects, but one key respect in universals are concerned - it would have to maintain that there are relational
which they obviously differ is that the four-category ontology, as I call it, unlike the instantiation, characterisation and exemplification modes which instantiate cor-
hylomorphic ontology, does not include the category of matter. It might be thought responding relational attributes. But this really makes no sense on the system's
that it also lacks the category of form, but that is not in fact so. For I believe that own terms. Consider, for instance, the case of the characterisation of an object
form, conceived as a type of universal, and more perspicuously termed substantial by a mode: for example, Dobbin's particular whiteness's being a characteristic
form, is really nothing other than secondary substance or substantial kind. We of Dobbin. As this example illustrates, characterisation is supposed to 'obtain'
may refer to such universal forms either by using certain abstract nouns, such as between entities in the category of modes and entities in the category of objects.
'humanity' and 'equinity', or else by using certain substantival nouns - what Locke This is so even if there are relational modes, such as, perhaps, a loving mode that
called `sortal' terms - such as 'man' and 'horse'. I believe that this is a grammatical characterises John and Mary. What there cannot be is a relational mode that
distinction which fails to reflect any real ontological difference. However, if that characterises an object and a mode. Moreover, if we supposed that there could
is so, then there is a very important ontological consequence. This is that primary be, we would immediately be faced with the threat of an infinite regress, of the
substances, or individual concrete objects, 'have' forms only and precisely in sort that F. H. Bradley famously described. For if it were the case that, in order for
the sense that they are particular instances of forms. Thus Dobbin is a particular mode M to characterise object 0, a relational characterisation mode, Mc had to
instance of the substantial kind or form horse, whereas Dobbin's whiteness is a par- characterise M and 0, then by the same token another relational characterisation
ticular instance of the colour universal or attribute whiteness. By this account, it mode, M", would have to characterise M', M and 0 - and so on ad infinitum. Here
makes no sense at all to say that Dobbin is a 'combination' of the form horse and it may be responded that this is just so much the worse for the four-category
some 'matter'. He is, to repeat, just a particular instance of that form, other such
instances being the various other particular horses that exist or have existed. ' For more on this distinction between 'constituent' and 'relational' ontologies, see
Being an instance of this form, Dobbin must certainly have material parts, such NICHOLAS WOLTERSTORFF, "Bergmann's Constituent Ontology", Nous 4, no. 2 (1970): 109-134.

98 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 99


E. J. Lowe E. J. Lowe
ESSENCE AND ONTOLOGY ESSENCE AND ONTOLOGY

ontology and simply demonstrates its inadequacy or even its incoherence. But that we need to maintain is that an object necessarily instantiates its kind and that
that would be far too rash a conclusion, for the system certainly has the resources a mode necessarily instantiates its attribute, both of which claims are prima facie
with which to dissolve the apparent difficulty, as we shall now see. highly plausible. It is surely part of the essence of a whiteness mode, for instance,
An important distinction is commonly made between internal and external that it is an instance of the universal whiteness. Similarly, it is very plausibly part
relations, the idea being that an internal relation holds of necessity between of the essence of a particular horse, Dobbin, that he is an instance of the kind horse.
its terms or relata, in virtue of their intrinsic features or natures, whereas an Ana logous points can be made regarding characterisation. It is surely part of the
external relation may hold or fail to hold between its relata irrespective of their essence of Dobbin's whiteness mode that it characterises Dobbin: for that mode
intrinsic features or natures. For instance, spatial relations between objects are depends for its very identity on its being Dobbin's, and could not possibly 'migrate' to
commonly supposed to be external, because it seems that the distance between another object, much less continue to exist in Dobbin's absence (any more than
two objects could be altered without affecting in any way the intrinsic features the Cheshire Cat's grin could continue to exist without the cat). This leaves us
or natures of those objects. By contrast, resemblance seems intelligible only when only with characterisation as a 'relation' between attributes and kinds. But what
conceived as being an internal relation. For example, that red resembles orange, i have in mind in speaking in these terms are precisely certain essential connexions
and indeed that it resembles orange more closely than it resembles yellow, seem between attributes and kinds, which are normally expressed in the language of
to be necessary truths that depend solely on the intrinsic natures of the colours natural law. We say, for instance, that electrons are negatively charged particles, thus
in question. But to talk of there being - that is, of there existing - internal relations expressing an essential connexion between the kind electron and the attribute
in cases like these is to indulge in unnecessary reification. We can put the point negative charge. Electrons, as a natural kind, have certain essential characteristics,
in this way: while there may be relational truths to be recognised in such cases of which negative charge - or, more exactly, unit negative charge - is one. To put it
(truths whose logical form is relational) - such as the truth that red resembles another way, in no possible world are there electrons which lack negative charge.
orange - there need not be relational truthmakers of those truths. Understanding A world which contained particles exactly similar to electrons in every respect
a truthmaker of a given proposition to be, at the very least, an entity (or plurality save that they were neutral, say, would not be a world containing neutral electrons.
of entities) whose existence necessitates the truth of that proposition, we can see Kinds depend for their very identity on their essential characteristics, just as modes
that the truthmaker of the proposition that red resembles orange is quite simply depend for their very identity on their objects or 'bearers'. Consequently, the
the colours red and orange themselves. For, in the language of possible worlds, in every characterisation 'relation' between attributes and kinds is an internal one and
world in which those colours exist, the proposition that red resembles orange is true. We do so 'no addition of being'. I concede that in saying all this I am glossing over
not need to invoke, as a putative truthmaker of this proposition, or even as part of certain complications which would need to be accommodated by a more detailed
any such truthmaker, a relation of partial or imperfect resemblance between red account, but I think that these complications raise no real difficulties for the sort
and orange, conceived as an entity additional to red and orange themselves' The of approach that I am now recommending. For instance, one difficulty might
lesson is that, while it might be convenient to talk of 'internal relations', we should be thought to be that the exact numerical value of the negative charge on the
not suppose that in so talking we are talking of really existing entities of a relational electron is arguably not a necessary feature of the electron, even if it necessarily
nature, such as relational attributes or modes. Consequently, if the four-category possesses unit negative charge: for the 'size' of this unit might conceivably differ
ontology can fairly represent instantiation, characterisation and exemplification being in different possible worlds. But then the proper response to this might just be
internal relations, it can avoid serious ontological commitment to them as entities to say that that value is not an essential characteristic of electrons and universally
to be included in one or other of its ontological categories and thereby avoid the characterises all particular electrons in the actual world for some reason that
threatened Bradleian regress, while at the same time escaping classification as is extrinsic to their nature as electrons - a reason to do, say, with some global
a relational ontology. property of space in this world.
Now, the three 'relations' in question most plausibly are internal, or at least I now pass on to the slightly more complicated case of exemplification. It
explicable in internalist terms. I make this latter qualification to accommodate seems clear that we can't simply say that exemplification, like instantiation and
the 'relation' of exemplification. That instantiation and characterisation are characterisation, is an 'internal' relation, because which attributes an object
internal relations is relatively easy to argue for. In the case of instantiation, all exemplifies can be a contingent matter. Dobbin, for example, is white, but could
perhaps instead have been brown. This is unlike the truth that Dobbin is warm-
' For more on truthmaking, see E. J. LOWE and ADOLF RAMC, eds., Truth and Truth-Making blooded, which is plausibly necessary, at least in a qualified sense that will be ex-
(Stocksfield: Acumen, 2009). plained below. However, what we can say is the following. Dobbin is white in

100 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 101


E. J. Lowe E. J. Lowe
ESSENCE AND ONTOLOGY ESSENCE AND ONTOLOGY

virtue of being characterised by a certain whiteness mode, call it W. Now, it is part which belong to ontological categories other than the category of object itself.
of the essence of W that it characterises Dobbin, since W depends for its identity The bylomorphic ontology is clearly a constituent ontology in this sense, since it
on Dobbin. Equally, it is part of the essence of w that it instantiates the attribute ma intains that objects, or individual substances, are `combinations' of matter and
whiteness. Hence, in any possible world in which W exists, W instantiates whiteness for m, where neither matter nor form is conceived to be an entity belonging to the
and characterises Dobbin, whence it follows that in any such world it is true that category of individual substance. Now, if the four-category ontology were fairly to
Dobbin is white, since he is characterised by a whiteness mode in that world. Thus be classified as a constituent ontology, what could it be taken to regard as being
W is a truthmaker of the proposition that Dobbin is white, as indeed would be any the `constituents' of objects, in the sense now relevant? Clearly, there are only
whiteness mode of Dobbin. But the proposition that Dobbin is white simply affirms three candidates, since there are only three other ontological categories for these
that Dobbin exemplifies whiteness. Hence, we can explain truths of exemplification putative constituents to be drawn from - kinds, attributes, and modes. However,
like this without invoking the existence of an exemplification relation. As for the even without examining the case of each in detail, it seems clear from what has
contingency of the truth that Dobbin is white, this simply arises from two facts: already been said about instantiation, exemplification, and characterisation -
first, that any whiteness mode of Dobbin's, such as W, is itself a contingent being, the three key `relations' that `relate' objects to entities of each of these other
and second that the ontological dependence between any such mode and Dobbin categories respectively - that they are not `constitutive' or `combinative' in
is asymmetrical. Such a mode does not exist in every possible world, and there nature. If any of them were, the consequence would be that the four-category
are possible worlds in which Dobbin exists but no such mode exists. By contrast, ontology is committed to some version of the bundle theory of objects - and yet
the reason why Dobbin is necessarily warm-blooded is that Dobbin instantiates the it is most emphatically not.
kind horse, and warm-bloodedness is an essential characteristic of that kind. Take the case of modes, for instance. The proper thing for a four-category
Here the truthmaker for the truth that Dobbin is warm-blooded is just Dobbin ontologist to say about modes, I believe, is that they are `abstractions' from objects,
himself: for in any possible world in which Dobbin exists, he instantiates the not constituents of them, for this explains their identity-dependence on their
kind horse and that kind is characterised by the attribute warm-bloodedness. This objects. Identity-dependence is not only an asymmetric relation of ontological
truth of exemplification is, then, a necessary truth: not in the unqualified sense dependence: it also implies ontological priority on the part of the entity depended
that it obtains in every possible world whatsoever, but in the qualified sense upon, with respect to the dependent entity. And this is precisely in accordance
that it obtains in every possible world in which Dobbin exists. It is an essential with the Aristotelian spirit of the four-category ontology, according to which
truth about Dobbin, whereas the truth that Dobbin is white is not. In short, we individual substances - objects, as we are calling them - have ultimate ontological
can explain all truths of exemplification, and explain too their modal status, priority over entities in any of the other three categories. I suggest, then, that
whether they be contingent or necessary, without invoking the existence of any within the four-category ontology we need to regard modes as being `aspects' of
relation of exemplification, but simply by appealing to the `internal' relations of objects, to which we can attend selectively in thought or perception, by means of
instantiation and characterisation, together with the truthmaking roles of objects what Locke called a `partial consideration'. These aspects explain the differential
and modes. For this reason, I maintain that the four-category ontology cannot behaviour of different objects: for instance, why some objects roll down an inclined
fairly be classified as being a relational ontology. plane while others do not - the former being spherical or cylindrical, the latter not.
I turn now, more briefly, to the question of whether the four-category on- But it is, after all, the whole object that rolls, not its sphericity or cylindricality. Nor
tology can instead fairly be classified as a constituent ontology. I take it to be a does it make much sense to suppose that its sphericity or cylindricality `drags
necessary feature of any such ontology that objects are regarded by it as pos- along' the object's other modes with it, and thereby makes the object as whole
sessing significant ontological structure, where this does not involve their mere move. To think in such terms is illicitly to hypostatise modes, treating them as
composition by other objects in at least some cases. That is to say, the mere fact that simple substances within an object, rather than just as particular `ways' an object
an ontology takes at least some objects not to be simple, in the sense of allowing is. I conclude that the four-category ontology, properly understood, has to be
that they possess other objects as parts, is not sufficient for it to be classified as being excluded both from the class of relational ontologies and from that of constituent
a constituent ontology - not even if the ontology allows that one object may be ontologies. Attempts to force it into either of these camps simply turn it into some
constituted by another, distinct object (for instance, a bronze statue by a lump of other kind of ontology altogether.
bronze), both of which are composed of the same parts at the time of constitution. It cannot have escaped notice that, in setting out and defending the four-
Rather, what is crucial for an ontology to qualify as `constituent' is that it should category ontology, I have frequently used modal notions, such as those of necessity
maintain that objects have an ontological structure involving `constituents and possibility, and also the notion of essence. In the remainder of this paper,

102 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 103


E. J. Lowe E. J. Lowe
ESSENCE AND ONTOLOGY ESSENCE AND ONTOLOGY

therefore, I shall try to explain and defend my usage, which is once more inspired as a proposition which tells us, in the most perspicuous fashion, what E is — or,
by the work of Aristotle. more broadly, since we do not want to restrict ourselves solely to the essences
of actually existing things, what E is or would be. This is perfectly in line with the
2. ESSENCE original Aristotelian understanding of the notion of essence, for the Latin-based
Currently dominant accounts of the traditional metaphysical distinction word 'essence' is just the standard translation of a phrase of Aristotle's which is
between essence and accident attempt to explain it in modal terms, and more more literally translated into English as 'the what it is to be' or 'the what it would
specifically in terms of the notions of metaphysical necessity and possibility. be to be'. We find a similar turn of phrase in Locke's Essay, where he tells us that
These in turn are commonly explicated in terms of the language of 'possible the word 'essence', in what he calls its 'proper original signification' just means
worlds'. Thus, a property F is said to be an essential property of an object a just in the very being of any thing, whereby it is, what it is'.6
case, in every possible world in which a exists, a is F. And a's essence is then said to It will be helpful at this point to proceed by way of examples, the first of
consist in the set or sum of a's essential properties. One difficulty of this approach, which I borrow from Spinoza' Consider a familiar geometrical figure, such as a
brought to our notice by the work of Kit Fine, is that it seems grossly to over- circle. And suppose that someone asks us what a circle is. This can be understood
generate essential properties.' For instance, by this account, one of Socrates's as a request for a real definition of this kind of geometrical figure - not a request
essential properties is his property of being either a man or a mouse and another for the meaning of the English word 'circle', for which we would do well to resort
is his property of being such that 2 + 2 = 4. It might be objected that these are not simply to a good English dictionary. And here, plausibly, is the real definition
genuine properties anyway and so a fortiori not essential properties of Socrates. that is required - one that will typically be found in textbooks of elementary
But there are other examples which cannot be objected to on these grounds, geometry:
such as Socrates's property of being the sole member of the set singleton Socrates,
that is, the set {Socrates} whose sole member is Socrates. Fine urges, plausibly, (C') A circle is the locus of a point moving continuously in a plane at a fixed
that it is not part of Socrates's essence that he belongs to this set, although it is distance from a given point.
plausibly the case that it is part of the essence of singleton Socrates that Socrates
is its sole member. The modal account of essence cannot, it seems, accommodate The 'given point' here is, of course, the circle's centre. This formula or recipe
this asymmetry. These points are too well-known for it to be necessary for me to tells us what a circle is, and it does so by revealing its generating principle - what it
dwell on them further. Suffice it to say that I am persuaded by Fine's objections takes for there to be or, more exactly, for there to come into being, a circle.
to the modal account of essence and accept the lesson that he draws: that it is Here is another geometrical example:
preferable to try to explicate the notions of metaphysical necessity and possibility
in terms of the notion of essence, rather than vice versa. This may also enable (E') An ellipse is the locus of a point moving continuously in a plane in
us to dispense with the language of possible worlds as a means of explicating such a fashion that the sum of the distances between it and two other
modal statements. That would be a good thing, in my view, since I regard this fixed points remains constant.
language as being fraught with ontological difficulties, even if it can sometimes
have a heuristic value. These 'fixed points' are the ellipse's foci. By contrast, consider this alternative
However, if we are to take this alternative line of approach, we need, of description of an ellipse (as a type of conic section), which is equally true of all
course, to provide a perspicuous account of the notion of essence which does ellipses:
not seek to explicate it in modal terms. Fortunately, we do have at our disposal
some resources wherewith to accomplish this, drawing on the Aristotelian and (E2) An ellipse is the closed curve of intersection between a cone and
Scholastic traditions in metaphysics. A key notion here, pointed out and exploited a plane cutting it at an oblique angle to its axis greater than that of
by Fine himself, is that of a real definition, understood as being a definition of the cone's side.
a thing (a res, or entity), in contradistinction to a verbal definition, which is a
definition of a word or phrase. A real definition of an entity, E, is to be understood 6 See John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1975), III, III, 15.
5 See KIT FINE, "Essence and Modality", in Philosophical Perspectives 8: Logic and Language, ' See Benedict de Spinoza, On the Improvement of the Understanding, Ethics, Correspondence,
ed. James E. Tomberlin (Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview, 1994). trans. R. H. M. Elwes (New York: Dover, 1955), 35.

104 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 105


E. J. Lowe E. J. Lowe
ESSENCE AND ONTOLOGY ESSENCE AND ONTOLOGY

This, I suggest, tells us a necessary property of all ellipses, but not the essence included in its essence. Thus, for instance, since the essence of an ellipse is that
of an ellipse - what an ellipse is. For it does not capture an ellipse's generating it is the locus of a point moving continuously in a plane in such a fashion that the sum of
principle. It characterises an ellipse in terms that are extrinsic to its nature as the distances between it and two other fixed points remains constant, and having foci a
the particular kind of geometrical figure that it is. Certainly, one can make an certain distance apart is properly included in this essence, it is part of the essence
elliptically shaped surface by cutting a cone in the prescribed fashion, but this of an ellipse that it has foci a certain distance apart - but this is obviously not the
procedure does not really explain why it is that what is so produced is an ellipse. whole essence of an ellipse, since it is also a part of the essence of an ellipse that
On the other hand, once we understand what an ellipse is, by learning its real the sum of the distances between its foci and any point on the ellipse is constant.
definition, we can go on to understand why it is that the cutting procedure in consider now a metaphysically necessary truth such as the fact that an ellipse is
question generates an ellipse, as opposed to any other kind of geometrical figure. the closed curve of intersection between a cone and a plane cutting it at an oblique angle
The reverse does not seem to hold: taking an ellipse to be the shape we get when to its axis greater than that of the cone's side. It is not part of the essence of any ellipse
we cut a cone in the prescribed fashion does not help us to understand why an that this condition holds, nor is part of the essence of any cone that it does. What
ellipse is the locus of a point moving continuously in a plane in such a fashion it is very plausible to contend, however, is that this metaphysically necessary
that the sum of the distances between it and two other fixed points remains truth holds in virtue of the essences of an ellipse and a cone, respectively. It is
constant. because of what an ellipse is, and what a cone is, that this relationship necessarily
So, at least, I suggest. The necessary property of all ellipses that I have just holds between ellipses and cones. But it is not part of anything's essence that it holds.
identified - that of being a closed curve of intersection between a cone and a plane For ellipses and cones, which are the only things whose essences have a role to
cutting it at an oblique angle to its axis greater than that of the cone's side - holds play in explaining why this necessary truth holds, are quite different things. Nor
of all ellipses not purely in virtue of their essence, but at least partly in virtue of is there any such thing as a 'cone-ellipse', part of whose essence it could be that
the essence of a quite different kind of geometrical object, a cone. That is what this truth obtains. Our proposal concerning metaphysically necessary truths is,
I mean by saying that to characterise an ellipse in terms of this property is to then, this: a metaphysically necessary truth is a truth which is either an essential
characterise it in terms that are extrinsic to its nature as the particular kind of truth or else a truth that obtains in virtue of the essences of two or more distinct
geometrical figure that it is. Here is another way of making this point: an ellipse things. On this account, all metaphysical necessity (and by the same token all
can exist even in a purely two-dimensional space, but a cone can exist only in a metaphysical possibility) is grounded in essence.
space of at least three dimensions - hence it can't be right to define an ellipse in A concern that might be raised here is that our example of ellipses and
terms of its relationship to a cone, since ellipses can exist perfectly well without cones concerns geometrical objects, rather than material ones - for it might be
cones. Yet another way of making the same point is the following: an ellipse suspected that our account cannot easily be extended to cover the latter. I think
evidently does not depend for its identity on any cone of which it may happen to this concern is unfounded. Consider instead, for instance, material objects of
be a section, but it does depend for its identity on the distances between its foci the following two kinds: a bronze statue and a lump of bronze. I would urge that it
and the sum of the distances between them and any point on the ellipse. is a metaphysically necessary truth, obtaining in virtue of the essences of such
As I intimated earlier, the view of essence and real definition that I have objects - obtaining, that is to say, in virtue of what a bronze statue is and what
just been articulating is one with a lengthy philosophical pedigree. We find it, a lump of bronze is - that at any time at which it exists a bronze statue coincides
for instance, in Spinoza's On the Improvement of the Understanding, where indeed with a lump of bronze, which is numerically distinct from that statue. Likewise, it
he uses the example of a circle with which I began. Now, any essential truth is is a metaphysical possibility, again obtaining in virtue of the essences of such
ipso facto a metaphysically necessary truth, although not vice versa: there can be objects, that the same bronze statue should coincide with different lumps of bronze
metaphysically necessary truths that aren't essential truths - understanding an at different times. And I say this despite the protestations of some metaphysicians
essential truth to be a truth concerning the essence of some entity. If we can truly that they do not understand how such things can be the case - how, for instance,
affirm that it is part of the essence of some entity, E, that p is the case, then p is two numerically distinct things, one of them a bronze statue and the other a lump
an essential truth and so a metaphysically necessary truth. Thus, for example, of bronze, can be composed of exactly the same bronze particles at one and the
it is part of the essence of a certain ellipse, E, that its foci are a certain distance same time. If they genuinely do not understand this, then I say that they have not
apart, whence it follows that it is metaphysically necessary that E's foci are that properly grasped what a bronze statue is or what a lump of bronze is. For in grasping
distance apart. By something's being a 'part of the essence' of a certain entity, those essences they would grasp what the identity and persistence conditions of
I just mean that it either is the whole essence of that entity or else is properly such objects are, and thereby know that these are different and that in virtue of

106 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 107


E. J. Lowe E.J. Lowe
ESSENCE AND ONTOLOGY ESSENCE AND ONTOLOGY

these different identity and persistence conditions the truths that they purport he is thinking about in order to be able to think about it. For, on this account,
not to understand are indeed truths. a thinker need not grasp the 'sense' of some referring expression in order to be
It will be recalled that, according to the currently prevailing modal account of able to refer successfully by means of such an expression to its referent: rather,
essence, an entity's essence consists in the set or sum of its essential properties, reference is supposedly secured by a causal connexion between the expression
these being the properties that it possesses in every possible world in which it and the thing referred to. This is not the place for me to enter into a full-scale
exists. Hence, according to this view, an entity's essence is a further entity, namely, debate about theories of reference. I would only urge that, even if the causal
a set or sum of certain properties. According to my version of the neo-Aristotelian approach accommodates some of our referential practices, it does not make sense
account of essence, however, an entity's essence is not some further entity.8 Rather, to suppose that, for successful reference to occur, no one need ever know what it
an entity's essence is just what that entity is, as revealed by its real definition. But is that they are thinking about. It suffices for my purposes that at least sometimes
what E is is not some entity distinct from E. It is either identical with E (and some a thinker must be able to know this.
scholars think that this was Aristotle's view) or else it is no entity at all: and the Here another objection may be raised, as follows. Sometimes, it may be con-
latter is my own view. On my view, we can quite properly say that it is part of the ceded, we have a concept of what it is that we are thinking about: but that is
essence of a certain entity, E, that it possesses a certain property, P. But this does all, and we cannot be entitled ever to suppose that anything actually falls under
not entitle us to say that P is a part of the essence of E. The latter would imply that that concept. For instance, we might have the concept of a table, and believe
E's essence is a further entity, with P as a part, which accords with the orthodox that we are thinking about such a thing: but for all that, it might well be that in
view that E's essence is a set or sum of certain properties. But I have rejected reality there are no tables, and hence no table for us to be thinking about. But let us
that view. We should not, in my opinion, reify essences. And although I speak reflect for a moment on what concepts are. And note that in thus reflecting we are
of essences as having 'parts', I have already explained what I mean by this, in a considering the essence of a concept: what a concept is. I propose that a concept is
way that does not require us to reify essences. Note that there is a particularly away of thinking of some thing or kind of things. But ways of thinking of things can be
objectionable feature of the view that an entity's essence is some further entity. more or less adequate to the nature of the things in question - that is, more or less
This is that, since it seems proper to say that every entity has an essence, the adequate reflections of their essence. A child's way of thinking of a triangle is less
view generates an infinite regress of essences. Neither the view that an entity is adequate than that of an experienced geometer. A concept of an entity E is fully
identical with its own essence, nor my preferred view that an entity's essence is adequate only if it captures the whole essence of E. Now, I concede that a thinker
not an entity at all, has this defect. And my view, as we shall shortly see, has an may be able to think of some entity without fully grasping its whole essence, and
additional advantage when we come to consider the epistemology of essence, that this is no doubt the case with the child's thought about triangles. But I see no
is, the proper account of our knowledge of essence. reason to suppose that we may never fully grasp the whole essence of a certain
Given that all metaphysical modality is grounded in essence, we can have kind of entity. Bear in mind, too, that we want to allow that we can grasp the
knowledge of metaphysical modality if we can have knowledge of essence. Can essences not only of actually existing things, but also, at least sometimes, of non-
we? Most assuredly we can. We have already seen this in the case of geometrical existent things - things such as unicorns and mermaids, perhaps. So I can happily
figures, such as an ellipse. Knowing an entity's essence is simply knowing what that allow that sometimes, in thinking about something, we succeed in grasping its
entity is. And at least in the case of some entities, we must be able to know what they essence and hence in thinking about it, even though no such thing actually exists.
are, because otherwise it would be hard to see how we could know anything at all I know, for instance, what a table is or would be, and hence grasp the essence of
about them. How, for example, could I know that a certain ellipse had a certain such a thing and can thereby think about tables: but this does not commit me to
eccentricity, if I did not know what an ellipse is? In order to think comprehendingly acknowledging the actual existence of tables. I might be open to persuasion, by
about something, I surely need to know what it is that I am thinking about. And a suitably ingenious philosopher, that tables do not really exist. But if I am even to
sometimes, at least, we surely succeed in thinking comprehendingly about some- be able to understand what such a philosopher is contending, I must know what
thing - for if we do not, then we surely never succeed in thinking at all, which a table is or would be — what its essence is. Otherwise, I do not really know what it is
is absurd. Here it may be objected that currently prevailing causal or 'direct' whose actual existence the philosopher is denying, when s/he denies that tables
theories of reference precisely deny that a thinker must know what it is that s/ actually exist. However, only a global sceptic is going to affirm that nothing that
we can think about actually exists, including even ourselves and our thoughts. And
See further my "Two Notions of Being: Entity and Essence", in Being: Developments in such an all-embracing scepticism is self-undermining and incoherent. So I find
Contemporary Metaphysics, ed. Robin Le Poidevin (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008). nothing in the present line of attack to suggest that I am wrong in supposing that

108 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 109


E.J. Lowe E.J. Lowe
ESSENCE AND ONTOLOGY ESSENCE AND ONTOLOGY

we can, at least sometimes, grasp the essences of at least some things - including BIBLIOGRAPHY
some actually existing things - and thereby come to know some modal truths.
ARISTOTLE. Categories and De Interpretatione, trans. J. L. Ackrill. Oxford: Oxford University
I mentioned earlier that, according to my account of essence, essences are
not entities. This means that grasping an essence - knowing what something is press, E nce and Modality". In Philosophical Perspectives 8: Logic and Language, edited
6s3e:
:E KIT, "Essence
- is not, by my account, a kind of knowledge by acquaintance of a special kind of Tomberlin, 1-16. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview, 1994.
entity, the thing in question's essence. All that grasping an essence amounts to,
L1:19
F10 HN.
JOHN. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, edited by P. H. Nidditch. Oxford:
on my view, is understanding a real definition, that is, understanding a special kind
Oxford University Press, 1975.
of proposition. To know what a circle is, for instance, I need to understand that
a circle is the locus of a point moving in a plane at a fixed distance from a given point. LOWE, E.J. The Four-Category Ontology: A Metaphysical Foundation for Natural Science. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2006.
Provided that I understand what a point and a plane are, and what motion and
"Two Notions of Being: Entity and Essence". In Being: Developments in Contemporary
distance are, I can understand what a circle is, by grasping this real definition,
Metaphysics, edited by Robin Le Poidevin. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
And bear in mind that I do not insist that we need fully grasp the whole essence
of a thing in order to be able to think about it to some degree adequately, so
that even if I do not fully grasp what motion, say, is, I can still achieve at least a Low2E0,0E8..J. and RAM I, ADOLF, eds. Truth and Truth-Making. Stocksfield: Acumen, 2009.
partial grasp of what a circle is by means of the foregoing real definition. If, by SPINOZA, BENEDICT DE. On the Improvement of the Understanding, Ethics, Correspondence,
contrast, knowledge of essence were knowledge by acquaintance of a special kind translated by R. H. M. Elwes. New York: Dover, 1955.
of entity, then indeed we would have cause to be doubtful about our ability ever WOLTERSTORFF, NICHOLAS. "Bergmann's Constituent Ontology". Noels 4 (1970): 109-134.
to grasp the essences of things. For what mental faculty of ours could possibly
be involved in this special kind of acquaintance? Surely not our faculty of sense
perception. Sense perception may provide us with knowledge by acquaintance of
concrete, physical things, existing in space and time, but hardly with knowledge
of their essences, conceived as further entities somehow grounding modal truths
about those concrete things. If appeal is instead made to some special intellectual
faculty of 'insight' or 'intuition', with essences as its special objects, then one is
open to the charge of anti-naturalistic obscurantism. My own account of what it
is to grasp an essence appeals only to an intellectual ability that, by any account,
we must already be acknowledged to possess: the ability to understand at least
some propositions, including those that express real definitions.
We now have in place the basic ingredients for a thoroughgoing epistemology
of metaphysical modality. Put simply, the theory is this. Metaphysical modalities
are grounded in essence. That is, all truths about what is metaphysically necessary
or possible are either straightforwardly essential truths or else obtain in virtue of
the essences of things. An essence is what is expressed by a real definition. And it
is part of our essence as rational, thinking beings that we can at least sometimes
understand a real definition - which is just a special kind of proposition - and
thereby grasp the essences of at least some things. Hence, we can know at least
sometimes that something is metaphysically necessary or possible: we can have
some knowledge of metaphysical modality. This itself is a modal truth, of course, and
one that obtains in virtue of our essence as rational, thinking beings. And since
we can, it seems clear, grasp our own essence - at least sufficiently well to know
the foregoing modal truth about ourselves - we know that we can have some know-
ledge of metaphysical modality.

110 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 111


AN ARISTOTELIAN ARGUMENT
AGAINST BARE PARTICULARS
Lukas Novak

ABSTRACT
The aim of the article is to provide an Aristotelian-inspired argument against the thesis
t hat particulars do not have any (non-trivial) de re necessary properties. This anti-essentialist
c la im is addressed in the form it takes within the implicit ontology of the Transparent Inten-
sional Logic (TIL) of Pavel Tichjr, the most developed logical formalism based on Fregean
fu ndaments up to date. The author sets out to show that given the reality of "accidental
change" (or any contingent variation across time or possible worlds), there must be tropes
or particular accidental forms - quite irrespectively of any assumptions concerning the
nature of universals. Since the tropes must ultimately differ essentially, it follows that there
are many essentially distinct natural kinds of particulars, so that insistence on essential
sameness of substances turns out as unwarranted. The article concludes with some general
thoughts concerning the relationship between ontology and logic. The author defends the
view that our ontology should not be tailored to fit the expressive and demonstrative powers
of a pragmatically chosen logical formalism, but precisely the other way around.

1. PRELIMINARIES
The distinction between de dicto and de re application of modal operators is
one well established in philosophy and logic since mediaeval times. Nevertheless,
whereas de dicto modality is usually regarded as quite unproblematic (I am leaving
Quine and his likes aside now) and the existence of de dicto necessary truths is
seldom taken into question, de re modality and especially de re necessity involves
a whole bunch of puzzles, of which the most fundamental one consists simply in
the question, whether there is anything as de re necessity at all. De re necessity
is the necessity of a property's belonging to a subject. If we define the essence
of an individual as the sum of its necessary properties, we can say that belief in
de re necessity amounts to essentialism, whereas denial of de re necessity entails
anti-essentialism. Nevertheless, the stipulative definition of essence that just
has been given, however common it is among the analytics, will probably be
regarded as quite imperfect by an Aristotelian. The elementary difference (among
other, more subtle ones) between the "Aristotelian" and the "analytical" essence
consists in the fact that the Aristotelian essence does not comprise all of the de
re necessary properties of a subject, but merely those that are constitutive for it.

SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 113


Lukcig Novak Lukcig Novak
AN ARISTOTELIAN ARGUMENT AGAINST BARE PARTICULARS AN ARISTOTELIAN ARGUMENT AGAINST BARE PARTICULARS

This is the classical difference between properties predicable per se primo modo, or systematically unmotivated: its philosophical background is in general quite
the true essential properties, and the properties predicable per se but only secundo "metaphysics -friendly" - it eschews nominalism, reductionism of all sorts, and
modo, a bit improperly called propria or properties in the strict sense, which do not above all, it is radically objectivist. Besides, the highly-developed devices of TIL
constitute that which the thing is, but merely flow, of necessity, from its essence. devised to capture the logical semantics of natural language constitute a very
s
traightforward development (and correction) of the Fregean semantic insights;
contingent therefore, we can regard TIL as one of the best developed incarnations of the
properties contemporary Fregean conception of the nature of logic.3 On the other hand, in
essence the proposed argumentation I need not invoke anything of the special technical
apparatus of TIL and I believe that my reasoning applies equally to any version
(----
non-essential of the theory of bare particulars.
I will not review here the various arguments for the conception of bare parti-
necessary
properties culars." I would just like to point to the fact that the intuitions behind the theory
seem to be rooted, in some way or other, in the Fregean approach to semantics
Analytic essentialism Aristotelian essentialism - especially, in the strict distinction between "object" and "concept" ("individual"
and "office" or "role" in TIL). Once this distinction has been made, it is very hard
Taking into account this difference, we may be tempted to distinguish be- to see how there might be a genuine case of logical de re necessity.5 For logical
tween weak essentialism and strong essentialism: Weak essentialism would amount necessity is the necessity that is distinguished against contradiction - but how
to the claim that there are de re necessary properties, strong essentialism would can there ever be any contradiction between a particular and a negation of a pro-
in addition posit properties that are not only necessary, but also constitutive for perty? It seems that contradiction requires by definition two properties. It is
their subject. On the other hand, it seems that weak essentialism entails the never the case that a property (whether a positive or a negative one) contradicts
strong one: if there are properties that are necessary for a subject, they either are a subject. When we say, for example, that being an octopus contradicts Socrates,
constitutive for that subject (and thus we have strong essentialism), or there must
be something in the subject that makes it require precisely these properties - and "Consider a specific type of thing: individuals. I would like the planet Venus to be a paradigm individual.
this "something" will then ultimately be some constitutive, i.e. strictly essential But what I mean is the massive body of rock rushing through space utterly indifferent to whether we
property. take an interest in it, refer to it, describe it, or even affix the name 'Venus' to it. The Venus I have in mind
If this argument is correct, it follows that the strong, or classical Aristotelian is, I think, roughly what Gustav Bergmann aptly calls a 'pure individuator' and what Miss Anscombe
scornfully refers to as a 'bare individual' (implying there are no such things). Venus is, of course, bare
essentialism is implied in the very acceptance of de re necessity; and since the not in the sense of lacking properties: indeed, for any relevant property X, Venus instantiates either X or
fact that the implication holds the other way around is evident, we can say that non-X. The planet is bare underneath this attire; it is the entity which enters the relation of instantiation
Aristotelian essentialism is equivalent to the belief in de re necessity. with the properties it happens to have while remaining itself; distinct from each property and from any
One of the greatest challenges both to Aristotelian essentialism and to the collection of them. Venus is bare because for any non-trivial property X it happens to instantiate, Venus
belief in de re necessity is the ontological conception of "bare particulars", which might conceivably have lacked X without thereby ceasing to be the same thing. There are, of course,
amounts to saying that all properties (except trivial ones like self-identity, and sundry trivial properties (e.g. the property of being X or non-X) which are necessarily instantiated by
Venus - and by everything else. Exactly one (trivial) property is both necessarily instantiated by Venus
some others') belong contingently to their subjects, or in other words, that indi- and necessarily not instantiated by any other individual: the property of being identical with Venus."
viduals have no (non-trivial) essences. I will tackle this view more or less in the
' For a comprehensive list of resources concerning the TIL see the TIL website: (http://
form it takes in the implicit ontology of the so-called Transparent Intensional til.phil.muni.cz/).
Logic (or TIL) of Pavel Tich3'7, arguably the most comprehensive and elaborate ' For an argumentation by Tichy see his "Einzeldinge als Amtsinhaber", Zeitschrift fur
formal hyper-intensional language existing (or, as its proponents like to put it, Semiotik 9, Heft 1-2 (1987): 13-50, translated as: "Individuals and their Roles", in Pavel Tichls
a system for the logical analysis of natural language).2 The choice of TIL is not Collected Papers in Logic and Philosophy, edited by Vladimir Svoboda, Bjorn Jespersen, and Colin
Cheyne (Otago: Otago UP, Praha: Filosofia, 2005), 711-748; but especially his "On Describing".
' Like "having the same size as x" for x etc. An attempt to maintain essentialism in terms of any weaker kind of necessity (say,
Tichj, simply identifies individuals with bare particulars in his "On Describing", Organon "metaphysical necessity") would of course amount to implicit surrender to the anti-essen-
F 14, no. 9 (2007): 424-425 (draft online, (http://til.phil. muni.cz/text/Tichy-OnDescribing.pdf): tialist's case.

114 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 115


Lukci§ Novak Lukci§ Novak
AN ARISTOTELIAN ARGUMENT AGAINST BARE PARTICULARS AN ARISTOTELIAN ARGUMENT AGAINST BARE PARTICULARS

what we actually mean is that being an octopus contradicts being a man, and Now let us analyse the situation. We have two states here: the terminus a quo,
since Socrates is a man, he cannot be, as such, an octopus. But this is merely a de characterised by Peter's still being ignorant of Pythagoras' theorem, and the
dicto impossibility, and we cannot derive any de re conclusion from that, unless ter minus ad quem, the state of Peter's having already acquired the relevant know-
we first assume that being a man is de re necessary for Socrates. And again: where ledge. Let us call these states "5-17 and "S-2" respectively. We also have two (appa-
is our justification for such a claim?' rently complex) items here: Peter-as-ignorant-of-PT in S-1 - let us call that item
Notice that this failure to justify essentialism is not merely accidental, but it “p..i" -, and Peter-as-knowing-the-PT in S-2 - let us call this entity "P-2".
appears to be systematic: it seems to be impossible in principle to transcend the What can we say about P-1 and P-2? In the first place, they clearly are not
sphere of properties in our modal reasoning, all necessities and impossibilities entirely and in all respects identical: for we are assuming that a change has taken
seem to be inherent in properties, not their subjects. From this point of view lace On the other hand, we assume that Peter taken as such, the subject, remains
the thesis that all particulars are "bare", that is, have no logically necessary P'and the same individual during the change. From that it clearly follows that
one
properties (except the trivial ones) seems almost analytic; or at the very best, at least one of the items P-1 and P-2 contains something that (i) is not identical
essentialism must remain a for ever unsubstantiated object of faith alone. to Peter, and that (ii) accounts for the absence of perfect identity of P-1 and P-2.
In what follows, I would like to propose a very simple argument in Aristotelian Now what is the nature of this "something", the distinguishing item? Clearly, what
vein to the effect that anti-essentialism is, despite appearances, unsustainable. distinguishes P-2 from P-1 is the item of knowledge that Peter acquired - let us
I will also try to hint at the direction where one should, in my opinion, look for call that item K. But what is K?
the solution to the anti-essentialist argument just sketched. I say "hint", for I feel What I am going to claim is that the item must be particular, i.e. not universal.
that a thorough refutation of the anti-essentialist line of reasoning would require For we have assumed that a change has taken place in the world of particulars: both
much more labour and much better understanding of the nature of the problem p-i and P-2 are thoroughly particular items. In our example, the distinguishing
than I have at the moment. item can be identified as the knowledge that Peter has acquired; but this know-
ledge is something particular, it is an entity that exists in a certain time and place
2. THE ARGUMENT (namely the place where Peter finds himself) and can easily cease to exist again.
Let us take for granted that in the world of particulars there exists what In no way can this entity be regarded as a universal, then.
Aristotle would call "accidental change" - that is, a change in which the subject I would like to be perfectly clear that I am not making here any anti-Platonist
that undergoes it retains its identity and merely loses or gains a certain property. argument against the independent existence of universals. For the sake of the
This is an assumption the anti-essentialist has no reason to deny: to claim the argument I readily concede that there well may be some universal Knowledge,
opposite, namely that all change is essential, amounts to the position directly which, due to the change having taken place, Peter exemplifies now but did not
opposite to anti-essentialism, namely to hyper-essentialism. For example, let exemplify before.' What I want to argue is that positing such a universal can
us assume that Peter's acquiring the knowledge of Pythagoras' theorem is an never be a sufficient explanation of what has happened. It is not enough to say
instance of such a change. that first Peter exemplified ignorance and subsequently knowledge of the PT. It
may well be so, but unless the exemplification made some real difference in the
world of particulars, there would not be any real change in the world of particulars,
6 I am a bit overstating the case of the anti-essentialist here. As I have already mentioned, the world we all live in. So in addition to a (putative) universal, there must be
even the anti-essentialist has to concede that there are some "trivial" properties which
are essential even to bare particulars. As it turns out, the class of this properties is not as something particular that had not been there before, some particular item distinct
negligible as e.g. the proponents of TIL originally wished to think - specifically, it turns out from Peter that starts its presence in Peter as a result of the change.
that properties can be construed that are "trivial" for one individual and "non-trivial" for Let me make the argument a bit more clear. Suppose that what happens
another. (This was shown by Pavel Cmorej in several articles in Slovak language; an English during the change P-1 —• P-2 is that Peter starts to exemplify Knowledge-of-PT.
translation of the most important one is available online: P. CMOREJ, "Empirical Essential So, presumably, what we have there at S-1 is Peter and Knowledge, but no relation
Properties and Their Constructions", Masaryk University Brno, the homepage of Transparent of exemplification between them, whereas at S-2 there is Peter, Knowledge-of-PT,
Intensional Logic, (http://til.phil.muni.cz/text/cmorej_empirical_essential_properties.pdf).
Nevertheless, it seems that the existence of this kind of de re necessity is not regarded by and the relation of exemplification of Knowledge-of-PT by Peter - let us call it
the proponents of the theory of bare particulars as a true counterexample. At any rate, my
argument does not depend at all on assumptions of any kind concerning the status of the ' I will avail myself of the terminological distinction between instantiation and exempli-
"trivial" essential properties. fication as maintained e.g. by E. J. Lowe in his contribution to this volume (see p. 98).

116 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 117


LUICCIg Novak Lukci§ Novak
AN ARISTOTELIAN ARGUMENT AGAINST BARE PARTICULARS AN ARISTOTELIAN ARGUMENT AGAINST BARE PARTICULARS

"EPK". Now what kind of entity is EPK, ontologically? It is clear in the first place $-1,
even if we conceived of universals as necessarily instantiated or exemplified
that it cannot be ontologically reduced to the (ordered) pair of Peter and Know. in order to exist. Furthermore, we would have to posit another relation of exem-
ledge-of-PT alone - for all that belongs to the make-up of that pair had been plification that would obtain between Peter and lu at S-2 but not at Si. No matter
there already at S-1, and we suppose that some change took place between S-1 how far we would be willing to allow the regress to go, there would ultimately
and S-2. Likewise, Epi, cannot be explained away as a mere linguistic or conceptual have to be some particular instance of exemplification to stop it.
product of indirect talk about Peter and Knowledge-of-PT - for there must at any To sum up this line of reasoning: it seems that instantiation must have a
rate be some grounding in reality that makes the talk about Peter exemplifying certain particular "formal effect", to speak scholastically, otherwise it would be
Knowledge-of-PT false in S-1 and true in S-2. And this grounding, whatever it a merely extrinsic relation that could not be used to explain real and particular
might be, is what we have called "EPK". So EPK must be some real entity in its own change at all. And in order that this effect may "come and go", that the subject
right; the entity that distinguishes the "ontological furniture" of S-2 from that m ay acquire and lose it, it must be really distinct from the changing subject. It
of S-1. must be a particular entity in its own right, then.
But now we may ask again: is this relation of exemplification a universal or a In short, what I am trying to show is that any non-essential change presup-
particular? If it is a particular, then we have shown that (irrespectively of whether poses the existence of particular "accidental forms", or "tropes", or "modes",
some universal Knowledge-of-PT exists) in order that there be a real change of irrespectively of whether we do or do not posit really existing universals as well.
P-1 into P-2, there must be some individual entity in reality that distinguishes My argument appealed to temporal variation or change in time. But it could
P-2 from P-18 - no matter whether we call it an individual instance of knowledge, as well have appealed to modal variation, that is to say, to mere synchronous
or an individual relation of exemplification that "formally" (in the scholastic possibility for a subject to have different properties than it in fact has. If there
jargon) makes Peter exemplify knowledge-of-PT. But can Er,,, be a universal at exist real possibilities "to be otherwise" in the world of particulars (for example,
all? It seems that it cannot, for several reasons. For example, universals are not I could have decided not to type this parenthesised sentence at all), then the real
generated and corrupted, but we have assumed that Ep,, has been generated in difference of these alternatives requires really distinct particular accidental
Peter at S-2, because it could not have been there at S-1.9 Besides, universals forms or tropes that constitute the differing particular patterns of situations.
seem not to be located in space and time; but EPK seems to be located in time if this line of argumentation is correct, it means that we have to concede that
(the time from S-2 onwards), and probably, at least in a certain sense, also in there exist at least two sorts of particulars: ontological subjects or substances,
space (for it is something that ontologically modifies Peter, and Peter is a spatial and tropes or Aristotelian accidents. Now: can the distinction between a sub-
entityw). So it seems that EPK cannot be regarded as a universal. Even if we stance and an accident be a merely accidental one? Clearly not: for if it were, it
assumed that there is some universal relation of exemplification Eu (let us leave would require another really distinct accidental form that would contingently
aside the question whether it be the relation of Exemplification, the relation of make this particular item an accident and that particular item a substance.
Exemplification-of-(Knowledge-of-PT)-by-Peter, or something else), that universal Since this new entity would clearly be an accident as well, and since we have
would not be the item that distinguishes P-2 from P4, because, as long as it were assumed that accidentality is itself accidental, it would require another entity to
a universal, we could always construe the situation so that it is "already there" at explain its accidentality, and so on, in infinitum. In other words: once we concede
that accidental differences are based on really distinct particular entities that
8 We are assuming that knowledge is something positive; if it were something negative, a "inform" the given subjects, we must also concede that ultimately, some entities
mere privation, then, analogically, there would have to be some particular entity within P-1 must differ by themselves, that is, essentially.
in addition to what P-1 has in common with P-2 that Peter would lose in the change. Notice furthermore that what is being proved here is not merely the existence
9 Even if universals are conceived in a non-Platonic way, so that the Principle of Instan- of two essentially distinct natural kinds, namely, substances and accidents. The
tiation holds ("every universal is instantiated"), and therefore it is assumed as generally same argument can be used to show that all differences between accidents
possible that universals be occasionally generated or corrupted, the example can be construed must ultimately be essential - for if they were but accidental on a certain level,
in such a way that in this case KNOWLEDGE-OF-PT is neither generated nor corrupted (by assum-
ing that there is another instance of it enduring throughout the respective interval of time).
they could only be so due to different higher-level accidents, so if there were
10 It is quite common to speak of some particular item of knowledge as located somewhere to be any differences at all, there ultimately would have to be some accidents
- in ancient times people used to travel far abroad in order to get into contact with the know- whose essential difference could account for the accidental difference of their
ledge of famous teachers or university masters. Of course this fact can be explained away - but bearers. Or put even more generally: all differences in reality are ultimately
what cannot? essential differences, either of substances, or at least of accidents. If there were

118 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 119


Lukcig Novak
AN ARISTOTELIAN ARGUMENT AGAINST BARE PARTICULARS
r Luke& Novak
AN ARISTOTELIAN ARGUMENT AGAINST BARE PARTICULARS

no essentially different particulars, there would be no differences in the realm at least: the problem whether there are de re necessities seems to be a genuine,
of particulars at all. non-trivial metaphysical question which deserves to be solved by means of an
Someone might object, though, that I have only proved the existence of essen_ enquiry into the nature of reality itself. If it seems that it is trivially solved as it
tially different tropes, but it still remains to show that substances are anything were a priori, merely by way of an implication of the formal make-up of our formal
more than almost-bare substantial particulars. But this objection does not take system of logic, then we should not assume that what looks like a genuine problem
into account the fact that as long as there is proof that there are at least some is in fact a pseudo-problem, but rather that our formal system of logic has some
essential differences among particulars, it is not the essentialist but the anti. metaphysical presumptions, whose validity cannot be properly evaluated within
essentialist who bears the burden of proof. It has been shown that - broadly or by means of that system. In other words: just like a physicist cannot disprove
speaking - essentialism is true. It is the anti-essentialist's task to show why sub- the existence of immaterial entities, because due to the limits of his methodology
stances should be such an exception among all the particulars as to lack all the he simply is not capable, as a physicist, to "see" anything immaterial, so a Fregean
lower-generic and specific essential determination; or, in other words, why there cannot disprove the existence of de re necessity, because his system of logic simply
is just one natural kind of substances, despite the vast variety of accidental kinds, would not allow him to see it, even if it existed. The argumentation of those who
would like to discard de re necessity on the basis of the fact that it cannot be
3. SOME CONCLUDING REMARKS captured by means of Fregean logical systems make the error of equating logic
By way of conclusion, let me say a few words concerning the anti-essentialist as such with a particular and limited notational system. But whereas there are
argument sketched above and the light which the present refutation can shed on many different logical systems of different expressivity, capable of capturing
it. The Aristotelian analysis of reality distinguishes between two very different different aspects of "logical forms" of statements, logic, or the logic, is just one.
kinds of distinctions: the distinction between a substance/subject and an acci- The correct step in case some system proves ill-fit to capture those features of
dent, and the distinction between a universal and a particular. The presented reality (or of our statements about reality) which we have chosen to enquire about
refutation of bare particulars was nothing but a defence of the view that in the seems to be to try to amend the system, or devise a better one, - and not give up
realm of particulars there must be both substances and accidents (and therefore the envisaged enquiry instead."
the two distinctions do not coincide).
Fregean semantics, on the other hand, identifies these two distinctions, to
the effect that for Frege a subject is always a particular, whereas its "properties" BIBLIOGRAPHY
are always universals." It seems to me that it is this unhappy confusion that
prevents those confined to the Fregean optics to see the justification for de re CMOREJ, PAVEL. "Empirical Essential Properties and Their Constructions", Masaryk Uni-
modalities. In Fregean semantics, essential properties have been isolated from versity Brno, the homepage of Transparent Intensional Logic, (http://til.phil.muni.
their subjects as it were a priori, as an outcome of the Fregean strict semantic cz/text/cmorej_empirical_essential_properties.pdf).
distinction between object and concept. For an Aristotelian, universals do not Loux, MICHAEL J. "What is constituent ontology". In Metaphysics: Aristotelian, Scholastic,
form a distinct ontological category - they are just abstractions from particulars. Analytic, edited by L. Novak, D. D. Novotny, P. Sousedik, D. Svoboda, 43-57. Ontos Verlag,
All predicable properties are therefore originally located in the things themselves, 2012.
they form the essences of particular substances and particular accidents. In terms LOWE, E. J. "Essence and ontology". In Metaphysics: Aristotelian, Scholastic, Analytic, edited
of Wolterstorff and Loux, Aristotelian ontology is "constituent", not "relational"." by L. Novak, D. D. Novotny, P. Sousedik, D. Svoboda, 93-111. Ontos Verlag, 2012.
The particulars are, so to speak, self-sufficient, as regards the explanation of their TIcui, PAVEL. "Einzeldinge als Amtsinhaber". Zeitschrift fur Semiotik 9: 12-50. Translated
variety. It appears therefore not only as unmotivated, but as ultimately absurd, as: "Individuals and their Roles". In Pavel TichY's Collected Papers in Logic and Philosophy,
to deny them essential determination. edited by Vladimir Svoboda, Bjorn Jespersen and Colin Cheyne, 711-748. Otago: Otago
UP and Praha: Filosofia, 2005.
What remains is the question, how and whether at all Fregean logic and se-
mantics might possibly be amended in order to be able to capture formally the de — "On Describing". Organon F 14, no. 4 (2007): 423-469. Draft online, (http://til.phil.muni.
re necessity. I will not go into that question here. But one thing seems to be clear cz/text/Tichy-OnDescribing.pdf ).

11 Speaking about first-order predication only, of course. 13 The work on this paper has been supported by the grant no. P401/11/0906 "Moinosti
'2 Cf. M. Loux's contribution to this volume (p. 43). realisticki epistemologie tvcifi v tvcif novoveice kritice" of the Czech Science Foundation (GAN).

120 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 121


y

THE ONTOLOGY OF NUMBER: IS NUMBER AN ACCIDENT?


prokop SousedIk, David Svoboda

ABSTRACT
The paper deals with the ontological status of number. The authors of the paper are
convinced that it is useful to discuss the concept of number within the framework of the
Aristotelian basic division of being into substance (ens in se) and accident (ens in alio). Number
can thus be taken as ens in se or ens in alio. Aristotle and his followers believed that number is
an accident and this concept is explained in the first part of the paper. In the second part it
is shown that the Aristotelian concept is not correct. However, if number is not an accident
then it seems that it must be identified with a Platonic entity (ens in se). In the third part the
authors reject this Platonic conclusion that G. Frege seems to have defended. In the fourth and
fifth part the authors show that from the logical point of view number is an object but from
the ontological point of view it is an entity that depends on linguistic structure (ens in alio).

1. INTRODUCTION
The issue of number has attracted attention since the origin of philosophy.
Many conceptions have arisen since then. An appropriate instrument by which
these conceptions can be classified is the fundamental idea of the Aristotelian-
scholastic ontology according to which being (ens) can be divided into two
different groups. In the first group there are substances, i.e. entities that exist
independently (entia in se); in the other group there are accidents (entia in alio), i.e.
entities that are dependent upon substances.
As the entities are divided into two groups, the various conceptions of number
can be similarly divided into two groups. In the first group there are conceptions
whose supporters (e.g. Pythagoras and Plato) held number to be an entity existing
independently outside of time and space (i.e. ens in se). In the other, there are
conceptions whose followers (Aristotle, Thomas Aquinas) considered number to
be an entity dependent on other beings (i.e. ens in alio).
It is obvious at first sight that the well known dispute between Plato and
Aristotle (even in this sort of modification) penetrates into this discussion on the
nature of number. If we take Plato's side, we assume the existence of independently
existing entities including numbers that are separated from our empirical world;
if we hold Aristotle's view we must deal with the empirical world and numbers
should be entities that are somehow in our empirical world and depend on it.

SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 123


Prokop Soused&, David Svoboda Prokop SousedIk, David Svoboda
IS NUMBER AN ACCIDENT? IS NUMBER AN ACCIDENT?

In this dilemma, we prefer Aristotle's view. Plato's conception seems to be Therefore quantity is traditionally defined as "the order of parts in the whole"
problematic for various ontological and epistemological reasons. We not only (ordo partium in toto).3
reject the Platonist metaphysics of number but we also disagree with the seeming_ There are various species of quantity, since there are different kinds of order-
ly more sober contemporary conceptions. We reject Frege's solution - however ing parts in the whole. The way of ordering the parts in the whole is determined
inspiring it may be in many respects - which in our opinion also leads to the by the kind of relationship which is among the parts. This relationship can be
conclusion that numbers are independently existing objects which bear the twofold: either the parts of the whole are connected to each other or there is
nature of classes. no such connexion between them. If the parts are connected to each other we
On the other hand, Aristotle's approach seems metaphysically more accept- ca ll quantity continuous; if the parts are not connected to each other quantity is
able to us. This approach leads to the conclusion that number is ontologically na med discrete. Discrete quantity is also called categorical multitude.
dependent on its bearer: hence it is not ens in se but ens in alio, in concrete terms The specific difference between continuous and discrete quantity is thus the
an accident of quantity.' The Peripatetic solution to the problem leads us to the existence or non-existence of the connexion between the appropriate parts. By
question to what extent this conception is acceptable. Is number an accident in connexion we mean this: the parts of a quantitative whole are connected to each
the same way as e.g. wisdom? other if the end of one part is identical to the beginning of the other; the parts are
These questions determine the first two parts of our contribution. In the first not connected to each other if the end of one part is not identical to the beginning
part we put forth Aquinas's conception of number according to which number is of the other. If the endpoint of one part is not identical to that of the other, these
an accident of quantity. In the second part this conception is critically considered parts are materially divided. Since this kind of division concerns only continuous
and rejected. However, this makes our position questionable, for if number is not quantity which determines only material substances, we call it a material division'
an accident of quantity (i.e. ens in alio), then it seems that it is a substance (ens in se), Hence, it is obvious that parts of continuous quantity are connected to each
This conclusion, however, implies (as mentioned above) the Platonic conception other while parts of discrete quantity are not connected to each other. Discrete
of number, which we do not accept. That is why in the rest of the paper we try to quantity originates by a material division of continuous quantity, thus materially
set out a reinterpretation of the Peripatetic concept of ens in alio so that number divided units are given.' On the contrary, the negation of a material division
can be conceived as a special kind of "accident". defines the quantitative one or the one as the principle of number.'
It does not follow explicitly from St. Thomas's texts whether he holds the
2. NUMBER AS A SPECIES OF QUANTITY discrete quantity for a genus of particular numbers (two, three, four etc.) or
As mentioned above, Aristotle and Thomas considered quantity to be an not; i.e. whether or not he identifies discrete quantity with number as such. On
accident. The characteristic feature of this accident is that it belongs only to the one hand there are statements in his works that make us hold that discrete
material and not to spiritual substance,2 since only a material substance can be quantity is an intermediate genus of particular numbers, i.e. statements that
more or less extended, i.e. quantitative. On the contrary, it can't be said that any identify discrete quantity with number as such; on the other hand, when Thomas
spiritual substance is extended. explicitly defines number, it seems that number as such cannot be identified with
However, what does quantity as a real accident cause in a material substance? discrete quantity and that number is subordinated to discrete quantity.'
This question can be answered if we realise what is the difference and similarity
STh I, q.14, a. 12, ad 1: "De ratione quantitatis est ordo partium."; Summa contra gentiles [SCG]
between material and spiritual substance. Both kinds of substance are similar 4, c. 65: "... positio, quae est ordo partium in toto, in eius [quantitatis] ratione includitur: est enim
as far as they represent a certain whole, i.e. a spiritual whole and a material quantitas positionem habens."
whole. What is the difference? The material whole consists of parts which are ' STh I, q. 30, a. 3, co.: "Est autem duplex divisio. Una materialis, quae fit secundum divisionem
ordered in such a way that one part has its being next to the other part; on the continui, et hanc consequitur numerus qui est species quantitatis."
contrary, the spiritual whole has no parts ordered in such a way (since it is simple). STh I, q. 30, a. 3, co.: "... divisionem continui consequitur numerus qui est species quantitatis."
Thus quantity adds to the material whole a certain order of (integral) parts. 6 THOMAS AQUINAS, In II Sent., dist. 3, q. 1, a. 3, ad 1: "... unum quod est principium numeri, qui
est discreta quantitas, causatus ex divisione materiae vel continui..."
' Cf. Aristotle, Categoriae, c. 6. ' The problem presented dealing with the mutual relation between number and quan-
2 Quantity is the first accident of a material substance, every other accident inheres in titative multitude (discrete quantity) is of minor importance for our further observations. We
the composite substance through quantity. Cf. THOMAS AQUINAS, Summa theologiae [STh] I, will thus further incline toward the opinion that the number itself is — according to Thomas
q. 77, a. 7, ad 2. - a species of discrete quantity.

124 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 125


Prokop Sousedfic, David Svoboda Prokop Sousedfic, David Svoboda
Is NUMBER AN ACCIDENT? IS NUMBER AN ACCIDENT?

Let us consider the two definitions of number which can be encountered in substance but an aggregate of more substances.12 The subject of the statement
Thomas's texts. According to the first, number is "an aggregate of (materially the Evangelists are four is not only one concrete substance (let us say John), but the
divided) units"' while according to the other, number is "[categorical] multitude whole set of Evangelists - Matthew, Mark, Luke and John. Thus the logical subject
measured by the one" (numerus est multitudo mensurata per unum).9 It is clear that in of number statements is a singular term referring to an aggregate and not to
both of these definitions the genus is multitude (respectively materially divided a first substance."
units), whereas in the first definition the specific difference is to be aggregated; in The epistemological scheme of this Aristotelian account corresponds to the
the other to be measured by the one. o ntological scheme, for our knowledge starts from sensual perception. In our
Number as such is divided into particular numbers (two, three, four etc.) and case, we begin with the observation of some aggregates (concrete numbers). In
is thus a genus and particular numbers are species. Particular numbers differ by a bstraction, which was later on called "psychological", we will leave aside the
specific differences. This is - in accordance with Thomas - the last unit of number, fact that these are aggregates of apples, sheep or people. Thus an aggregate of
which defines its species. It is the last unit which makes number three different further unspecified units is gained, i.e. the concept of particular number. This
from number two, number four different from number three etc. From the above aptly corresponds to the definition according to which number is an aggregate of
presented definition of number, it follows that the quantitative one is not number materially divided units. However, the definition according to which number is a
but it is the principle of number.'9 multitude measured by one seems to be less plausible from this perspective, since
Since the numbers two, three, etc. are gained by the abstractive act of our it is unclear how some multitude measured by one could result from a psycho-
intellect from concrete numbers of things, the former numbers exist only as logical abstraction. Hence in the following observations we will use the first
an object of our intellect. Numbers which originated by the abstractive act of mentioned definition (number is an aggregate of materially divided units)."
our intellect are called absolute numbers and under these numbers the so-called
concrete numbers of things are situated, e.g. two particular people, two particular 3. PROBLEMS WITH THE CATEGORY OF QUANTITY
rams etc." A concrete number exists, unlike an absolute number, in the real world. The Peripatetic approach seems, at first sight, to be ontologically and epi-
What we have done so far in accordance with Thomas and Aristotle is the stemologically very sober and well in accordance with the "healthy spirit" of
reconstruction of Porphyrian Tree for the category of quantity. It can be seen, Aristotle's philosophy. In spite of this there are many problems connected with
hence, that number as a species of quantity does not differ essentially from other this conception which can hardly be overcome. There are many arguments
accidents. A number exists either as an absolute number (number 2, 3, 4 etc.) or against this conception. Although these arguments seem to be somewhat hetero-
as a concrete number of some particulars (two people, three rams, four dogs etc). geneous, they can be arranged. If number is subsumed under the category of
It follows that (from the logical point of view) the statement in which an ab- quantity, then number statements must have a subject - predicate structure. In
solute number is predicated (let us call it in accordance with Frege a number place of the subject there is a singular term which refers to a concrete aggregate;
statement) has the same subject-predicate structure as any common singular in place of the predicate there is a universal term which is in our case a number.
statement. In any number statement there must be a singular term in place of Hence the arguments against the subsumption of number under the category of
the subject which refers to the logical particular of a certain kind (in this case to quantity can be divided into two groups. In the first group there are arguments
an aggregate) and a common term in place of the predicate to which the given that question the claim that the subject of a number statement is a singular term
particular is subordinated. The only difference between "common" accidents
and numbers lies in the fact that the subject of a number statement is not one " THOMAS AQUINAS, Quaestiones de quolibet XI, q. 1, ad 1: "... numerus non est in rebus numeratis
sicut in loco, sed sicut accidens in subiecto."
8 THOMAS AQUINAS, In VII Physic, lect. 8: "numerus... est... aggregatio unitatum".
13 Ibid.: "Praeterea, unus numerus, licet sit in omnibus numeratis sicut unica essentia, non tamen
9 In I Sent, dist. 24, a. 2, obiec. 4: "numerus est multitudo mensurata per unum"; In I Sent, dist. est in qualibet parte; quia non quaelibet pars numeratur eodem numero."
24, a. 3, ad 3; STh I, q. 7, a. 4.
" It should be said that a very similar conception was later on defended by J. S. MILL, A
'° THOMAS AQUINAS, De instantibus, c. 3: "... unitatem numeri, quam constat non esse numerum.?; System of Logic (London: Parker, 1843), book III, chap. 24, §5. A resembling approach is defended
this statement is, however, specified in De potentia, q. 7, a. 3, ad 7:"... per reductionem [est] ... unitas nowadays e.g. by E. J. Lowe, who claims that a number is a universal and its instances are
in genere numeri..." particular groups or aggregates. This corresponds almost literally to Aquinas's conception
" STh I, q. 30, a. 1, ad 4: "... numerus est duplex, scilicet numerus simplex vel absolutus, ut duo et according to which it is necessary to distinguish between an absolute number and a concrete
tria et quatuor; et numerus qui est in rebus numeratis, ut duo homines et duo equi. Si accipiatur numerus number. Cf. E. J. LOWE, The Possibility of Metaphysics - Substance, Identity, and Time (Oxford:
absolute sive abstracte... sic non." Clarendon Press, 1998), 210-227.

126 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 127


Prokop Sousedik, David Svoboda Prokop Sousedik, David Svoboda
IS NUMBER AN ACCIDENT? IS NUMBER AN ACCIDENT?

which refers to a concrete aggregate. In the second group there are arguments concrete units there are many dissimilarities, among abstract units there cannot
that question the claim that the predicate of a number statement is a number. be any differences and thus one can hardly speak about their aggregation."
For historical reasons we start with the second group of arguments. The scho- Let us proceed to the second group of arguments now. As stated above, these
lasticists themselves noticed that there is a very disagreeable consequence of the argum ents are concerned with the subject of a number statement. What is then
subsumption of number under the category of quantity. For if we say that some the subject of the statement The Evangelists are four? At first sight it is obvious that
aggregate is n-numbered, we predicate of it the whole content of the predicate. the subject Evangelists cannot be applied distributively. (It cannot refer in the same
Now it is clear that the content of a predicate includes every concept which is way as it refers in the statement The Evangelists are saints, in which saintliness is
superior to it. So if a number is predicated, the predicate includes the concept of predicated of each of the Evangelists separately.) Evangelists are surely not four
discrete quantity. However, discrete quantity, as we know, can be predicated only separately but only collectively. Hence, the subject of the number statement must
of a set of materially divided units. In the number statement the Evangelists are four be (according to Aquinas) a group of individuals who participated in the origin of
it is therefore claimed that Matthew, Mark, Luke and John are materially divided the New Testament and thus they create a unity of a special kind. This unity, to
units. Numbers, however, can be predicated not only of aggregates, whose parts which we refer through a singular term in the place of the subject, has been called
are materially divided, but also of aggregates whose parts are not materially an aggregate and it is characterised by the number four. So it is clear that there is
divided. We commonly speak about the number of prime numbers, the number the same subject in the following two statements: The Evangelists are four and The
of Aristotelian categories, the number of ideas etc. However, categories or ideas Evangelists are the authors of the first part of the New Testament. However, if we admit
are certainly not materially divided.'s that in number statements there is in place of the subject a singular term which
Aquinas was well aware of this problem. A property abstracted from external refers to the appropriate aggregate, serious difficulties arise.
things surely cannot be predicated of non-material entities without a change The first problem is closely connected with the ontological character of num-
in the sense. So far there is agreement between Aquinas and Frege. Further on, ber. It should be recalled that a concrete number is a special kind of accident,
however, the views of the two philosophers differ. While Thomas holds that num- since its subject is not one singular substance but an aggregate of substances.
ber statements predicated of non-materially divided entities have a different So if a number is predicated it is clear that the subject of the number statement
sense than number statements concerning materially divided entities (they is not a concrete individual substance but it is an aggregate of individuals and
are analogical or metaphoric), Frege regards it as a reductio ad absurdum of the the number is thus predicated not of a concrete substance but of a group of
categorical conception of number. It seems absurd to claim that number ten is substances. The scholasticists were well aware of this problem and it aroused
predicated of the Aristotelian categories in a different sense than of the fingers many discussions. Let us leave these discussions aside and assume that a good
of my hands.16 solution to this problem was found.
Another problem is linked with the manner in which a number is formed, However, even under this presupposition (which is of ontological character)
i.e. with the process of abstraction. If the definition according to which number other problems arise which can hardly be overcome. If a number is predicated of
is an aggregate of units is accepted, it must also be admitted that number, in an aggregate, then the aggregate must have a certain kind of unity. This unity
the absolute sense, originates through an abstraction from concrete numbers can be either a fusion of individuals, or a set of individuals. If the aggregate does
(concrete n-tuples). In this abstraction we leave aside all dissimilarities due to really have a certain kind of unity, then in place of the subject there must be a
which the concrete units differ from each other. Hence, the result of this abstrac- singular term and in place of the predicate there has to be a universal term. The
tion is an absolute number, i.e. a set of units which do not mutually differ. How- predicate (number) must determine the unity of the aggregate as a whole and not
ever, the problematic consequence of this abstraction is the fact that the set of distributively parts of this whole, since e.g. the Evangelists are four altogether and
units abstracted in such a way becomes an undistinguishable unity. While among not separately. From the logical point of view it should be a singular statement.
However, from the ontological point of view the particular which the subject
15 Frege says to this problem: "It would be really remarkable if we could transfer the property term refers to must be an instantiation of the universal to which it is referred by
abstracted from external things to events, ideas, concepts without any change of the sense. The result the predicate. Just as a group is characterised by non-distributive predicates, e.g.
would be the same as if we wanted to speak about fusible event, blue idea, salty concept or solid judge- a class can be called disciplined, so a group is determined by number predicates.
ment." - G. FREGE, Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik: eine logisch-mathematische Untersuchung ither den
Begriff der Zahl (Breslau: Koebner, 1884) [GA], 31.
16 Cf. GA, 31. I.7 Cf. GA, 40 -41.

128 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 129


Prokop Sousedik, David Svoboda Prokop Sousedik, David Svoboda
IS NUMBER AN ACCIDENT? IS NUMBER AN ACCIDENT?

However, if a statement with a number predicate is a singular statement, then Evangelists should be an instance of the universal number four. However, it seems
the rules of logic must be applicable to it. One logical rule says that in extensional to us very problematic. If some particular is an instance of a universal number,
contexts expressions with the same reference can be replaced salva veritate. Let us then this particular should possess everything subsumed under the concept of
apply this rule to a singular term which stands in place of the subject and which number. Since number is a species of discrete quantity, it must include multitude.
refers to a concrete aggregate. For the sake of our argument it will be useful to However, multitude negates unity. So if number includes multitude, it seems that
examine primarily the statements which have in place of the predicate a common its instances cannot be real unities. Frege says in a similar way: "... number is
(not quantitative) property. E.g. a teacher says: The pupils of the class in which I taught only another name for dissimilarity. Exact identity is unity, multitude originates with
maths today were undisciplined. The subject (in our case a definite description) dissFimuirlathrieties."
as
refers to a definite unity (aggregate) and the predicate to the property which the isimilar argument can be encountered in the The Foundations of
unity instantiates. "To be undisciplined" is naturally the property of the class Arithmetic where Frege criticises the conception according to which number is
as a whole and not of its parts taken separately. The teacher does not naturally a property of external things. In fact, Frege refuses the view that the subject
want to say that each and every student was undisciplined and thus that some of of a number statement is a singular term which refers to a concrete aggregate.
his favourite pupils were undisciplined as well. Now, it is clear that in statements Frege's argument can be reconstructed as a reductio ad absurdum. Let's presuppose
like these the subject term can be replaced by another term which has the same that number is a property of external things and this fact is expressed through
reference. In our case the term the pupils of the class in which I taught maths today can a singular statement in which we refer to the appropriate aggregate by a singular
be replaced by the proper name of this class. We can thus say VIII. C was undisci- term. From the logical point of view it is thus clear that a number statement does
plined. A similar conclusion should be reached in the case of a number statement, not differ from a statement, e.g. This stone weighs 2 kg.19 However, the identification
It can be said The pupils of the classroom in which I taught maths today were thirty, of number statements with usual singular statements leads, according to Frege,
However, if the subject term of this statement is replaced by the proper name of to contradictory consequences. Frege says:
the class, then we come to the senseless statement VIII.0 were thirty. It is clear that If I put a stone in someone's hand asking how much it weighs, I gave him the whole
the logic of our speech does agree with the solution according to which number is object for his consideration. If I give him a pack of cards and ask him about number,
a predicate which is predicated of a singular subject. However, it does not follow the person does not know if I want to know the number of cards, the number of the
that the Peripatetic conception of number is necessarily unacceptable. complete pack or the number of trumps in skat.2°
Our considerations so far stayed only at the linguistic or logical level. An
Hence, it is clear that various numbers can be ascribed to the pack of cards. It is
ontologist or metaphysician could object that language only disguises our ideas
obvious that one thing cannot be in the same way a bearer of contrary predicates
and that is why the inadequacy of the metaphysical conception cannot be proved
(various numbers). The assumption that in a number statement we characterise
in the merely linguistic domain. Although our approach to metaphysics is de-
external things (aggregate) leads to a contradictory conclusion and thus it must
scriptive and the argument presented above could thus be sufficient, the same
be rejected.
argument can be introduced at the ontological level as well. In other words: as
Our two kinds of arguments against the identification of numbers with the
the identification of number with a predicate can be shown as unacceptable, so
accident of quantity have something in common. Both hint at the fact that direct
the identification of number with a universal can be shown to be unacceptable too,
reference to an aggregate whose elements are counted, leads to an absurd or
It should be recalled that if a singular term is used in place of a subject it is
contradictory conclusion. In other words, they hint at the fact that, in the case
presupposed that there is a certain unity to which the subject term refers. This
of number statements, the traditional division of statements into the subject
unity is represented not only by a concrete individual substance (St. John the
(aggregate) and the predicate (number) fails.
Evangelist), but also by an aggregate (the Four Evangelists). In any case, the unity
is always an instance of various universals. St. John the Evangelist is an instance
of saintliness, a concrete pupil is an instance of naughtiness, the Four Evangelists
are the instance of authors of the first part of the New Testament, the class of students is GA, 42.
is an instance of undiscipline. 19 There is a certain difference only at the ontological level. While in the statement This
The relation between an individual and a universal should be applicable to stone weighs 2 kg the subject term refers to a concrete individual, in a number statement the
number as well. A concrete aggregate (or concrete number) should be a parti- singular term refers to a group or an aggregate of individuals.
cular which is an instance of a universal number (absolute number). Thus, the 20 GA, 29.

130 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 131


Prokop Soused&, David Svoboda Prokop SousedIk, David Svoboda
IS NUMBER AN ACCIDENT? IS NUMBER AN ACCIDENT?

4. FROM THINGS TO CONCEPTS - FROM BEING TO LANGUAGE


on ly those individuals of which the given sortal concept can be truly predicated.
We have shown in the previous paragraph that the identification of number Hence, number is not conjoined with an aggregate of external things but rather
statements with singular subject-predicate statements has absurd or even con, with a sortal concept.
tradictory consequences. This implies that the whole Peripatetic conception If we agree with Frege on this point together with him we have turned from
according to which number is subsumed under the category of quantity is unac- objects to concepts or (in other words) we have made a shift from being to
ceptable. If number is not a species of quantity, it does not exist in external things. la nguage. Following this linguistic turn other problems mentioned above can easily
However, where else could number exist if not in external things? be solved. E.g. let us reconsider the argument according to which the replacement
In solving this question we are inspired by Frege's example of the pack of cards. of a singular term (in the place of the subject of a number statement) with another
The main problem lies in the fact that contrary predicates (different numbers) singular term with the same reference leads to a meaningless statement. In our
are ascribed to one and the same pack of cards. According to Frege we come to case the description the pupils of the class where I taught maths today was replaced by
this unacceptable conclusion because we incorrectly conjoin number with an the proper name VIII. C. It can easily be explained why we came to the meaningless
object (aggregate). However, what else besides an aggregate should number be statement if Frege's conception is accepted. The replacement of the description
conjoined with? by the proper name leads to nonsense because there is no concept conjoined with
Trying to answer to this question we shall notice that the same pack of cards the proper name VIII. C.23 However, we come to a nonsensical statement even if
can be referred to in many different ways, e.g. the cards in my hand, piles of cards in the description is replaced by another description. This happens if the concept
my hand, suits in my hand etc. If we refer to the pack in these various ways, what is cannot be held as a unit of multitude, i.e., as a sortal concept. An example of the
changed is not the object of reference but the concept determining "the way of concept which is chosen inappropriately (i.e. of a non-sortal concept) could be the
givenness" (Art des Gegebenseins) of the appropriate object (aggregate). Herewith class where I taught maths today. It is clear that in the number statement Pupils of the
the answer to our question can already be given. Number cannot be conjoined class where I taught maths today were thirty it is inadequate to replace the subject
with the constant object, i.e. with the same pack of cards, but rather with the of this statement with the expression the class where I taught maths today. It would
concept through which we refer to the object (pack of cards). One and the same also lead to a nonsensical statement.
pack of cards can be referred to by various concepts and different numbers can it should not be overlooked that thanks to "the turn to concepts" we can
be further conjoined with these concepts. also solve the above mentioned problem with the application of number to a
What kind of concepts, however, are we dealing with? These concepts must non-material multitude, since sortal concepts make up the unity of both mate-
provide the criterion of identity through which we are able to identify an appro- rially divided unities and materially not divided entities. The concepts under
priate aggregate. In other words, these concepts have to be descriptions. Never- which materially undivided unities are subsumed do not ontologically differ
theless, this is only a necessary but not a sufficient condition. Besides, these from the concepts through which materially divided units are united. Number
concepts must also have so-called unifying power. This power causes that mutually can be conjoined with these concepts every time and in the same sense. There-
divided entities (i.e. some multitude) form a certain type of unity to which it is fore the absurd idea - according to which we predicate number of material
further referred. E.g., it is the concept a card in my hand through which the real objects in another sense than of non-material objects - can be rejected. There
cards in my hand have a special type of unity. This unity is possible only if the is no ontological difference between the concepts the fingers of my hand and the
concept expresses a property shared by the units of some multitude and thanks Aristotelian categories, the ontological difference is rather between my material
to this property we are able to determine the united objects as opposed to other fingers and non-material categories.
objects. These concepts are nowadays called sortal concepts." It should be said Frege's concept of number differs from that of Aristotle's or Aquinas's primarily
that sortal concepts not only help us to define the united objects but they are in the fact that Frege conjoins number to concept and not to object. It is, however,
also used as a unit of counting." So it is clear that the united objects include interesting to point out that the essential difference cannot be found in the
definitions themselves. Frege would probably not object to Aquinas's definition
21 Cf. GA, 55; P. F. STRAWSON, Individuals, An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics (London: Rout-
ledge, 1964), 168; D. HEIDER, "Sortalni terminy a problem identity. Neoaristotelismus v sou- identify the counted elements. Something is thus held as a part of the counted amount, some-
L'asne analyticke metafyzice", Filosoficky 6asopis 53, no. 2 (2005): 167-194. thing is not. The only sensible candidate in this respect is a sortal concept. The unit of counting
22 Since if we count individuals that form a certain kind of unity thanks to this concept, can be e.g. a card in my hand or a suit of cards.
a unit of the counted multitude must be available beforehand. Thanks to this unit we can 23 This can be seen as another argument in favour of Mill-Kripke theory of proper names.

132 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 133


Prokop Sousedik, David Svoboda Prokop Sousedik, David Svoboda
IS NUMBER AN ACCIDENT? IS NUMBER AN ACCIDENT?

according to which number is a multitude measured by the one." Nevertheless he 5. BALK TO PLATONISM?
would certainly add that the one is an arbitrarily chosen unit, i.e. a sortal concept. if a number statement really expresses identity and is not a subject-predicate
Frege would not probably object to the other definition according to which number statement, then we have definitively left Aquinas's concept of number. Number
in an aggregate of units, but he might also add that this aggregation or unification is not an aggregate or the property of materially divided units.
is achieved again by the sortal concept." However, these additions are very im. Now, what conception of number should further be considered? Above we
portant from our point of view. They show that number must be conjoined to have come to the conclusion that the statement The number of Jupiter's moons is
a concept and not to an aggregate. four has the same logical structure as the statement The discoverer of America is
These thoughts could lead us to the incorrect conclusion that in place of the Columbus (both statements express identity). The number (four) is related to
subject of number statements there stands not an aggregate but rather a concept the concept (Jupiter's moons) in the same way as the empirical object (Columbus)
and in place of the predicate there is a number. It would follow that from the to the concept (discoverer of America). However, it leads us to a very problematic
logical point of view a number statement is a subject-predicate statement. How- conclusion. Columbus is apparently a self-standing entity (ens in se) and it seems
ever, according to Frege number cannot be conjoined to a concept in such a way! that numbers should have the same ontological status as well. The expression
Number is not attributed to a concept in the same manner as properties are Columbus should thus denote an entity of the same ontological category as the
ascribed to individuals, e.g. as the discoverer of America is ascribed to Columbus. numeral four. Both Columbus and number four should thus be a self-standing
According to Frege it is precisely on the contrary: number is conjoined to a concept entity, i.e. ens in se. Intuitively, however, it is obvious that there is an essential
in the same manner as a concrete object is conjoined to its description. Similarly, difference between Columbus and number four. Columbus is a self-standing and
as the descriptive concept the discoverer of America is conjoined with the concrete empirical object while number four is certainly not an empirical object. However,
object, Columbus, so the abstract object - number four - is conjoined with the if number four is not an empirical object, it seems that it should exist outside of
concept Jupiter's moons." The expressions discoverer of America and Jupiter's moons our time and space. It seems that non-empirical objects have a similar ontological
play the same logical role - they refer to the appropriate object that is said to be status as Plato's ideas. Hence one should not be surprised that Frege admits the
conjoined with the appropriate concept. This logical function of expression is existence of ideal objects which exist in the so-called Third Realm."
also often expressed at the level of natural language: we put the definite article As it is known, Frege's Platonism is closely connected with a very important
in front of descriptions in some languages; we often put the expression the number logical-technical issue. Frege is convinced that the conditions of the identity of
of in front of a concept referring to an abstract number. any abstract object make up the constitutive features of this object. If numbers
The expression (the number of) Jupiter's moons thus does not refer to some are conjoined with concepts, then a criterion must be put forth through which
aggregate of astronomic objects but rather to the abstract object which is number it can be determined whether any two concepts are identical. Frege sets out that
four. Now it is clear that our perspective so far must be changed. The number the two concepts are identical if there is a one-to-one relationship among the
statement (the number of) Jupiter's moons is four is (from the logical point of view) of elements which are subsumed under these concepts (so-called Hume's principle).
the same kind as the statement the discoverer of America is Columbus. Both sentences consequently, number is a class of such concepts among which there is such
express identity, i.e. the expressions on both sides of the copula are singular terms a relation. Thus, numbers are reduced to set-theoretical objects (classes of equi-
referring to the same object. Frege puts it in this way: Hence, we have an equation valent classes). This reduction causes serious technical problems.
that claims that the expression "the number of Jupiter's moons" denotes the same object The first problem is of a logical-mathematical nature and is the well known
as the expression "four".27 However, this object is not a concrete (as it holds for the paradox articulated by Bertrand Russell at the beginning of the 20th century.
discoverer of America) but rather an abstract object.
28 Cf. G. FREGE, "Der Gedanke. Eine logische Untersuchung", Beitrage zur Philosophie des
deutschen Idealismus 1, Heft 2 (1918-1919): 58-77: "So scheint das Ergebnis zu sein: Die Gedanken sind
weder Dinge der Aufgenwelt noch Vorstellungen. Ein drittes Reich mufg anerkannt werden. Was zu diesem
24 THOMAS AQUINAS, In I Sent. dist. 24, a. 2, obiec. 4: "numerus est multitudo mensurata per gehort, stimmt mit den Vorstellungen darin iiberein, daf3 es nicht mit den Sinnen wahrgenommen werden
unum". kann, mit den Dingen aber darin, dal3 es keines Tragers bedarf, zu dessen Bewu$tseinsinhalte es gehort.
So ist z. B. der Gedanke, den wir im pythagoreischen Lehrsatz aussprachen, zeitlos wahr, unabhangig
" THOMAS AQUINAS, In Phys., lect. 8: "numerus... est... aggregatio unitatum"
davon wahr, ob irgendjemand ihn fur wahr halt. Er bedarf keines Tragers. Er ist wahr nicht erst, seitdem
26 Cf. GA, 57. er entdeckt worden ist, wie ein Planet, schon bevor jemand ihn gesehen hat, mit andern Planeten in
2' Cf. GA, 57. Wechselwirkung gewesen ist."

134 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 135


Prokop SousedIk, David Svoboda Prokop Sousedfic, David Svoboda
IS NUMBER AN ACCIDENT? Is NUMBER AN ACCIDENT?

Russell shows in a short letter to Frege that classes or extensions cannot be a nd number four, since both are objects. However, while Columbus is an empirical
held ipso facto for objects. Frege's definition, according to which number is an object, number four is an abstract object. The distinction between a concrete
extension of extensions (a class of equivalent classes), is thus unacceptable. This and an abstract object is apparently well in agreement with Platonism: empirical
fact, however, did not lead Russell to the complete rejection of Frege's conception objects are perceived by our senses while abstract objects by our reason.
but rather to a modification of it.29 Nevertheless, it seems to us that the expression "abstract" conceals an impor-
From our perspective, the critique of Paul Benacerraf seems to be more in. tant clue, thanks to which this Platonist conclusion can be reasonably modified.
teresting." It is useful to recall that Frege aimed at the solid foundation of arith- The verb "to abstract" means literally to tow away. An abstract concept of wisdom
metic. In his project he followed - to a certain extent - Descartes's idea according can be gained if we "tow away" the form of wisdom from its subject, e.g. from a
to which it is necessary to search for an indubitable foundation of our knowledge. concrete man. It seems that in the case of wisdom the abstraction is clear. However,
Frege thought that the indubitable foundation of arithmetic is a set or a class. there are some problems as far as the abstraction of numbers is concerned. In our
Benacerraf, however, pointed out that within a set theory there can be different previous observation we have shown that the foundation of abstraction cannot
definitions of number. E.g., number two can be identified, according to von Neu- be a concrete aggregate; we do not acquire number four from Jupiter's moons;
mann, as a set-theoretical object {0,{0}} or, according to Zermelo arithmetic, number four thus cannot inhere in Jupiter's moons in the same manner as wisdom
{IOW" If Benacerraf's observation is accepted, it follows that sets or classes can inheres in Socrates. What else then should be taken into account? The answer is
hardly be held as the foundation on which the whole of arithmetic can be founded. ready at hand. Since we know that numbers must be conjoined with concepts let
Neither Russell's, nor Benacerraf's arguments are decisive from our point of us try to focus on the concepts instead of objects!
view. What seems questionable to us is the fact that Frege's reflections reintroduce At first sight it seems that this will not be of much help. It is clear that a
the possibility of identifying numbers with independently existing entities and concept can be analysed into its elements, e.g. in the concept of moon opupiter
herewith the Platonic concept of numbers. The Platonic conception of number, there are concepts like an astronomic object, a satellite etc. Nevertheless, it is obvious
however, is unacceptable for us. that if we analyse this concept as far as we can, no concept of number can be
found. No concept as such is therefore conjoined with any number, hence no
6. NUMBER AS ENS IN ALIO abstraction from any concept taken on its own could lead us to number.
The situation in which we find ourselves is anything but enviable. The more To find the way out of this problem it is useful to compare the consideration
ontologically sober solution according to which number is an accident (and it of a concept taken on its own with the examination of a concrete man." A con-
is subsumed under the category of quantity) leads to unacceptable, sometimes crete man can be considered in two ways. Firstly, he can be examined as an
even contradictory consequences. If we, together with Frege, reject this solution, independently existing object, i.e. his absolute properties (weight, height, health
there seems to be only one way out - it should be admitted that number is an condition etc.) can be taken into account; secondly, his relationships to other
object. However, this conception leads to Platonism which is unacceptable for objects can be investigated, i.e. his relational properties (to be subordinate to some-
us. We are facing two mutually incompatible conceptions ("Aristotelian naturalism one or to be superior to someone else, etc.) can be explored.
versus Platonic idealism"). Now, the question is whether there is a middle way out Let us focus on the relational properties of a concrete individual, e.g. someone
which could avoid the Scylla of "Aristotelian naturalism" and the Charybdis of who is the dean of the Catholic Theological Faculty in Prague. It means that
"Platonic idealism". there are strictly defined relationships between him and the other employees of
Let us return first to Frege's solution and accept the conclusion according the university. Nobody is a dean taken on its own, but only in relation to other
to which number is an object which is conjoined with a concept. Number four people. The function of a dean is defined purely by different industrial relations.
is thus conjoined with Jupiter's moons in the same way as Columbus is conjoined In other words: if we want to understand who is a dean, then the functions of
with the concept discoverer of America. There is an agreement between Columbus other representatives of the faculty must be comprehended as well.
So if we say that someone is a dean, we connect with him a "position" in a
29 V. KOLMAN, Logika G. Frega (Praha: Filosofia, 2002). relational system. Dean is thus an object, which is produced by the industrial
30 P. BENACERRAF, "What Numbers Could Not Be", Philosophical Review 74 (1965): 47-73. relations of a given university. From the logical point of view this object can be
" J. VON NEUMANN, "Eine Axiomatisierung der Mengenlehre", Journal fur die reine and
angewandte Mathematik 154 (1925): 219-240; E. ZERMELO, "Untersuchen uber die Grundlagen 32 We are inspired here by S. SHAPIRO, Philosophy of Mathematics - Structure and Ontology

der Mengenlehre I", Mathematische Annalen 65 (1908): 261-281. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997).

136 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 137


Prokop Soused&, David Svoboda Prokop Sousedik, David Svoboda
Is NUMBER AN ACCIDENT? IS NUMBER AN ACCIDENT?

characterised in the same way as any common empirical object. As we say Socrates this room. Such information, however, usually needs specification, i.e., we want to
is wise, it can be said The dean is an employee of the university. Both Socrates and dean know the number of the people in the square or, respectively, the number of the
refers to an object which is subsequently determined by a predicate. From the people in this room. If we want to know the number, we thereby want to know
logical point of view there is no difference between these two sentences. which object is conjoined with the appropriate concept. This object is naturally
However, from the ontological point of view one should be cautious. While the appropriate number. Through assigning a number we have defined the "place"
Socrates refers to an object, which has an independent existence on its own, which a concept has in a relational system.
dean refers, as follows from our observations, to an object that has a completely A system whose relations produce numbers is, in many respects, similar to
different ontological status. The dean does not exist independently on his own, other systems. As the industrial relations of a faculty order concrete people, so the
but the existence of this object depends on the industrial relations of a given relations of more or fewer order concepts or classes. As a concrete man is conjoined
university, it depends on the system of a university. Hence, it can be put forth that with an abstract object produced by industrial relations (e.g. dean), so the concept
a dean, unlike Socrates, is not an object which has an independent existence on is conjoined with an appropriate object which is not a working position but rather
its own, but rather it is an object, like Scicrates's wisdom, whose existence depends a certain number. It is clear that in the systems of concepts which are ordered by
on another subject. This subject is not a concrete individual but the system of the relation more or fewer we can abstract from the given concepts and thereby to
a university: as Socrates's wisdom cannot exist without Socrates, so the dean acquire an abstract structure. This abstract structure can be called arithmetic. We
cannot exist without the system of a university; as Socrates's wisdom depends on can surely consider arithmetic in a similar manner as we consider the abstract
its subject, so the function of a dean depends on its subject. In this sense it can be structure of faculty. We do it when we leave aside the concept which we order
said that a dean is, like Socrates's wisdom, ens in alio and the system of a university through counting and it happens when we are not counting things (e.g. people in
is, like Socrates, ens in se. However, it is clear that in comparison with the original the square) but rather when we are just counting (e.g. 7 + 5 = 12). It is perhaps not
Peripatetic tradition the terms ens in alio, ens in se are used (to a certain degree) necessary to add here that mathematicians want to describe general properties
in a different sense. Of course it is questionable to maintain that the system of a of the structure which they examine."
university has an independent existence on its own. An examination of this structure is not, however, the goal of our paper
Even if there is a difference between a system and a concrete individual it is for it belongs rather to mathematics than to philosophy. The important thing
clear that both can be considered in the same way. Firstly, both can be considered for us is the fact that if we turn our attention to the system or structure, the
in their "concreteness". If we consider the system of a faculty in this way, it can aforementioned problems with number can be solved. This shift will enable us
be taken into account who is employed at this faculty, how old this faculty is etc. to speak about the position in a system or a structure - from the logical point
Secondly, both can be considered in their "abstractness". Socrates instantiates of view -in the same way as we speak about ordinary empirical objects. This
the abstract property "human being" and the concrete system of the Catholic shift also makes clear that the ontological status of these objects is somewhat
Theological Faculty in Prague instantiates some properties as well. If we consider different than the ontological status of some empirical objects (substances). While
the faculty in this way, we have in mind those relationships which produce cer- common empirical objects exist on their own, i.e., they are entia in se, numbers
tain positions (dean, vice dean etc.) and take into account only its structure. This are produced by the relations of the system. From the ontological point of view
structure can certainly be carried out by various systems of different faculties it must be said that numbers depend on the appropriate system. This leads us to
that differ as far as their staff constitution is concerned. The faculties of one the conclusion: If we modify the meaning of the Peripatetic concept substance
university can be considered as various concrete systems that share the same (ens in se) and accident (ens in alio), we could say that a system that is ordered by
abstract structure or (to put it in a slightly different way) they can be seen as the relation of more and fewer is a "substance", and objects which are produced by
instantiations of the same abstract structure. these relations are its "accidents".
The faculty which has been just under consideration is one of many kinds of
systems in which concrete individuals are ordered. Besides such systems there
are also systems in which concepts or classes are ordered. If we accept the fact
that concepts can be truly predicated of certain multitudes of individuals, then
it is possible to order these concepts according to relations of more or fewer. It can '3 Mathematicians tend to describe the properties of a structure with the help of axioms.
thus be said that the individuals subsumed under the concept people in the square From the axioms of arithmetic it follows that it is a structure with the successor relation, the
are more numerous than the individuals subsumed under the concept people in initial object 0 and a second order induction principle.

138 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT • 139


Prokop SousedIk, David Svoboda
IS NUMBER AN ACCIDENT?

BIBLIOGRAPHY

AQUINAS, THOMAS. Summa theologiae. Vol. 4-12 of Opera omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita,
Romae, 1888-1906.
— Summa contra Gentiles. Vol. 13-15 of Opera omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita. Rornae,
1918-1930.
SECTION IV
— Quaestiones de quolibet I-XII. Edited by R. M. Spiazzi. Turin, 1956.
— De instantibus. Edited by P. Mandonet. Vol. 4 of Opuscula omnia. Paris: Lethielleux, 1927,
— Scriptum super libros Sententiarum . Edited by P. Mandonnet and M. F. Moos. Paris,
1929-1947.
— De potentia. Vol. 2 of Quaestiones disputatae. Cura et studio R. P. Pauli M. Passion. Taurini:
EXISTENCE
Marietti 1965.
— Sententia super Physicam. Vol. 2 of Opera omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita. Romae,8
ARISTOTLE. Categoriae et liber De interpretatione, Ed. L. Minio-Paluello. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1894.
BENACERRAF, PAUL. "What Numbers Could Not Be". Philosophical Review 74 (1965): 47-73, ie
FREGE, GOTTLOB. "Der Gedanke. Eine logische Untersuchung." In Beitriige zurPhilosophy h
des deutschen Idealismus 1, Heft 2 (1918-1919): 58-77.
— Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik: eine logisch-mathematische Untersuchung iiber den Begriffder
Zahl. Breslau: Koebner, 1884.
HEIDER, DANIEL. "Sortalni terminy a problem identity. Neoaristotelismus v soaasne
analyticke metafyzice". Filosoficlq easopis 2 (2005): 167-194.
KOLMAN, VOJTICH. Logika G. Frega. Praha: Filosofia, 2002.
Lowe, E. J. The Posibility of Metaphysics - Substance, Identity, and Time. Oxford: Oxford Claren-
don Press, 1998.
MILL, JOHN STUART. A System of Logic. London: Parker, 1843.
NEUMANN, JOHN VON, "Eine Axiomatisierung der Mengenlehre". Journal fur die reine and
angewandte Mathematik 154, (1925): 219-240.
SHAPIRO, STEWART. Philosophy of Mathematics - Structure and Ontology. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1997.
STRAWSON, PETER FREDERICK. Individuals. An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics. London:
Routledge, 1964.
ZERMELO, ERNST. "Untersuchen fiber die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre". Mathematische
Annalen 65 (1908): 261-281.

140 • SUBSTANCE & ACCIDENT


EXISTENTIAL INERTIA
Edward Feser

ABSTRACT
The "existential inertia" thesis holds that, once in existence, the natural world tends
to remain in existence without need of a divine conserving cause. Critics of the doctrine of
divine conservation often allege that its defenders have not provided arguments in favour of
it and against the rival doctrine of existential inertia. But in fact, when properly understood,
the traditional theistic arguments summed up in Aquinas's Five Ways can themselves be
seen to be (or at least to imply) arguments against existential inertia and in favour of divine
conservation. Moreover, they are challenging arguments, to which defenders of the existential
inertia thesis have yet seriously to respond. The paper presents these arguments and reaffirms
the traditional Thomistic doctrine of divine conservation.

1. INTRODUCTION
The Doctrine of Divine Conservation (DDC) holds that the things that God
has created could not continue in existence for an instant if He were not actively
preserving them in being. DDC is a standard component of classical philosophical
theology. It is implied in scripture,' affirmed by St. Augustine' and St. Thomas
Aquinas,' and taught by the Catholic Church' That suffices to establish the
theological importance of DDC, and thus the significance of any challenge to
the doctrine, such as that posed by what Mortimer Adler called the "principle of
inertia in being"5 and what, following John Beaudoin's more elegant formulation,
we will call the Doctrine of Existential Inertia (DEO.' According to DEI, the world

' Wisdom 11, 25; Hebrews 1, 3; Colossians 1, 17.


2 De Genesi ad litteram IV, 12 and V, 20.
' Summa contra gentiles III, c. 65 and Summa theologiae [STh] I, q. 104, a. 1.
' It is taught explicitly in the Catechism of the Council of Trent (or Roman Catechism), Part
I, Article I. Theologians regard it as implicit in the teaching of the first Vatican Council that
"God protects and governs by His providence all things which He created" (H. DENZINGER, Sources of
Catholic Dogma (St. Louis: Herder, 1957), § 1784 [DS 3001]). It is classified as de fide in LUDWIG
OTT'S Fundamentals of Catholic Dogma (Cork: Mercier Press, 1955), 87.
5 MORTIMER ADLER, How to Think About God: A Guide for the 20th-Century Pagan (New York:

Collier/Macmillan, 1980), 125, 132.


6 JOHN BEAUDOIN, "The world's continuance: divine conservation or existential inertia?",
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 61 (2007): 83-98. The expression "existential inertia"

EXISTENCE • 143
Edward Feser Edward Feser
EXISTENTIAL INERTIA EXISTENTIAL INERTIA

of contingent things, once it exists, will tend to continue in existence on its own 2. DDC, DEI, AND THE FIVE WAYS
at least until something positively acts to destroy it. It thus has no need to be How to interpret the Five Ways, and whether and how they might be defended
conserved in being by God. against the standard objections, are, of course, large questions that I cannot
Beaudoin asserts that "despite its centrality to the orthodox view about address in any detail here. I have done so elsewhere Here I will ignore exegetical
God's relationship to his creation ... attempts to prove that the world could not questions, borrowing freely from the history of Thomistic interpretation of the
endure but for God's conserving activity are scarce."' Similarly, Robert Pasnau proofs rather than sticking closely to Aquinas's texts.m I will focus on what I take
and Christopher Shields claim that Aquinas, when defending DDC, "does not offer to be the nerve of each of the arguments, treating them (somewhat anachronis-
anything like a decisive refutation" of DEL' If accurate, such claims would be tically) as representative of the five main traditional Thomistic approaches to
surprising given the centrality of DDC to the tradition. But such claims are not arguing from the world to the existence of a divine conserver of the world (some of
accurate. For the main arguments for God's existence within classical philo- the details of which are not explicit in Aquinas but suggested in the work of later
sophical theology are, when properly understood, themselves arguments for DDC Thomists). These approaches can be summarised as follows: The first argues that
and against DEI. In particular, this is precisely how Aquinas's famous Five Ways the existence, even for an instant, of composites of act and potency presupposes
(which are really just summaries of traditional arguments Aquinas did not claim the simultaneous existence of that which is pure act; the second argues that the
to have invented himself) should be understood, or so I will argue. DDC is not existence, even for an instant, of composites of essence and existence presupposes
regarded by Aquinas and other defenders of the arguments in question as some the simultaneous existence of that which is being or existence itself; the third
additional thesis that must be established separately, after God's existence has argues that the existence, even for an instant, of composites of form and matter
first been demonstrated via the theistic proofs. Rather, the proofs are intended presupposes the simultaneous existence of an absolutely necessary being; the
to establish God's existence precisely by showing that the world could not exist fourth argues that the existence, even for an instant, of things which are many
even for an instant, or at least could not exist in the specific ways it actually does and come in degrees of perfection presupposes the simultaneous existence of
exist, were it riot for the continual conserving action of God. And if the proofs something one and absolutely perfect; and the fifth argues that the existence,
succeed, then DEI would by implication be thereby "decisively refuted" (as Pasnau even for an instant, of finality or directedness toward an end presupposes the
and Shields put it). simultaneous existence of a supreme ordering intellect. Let us examine each of
In the next section, I will develop and defend the suggestion that the tradi- these in turn.
tional proofs represented by the Five Ways are best read as defences of DDC and,
consequently, as implicit critiques of DEI. That they are challenging critiques, 2.1 The First Way
deserving the attention of contemporary philosophers, is something I hope will be The First Way is otherwise known as the argument from motion to an Un-
evident from the discussion, as well as from the third section, where I will explore moved Mover, where by "motion" Aquinas means change of any sort and where by
how the traditional proofs so interpreted might form the basis of a response to "change" he means the reduction of potency to act (or potentiality to actuality).
recent defences of DEI. While the paper does not pretend to resolve the dispute Given the details of Aquinas's presentation of the argument in the Summa theolo-
between DDC and DEL I hope it will contribute to a proper understanding of that giae and elsewhere, contemporary discussions of it tend, understandably, to focus
dispute. on a myriad of questions about whether its treatment of local motion is vitiated
by Newton's law of inertia, whether the cause of something's actually having
some feature F must itself actually be F, and so forth. But I would suggest that
is used by other writers too. See e.g. NORMAN KRETZMANN, The Metaphysics of Theism (Oxford: the heart of the argument is actually much more straightforward than it might
Clarendon Press, 1997), 98. Cf. ROBERT PASNAU and CHRISTOPHER SHIELDS, The Philosophy of at first appear, or at least that the argument suggests a more straightforward
Aquinas (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 2004), 144-145, which speaks of "the principle of inertia
for existence". JONATHAN KVANVIG and HUGH MCCANN characterise the rival to DDC as the
argument that can be expressed exclusively in the language of act and potency,
doctrine of the world's "self-sustenance", and regard talk of existential inertia as one possible leaving to one side questions about local motion and the like. Moreover, while it
construal of self-sustenance. See their article "Divine Conservation and the Persistence of
the World", in Divine and Human Action: Essays in the Metaphysics of Theism, ed. Thomas V. Morris 9 See EDWARD FESER, Aquinas (Oxford: Oneworld, 2009), especially chapter 3.
(Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1988), 13-49. 10 Aquinas's own presentation of the Five Ways is to be found in STh I, q. 2, a. 3. All quotes
7 BEAuDoIN, "The world's continuance: divine conservation or existential inertia?", 84. from the Summa theologiae are taken from ST. THOMAS AQUINAS, Summa Theologica, trans.
$ PASNAU and SHIELDS, Philosophy of Aquinas, 144. Fathers of the English Dominican Province (New York: Benziger Brothers, 1948).

144 • EXISTENCE EXISTENCE • 145


Edward Feser Edward Feser
EXISTENTIAL INERTIA EXISTENTIAL INERTIA

is natural and useful to introduce the notion of the reduction of potency to act is Aquinas's ultimate concern in the argument - is itself a highly abstract notion
using events as examples - like Aquinas's example of wood being heated by fire -I in any event. And the point of focusing on it is to make as evident as possible the
would suggest also that the thrust of the argument is best understood in terms relevance of the argument from motion to the dispute between DDC and DEI.
of substances rather than events. For the occurrence of an event ultimately pre- All the same, the reader might reasonably ask what sort of potency it is the
supposes (for an Aristotelian like Aquinas, certainly) the existence of a substance actualisation of which premise (3) tells us is presupposed by the existence at any
or substances;" and the existence of a natural substance involves, no less than the moment of a natural substance S. The answer is that there are several possible
events it enters into do, the reduction of potency to act. Accordingly, we might a nswers. In an Aristotelian vein, one might hold that any natural substance S
present a "streamlined" reconstruction of the argument as follows: must be a composite of prime matter and substantial form, and that since prime
matter is of itself purely potential, S cannot exist unless some actualiser A conjoins
1. That the actualisation of potency is a real feature of the world follows from
(and keeps conjoined) to its prime matter the substantial form of S. Or, in a more
the occurrence of the events we know of via sensory experience.
distinctively Thomistic vein, one might hold that any natural substance S must
2. The occurrence of any event E presupposes the operation of a substance. be a composite of an essence and an act of existence, and that since an essence
3. The existence of any natural substance S at any given moment presupposes is of itself purely potential, S cannot exist unless some actualiser A conjoins (and
the concurrent actualisation of a potency. keeps conjoined) to its essence S's act of existence. Or, in a more Neo-Platonic
vein, one might hold that any natural substance S will be in some respect or other
4. No mere potency can actualise a potency; only something actual can do so, composite so that its parts only potentially constitute the whole unless conjoined
5. So any actualiser A of S's current existence must itself be actual. (and kept conjoined) by some actualiser A which is incomposite or One. Indeed,
a mong the rest of the Five Ways are arguments which deploy precisely these sorts
6. A's own existence at the moment it actualises S itself presupposes either of analyses of natural substances. The argument from motion to an Unmoved
(a) the concurrent actualisation of a further potency or (b) A's being purely Mover - or what we might more fittingly (if less elegantly) call the argument from
actual. the actualisation of potency to that which is Actus Purus - can be understood,
7. If A's existence at the moment it actualises S presupposes the concurrent then, as holding that whatever the metaphysical details turn out to be vis-a-vis the
actualisation of a further potency, then there exists a regress of concurrent structure of events and substances, they will involve the actualisation of potency,
actualisers that is either infinite or terminates in a purely actual actualiser. and that this presupposes the operation of that which is pure act.
The rest of the argument will be familiar to those acquainted with the lite-
8. But such a regress of concurrent actualisers would constitute a causal
rature on the Five Ways. For example, the notion of a causal series ordered per se,
series ordered per se, and such a series cannot regress infinitely.
to which (8) appeals, is the notion of a series all but one of whose members have
9. So either A itself is purely actual or there is a purely actual actualiser no independent causal power, but derive their efficacy from an uncaused cause
which terminates the regress of concurrent actualisers. to whom they are related as instruments. (Recall Aquinas's example of the stick
10. So the occurrence of E and thus the existence of S at any given moment which can move the stone only insofar as it is being used by the hand to move
presupposes the existence of a purely actual actualiser. it.) That Aquinas has this sort of series in mind (rather than a series ordered per
accidens, of the sort which might trace back infinitely into the past) is well known
The argument is, admittedly, highly abstract compared to Aquinas's own pre- to serious students of the argument, even if not to some of its popular critics
sentation. Again, I am not putting forward textual exegesis here, but something and defenders. And the idea (at least as some commentators would interpret or
more like "rational reconstruction" (if such positivist jargon can be forgiven in extend Aquinas's argument) is that if A's existence depends on the concurrent
this context) in light of the history of Thomistic interpretation of the argument. existence and actualising activity of some further actualiser B, and B's existence
But the reduction of potency to act - the explanation of which, as I have indicated, depends on the concurrent existence and actualising activity of some further
actualiser C, then we clearly have a series ordered per se which can terminate only
" "It is evident that anything whatever operates so far as it is a being" (Quaestiones
disputatae de anima, a. 19, co., as translated by John Patrick Rowan in ST. THOMAS AQUINAS,
in that which can actualise without itself requiring actualisation - something
The Soul (St. Louis: B. Herder, 1949)). See FESER, Aquinas, 74-76 for discussion and defence of the that just is, already, purely actual. As I have said, a more detailed discussion and
suggestion that the argument from motion is ultimately concerned to explain the existence defence of the argument is not something I can get into here, and I have in any
of the things which move no less than the fact of their motion. event done so elsewhere. The point for now is to note that the argument clearly

146 • EXISTENCE EXISTENCE • 147


Edward Feser Edward Feser
EXISTENTIAL INERTIA EXISTENTIAL INERTIA

constitutes a defence of DDC and a critique of DEI. For if successful, it would show I 5. So there must be some concurrent efficient cause C distinct from S which
that no natural substance could exist at any given moment without a purely is conjoining S's essence to an act of existence.
actual actualiser either directly or indirectly maintaining it in existence. And 7
the notion of Actus Purus or pure act is the philosophical core of at least the 6. C's own existence at the moment it conjoins S's essence to an act of exis-
tence presupposes either (a) that C's essence is concurrently being con-
Aristotelian-Thomistic conception of God. joined to an act of existence, or (b) that in C essence and existence are
2.2 The Second Way 7. df ecns
The Second Way is also known as the argument from efficient causality to t existence at the moment it conjoins S's essence to an act of existence
an Uncaused Cause. As is often noted, the argument can seem at first glance to presupposes that C's own essence is concurrently being conjoined to an
differ from the First Way only verbally. But several commentators have suggested act of existence, then there exists a regress of concurrent conjoiners of
(correctly, in my view) that there is a substantive difference between them insofar essences and acts of existence that is either infinite or terminates in
as the Second Way takes as its explanandum the existence or being of things, something whose essence and existence are identical.
whereas the First Way seeks to explain their motion or change (even if it, too, as 8. But such a regress of concurrent conjoiners of essence and existence would
I have suggested, must account for their existence in the course of explaining constitute a causal series ordered per se, and such a series cannot regress
their motion). In this respect, the Second Way is reminiscent of what is sometimes infinitely.
called the "existential proof" of Aquinas's De ente et essentia, and since the point of
the Five Ways is to survey what Aquinas takes to be the main arguments for God's 9. So either C's own essence and existence are identical, or there is something
existence, it is natural to wonder whether the former argument was intended as else whose essence and existence are identical which terminates the
a summary of the latter. The suggestion is controversial but, I think, correct, and regress of concurrent conjoiners of essences with acts of existence.
I will take it for granted in my discussion here.12 10.So the existence of S at any given moment presupposes the existence of
Now, the existential proof presupposes Aquinas's famous doctrine (alluded to something in which essence and existence are identical.
above) of the real distinction between essence and existence in everything other There are obvious parallels between this argument and the argument for
than God. The proof seeks to show that nothing in which essence and existence a purely actual actualiser. The notion of a causal series ordered per se plays
are distinct could exist even for an instant unless there is something in which a similar role in both, and that which initiates the potential regress is similar too.
essence and existence are identical - something which just is ipsum esse subsistens, In the first argument, the idea was that the existence of any natural substance S
Subsistent Being Itself - conjoining its essence to an act of existence and thereby
at any given moment presupposes the actualisation at that moment of a potency,
maintaining it in being. Reading the Second Way in light of this approach suggests and that whatever does the actualising must itself already be actual. We saw
the following reconstruction: that this actualising might be conceived of more concretely in terms of S's prime
1. That efficient causation is a real feature of the world is evident from matter having conjoined to it the substantial form of S, or in terms of S's essence
sensory experience. being conjoined to an act of existence. The argument for an Uncaused Cause, as
I have interpreted it, essentially makes a separate argument of this second more
2. Nothing can be the efficient cause of itself.
concrete conceptualisation of the actualising of S. It holds that S's essence, and
3. The existence of any natural substance S at any given moment presupposes thus S itself, is merely potential until that essence is conjoined with an act of
that its essence is concurrently being conjoined to an act of existence. existence. But if S or S's essence did this conjoining, then S would be the cause of
4. If S itself were somehow conjoining its own essence to an act of existence, itself, which is impossible. Hence the conjoining must be done by some cause C
it would be the efficient cause of itself. distinct from S. But the distinction between S's essence and existence that this
presupposes is as real after S first comes into existence as it was before; and for S
12 WILLIAM LANE CRAIG, who agrees that the Second Way is concerned to explain the
or S's essence to conjoin S's essence to an act of existence even after S first comes
existence or being of things, nevertheless resists any assimilation of it to the argument of De into existence would be for S to cause itself, which is no less impossible after S
ente et essentia. See his The Cosmological Argument from Plato to Leibniz (New York: Harper and Row, already exists than before. Hence the conjoining of S's essence and existence by
1980), 177.1 defend the assimilation and reply to Craig in my Aquinas, 84-87. a cause distinct from S must be maintained at any moment S exists.

148 • EXISTENCE EXISTENCE • 149


Edward Feser Edward Feser
EXISTENTIAL INERTIA EXISTENTIAL INERTIA

As with the argument for a purely actual actualiser, there is much more to way make precisely this suggestion.'" Where they go wrong is in assuming that
be said about the argument, and as with the former argument, a completely Aq uinas would disagree with them. For in fact, Aquinas himself holds that while
general treatment is beyond the scope of this paper. The point to emphasise for individual material things are generated and corrupted, matter and form them-
our purposes is that here too we have an argument for DDC and against DEI. For selves are (apart from special divine creation, to which he would not appeal for
if S cannot cause its own continuance in existence any more than its coming i nto the purposes of the argument at hand lest he argue in a circle) not susceptible
being, then DEI is false. And if what does cause its continuance in existence must of generation and corruption." So, Aquinas is happy to concede, at least for the
ultimately be something in which essence and existence are identical, then since sake of argument, that matter might be a kind of necessary being. Moreover, he
this just is the core of the Thomistic conception of God, DDC is true. recognises the existence of other non-divine necessary beings as well, such as
a ngels and even heavenly bodies (which, given the astronomical knowledge then
3.3 The Third Way available, the mediaevals mistakenly regarded as not undergoing corruption).
The Third Way is otherwise known as the argument from the contingency of This should not be surprising when we keep in mind that getting to the existence
the world to the existence of an absolutely necessary being. It would be a serious of a necessary being is only the first half of the Third Way. The second half is
mistake to read into the argument themes of the sort familiar from contemporary devoted to showing that any necessary being that does not have its necessity
discussions of contingency and necessity, such as appeals to the "conceivability" of itself must ultimately derive it from a necessary being which does have its
of this or that, or to possible worlds, or the assimilation of metaphysical necessity necessity of itself. In particular, it is Aquinas's view that even if matter and form,
to logical necessity. For Aquinas, as for Aristotelians generally, possibility and angels and heavenly bodies count as necessary beings of a sort, they do not have
necessity are grounded in what is actual. We do not determine the essence of a their necessity of themselves but must derive it from an absolutely necessary
thing by first considering what it would be like in various possible worlds; rather, being, namely God.'"
we determine what it would be like in various possible worlds only after first That the matter which persists throughout the generations and corruptions
determining its essence, which means determining what it is like in the actual of particular material objects cannot have its necessity of itself should be obvious
world. Hence, when in the Third Way Aquinas says that the things our senses when we consider that for Aquinas such matter is just prime matter or pure
reveal to us are "possible not to be", he does not mean that we can "conceive" of potentiality, which by itself and apart from the forms it takes on has no actuality
them going out of existence or that there is at least one possible world in which nor indeed any reality at all, necessary or otherwise. And for Aquinas the forms
they do so. He means that there is something in their nature that makes them in question have (apart from the postmortem souls of human beings) no existence
inherently incapable of persisting indefinitely. And when he goes on to say that apart from matter, so that they cannot be said to have their necessity of them-
"that which is possible not to be at some time is not", he is not fallaciously arguing selves either. Nor will it do to suggest that any particular form/matter composite
that if some event is possible in some completely abstract way - in the sense that might have its necessity of itself, even apart from the fact that such composites
we can conceive of it without contradiction, say, or that there is a possible world have an inherent tendency to go out of existence. For since in purely material
where it occurs - then it will happen in the actual world. He is saying rather that substances matter depends on form and form depends on matter, we would have
if a thing has an inherent tendency to go out of existence, then eventually that a vicious explanatory circle unless there was something outside the form/matter
tendency will be manifested in its actually going out of existence. composite which accounts for its existence." Then there is the fact that material
The basis of this tendency in the things of our experience is their form/matter objects are composites of essence and existence as well, as are disembodied
composition, for "a possibility of non-being is in the nature of those things...
whose matter is subject to contrariety of forms"." But even if one concedes that
4 See e.g. J. L. MACKIE, The Miracle of Theism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982), 91; and BEDE
material things have and will realise such a tendency, and even if one concedes RUNDLE, Why there is Something rather than Nothing (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004), 96 -97.
too Aquinas's further claim that if everything is "possible not to be" then at one
15 De principiis naturae, c. 2.
time there would have been nothing, might one not argue that the underlying
16 That angels and the like are "necessary" in this derivative sense does not entail for
matter out of which the things of our experience are made is itself not "possible Aquinas that they cannot go out of existence, only that they cannot do so in the way material
not to be", that it is a kind of necessary being? Indeed, some critics of the Third things do, i.e. via corruption. Such a derivatively necessary being could go out of existence via
annihilation, if God ceased conjoining its essence to an act of existence.
' 3 De potentia q. 5, a. 3, co., as translated by Lawrence Shapcote in THOMAS AQUINAS, On the " Cf. CHRISTOPHER F. J. MARTIN, Thomas Aquinas: God and Explanations (Edinburgh: Edin-
Power of God (Westminster, MD: The Newman Press, 1932). burgh University Press, 1997), 166-67.

150 • EXISTENCE EXISTENCE • 151


Edward Feser Edward Feser
EXISTENTIAL INERTIA EXISTENTIAL INERTIA

human souls and angels; and for reasons already stated, such composites must ultima te explanation arrived at is an absolutely necessary being which is not
be sustained in being by something in which essence and existence are identical. a compound of essence and existence but that in which essence and existence are
In this way, then, necessary beings other than God must derive their necessity identical, an argument for DDC as well.
from God."
With this interpretive background in place, we can propose the following 2.4 The Fourth Way
reconstruction of the basic thrust of the argument from contingency: The Fourth Way is sometimes described as an argument from grades of per-
fection to a divine Exemplar, and sometimes as a henological argument from the
1. That the particular substances revealed to us in sensory experience are
multiplicity of things to a divine Unity. Like the Five Ways in general, it is very
contingent is evident from the fact that they are generated and corrupted.
widely misunderstood, perhaps even more so than the other arguments. For
2. Their generation and corruption presuppose matter and form, which are exam ple, it is often assumed that Aquinas is arguing that every attribute that
neither generated nor corrupted and are thus necessary. comes in degrees must have its fullest exemplar in God; and it is then objected
3. But matter of itself is pure potency and material forms of themselves are that this entails such absurdities as that God must be the supreme exemplar
mere abstractions, so that neither can exist apart from the other; and even of smelliness. But in fact Aquinas is concerned only with what the Scholastics
when existing together they cannot depend on each other alone on pain called the transcendentals - being, one, good, true, and the like - which, unlike
of vicious circularity. smelliness, sweetness, heat, cold, red, green, etc., are predicable of everything
without exception. And it is because the transcendentals are (as the Scholastics
4. So matter and form do not have their necessity of themselves but must held) "convertible" with one another that Aquinas takes what is most true, most
derive it from something else. good, and so forth to be one and the same thing, and to be identical in turn with
5. Material substances are also composites of essence and existence, as are what is "uttermost being".
non-divine necessary beings like angels, and any such composite must The argument is also often read in Platonic terms, and while this is not an
have its essence and existence conjoined by something distinct from it. egregious misunderstanding, it is also not quite right. Aquinas is indeed commit-
ted to a doctrine of "participation", but he does not understand participation in
6. So these other necessary beings too must derive their necessity from terms of purely formal causation, and he does not regard the being, goodness,
something else. unity, and truth in which things participate as abstract objects a la Plato's Forms.
7. But a regress of necessary beings deriving their necessity from another Rather, he takes the transcendentals participated in to be also the efficient causes
would constitute a causal series ordered per se, which of its nature cannot of things' being good, true, one, etc. to the extent that they are, where what this
regress infinitely. ultimately entails is that the Subsistent Being Itself with which all the trans-
cendentals are identical is the one efficient cause of their being, goodness, truth,
8. So there must be something which is necessary in an absolute way, not unity, etc. at any given moment.
deriving its necessity from another and (therefore) not a composite of form
In short, we can think of the Fourth Way as a kind of extension, via the doc-
and matter or essence and existence.
trine of the transcendentals, of the basic thrust of the earlier argument for an
Note that prime matter cannot at any moment exist without form and a ma- Uncaused Cause whose essence and existence are identical. That in which essence
terial form cannot at any moment exist without prime matter; they depend on and existence are distinct, and which is thus limited in being, depends upon that
each other at every moment in which they are conjoined together in a material which just is pure existence or being. But being is convertible with goodness,
substance. Hence the circularity inherent in explaining the existence of a material unity, truth, etc. Hence that which is good only in some limited way must depend
substance's form in terms of its matter and the existence of its matter in terms of on that which is pure goodness, that which has unity only in some limited way
its form holds at any moment at which the substance exists, so that they require must depend on that which is absolutely one, and so forth.'9 This suggests the
an external cause of their conjunction at any moment it exists. Something similar following reconstruction of the argument from grades of perfection:
holds of any composite of essence and existence, for reasons already explained.
So, we have in the present argument too an argument against DEI and, since the
19 Once again, see my Aquinas for a detailed defence of my proposed reading of the Fourth

18 For a detailed defence of this reading of the Third Way, see FESER, Aquinas, 90-99. Way, especially 99-109.

152 • EXISTENCE EXISTENCE • 153


Edward Feser Edward Feser
EXISTENTIAL INERTIA EXISTENTIAL INERTIA

1. The things of our experience exhibit goodness, unity, and the other trans• Aq uinas's argument is nothing like this. He regards teleology as immanent to
cendentals only to some limited degree. the natural order, as manifest in even the simplest causal processes rather than
2. But they can do so only insofar as they participate in that which is good, on ly in complex phenomena, and as something that leads us conclusively to the
one, etc. without limitation. existence of a supreme intellect rather than merely as a matter of probability.
Take a simple causal regularity, such as a match's tendency to generate flame
3. Moreover, the transcendentals are convertible with one another, and ulti- and heat when struck, or ice's tendency to cool the air or liquid surrounding it,
mately with Being Itself. or some even more basic causal regularity at the micro leve1.20 Why is it that it is
4. So there is some one thing which is being itself, goodness itself, unity flame and heat specifically that a match will tend to generate when struck? It will
itself, and so forth, in which the things of our experience participate to not always actually generate it, of course, for it might be impeded in some way
the degrees they do. from doing so - oxygen might be absent, or it might have been water damaged, or
it might have simply gotten so old that the chemicals in the match head have lost
5. But that in which things participate is their efficient cause. their potency. But unless impeded in such ways, it will produce its characteristic
6. So the one thing which is being itself, goodness itself, unity itself, etc. is effects, and only those effects, rather than generating frost and cold, say, or the
the efficient cause of the things of our experience. smell of lilacs, or a thunderclap. Again, why? Aquinas's answer is that "every
agent acts for an end: otherwise one thing would not follow more than another
Keep in mind that for Platonism, things participate in the Forms at every from the action of the agent, unless it were by chance."" By "agent" he means
moment in which they exist at all, and otherwise would not exist at all. For in- an efficient cause, and by "acting for an end" he means that such a cause is as it
stance, a dog is a dog only insofar as it participates in the Form of Dog, and if it were "directed toward" the production of its characteristic effect or effects as to
were to cease participating in that Form even for an instant, it would cease to an end or goal. In this way, efficient causality presupposes final causality: If we
exist qua dog. And though Aquinas's notion of participation is not identical to do not suppose that some cause A of its nature "points to" or is "directed at" the
Plato's, it has that much in common with it. Just as that in which essence and generation of some effect or range of effects B, specifically - rather than to C, D,
existence are distinct - that is to say, that which has being only in a limited way or no effect at all - then we have no way of making intelligible why it does in fact
- could not in Aquinas's view exist for an instant if it were not sustained in being regularly generate B rather than these other effects. Notice that this does not
by that which just is Being Itself, so too he thinks that that which has goodness, involve attributing anything like a biological function to such causes - biological
unity, etc. only in a limited way could not exist (or at least not exist qua good, functions are, contrary to a common misconception, only one, relatively rare kind
one, and so forth) even for an instant if it were not sustained by that which just is of finality in nature, and do not exhaust final causality - and that it has nothing
supreme goodness, unity, etc. So, once again we have an implicit argument against to do with complexity. Furthermore, the end-directedness in question is inherent
DEI and (given that that which is being itself, goodness itself, unity itself, etc. is to causes, something they have by virtue of their natures or essences. At least in
God) an implicit argument for DDC. the case of natural causes (such as ice's tendency to cool surrounding water or air)
we can determine from the regularity of their behaviour alone what their causal
2.5 The Fifth Way
tendencies and thus "final causes" are, and do not need to advert to the intentions
The Fifth Way is also known as the argument from finality to a supreme order- of a designer. (Indeed, Aristotle, who believed both in final causes and in God, did
ing intelligence. It might also be described as a teleological argument, but it has not think that the former needed to be explained in terms of the latter.)
nothing to do with the "design argument" of William Paley. Paley and other de- This essentially Aristotelian, anti-mechanistic conception of the world as
fenders of the latter sort of argument take for granted a mechanistic conception immanently teleological is what Aquinas means to affirm in the first half of the
of the natural order on which it is devoid of anything like Aristotelian substantial Fifth Way, when he writes:
forms or final causes. While they argue that certain natural phenomena are
teleological, the teleology in question is understood to be extrinsic or imposed 20 Nothing hinges on the specific examples. If a reductionist insists that the causal
from outside rather than immanent or "built in", as Aristotelian natures and final properties of matches, or ice, or any macro level object can be reduced without remainder to
causes are. The basis for a Paleyan inference to design is a judgement to the effect the causal properties of some micro level entities, the defender of the Fifth Way can simply
that certain natural phenomena are too complex plausibly to have arisen through re-state the point in terms of those more basic regularities.
natural processes and are thus probably the artefacts of a superior intelligence. 21 STh I, q. 99, a. 99, co.

154 • EXISTENCE EXISTENCE • 155


Edward Feser Edward Feser
EXISTENTIAL INERTIA EXISTENTIAL INERTIA

We see that things which lack intelligence, such as natural bodies, act for an end, the other final causes operative in the order of unintelligent natural processes,
and this is evident from their acting always, or nearly always, in the same way, R; which means it is true of the entire order of efficient causes making up the natural
as to obtain the best result. Hence it is plain that not fortuitously, but designedly, world, since all efficient causality presupposes final causality.
do they achieve their end." so, there must be an intellect outside the natural order directing things to
By "designedly" (ex intentione), he does not mean "because of a designer", a la their ends, where these ends pre-exist as ideas in said intellect. And notice that
Paley. Rather, he means, as Aristotle would, "because of the teleology or end_ this must be the case at any moment at which natural substances exist at all, for
directedness inherent in things, rather than by chance"." Whether this teleology they retain their inherent causal powers and thus their immanent finality or
must itself be explained in terms of intelligence is a further question, one Aquinas end-directedness at every moment at which they exist. Notice too that precisely
gets to only in the next sentence, when he writes that "whatever lacks intelligence since this finality or end-directedness is immanent, "built into" things given
cannot move towards an end, unless it be directed by some being endowed with their natures or essences, that which directs natural things to their ends must be
knowledge and intelligence." The claim is peremptory; there is no question here what gives them their natures or essences, and thus what conjoins their essences
of "weighing probabilities" or the like. Why? to an act of existence. Since for reasons already stated this must ultimately be
The basic idea is this. A cause cannot be efficacious unless it exists in some way. something in which essence and existence are identical, we are led by yet another
But in the case of the final cause of some unintelligent causal process, the cause route to the existence of God, and not merely to a finite designer (which Paley-
in question does not exist in the natural order. For instance, the oak is the end or style arguments cannot rule out).24
final cause of the acorn, and yet until the acorn develops into the oak, the oak does We are led, then, to the following reconstruction of the overall thrust of the
not actually exist in the natural world. Now with artefacts, the final cause can be argument from finality:
efficacious because it exists (or rather its form exists) in the mind of the artificer,
1. That unintelligent natural causes regularly generate certain specific ef-
For example, a building is the final cause of the actions of a builder, and it serves as fects or ranges of effects is evident from sensory experience.
a genuine cause despite its not yet existing in the natural order by existing at least
as an idea in the builder's intellect. Now unless there is some third alternative, 2. Such regularities are intelligible only on the assumption that these effi-
this is how the final causes operative in the order of unintelligent natural things cient causes inherently "point to" or are "directed at" their effects as to
must exist, for they have to exist somehow in order to be efficacious. But there is an end or final cause.
no third alternative, given Aquinas's rejection of Platonism. If the oak does not 3. So there are final causes or ends immanent to the natural order.
exist in a Platonic third realm and it does not yet exist either in the natural world,
the only place left for it to exist, as it must if it is to have any efficacy vis-à-vis 4. But unintelligent natural causes can "point to" or be "directed at" such
the acorn, is as a form or idea in an intellect. And the same thing is true of all ends only if guided by an intelligence.
5. So there is such an intelligence.
22 STh I, q. 2, a. 3, co. 6. But since the ends or final causes in question are inherent in things by
23 CHRISTOPHER F. J. MARTIN translates ex intentione as "in virtue of some tendency"
virtue of their natures or essence, the intelligence in question must be
(Thomas Aquinas: God and Explanations, 179), which is, I think, to be preferred both to the the cause also of natural things having the natures or essences they do.
widely used Fathers of the English Dominican Province translation quoted above and to the
common alternative translation "by intention". "Designedly" and "by intention", while not 7. This entails its being that which conjoins their essences to an act of
incorrect, can be misleading given the way "design" and "intention" are typically used in existence, and only that in which essence and existence are identical can
contemporary philosophical discussion of these issues, which differs from the way they are ultimately accomplish this.
used in Scholastic philosophy. As BERNARD WUELLNER explains in his Dictionary of Scholastic
Philosophy (Milwaukee: Bruce Publishing Company, 1956), 63, in Scholastic metaphysics "in-
8. So the intelligence in question is something in which essence and existence
tention" can mean "the direction or application of causal power to an effect; the influence of the are identical.
primary cause on the instrument". (For the first "of", Wuellner's text actually reads "or", but
this is evidently a typo.) Wuellner adds: "This may be the primary meaning of intention as it best 24 For a more detailed defence of the reading of the Fifth Way proposed in the text, see
shows the notion of directing or tending on the part of a being or power." Again, what is in view is the FESER, Aquinas, 110-20. For further discussion of the differences between a Paleyan conception
Aristotelian notion of immanent teleology, rather than the extrinsic teleology in terms of which of teleology and an Aristotelian one, see EDWARD FESER, "Teleology: A Shopper's Guide",
Paley and his contemporary successors frame their "design argument". Philosophia Christi 12, no. 1 (2010): 142-159.

156 • EXISTENCE EXISTENCE • 157


Edward Feser Edward Feser
EXISTENTIAL INERTIA EXISTENTIAL INERTIA

Once again we have an implicit argument against DEI, since the claim is a later subsection. Let's consider for the moment the negative argument, which
that a natural substance could not have the final cause or end it has even for an a ppeals to a distinction between radical and superficial contingency. The reason
instant without some intelligence distinct from it ordering it to that end, which the opponent of DEI maintains that a natural substance will go out of existence
(it is argued) entails in turn that this intelligence must be keeping its essence without a divine sustaining cause, Adler says, is because such substances are
conjoined to an act of existence at every such instant. And since that intelligence contingent in the sense of being generated and corrupted, and thus have no
would have to be something in which essence and existence are identical, we also tendency of their own to continue in existence. But the contingency in question,
have an implicit argument for DDC. objects Adler, is only superficial. When natural substances go out of existence,
The reference, yet again, to the essence/existence distinction is likely to raise they are merely broken down into their material components, which persist
in many readers' minds a thought that has no doubt occurred to them already, viz, in another form. They are not radically contingent in the sense of being utterly
that the Five Ways as I (and other Thomists historically) have interpreted them annihilated. If they were, we would have grounds for saying that they have no
overlap significantly. That impression is not entirely misleading. The Aristotelian. inherent tendency to remain in existence, but since their contingency is only
Thomistic metaphysical framework upon which the arguments rest - comprising superficial - they do not really go out of existence, but merely change form - such
the act/potency, form/matter, and essence/existence distinctions, the notions of an inference is blocked. And with the inference to the falsity of DEI blocked, so
the transcendentals, of causal powers, finality, causal series ordered per se, and so too is the inference to DDC.
on and so forth - constitutes a tightly integrated structure which offers several Adler attributes to Etienne Gilson an acknowledgement that generation
avenues of approach to what is ultimately one and the same summit. Still, the and corruption are not the same thing as exnihilation (coming into being out
avenues are different, at least at their beginning points. And even where they of nothing) and annihilation, but says that he cannot find an explicit acknow-
overlap, there is value in considering the proofs individually. If we might borrow ledgement of this distinction in Aquinas." This is odd, given that (as I noted above
Wittgenstein's description of his own (admittedly very different!) method, in when discussing the Third Way) Aquinas explicitly affirms in De principiis naturae
order fully to grasp the theological implications of the Aristotelian-Thomistic that it is only particular individual material substances that are generated and
system, "the very nature of the investigation ... compels us to travel over a wide corrupted, while matter and form themselves are not. It is also odd that Adler does
field of thought criss-cross in every direction", making "a number of sketches of not take account of the fact that Aquinas explicitly acknowledges in the Third Way
landscapes ... in the course of these long and involved journeyings", and with "the that there can be non-divine beings which are necessary - that is to say, beings
same or almost the same points ... always being approached afresh from different which have no inherent tendency to go out of existence - while maintaining that
directions, and new sketches made."25 such beings nevertheless require a divine sustaining cause insofar as they do not
have their necessity of themselves. Had he taken account of it, he might have seen
3. RECENT DEBATE OVER DDC AND DEI that the fact that something has no tendency to go out of existence by itself does
If I am right, then, each of the traditional theistic arguments represented by nothing to show that it possesses existential inertia. For everything depends on
the Five Ways embodies, or at least suggests, an argument for DDC and against DEI. why it lacks such a tendency. If there is something in a thing's own nature that
Let us turn now to some recent defences of DEI and critiques of DDC and consider explains why it lacks that tendency, then DEI would indeed be vindicated. But if
how a defender of the Five Ways as I have interpreted them might respond. there is nothing in its nature that could account for the lack of such a tendency,
then DEI is false and we have to appeal to something external to the thing to
3.1 Radical versus superficial contingency account for it.
One of the more noteworthy defences of DEI comes, somewhat surprisingly, Unfortunately, Adler never addresses the question of what there might be in a
from Mortimer Adler, who was himself something of a Thomist.26 Adler presents thing's nature that could either give it, or prevent it from possessing, existential
two arguments, a negative argument intended to undermine what he takes to inertia. But that question is at the heart of the dispute between Aquinas and
be the main grounds for rejecting DEI, and a positive argument from Ockham's the defender of DEI. Adler mistakenly assumes that Aquinas's position has to do
razor for preferring DEI to its rejection. I will address the positive argument in fundamentally with contingency as such, that Aquinas is saying something like:
If S is contingent, then S lacks existential inertia.
23 As translated by G. E. M. Anscombe in LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN, Philosophical Investigations,
3'd ed. (New York: Macmillan, 1968), v.
26 ADLER, How to Think About God, especially chapter 13.
27 Ibid., 127.

158 • EXISTENCE EXISTENCE • 159


Edward Feser Edward Feser
EXISTENTIAL INERTIA EXISTENTIAL INERTIA

and Adler's objection is that at least in the case where the contingency in question of some material substance, but rather is itself a substance composed of prime
is superficial rather than radical, the conditional is false. But Aquinas is not saying matter and substantial form. Its going out of existence consists in its prime matter
that, or rather not merely saying that. He is saying instead something like: losing the substantial form of a cat and taking on some other substantial form or
forms, such as the forms of the chemical elements that existed in the cat virtually
If S has feature F, then S lacks existential inertia whether S is contingent or while it was still alive. And because the substantial form of the cat is lost, there
necessary. is absolutely nothing of the cat left after its death. The "parts" which carry on
And what F is, specifically, is being metaphysically composite - being, that is to say, are not really cat parts in the strict sense - they cannot be, since there is no
a compound of form and matter, or of essence and existence, or, more generally, substantial form of a cat left to inform them - but rather new substances which
of act and potency. This is explicitly what is at issue in the first three Ways as i ca me into being when the prime matter acquired new substantial forms. (A dead
have proposed interpreting them, and it is implicit in the Fourth and Fifth Ways cat is not a kind of cat, but rather, as Monty Python might put it, an "ex-cat".)"
as well insofar as they too ultimately infer to something which maintains its effect Even if Adler insisted that a cat or any other natural object was really just an
in existence by conjoining an essence to an act of existence." aggregate of material parts or a mode of a substance constituted by the material
Adler's failure to see that it is compositeness rather than contingency that lies world as a whole, the hylomorphist could respond that the fundamental material
at the heart of Aquinas's objection to DEI is related to a muddle in his distinction parts themselves - basic particles, or whatever - or the world considered as one
between radical and superficial contingency. Adler holds that a cat, say, is only gigantic substance, would still be composed of prime matter and substantial form.
superficially rather than radically contingent because its parts remain after the And if the material world is susceptible of a hylomorphic analysis at some level of
cat dies; and this is meant to support the claim that the cat possesses existential description, we have an argument from the nature of material substances against
inertia. This at least gives the impression that the cat is no more than the sum DEI. That argument is already implicit in what was said in the previous section
of its parts - that something of the cat in fact remains after its death insofar about the Third Way, but it will be worthwhile to make it explicit at this point,
as its parts persist, which is at least a natural way to read the claim that its adding as a first premise a familiar principle of Scholastic metaphysics:
contingency is only "superficial". Alternatively, D. Q. Mclnerny suggests that 1. A cause cannot give what it does not have to give.
Adler thinks of a radically contingent being as one which depends on something
2. A material substance is a composite of prime matter and substantial form.
else for its very existence, but of a superficially contingent being as one which
depends on something else only for a "mode of being"." And if so, then (now to 3. Something has existential inertia if and only if it has of itself a tendency
go beyond what Mclnerny himself says) it would seem to follow that for Adler, to persist in existence once it exists.
being a cat - or being a tree, or a stone, or a car, or any other of the ordinary 4. But prime matter by itself and apart from substantial form is pure potency,
objects of our experience - is really only a mode of the material world itself, and thus has of itself no tendency to persist in existence.
which persists as a substance throughout the acquisition and loss of these modes.
Whichever of these readings we adopt, from the point of view of the Aristotelian 5. And substantial form by itself and apart from prime matter is a mere
hylomorphism informing Aquinas's position, Adler simply misunderstands the abstraction, and thus of itself also has no tendency to persist in existence."
nature of material substances, or at least begs the question against Aquinas, 6. So neither prime matter as the material cause of a material substance, nor
For the hylomorphist, a cat is neither an aggregate of material parts nor a mode substantial form as its formal cause, can impart to the material substance
they compose a tendency to persist in existence.
28 That it is being composite that ultimately makes a thing dependent for its continued
existence upon a sustaining cause is emphasised in DAVID BRAINE, The Reality of Time and
the Existence of God: The Project of Proving God's Existence (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988). See " Accordingly, Mclnerny says that in the relevant sense, and contrary to what Adler
especially pp. 177-196 and 342-345. That whatever is composite must ultimately be explained claims, a material substance qua substance is "annihilated" when it goes out of existence;
in terms of that which just is existence itself is also more or less the thrust of the arguments for the substance really is completely gone even if its prime matter persists under another
of BARRY MILLER, From Existence to God (London: Routledge, 1992) and WILLIAM F. VALLICELLA, substantial form. (Ibid., 138) But it seems to me less misleading to reserve the description
A Paradigm Theory of Existence: Onto-Theology Vindicated (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, "annihilation" for the case where neither the substance nor its prime matter persist in any
2002). way.
29 D. Q. McINERNy, Natural Theology (Elmhurst, PA: Priestly Fraternity of St. Peter, 2005), 137. " I ignore for present purposes the special case of the rational soul.

160 • EXISTENCE EXISTENCE • 161


Edward Feser Edward Feser
EXISTENTIAL INERTIA EXISTENTIAL INERTIA

7. But there are no other internal principles from which such a substance composite, or on which it does but where this compositeness somehow does not
might derive such a tendency.32 entail a rejection of DEI. Yet he gives no such account.
What he does tell us is merely that DEI is committed to the minimal claim
8. So no material substance has a tendency of itself to persist in existence
t hat there exist some fundamental constituents of the natural world - whether
once it exists.
they are conceived of as particles, or superstrings, or some continuous ever-
9. So no material substance has existential inertia. morphing kind of stuff is irrelevant, he says - which are contingent but which
nevertheless given their nature have no inherent tendency to go out of existence."
3.2 Nothing to explain? He acknowledges that it will not do to suggest that it is simply a "brute fact" that
This argument, as well as the readings of the Five Ways I've proposed, also things have existential inertia, and that it would be a "metaphysical muddle" to
constitute an obvious response to an objection sometimes raised against DDC to think of existential inertia as an active power a thing exerts on itself." At the
the effect that it is an answer to a question that we shouldn't bother asking in the same time, he never explains how it is that the basic constituents he speaks of
first place. For instance, Bede Rundle holds that "no form of causation, divine or would have existential inertia despite being contingent. He merely puts forward
otherwise, is in general required to ensure persistence in being ... Many things in the suggestion that they could have it as a claim that is not obviously incoherent,
the universe, as indeed the universe itself, do not have to fight for their survival, and suggests also that "it is far from clear that the proponent of DDC will fare
but, in the absence of forces which would bring them to an end, their continuation better" in explaining why God's existence is not a brute fact."
from moment to moment is in no need of explanation."33 But if the composite act/ But it is obvious from the foregoing that the DDC proponent does fare better,
potency or form/matter or essence/existence structure of natural substances for he can say that the reason God's existence is necessary is that He is Pure Act,
entails that they cannot persist in existence on their own, then the fact of their Subsistent Being Itself, something absolutely One. The DDC proponent has - in
persistence does require explanation, and the arguments in question purport to the Aristotelian-Thomistic theories of act and potency, form and matter, essence
show that DDC is that explanation. and existence, final causality, the transcendentals, and so forth - a worked-out
Other critics of DDC do not deny that the persistence of natural substances general metaphysics that both explains why natural substances lack existential
requires explanation, but claim that DEI suffices to explain it. Adler takes this inertia and provides an account of the divine nature. This general metaphysics is
approach himself, as does Beaudoin. The trouble is that for this strategy to work, independently motivated, put forward as a way of accounting for basic features
the defender of DEI has to provide some account of natural substances that is both of the natural world and of our scientific knowledge of it that are acknowledged
consistent with what we know about them and does not entail rejecting DEI, and no by the theist and the atheist alike. By contrast, Beaudoin offers little more than
such account has been offered. For instance, as Beaudoin acknowledges, a plausible the bare assertion that at least at some, fundamental level, the natural world of
version of DEI will have to acknowledge that natural substances are contingent. contingent things enjoys existential inertia, where the assertion seems to have
But why are they contingent? As we saw when discussing Adler, Aquinas's answer no theoretical motivation other than as a means of blocking an inference to DDC.
is that they are composite in various ways, and it is this compositeness that entails It would be tempting to accuse Beaudoin of putting forward a "dormitive power"
that they cannot enjoy existential inertia. Only something non-composite, and explanation of why things have existential inertia, except that this would be
thus something necessary (indeed something divine) can in his view have that. unfair to "dormitive power" explanations. For to say that opium puts people to
So, to defend his proposal Beaudoin would have to provide some account of sleep because of its dormitive power is (contrary to the stock dismissal of such
natural substances on which their contingency does not derive from their being
" BEAUDOIN, "The world's continuance: divine conservation or existential inertia?", 86-87.
" This premise reflects the Aristotelian thesis that among the four causes of a thing, its Beaudoin says that a stronger version of DEI would assert that the everyday objects comprised
formal and material causes are intrinsic to it while its final and efficient causes are extrinsic. of arrangements of these fundamental constituents also enjoy existential inertia, but that this
See AQUINAS, De principiis naturae, c. 3. To be sure, that a natural substance has such-and-such is not essential to countering DDC and that such a stronger thesis is in any event implausible
a final cause is something intrinsic to it, but that is true by virtue of its formal cause. To in light of "radioactive decay and some other quantum-level events".
take an example from earlier, the tendency of ice to cool what surrounds it is intrinsic to it, " Ibid., 88 and 93. Beaudoin agrees with Kvanvig and McCann that it would be incoherent
something determined by the substantial form of the water that it is composed of. It is part of to suggest that the continued existence of a thing can be explained in terms of an "active
its nature to have the generation of this outcome as an "end". But the end itself - coolness in power" of self-sustenance, since the operation of such a power would itself presuppose the
the surrounding environment - is obviously something extrinsic to the ice. thing's continued existence.
" RUNDLE, Why there is Something rather than Nothing, 93. 36 Ibid., 89.

162 • EXISTENCE EXISTENCE • 163


Edward Feser Edward Feser
EXISTENTIAL INERTIA EXISTENTIAL INERTIA

explanations as tautologous) at least minimally informative: It tells us that the And in fact both are right and both wrong: though the view of the ancients is clearer
fact that opium puts people to sleep is no accident, but is rooted in some active in so far as they have a clear and acknowledged terminus, while the modern system
power opium has by nature. But Beaudoin explicitly eschews the suggestion that tries to make it look as if everything were explained."
existential inertia involves the operation of an active power, and offers no other Of course, Wittgenstein was not endorsing the Thomistic arguments for God's
explanation of why a thing might have it. existence, or any other such arguments. But those arguments are indeed "clearer"
For this reason, it will not do to suggest, as both Adler and Beaudoin appear to than is the scientism Wittgenstein is criticising, not only about what their pro-
that an appeal to Ockham's razor or the principle of parsimony favours DEI over posed terminus is but also (and contrary to what Wittgenstein implies) about
DDC. For this would be so only if both views offered equally good explanations how that proposed terminus really does "explain everything". For if there really
of the relevant facts - such as the contingency of the natural world - where DEI is something that just is Pure Act, Subsistent Being Itself, absolute simplicity,
did so without postulating as many entities as DDC. But DEI does not offer any and so forth, then there is no mystery about why this something requires no
explanation at all. It simply amounts to the denial of the DDC explanation. DEl further explanation. But the same cannot be said for "laws of nature", inertial or
proponents do not say: "Yes, given an Aristotelian-Thomistic analysis of natural otherwise. As Kvanvig and McCann emphasise, "laws, after all, are descriptive in
substances in terms of act and potency, form and matter, essence and existence, import. They do not operate at all, despite our figures of speech, and they do not
and so forth, no such substances can have existential inertia; but here is an alter- do anything in or to the world. If they are true, it is because things themselves
native analysis of the nature of such substances on which they do have it." Rather, have features the laws describe."" But neither will it do to appeal to these "things
they offer no analysis at all. True, they do not affirm the Aristotelian-Thomistic themselves", to some basic material entities which by their nature operate in
conceptual apparatus, but neither do they put anything in its place. And merely accordance with the laws, as if they constituted a plausible explanatory terminus.
to refrain from describing a phenomenon in some particular way is not to provide For we need to know why these entities exist - not merely how they got here in the
an alternative description of it. first place, but why they persist in existence. And as Braine emphasises, it would
be incoherent to suggest that their natures explain their persistence in being,
3.3 The mythology of inertia since their having natures in the first place presupposes that they persist in being.4'
To reason from the premise that material substances are governed by Newton's It is worth reemphasising that the DEI proponent has no to quoque escape
law of inertia with respect to motion to the conclusion that they therefore enjoy available here, no way of stalemating the defender of DDC by accusing him of a
existential inertia as well would be a gross non sequitur, and Beaudoin explicitly similar failure of explanation. For, to repeat, the difficulty arises from the com-
rejects any such argument." He also follows Jonathan Kvanvig and Hugh McCann posite nature of any explanans posited by DEI, and the whole point of DDC, at
in rejecting the suggestion that the principle of the conservation of mass-energy least as understood by thinkers like Aquinas, is to end the explanatory regress
entails DEI.38 Still, both principles hover like specters over the debate about DE by concluding to something non-composite."
and DDC, and defenders of DEI clearly believe that these findings of modern science
at least lend plausibility to DEI and to that extent pose a difficulty for DDC. The
idea seems to be that since the principles in question "explain" the phenomena
of motion, mass, and energy, so too might a further inertial principle plausibly
"explain" the continuance of the world. David Braine characterises this sort of
thinking as beholden to what he aptly labels "the mythology of inertia", and he " BRAINE, The Reality of Time and the Existence of God, 14-15. The WITTGENSTEIN passage is

quotes the following lines from Wittgenstein to indicate what is wrong with it: from the D. F. Pears and B. F. McGuinness translation of Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1961), at 6.371 and 6.372.
The whole modern conception of the world is founded on the illusion that the so- " KVANVIG and MCCANN, "Divine Conservation and the Persistence of the World", 34.
called laws of nature are the explanations of natural phenomena. 4 ' BRAINE, The Reality of Time and the Existence of God, 10.

Thus people today stop at the laws of nature, treating them as something inviolable, " Though Beaudoin eschews an active power construal of DEI, he does regard existential
just as God and Fate were treated in past ages. inertia as part of the essence or nature of whatever fundamental material elements turn out
to have it (p. 94). But here as elsewhere, he never considers, much less answers, the question
" Ibid. dhow something composed of act and potency, or form and matter, or essence and existence
38 Ibid., 90-91; and KVANVIG and MCCANN, "Divine Conservation and the Persistence of could possibly have existential inertia, despite the Thomist's claim to have shown that it
the World", 31-34. cannot have it.

164 • EXISTENCE EXISTENCE • 165


Edward Feser Edward Feser
EXISTENTIAL INERTIA EXISTENTIAL INERTIA

4. CONCLUSION BEAUDOIN, JOHN. "The world's continuance: divine conservation or existential inertia?".
Obviously, whether the Aristotelian-Thomistic critique of DEI and defence International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 61 (2007): 83-98.
of DDC that I have been developing here succeeds is a question that cannot be BRAINE, DAVID. The Reality of Time and the Existence of God: The Project of Proving God's Existence.
settled apart from a more detailed evaluation of the family of theistic arguments oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988.
represented by the Five Ways. (As I have said, I have presented such an evaluation catechism of the Council of Trent. For Parish Priests Issued by Order of Pope Pius V. Translated
elsewhere, in my Aquinas.) Equally obviously, there are more fundamental meta. by John A. McHugh OP and Chas J. Callan, OP. Tan Books & Pub, 2008.
physical considerations to be evaluated as well. In particular, as my discussion has CRAIG, WILLIAM LANE. The Cosmological Argument from Plato to Leibniz. New York: Harper
made clear, the dispute between the proponent of DEI on the one hand and at least and Row,
Thomistic defenders of DDC on the other crucially hinges on whether something ,H1980
EINRICH. Sources of Catholic Dogma. St. Louis: Herder, 1957.
like a general Aristotelian-Thomistic metaphysics and philosophy of nature FESER, EDWARD. Aquinas. Oxford: Oneworld, 2009.
are correct. These issues too are beyond the scope of this paper (though I have
"Existential Inertia and the Five Ways" in American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 85,
also defended the relevant metaphysics and philosophy of nature elsewhere), no. 2 (Spring 2011): 237-267.
Enough has been said here, though, to show that the Thomistic critique of DEI
and associated defence of DDC constitute serious arguments, and have yet to be "Teleology: A Shopper's Guide". Philosophia Christi 12, no. 1 (2010): 142-159.
seriously answered by defenders of the existential inertia thesis." The Last Superstition: A Refutation of the New Atheism. South Bend, IN: St. Augustine's
Press, 2008.
N2N, NORMAN. The Metaphysics of Theism. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997.
JONATHAN and MCCANN, HUGH. "Divine Conservation and the Persistence of
BIBLIOGRAPHY
tTNrzvemisG'World".
REthe
KKvA orld". In Divine and Human Action: Essays in the Metaphysics of Theism, edited by
ADLER, MORTIMER. How to Think About God: A Guide for the 20th-Century Pagan. New York: Thomas V. Morris, 13-49. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1988.
Collier/Macmillan, 1980. MACKIE, J. L., The Miracle of Theism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982.

AUGUSTINUS, AURELIUS. De Genesi ad litteram. Patrologia Latina 43: 391-446. MARTIN, CHRISTOPHER F. J. Thomas Aquinas: God and Explanations. Edinburgh: Edinburgh

AQUINAS, THOMAS. Summa contra gentiles. Vol. 13-15 of Opera omnia iussu Leonis XIII P.M. University Press, 1997.
edita. Romae, 1918-1930. MCINERNY, D. Q. Natural Theology. Elmhurst, PA: Priestly Fraternity of St. Peter, 2005.

-On the Power of God. Translated by Lawrence Shapcote. Westminster, MD: The Newman MILLER, BARRY. From Existence to God. London: Routledge, 1992.
Press, 1932. ODERBERG, DAVID S. Real Essentialism. London: Routledge, 2007.
-Summa theologiae. Vol. 4-12 of Opera omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita. Romae, OTT, LUDWIG. Fundamentals of Catholic Dogma. Cork: Mercier Press, 1955.
1888-1906. PASNAU, ROBERT and SHIELDS, CHRISTOPHER, The Philosophy of Aquinas. Boulder, CO: West-
-Summa Theologica. Translated by Fathers of the English Dominican Province. London: view Press, 2004.
Burns, Oates, and Washbourne 1912-36. Reprint, New York: Benziger Brothers 1947-98.
Ross, JAMES. Thought and World: The Hidden Necessities. Notre Dame: University of Notre
Reprint, New York: Christian Classics, 1981.
Dame Press, 2008.
-The Soul. A translation of St. Thomas Aquinas' De anima. Translated by John Patrick Rowan. RUNDLE, BEDE, Why there is Something rather than Nothing. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004.
St. Louis: B. Herder, 1949.
VALLICELLA, WILLIAM F. A Paradigm Theory of Existence: Onto-Theology Vindicated. Dordrecht:
43 See FESER, Aquinas, and, for a semi-popular and more polemical treatment, EDWARD Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2002.
FESER, The Last Superstition: A Refutation of the New Atheism (South Bend, IN: St. Augustine's Press, WITTGENSTEIN, LUDWIG. Philosophical Investigations. Translated by G. E. M. Anscombe.
2008). Cf. DAVID S. ODERBERG, Real Essentialism (London: Routledge, 2007), and JAMES ROSS, 3rd edition. New York: Macmillan, 1968.
Thought and World: The Hidden Necessities (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 2008).
-Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Translated by D. F. Pears and B. F. McGuinness. London:
" A longer version of this paper was published under the title "Existential Inertia and the Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1961.
Five Ways", in American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 85, no. 2 (2011): 237-267. For comments
on earlier versions of the paper, I thank Mark Anderson, David Clemenson, David Oderberg, WUELLNER, BERNARD. Dictionary of Scholastic Philosophy. Milwaukee: Bruce Publishing
Bill Vallicella, an anonymous referee, and audience members at a conference on Metaphysics Company, 1956.
Aristotelian, Scholastic, Analytic in Prague in July 2010.

166 • EXISTENCE EXISTENCE • 167


AQUINAS VS. BURIDAN ON ESSENCE AND EXISTENCE,
AND THE COMMENSURABILITY OF PARADIGMS
Gyula Klima

ABSTRACT
This paper argues that although Anthony Kenny's objections to Aquinas's "intellectus
essentiae" argument for the real distinction of essence and existence in creatures are quite
easily answerable in terms of a proper reconstruction of the argument, the argument thus
reconstructed is still open to an objection offered by John Buridan in his Questions on Aristotle's
Metaphysics. The discussion of how Aquinas could handle Buridan's objection will show that
the conflict between their judgements concerning the validity of the argument rests on a
fundamental difference between Aquinas's and Buridan's conceptions of how our concepts
latch onto things in the world. These considerations lead at the end of the paper to some
general reflections on the possibility of arguing "across" paradigmatically different conceptual
frameworks.

1.INTRODUCTION
In this paper I will argue that although Anthony Kenny's objections to Aquinas's
"intellectus essentiae" argument for the real distinction of essence and existence in
creatures are quite easily answerable in terms of a proper reconstruction of the
argument, the argument thus reconstructed is still open to an objection offered
by John Buridan in his Questions on Aristotle's Metaphysics. The discussion of how
Aquinas could handle Buridan's objection will show that the conflict between
their judgements concerning the validity of the argument rests on a fundamental
difference between Aquinas's and Buridan's conceptions of how our concepts latch
onto things in the world. These considerations will lead at the end of the paper to
some general and rather sketchy reflections on the possibility of arguing "across"
paradigmatically different conceptual frameworks.

2.KENNY ON THE "INTELLECTUS ESSENTIAE" ARGUMENT


Aquinas's famous intellectus essentiae argument in his De Ente et Essentia is
taken by many commentators to be one of his most serious attempts to prove his
metaphysical thesis of the real distinction of essence and existence in creatures.
Others would claim that this argument is only a part of a larger argument,
which as a whole intends to prove the real distinction of essence and existence

EXISTENCE • 169
Gyula Klima Gyula Klima
AQUINAS VS. BURIDAN ON ESSENCE AND EXISTENCE AQUINAS VS. BURIDAN ON ESSENCE AND EXISTENCE

in creatures and the identity thereof in God. In any case, that interpretational ter m 'phoenix'. But then the argument proves too much, for then, in the same
issue aside, the intellectus essentiae argument in itself can quite justifiably be taken way, we know what the term 'God' means, but we do not know whether it is true
to be an intriguing attempt to prove the real distinction between essence and of a nything, for we do not know whether there is a God. Thus, if this is what the
existence at least in some cases, which then can be regarded as the starting point distinction of essence and existence means, then they are distinct in God just as
of the larger argument for the entire thesis. The larger argument would then seek well as they are in creatures.
to establish that if essence and existence are identical in some case, then they On the other prong of his attack Kenny argues that if Aquinas was talking about
can be identical only in a unique case, namely, in the case of God, from which it existence in the sense of "individual being", meaning actuality, corresponding to
follows that essence and existence must be distinct in all other cases, namely, i n the Fregean notion of Wirklichkeit, then essence and existence are identical both
all creatures. in God and in creatures. For then we have to say that just as for God to be actual
In this paper, however, leaving the rest of the argument aside, I will confine my is for Him to be God, so for a dog, say, Fido, to be actual is for Fido to be a dog.
discussion to the piece of reasoning embodied in the following lines in Aquinas's Therefore, if this is what the identity of essence and existence means, then Fido's
text: essence is just as identical with his existence as God's essence is with His existence.
Whatever is not included in the understanding of an essence or quiddity is coming Thus, Kenny concludes, either way, the intellectus essentiae argument fails
to it from outside, entering into composition with the essence; for no essence can be to establish Aquinas's desired conclusion. However, as I have argued in detail
understood without its parts. But every essence can be understood without knowing elsewhere,' Kenny's argument fails on several counts.
about its existence, for I can understand what a man or a phoenix is, and not know In the first place, Aquinas simply does not have a notion equivalent to the
whether it actually exists in the nature of things. Therefore, it is clear that existence Fregean notion of an existential quantifier. In fact, a notion that would come
is distinct from essence, unless, perhaps, there is a thing whose quiddity is its own closest to this notion in Aquinas's conceptual arsenal would be regarded by
existence.' him not as a concept of existence, but as a signum quantitatis, namely, a signum
In his controversial book, Aquinas on Being,' Anthony Kenny launched a two- particulare, the syncategorematic concept expressed by the Latin terms `quidam',
pronged attack against Aquinas's argument. 'aliquid' or their equivalents, which render a proposition to which they are
On the first prong, he tried to establish that if Aquinas in this argument was prefixed a particular, as opposed to a universal, singular or indefinite proposition
talking about existence in the sense of "specific existence", expressed by the (as in, 'Quidam homo est animal' = 'Some man is an animal', as opposed to 'Every
Fregean existential quantifier, then he was either talking nonsense or essence and man is an animal', 'Socrates is an animal' or 'A man is an animal', respectively).
existence are distinct both in God and in creatures. Kenny's reasoning is based on In any case, Kenny's reason for holding that Aquinas would have to use in his
the idea that Aquinas's argument can plausibly be understood as claiming in its argument the notion of specific existence, and, correspondingly, the notion of
premises that while we know, for instance, what is meant by the word 'phoenix', nominal as opposed to real essence," is his unjustified assumption that Aquinas
namely, a mythical bird that sometimes bursts out in flames and is later reborn would take a phoenix by definition to be a fictitious bird as we do. However, from
from its ashes, we just do not know if there is such a thing, i.e., we do not know if his argument, as well as from the parallel text of his Commentary on the Sentences
the word is true of something. Indeed, we actually know that the word 'phoenix' (In II. Sent., d. 3, q. 1, a. 1, co.), it is quite clear that Aquinas uses this example as
is not true of anything, for nothing is a phoenix, which is precisely the Fregean
quantificational interpretation of the notion of existence. However, as Kenny ' G. KLIMA, "On Kenny on Aquinas on Being: A critical review of Aquinas on Being by Anthony
correctly concludes, on this interpretation Aquinas's argument would either Kenny", feature review in International Philosophical Quarterly 44 (2004): 567-580.
amount to nonsense or it would prove too much. For on this understanding of the ' A nominal essence is what is described by a nominal definition, which merely provides
notion of existence, the thesis of the real identity of God's essence and existence the meaning of a name, regardless of whether there is or even just can be anything that fits
would amount to something like the ungrammatical gibberish: "God's essence that description, while a real essence is what is signified by a real or quidditative definition,
is 3". On the other hand, if we assume that the argument is not nonsensical and which identifies the essential features of the thing that is referred to by name according
to the meaning specified by the corresponding nominal definition. Therefore, we can have
works, then it must work in the same way for the term 'God' as it does for the nominal essences expressed/described by nominal definitions even of non-entities or mere
impossibilia, whereas real essences can only be had by really existing genuine entities. For
1 THOMAS AQUINAS, "On Being and Essence", c. 5, in Medieval Philosophy: Essential Readings a good description of the contrast between nominal and quidditative definitions in the
with Commentary, ed. G. Klima (Blackwell Publishers, 2007), 240. Thomistic tradition, see THOMAS DE VIO CARDINAL'S CAJETANUS, "Super Librum De Ente et
2 ANTHONY KENNY, Aquinas on Being (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002). Essentia Sancti Thomae", in IDEM, Opuscula Omnia (Bergomi: Typis Comini Venturae, 1590), 299.

170 • EXISTENCE EXISTENCE • 171


Gyula Klima Gyula Klima
AQUINAS VS. BURIDAN ON ESSENCE AND EXISTENCE AQUINAS VS. BURIDAN ON ESSENCE AND EXISTENCE

the illustration of a real, but ephemeral natural phenomenon, like a lunar eclipse 1. The nature of c is known.
or a rainbow, the essence of which we could know perfectly well in terms of a 2. The existence of c is not known.
scientific definition without knowing whether this kind of thing actually exists 3. Therefore, the nature of c is not the existence of c.
at the present time. So, Kenny's objection definitely fails on the first prong, on
account of simply missing Aquinas's point in the argument, taking it to deal with In fact, if we name the individualised nature of c by the proper name 'n', and its
nominal, rather than real essences, and operating with a notion of existence that individualised act of existence by the proper name 'e', then this argument may be
is alien to Aquinas's thought. regarded as an instance of the following valid argument form of predicate logic:
But Kenny's objection fails on its second prong as well, even if the interpreta- 1. Kn
tion it involves is somewhat closer to Aquinas's original intention. For Kenny
2. -Ke
bases his objection on the false assumption that the distinctness of essence and
existence would have to mean that it is possible to have one without the other. And 3. e n
so, he argues, since it is impossible to have a dog's existence without its essence Accordingly, in this reconstruction, the argument is certainly immune to
for a dog cannot be without being a dog - essence and existence would have to be Kenny's criticism; indeed, it may appear to be absolutely uncontroversial. How-
the same also in the case of this creature. However, this assumption is obviously ever, John Buridan attacked the argument precisely in this reconstruction, on
false: for it is clearly possible to have distinct, yet necessarily co-occurring items account of the logical peculiarities of the intentional verb it involves.
in reality. For example, it is clear that the triangularity of any particular triangle
(its having three angles) is not the same as its trilaterality (its having three sides), 4. BURIDAN'S CRITICISM
unless sides and angles are the same items. But it is also clear that one cannot Buridan takes on Aquinas's argument in his Questions on Aristotle's Metaphysics.
have a particular triangularity without a particular trilaterality. So, we have In the first place, in the following passage he reconstructs the argument precisely
two really distinct items here, which are nevertheless inseparable in reality, in the way I presented it above, as an objection to his own position, which he is
Again, this particular material form, say, the substantial form of this particular going to answer after his own determination of the issue:
block of wood, cannot exist without the matter it informs, and the matter it
informs cannot exist (at least on Aquinas's conception), without this form actually ... I can have scientific knowledge of roses or thunder, and yet I may not know whether
informing it (since for both of them to be is nothing but for this particular block there is a rose or whether there is thunder. Therefore, if one of these is known and
the other is unknown to me, then it follows that the one is not the same as the other.'
of wood to be). Still, Aquinas would take this form and this matter to be really
distinct items in reality, since they are precisely those mutually exclusive, non- It is noteworthy in this reconstruction that Buridan is absolutely clear on the
overlapping, essential parts of the substance of this block of wood into which it point of the argument Kenny missed, namely, that it is to prove the thesis of real
has to be analysed in Aristotle's hylomorphist metaphysics. Therefore, pace Kenny, distinction concerning the real essences of scientifically known but ephemeral
real distinction does not have to mean real separability, which finishes off the natural phenomena, whose actual existence may not be known at any given time
other prong of his attack. despite our scientific knowledge of their nature.
Buridan's criticism is based on the well-known phenomenon of the breakdown of the
3. RECONSTRUCTING THE ARGUMENT principle of the substitutivity of identicals in intentional contexts. It is easy to see
Accordingly, to avoid the misunderstandings involved in Kenny's criticism, we this point, if we consider that the validity of Aquinas's argument as reconstructed
have to understand the argument as dealing with real, individualised essences, above requires that its premises together with the negation of the conclusion should
and arguing for their real, mind-independent distinction from real, individual form an inconsistent set of propositions. Indeed, if the principle of the substitutivity
of identicals is valid, then from the negation of the conclusion, which would claim
acts of existence at least in those cases in which we have knowledge of the essence the identity of existence and essence, we could promptly derive a contradiction,
without knowing whether it is actually present in any actually existing indivi- proving the requisite inconsistency. However, if this principle is not valid, then the
dual. Therefore, taking c to be any arbitrarily chosen thing whose nature is known
but whose existence is not known, the gist of the argument may be reconstructed JOHANNIS BURIDANI Quaestiones in Aristotelis Metaphysicam: Kommentar zur Aristotelischen
as follows: Metaphysik (Paris, 1518; reprint, Frankfurt am Main: Minerva, 1964), selections from lb. 8, q.
4, emended ad sensum and translated by G. Klima, in Medieval Philosophy: Essential Readings with
Commentary, ed. G. Klima (Blackwell Publishers, 2007), 250.

172 • EXISTENCE EXISTENCE • 173


Gyula Klima Gyula Klima
AQUINAS VS. BURIDAN ON ESSENCE AND EXISTENCE AQUINAS VS. BURIDAN ON ESSENCE AND EXISTENCE

contradiction is not derivable, which invalidates the original argument. Accordingly ample, the premises and the conclusion would have to be reformulated in the
Buridan starts his response to Aquinas's argument as he reconstructed it by making
two important claims: first, that essence and existence differ in their concepts.
following way:
second, that for this reason the argument as stated is a non sequitur:... for the sal( 1'.1 know the essence of a rose qua the essence of that rose.
of answering the objections it seems that we should say in this question that es• 2'. I do not know the existence of that rose qua the existence of that rose.
sence and existence differ in their concepts. For the name "rose" and this name or
expression "that a rose exists" are imposed from different concepts. Therefore, when 3'. Therefore, the existence of that rose is not the same as the essence of
it is said that I think of a rose, while I do not think that it exists, this I concede. But that rose.
from this it does not follow that, therefore, the existence of a rose6 differs from the
rose; what follows is only that it is according to different concepts or on different
That this argument is not valid is clear from the fact that from its premises
accounts that the rose is thought of in terms of the name "rose" and the expression a nd the negation of its conclusion we cannot derive a contradiction. For if we
"that a rose exists."' assume that the existence of that rose is the same as the essence of that rose, then
from the two premises we can only conclude either that I know the existence of
However, besides simply claiming the invalidity of the argument, Buridan that rose qua the essence of that rose, or that I do not know the essence of that
also provides an explanation why it has to be invalid with an intentional verb: rose qua the existence of that rose, but either of these is clearly compatible with
Here you need to know that we recognise, know, or understand things according the other premise, namely, that I do not know the existence of that rose qua the
to determinate and distinct concepts, and we can understand a thing according to existence of that rose or that I know the essence of that rose qua the essence of
one concept and ignore it according to another; therefore, the terms following such that rose. After all, I can clearly know something qua F and not know it qua G, even
verbs as "understand" or "know" appellate [i.e., obliquely refer to] the concepts
if it is both F and G, for I simply do not know that this F is also a G.
according to which they were imposed [to signify], but they do not so appellate
their concepts when they precede these verbs. It is for this reason that you have it To see that it is quite possible that I know the existence of that rose (which is
from Aristotle that this consequence is not valid: "I know Coriscus, and Coriscus is the same as the essence of that rose) qua the essence of that rose while I do not
the one approaching; therefore, I know the one approaching." And this is because to know the existence of that rose qua the existence of that rose, we should just
know the one approaching is to know the thing according to the concept according consider the perfectly analogous example from Aristotle, according to which it
to which it is called the one approaching. Now, although I know Coriscus, it does not is quite possible that I know the one approaching (who is Coriscus) qua Coriscus,
follow, even if he is the one approaching, that I recognise him under the concept but I do not know the one approaching qua the one approaching (for I see him
according to which I know him to be approaching. But this would be a valid exposi-
tory syllogism: "Coriscus I know; and Coriscus is the one approaching; therefore,
from afar and I do not recognise that he is Coriscus, which is the relevant sense
the one approaching I know." Therefore, the situation is similar in the case under of 'knowing' in this context).
consideration: I understand a rose, but I do not understand a rose to exist, although Thus, it seems that as long as we can know the same item qua some essence,
a rose to exist I understand. The same applies to the other case: I concede that I have but not qua some act of existence, it is quite possible for us to know the essence
scientific knowledge about roses and thunder in terms of several conclusions, yet I of a certain thing without knowing whether it exists or not, despite the fact that
do not have scientific knowledge about roses or thunder in terms of the conclusion its essence and existence are the same. Therefore, Aquinas's argument fails to
that a rose or thunder exists.' establish its desired conclusion, the real distinction of the essence and existence
Buridan's criticism, as can be seen, is based on his celebrated theory of appel- of a thing on the basis of the fact that we may know its essence without knowing
latio rationis, the theory according to which intentional verbs and their participles its existence.
make their grammatical direct objects following them appellate, that is, obliquely
refer to, their concepts. Indeed, if we make this oblique reference explicit, then 5. A THOMISTIC RESPONSE TO BURIDAN'S CRITICISM, AND ITS IMPLICATIONS
the proposed argument will obviously be invalid. For then, using Buridan's ex- But this does not have to be the end of the story for Aquinas. In fact, if we take
a closer look at Aquinas's actual formulation of the argument, we have to notice
something that is entirely neglected in the version of it criticised by Buridan;
namely, Aquinas's talking about "parts of the essence" without which it cannot
6 Buridan uses these sentential nominalisations equivalently with the abstract nouns
formed from their verbs. This issue need not detain us here. be understood. What can he possibly mean by this? And what is the relevance of
this to the validity of his argument?
' Ibid.
' Ibid.

174 • EXISTENCE EXISTENCE • 175


Gyula Klima Gyula Klima
AQUINAS VS. BURIDAN ON ESSENCE AND EXISTENCE AQUINAS VS. BURIDAN ON ESSENCE AND EXISTENCE

Since according to Aquinas the essence or quiddity of a thing is what is signi, radically different. For instance, suppose I have perfect quidditative knowledge of
fled in it by its quidditative definition9 and the essence of a thing in and of itself all things moving toward me as such. Therefore, anything that moves toward me I
is not a conglomerate of several distinct items, by "the parts of its essence", he know precisely insofar as it moves toward me. But I also know that anything that
means whatever is signified precisely by the parts of the quidditative definition moves toward me approaches and anything that approaches moves toward me.
of the thing.'° In fact, since on his interpretation the definition is not primarily Thus, it cannot be the case that I know the thing moving toward me insofar as it is
a linguistic expression, but an intention, that is, a concept of the mind expressed moving toward me and I do not know the same thing insofar as it is approaching.
by the corresponding linguistic expression rendering this expression meaningful, And this is because the concepts appellated by the phrases 'the thing moving
we can say that on Aquinas's conception having scientific, quidditative knowledge toward me' and 'the thing approaching' are logically equivalent; indeed, they
about a thing is having in mind its quidditative concept, expressible by a scientific, are the same.
quidditative definition. In this context, therefore, we need to distinguish be- Or consider another, perhaps more intuitive example. If I have the scientific
tween merely having some (no matter how vague and confused) concept of concept of a rainbow, say, as being the refraction of light on water suspended in
a thing, resulting from the mind's first, spontaneous abstractive act, and having air, then I cannot know a rainbow qua rainbow, without knowing it at the same
its quidditative concept, which is a clear and distinct, articulate concept, re- time qua the refraction of light on water suspended in air. To be sure, before
sulting from scientific enquiry into the nature of the thing." Having this sort forming the scientific concept, I can certainly have some vague and confused
of quidditative concept, therefore, means clearly knowing its implications: for knowledge of it as some colourful arch in the sky, without knowing it qua the
instance, if I have the clear and distinct quidditative knowledge of diamonds as refraction of light on water suspended in air. However, once I have formed its
being tetrahedrally crystallised pieces of carbon, then on account of having that quidditative concept, I cannot have knowledge of the same thing without knowing
concept, as well as the concept of electric conductivity, I know just as well that the implications of its quidditative concept.
diamonds are poor conductors (as opposed, say, to graphite). But then the situation would have to be similar with the notions of essence
Now what does all this mean concerning the validity of Aquinas's argument and existence, provided we are talking about the clear and distinct scientific
and its Buridanian criticism? Concerning Buridan's criticism we should note that understanding of a thing's essence, which involves having the articulate, quid-
the breakdown of the substitutivity of identicals on account of the appellation ditative concept of the thing, and knowing its logical implications. For in this
of concepts in intentional contexts is conditioned on the logical independence of situation, if the existence of the thing were the same as the essence of the thing,
the appellated concepts in terms of which one and the same thing is conceived, or, using Aquinas's phrase, it were "a part of" the essence of the thing, then this
known or understood. This is why it is possible for me to know, e.g., my father, would mean that having the quidditative cognition of the thing would entail also
and not to know the man approaching, even if the man approaching is actually having its cognition in terms of its existence: that is to say, we could not have its
my father. For I may certainly have the recognition of him in terms of the concept quidditative knowledge without knowing that it exists. Indeed, this is precisely
whereby I conceive of him as my father, while lacking the recognition of him what Aquinas hypothetically concedes in the conclusion of his argument:
insofar as I merely cognise him as the man approaching (insofar as 'having the Therefore, it is clear that existence is distinct from essence, unless, perhaps, there
recognition' of this person would mean being able to give an adequate answer is a thing whose quiddity is its own existence.
to a question asking about the identity of this person). But this is so because the
two acts of cognition in question are logically independent, whence I may perfectly That is to say, if there is a thing whose essence and existence are the same, then
well have the one without the other. having a clear and distinct cognition of the thing's essence would immediately
However, if the appellated concepts or acts of cognition are not logically inde- give us the knowledge that the thing exists, which is the exact reason why Aquinas
pendent, whence I cannot have the one without the other, then the situation is would say that although God's existence is self-evident in itself, that is, it would be
knowable a priori by anyone with a clear and distinct cognition of divine essence,
still, it is not self-evident to us, namely, human beings in our natural state, for in
9 See the end of c. 1 of De Ente et Essentia. The quidditative definition of the thing Aquinas
this state we just cannot have the clear and distinct cognition of divine essence
has there in mind is the definition of its most specific species consisting of its proximate genus
and its specific difference.
that would allow us to realise the self-evident character of His existence.'2
'° For this point see for instance the entire discussion of c. 4 of his De Ente et Essentia.
" For a painstaking and extremely illuminating discussion of distinct versus confused
concepts or acts of cognition, see q. 1 of Cajetan's commentary on Aquinas's De Ente et Essentia. 12 THOMAS AQUINAS, Summa theologiae 1, q. 2, a. 2.

176 • EXISTENCE EXISTENCE • 177


Gyula Klima Gyula Klima
AQUINAS VS. BURIDAN ON ESSENCE AND EXISTENCE AQUINAS VS. BURIDAN ON ESSENCE AND EXISTENCE

But then, how come Buridan didn't realise this point when he formulated know ing, on that account, the existence of these things, that is to say, knowing
his objection? Didn't he notice the possibility of the logical dependency of the their essence, we would have to know that they exist.
appellated concepts that would again render Aquinas's argument valid?
Without going into much detail, I would suggest that the answer to th e 6. A FINAL OBJECTION AND REPLY
questions is that on Buridan's conception of how our essential concepts latch Perhaps, the best way to explicate this last claim is to answer on Aquinas's be-
onto things in the world, our concept of the quiddity of a contingently existing ha lf one final objection." For on this understanding of Aquinas's position, one may
thing always has to be distinct and logically independent from our concept of the still raise the following objection: can I plausibly assume that I can have scientific
existence of that thing even if the thing in reality is both its own essence and knowledge of a certain kind of thing without knowing whether any singular
its own existence. For on Buridan's conception the quidditative definition of a thing of that kind exists at the moment, without also assuming that the essence and
certain specific kind of things signifies these things absolutely, whether they are existence of any singular thing of that kind are really distinct items in reality? If not, then
past, present, future or merely possible, while in the context of a present tense the argument, implicitly assuming its own conclusion is clearly question-begging.
proposition it supposits only for the presently existing ones, if there are any. In response, it would seem we might just ask back: do we acquire scientific
The term 'exists' on the other hand, supposits only for presently existing things. knowledge of the essence of ununoctium by learning that it is an element of atomic
Therefore, if the kind of thing in question merely contingently exists, then there number 118? One can certainly raise this question and answer it affirmatively
is no way for us to know on the basis of simply comprehending the definition of without even thinking about the issue of whether there are any presently exist-
this kind of thing whether even a single thing of this kind falls under term 'exist' ing samples of this very unstable element in any lab on earth (let alone in any
right now, i.e., whether it actually exists. uncharted parts of the physical universe). However, based on this affirmation,
The picture, however, is radically different with Aquinas's conception. For and then reflecting on the issue that we have no idea whether any atoms of this
Aquinas, our specific quidditative concept of a thing grasps precisely that formal element are in existence right now, one can, without further ado, accept the
content in the thing that essentially "shapes" the thing into the kind of thing it generalised premise that one can know the essence of a certain kind of thing
is. (A good illustration of what this formal content is would be the genetic code of without knowing its existence.
a biological species determining the essential features of the kind of organism However, relying on Buridan's objection, one might retort at once that I
pertaining to that species, or the configuration of the nuclei of elemental atoms could claim to have scientific knowledge of the essence of ununoctium only if
describable in terms of their atomic number, determining their electron-con- I knew its actual existence, provided its essence and existence were in fact the
figuration and thereby their essential chemical features.) Therefore, if this formal same. I may simply (mistakenly) think that I know its essence on the basis of this
content involves the existence of the thing, then it is impossible to form this definition, but in fact this is a very imperfect form of knowledge of that essence,
quidditative concept of any single thing of this kind without at the same time not explicating everything it involves, whence I claim to have knowledge of essence
forming the concept of its existence and conceiving of it as existent and thereby without knowing existence simply on the basis of having a rather lax criterion for
knowing that it exists. scientific knowledge, which, however, by stricter criteria, would have to contain
For Buridan, on the other hand, concept formation does not consist in this sort the knowledge of the existence of the thing, if the essence and existence of the
of mental grasping of a formal content. It is merely the formation of an indifferent thing are in fact the same. So, I can assume that I know the essence of the thing
mental representation of a certain kind of things, the content of which is nothing without its existence only by presuming the conclusion, which still leaves the
but those things themselves, regardless of whether they actually exist or not. argument begging the question.
But it is quite obvious that one could form a concept of this sort without forming In answering this retort, we must not forget that the charge of question-
the concept of the existence of any single thing of this kind. Thus, it appears begging (petitio principii) is the charge of an informal, epistemic fallacy (i.e., the
that in view of Buridan's objection formulated on the basis of his conception argument is not claimed to be invalid or unsound): according to this charge, one
of the mental representation of essence and existence, the issue of the validity cannot plausibly assume the premises without assuming the conclusion, i.e., the
of Aquinas's argument in the last analysis turns on Aquinas's own conception of knowledge of the premises cannot be obtained without a previous knowledge
mental representation. For the ultimate question is, whether Aquinas's conception of the conclusion (or something equivalent to it). So, a defender of an argument
can support the claim that if essence and existence were in general the same, then
their concepts could not be logically independently formed in our minds, and " I owe the original objection and the retort to my initial response to it to my student
thus we could not have the scientific knowledge of essences of things without Timothy Kieras S.I.

178 • EXISTENCE EXISTENCE • 179


Gyula Klima Gyula Klima
AQUINAS VS. BURIDAN ON ESSENCE AND EXISTENCE AQUINAS VS. BURIDAN ON ESSENCE AND EXISTENCE

so accused should be able to point out independent, plausible grounds for the has by virtue of having its essence) in order to know of some attribute that it is
acceptability of the premises. not
one of its essential attributes in this strict sense (just like I do not have to
That is precisely what I attempted in the first paragraph of this section know every place on earth in order to know that something is nowhere on this
with reference to ununoctium. But the retort, as I summarised it in the second ea rth, simply because I know that it is, say, on the moon). But then, I can certainly
paragraph of this section above, seems to undermine this attempt by claiming know the essence of the thing in terms of its scientific, quidditative definition, by
that as long as I do not know whether essence and existence are not the same I virtue of which I know a priori that every singular thing that had, has, will have,
cannot claim to have scientific knowledge of the essence of something without or can have that essence had, has, will have, or can have the attributes explicitly
knowing its existence, which may just not be explicated in the rather incomplete or implicitly involved in that definition (even if I may not explicitly know all the
knowledge of the essence I have in terms of the formulaic quidditative definition a ttributes involved in that definition in this way). However, at the same time, I
of the thing in question. know that by virtue of knowing the essence of all these singulars in terms of
However, this objection is based on a very, indeed, as I will argue, unreason. their quidditative definition I do not know of any of them a priori whether they
ably strong interpretation of what is required for the scientific knowledge of actually exist; I can only learn about their actual existence a posteriori. Therefore,
the essence of something. For let us not forget that for Aquinas the essence of even if I may not explicitly know all essential attributes of the thing a priori (while
something is whatever it is that its specific quidditative definition signifies in it. I do know some, namely, at least those explicated in the definition and those
So, if I have the specific quidditative definition of the thing, I do have scientific implications of this definition that I am aware of), I know that their existence is
knowledge of this essence (as opposed to the confused, pre-scientific knowledge not one of them; that is to say, I do have scientific knowledge of the essence of
I may have on the basis of knowing some generic and typical accidental attributes this kind of thing, but I do not have this knowledge of the existence of any single
of that kind of thing), and this may still not involve the existence of the thing. thing of that kind by virtue of having this knowledge.
Nevertheless, the objector might still claim that I do not have a sufficiently However, on the basis of this understanding of what is and what is not involved
clear and distinct knowledge of this essence until I know everything its essence in the scientific understanding of the essence of a thing one can plausibly concede
involves, i.e., all the essential attributes the thing has by virtue of having this to know scientifically what a certain kind of thing is and not to know whether any
essence, whereas a quidditative definition merely provides us explicitly with instance of that kind of thing actually exists without presuming, or even thinking
two specifying attributes (genus and specific difference, plus the more generic about, the issue of the real distinction of essence and existence. Therefore, Aqui-
attributes implied by these higher up on the Porphyrian Tree); and so, it may nas's argument proves this claim, without begging the question.
well be possible that existence is also among these essential attributes, just like But even if this defence answers the charge of its begging the question, one
any other essential attribute not explicated by the simple, formulaic definition, really big question still remains concerning the demonstrative force of Aquinas's
Do we really understand, for instance, everything that is essentially involved in argument. If it can be "saved" from Buridan's criticism only with appealing to
having a rational nature? If not, then it may well be the case that existence is one Aquinas's own interpretation of the notion of essence as it is described in his
of those things, but we claim to ignore it, simply because it is not explicated by own conceptual framework, whereas Buridan's criticism seems to be justified
the definition. in his conceptual framework, does this mean that there is no absolute answer to
But it is at this point that the unreasonably strong requirement for the scien- the question whether the essence and existence of at least some creatures are
tific knowledge of essence becomes explicit. The retort in this form assumes that really distinct? In other words, do we have to make our answer relative to the
we can have scientific knowledge of essence only if we are able to explicate a priori conceptual framework of each author, thereby somehow trivialising both their
all the essential attributes a thing has by virtue of having that essence. But this is disagreement and the metaphysical point of the thesis itself?
an unreasonably strong requirement, for scientific knowledge of specific essences I would briefly reply that we do have to make our answer concerning the
certainly does not require a priori, logical omniscience (i.e., the claim that if x's validity of Aquinas's argument relative to the conceptual framework in which it is
having F implies its having G, then if I know that x is an F, then I know that x is evaluated, but this still will not trivialise the issue. For even if we have to say that
a G; for then by knowing the axioms I would have to know all conclusions of any Aquinas's argument is demonstrative in his own conceptual framework, but not
axiomatic deductive science, which is simply not the case). Thus, I certainly can in Buridan's, this does not mean that their disagreement is something as trivial
have scientific knowledge of some essence without knowing all attributes a thing as a mere verbal disagreement. For in the case of mere verbal disagreement, the
must have by virtue of having that essence. Furthermore, and more importantly, parties can easily resolve their apparent disagreement by simply "re-labelling"
I do not have to know all essential attributes of a thing (i.e., attributes the thing the concepts they both share, but simply express by different terms. However, with

180 • EXISTENCE EXISTENCE • 181


Gyula Klima
AQUINAS VS. BURIDAN ON ESSENCE AND EXISTENCE

the disagreement between Aquinas and Buridan the case is just the reverse: they
share the same words in the same language to express their own, rather different
concepts of essence and existence, fitting into radically different conceptual
frameworks, based on their very different conceptions of how our concepts latch
onto things in reality. SECTION V
Therefore, if we want to deliver judgement on the demonstrative force of
the argument without talking past Aquinas, but also taking into account the
historically accumulated different conceptual frameworks in which it can still
be competently evaluated, then we should evaluate not only the argument it-
self, and not only relative to this or that conceptual framework, but we should
also evaluate those frameworks themselves. However, that is a whole new ball
MODALITIES
game, requiring the consideration of overall consistency, explanatory force and
comprehensiveness of entire systems of thought in a conceptual framework that
accommodates them all, in the sense of making all their claims and arguments
at least logically commensurable with each other. This is certainly a difficult task;
nevertheless, once we are aware of what it involves, it should not be impossible.
After all, the very existence of this paper should demonstrate that such a con-
ceptual framework is at least possible; we just need to work it out to make it
actual.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

AQUINAS, THOMAS. "On Being and Essence". In Medieval Philosophy: Essential Readings with
Commentary, edited by G. Klima, 227-249. Blackwell Publishers, 2007.
— Summa theologiae. Corpus Thomisticum. Textum Leoninum Romae 1888 editum ac
automato translatum a Roberto Busa SJ in taenias magneticas denuo recognovit En-
rique Alarcon atque instruxit. (http://www.corpusthomisticum.oresth°000.html)
BURIDAN, JOHANNES. Quaestiones in Aristotelis Metaphysicam: Kommentar zur Aristotelischen
Metaphysik. Paris, 1518. Reprint, Frankfurt am Main: Minerva, 1964.
— Quaestiones in Aristotelis Metaphysicam. Selections from lb. 8, q. 4. Emended ad sensum and
translated by Gyula Klima. In Medieval Philosophy: Essential Readings with Commentary,
edited by Gyula Klima, 250-253. Blackwell Publishers, 2007.
CAJETANUS, THOMAS DE VIO, CARDINALIS. "Super Librum De Ente et Essentia Sancti Tho-
mae". In Opuscula Omnia, 299. Bergomi: Typis Comini Venturae, 1590.
KENNY, ANTHONY. Aquinas on Being. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002.
KLIMA, GYULA. "On Kenny on Aquinas on Being: A critical review of Aquinas on Being
by Anthony Kenny". Feature review in International Philosophical Quarterly 44 (2004):
567-580.

182 • EXISTENCE
POTENTIALITY IN SCHOLASTICISM (POTENTIAE)
AND THE CONTEMPORARY DEBATE ON "POWERS"
Edmund Runggaldier

ABSTRACT
Scholastic philosophers distinguished between potentiae in a logical sense (potentiae ob-
iectivae) on the one hand and potentiae in the sense of capacities or active dispositions of living
beings or real things (potentiae subiectivae) on the other. They were familiar with two different
accounts of modality. One corresponds in a certain sense to the modern possible-worlds-
approach; the other has its basis in everyday life, i.e., in our experience of having certain
capacities and acting accordingly: We bring about certain states of affairs. Nowadays we have
a similar duality of approaches to the problem of powers and active dispositions, and a new
debate on agent causation.

1. INTRODUCTION
Empiricist and conventionalist philosophers reduced disposition-ascriptions
to conditional statements: an object or individual has a disposition D towards
some manifestation M in certain conditions C iff that object would display M if
exposed to C. On this reductive account, there is no explanatory work left for
dispositions to do. Disposition-ascriptions do not explain why an event happens;
they do only state, in an abbreviated manner, that one event follows another in
certain circumstances.
The reductionist approach has been subject to criticism in recent years.
Stephen Mumford,' George Molnar,' Brian Ellis,' Alexander Bird4 - to name just a
few - have argued against a mere conditional analysis of dispositions, and pleaded
for a realist understanding instead: dispositions are irreducible properties whose
reality is not exhausted by their manifestations. They thus figure among the basic
furniture of the world, existing independently of whether they are manifested.
Being disposed to shatter or to dissolve are real properties that distinguish

1 S. MUMFORD, Dispositions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998); Laws in Nature, (London:
Routledge, 2004).
2 G. MOLNAR, Powers: A Study in Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003).

' B. ELLIS, Scientific Essentialism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001); The Philo-
sophy of Nature (Chesham: Acumen, 2002).
' A. BIRD, Nature's Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).

MODALITIES • 185
Edmund Runggaldier Edmund Runggaldier
POTENTIALITY IN SCHOLASTICISM POTENTIALITY IN SCHOLASTICISM

their bearers from objects that lack them, even if these bearers never shatter or senses or accounts of dispositions and powers, but on this Aristotelian approach
dissolve. Thoroughgoing argumentation for claims such as these has rehabilitated they are ontologically primary.
dispositions and powers in metaphysical debates. There are similarities between the contemporary and the scholastic reasons
The reasons for the claim that dispositions and powers are real, irreducible of r maintaining dispositions and powers in one's ontology. The greater ontologi-
properties, stem mainly from two fields: recent realist accounts in the philosophy ca l contexts of agency and causality which provide a backdrop for these reasons
of science, especially the philosophy of chemistry and biology on the one hand are, however, different between the contemporary and scholastic accounts. To
and the presuppositions we harbour when interacting with macroscopic objects appreciate the scholastic account as an alternative worthy of consideration, it is
in our everyday life, including living beings on the other. helpful to see in more detail the diverging ontological frameworks.
According to some philosophers of science (see, e.g., Cartwright% dispositions The scholastic ontology of dispositions is, first of all, grounded in the ontology
play an essential part in the scientific picture of reality. Therefore, if we want to of their bearers. The reality of dispositions depends on the reality of agents ha-
stick to this picture, they cannot be eliminated. Chemical substances and ele- ving them. This presupposes a multi-categorical ontology with substances and
ments, for instance, are typically characterised in terms of the dispositions they properties. The account of their causal role, then, is different too. For explanatory
have. Their identity does not depend on subjective factors such as conventions, purposes contemporary realists assume that dispositions and powers have causal
decisions, or opinions, but on their objective valences. In fact, chemists do not roles, but in the Aristotelian scholastic ontology their causal role is derivative. It
explain chemical reactions mechanistically, using exclusively categorical terms, is their bearers that are causally efficacious. Dispositional explanations of events
but by reference both to external triggering causes and to internal dispositions. thus ultimately refer to things being - in a wide sense - agents. This presupposes
A look at scientific practice thus suggests that we must not let go of dispositions that it is not only conscious beings endowed with intentionality which are agents,
and powers if we want to account for the various processes that take place in but so are other living beings and even inorganic macroscopic objects. To talk of
nature. things acting and reacting does not imply that one attributes intentional atti-
The assumption that dispositions are real properties is central to our everyday tudes to inanimate things, but it does imply a more complex theory of causality.
life as well. We quite naturally ascribe dispositions to other persons and to The Aristotelian conception of causality is, as we will see, wider than mere event
animals, as well as to materials, and even to machines. In order to understand causality or causality in the Humean sense.
the behaviour of other persons, we want to know their convictions, character
traits and habits, all of which are dispositional in nature. Dispositional realism is 2. MAIN SCHOLASTIC DISTINCTIONS
thus deeply rooted in our conception of the world: the assumption that the macro- Scholastics distinguished between potentiae subjectivae and potentiae objectivae:
scopic objects we interact with - be they persons, animals, plants, etc. - have "subjective potencies" are dispositions and powers inherent to a subject or bearer.
various tendencies, capacities, powers, etc., is fundamental for our orientation "Subjective" in this context means predicable of a real subject or individual.
in everyday life. Hence, not only do the microscopic worlds of chemistry and the Typical examples of subjective potencies are our own capacities and powers: We
biological sciences support the dispositionalist view, so does our daily acquaint- are, due to certain dispositions and powers, capable of acting and doing certain
ance with the macroscopic world of everyday life. things.
The scholastic approach in the Aristotelian tradition to the problem of dispo- Potentiae subjectivae are not only instantiated in persons, but in other living
sitions and powers is centred on everyday life, i.e., our Lebenswelt, in particular on beings as well and, as mentioned, even in everyday things. They are real pro-
our personal experience of being agents. This experience of being able to act and perties, belonging to real things, and are thus called "potentiae reales" as well:
react is the key notion for understanding what power ascriptions consist in. We they are not conceived of as mere possibilities existing in another possible world
experience ourselves as having the power to change our environment and thus to accessible from our own world. Potentiae subjectivae are integral parts of the world
change ourselves too. The scholastic assumption that dispositions and powers are we inhabit. That they are real properties means that objects having them in this
real properties is grounded in the firm belief that we are able to do certain things world are able to do or to receive certain things (potentia rei existentis ad aliquid
and that it is the disposition which makes all the difference between being able faciendum vel recipiendum).6
and not being able to do these things. This does not exclude that there are other

5 N. CARTWRIGHT, Nature's Capacities and their Measurement (Oxford: Oxford University


Press, 1989). 6 J. DONAT, Ontologia (Oeniponte: Felicianus Rauch, 1953), 32.

186 • MODALITIES MODALITIES • 187


Edmund Runggaldier Edmund Runggaldier
POTENTIALITY IN SCHOLASTICISM POTENTIALITY IN SCHOLASTICISM

The scholastics contrasted the potentiae subjectivae with the potentiae objectivae tra des, i.e., active and passive incapacities. Potency, capacity, power, and their
"objective potencies" are potentialities as mere possibilities. Potentia in this sens contraries are the basic notions for the account of possibilities and impossibilities.'
of objectiva simply means that something can exist or be real (aptitudo ad exis. incapacity or impossibility is the privation (privatio) of potency. For something
tendum..., ad modum rei recipientis existentiam). As a merely possible entity it does to be a privation, however, two conditions are required: (1) the absence of the
not exist in the actual world (reapse non existit..., non est quidquam reale existens), it is Opposite state; (2) the privation must belong to a bearer or definite subject at a
thus called "potentia logica" as well, something conceived in the mind or captured definite time. To be blind, i.e., to be incapable of seeing, is a typical privatio. But
as mental content (non existit nisi tamquam objectum in mentis repraesentatione).7 only that is said to be blind which is naturally fitted to have sight and at the time
Potentia objectiva and logica, not being a real property, does not need a bearer. when it is naturally fitted to have it.'"
Potentia in both its senses is always seen in relation to its manifestation or On the other hand, some modalities are accounted for in an objective or logical
realisation, called its "actus". It is the actus which is primary or fundamental, sense, i.e. in the sense of the modern possible-worlds approach. For example, it
both on the epistemic and ontological levels. It would not be possible to acquire is impossible that the diagonal of a square should be commensurable with a side.
knowledge of potencies without knowledge of their manifestations or actuali- "Impossible" in this context means that the statement that it is commensurable
sations and there would not be any potency without the actus. is necessarily false."
The actus, on the other hand, is twofold. In the most general sense the actus is The most basic of the various senses of the modalities "possibility" and "im-
simply the realisation of something possible, i.e., of a potentia objectiva, whereas possibility", however, is that of being capable or incapable: an event or action is
in the strict or fundamental sense it is the realisation or manifestation of a possible when its bearer or subject can change, otherwise it is impossible. All the
real capacity or a power, i.e., of a potentia subjectiva. Scholastics distinguished other senses of "capable" or "potent" refer to this kind of potency."
accordingly between first act (actus primus) and second act (actus secundus). In To sum up: For Aquinas and the scholastics the proper notion of possibility, in
the case of a realisation in the first sense some object or living being begins to the primary sense of potency, refers to the capacity to change."
exist, whereas in the second case some existing object begins to act or some living
being starts to operate. 3. THE ARISTOTELIAN BACKGROUND
In the Aristotelian tradition events are changes understood as realisations Aristotelian ontologies are multi-categorical: beside the fundamental dis-
of potencies. They are shifts from potentiae to actus. According to the above- tinction between the first category of individual things and living beings, i.e.
mentioned distinction, these changes are twofold: they can be realisations of substances on the one hand and the categories of properties and other accidental
potentiae objectivae, possibilities in a wide sense or possible entities, i.e., actus primi, determinations on the other, there is the distinction between that which is real
or realisations of potentiae subjectivae, dispositions or powers, i.e., actus secundi. or actualised (v-rEXExEia, in actu) and that which is merely possible (SuvcipEt, in
The key for understanding actus as the realisation or actualisation of a potentia potentia). We read in Aristotle:
is our experience as acting agents: we act and operate in virtue of our capacities as
And since 'being' is in one way divided into individual thing, quality, and quantity,
potentiae subjectivae. Aquinas summarises the point at the beginning of his quaestio and is in another way distinguished in respect of potency (xath Stivaptv) and
de potentia: "...we must observe that we speak of power in relation to act. [...] the complete reality (v-reAgxEtav), and of function (Kat& TO gqyov), let us now add
word 'act' was first universally employed in the sense of operation..." 8 a discussion of potency and complete reality."
Scholastics distinguished further between potentia activa as the capacity to act
actively, for example deciding, speaking or doing something, and potentia passiva Change or movement is accordingly the passage from a potential or possible
as the capacity.to be affected or to receive something, i.e., between the power state to a real one and vice versa. Aristotelian ontologies are thus characterised
of acting and that of being acted upon. If something has the capacity to change by a kind of tension between potency (potentia) and actuality (actus).
another thing, this other thing has the capacity to be changed. If it is impossible
9THOMAS AQUINAS, In Duodecim Libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelis [In Met.] V, lect. 14.
to alter it, it lacks the necessary potentia passiva.
" Ibid., n. 967.
The scholastic account of the modalities of "possible" and "impossible" is
grounded in the distinction between active and passive potencies and their con- " Ibid., n. 971.
" Ibid., n. 975.
Ibid. " Ibid., n. 976.
8 THOMAS AQUINAS, De potentia, q. 1, a. 1, co. " ARISTOTLE, Metaphysics IX, 1, 1045 b 33 ff (ed. and transl. W. D. Ross).

188 • MODALITIES MODALITIES • 189


Edmund Runggaldier Edmund Runggaldier
POTENTIALITY IN SCHOLASTICISM POTENTIALITY IN SCHOLASTICISM

The topic of book IX is potency (5Uvaptc) and actuality (bagya.a, vrEXexetc) Besides, Aristotle and the scholastics were not sensitive to the modern notion
i.e., the tension between that which is possible and that which is real or actual' of consciousness. Nonetheless, they distinguished between rational or mental
The background of the Aristotelian approach to this division is, however, not the capacities and natural ones. Rational capacities are those potentiae subjectivae
distinction between merely possible worlds and our actual world, but rather the which are not directed toward one single type of manifestation, but towards
experience of planning for the future, deliberating, and deciding: we take into contraries. For example, men who have learnt an art possess capacities to do
consideration the real possibilities we have in our everyday-life world, which We contrary things. A doctor who possesses the art of healing is capable of healing as
live in. well as making sick. Natural or physical potencies on the other hand are directed
Aristotle distinguishes in book IX in detail between the different kinds or toward only one manifestation.
modes of potency hinted at in book V and relates them to a primary kind, easily We read in Aristotle:
accessible or experienceable in everyday life, which is, ultimately, the capacity And all those potencies which are rational are open to contrary determinations, and
to change. When things change, living beings included, they actualise certain those which are irrational are each determined to one thing; for example, what is
possibilities and thereby lose others. Change is - as we have seen - passing from hot is capable of heating, whereas the medical art is concerned with both sickness
a possible state to an actual one. and health."
In book V Aristotle defines "potency" (Soyaptc) in the most general sense as Since potencies are real only if instantiated in a bearer or substance, one has
the "principle of change" in things, and in the narrower sense as the power of to analyse them in relation to the things in which they are found. Potencies differ
producing change or of being changed. He thus refers explicitly to that which
has potency (-th Suva-thv)." In book IX Aristotle also characterises potency as the from each other on the basis of a difference in their subjects.
power to produce change or motion, in both an active and a passive sense. Potency
4. EFFICIENT CAUSATION
presupposes the reality of a bearer's having this power.
The causal efficacy of powers is due to some more basic kind of reality, i.e., to In scholastic philosophy potencies and powers, potentiae subjectivae, have
the reality of individual substances or things. These do the acting, as we shall see. a causal role, but this role is derivative. The proper causae are their bearers. The
Aristotle, in fact, explicitly refers to his treatment of primary or basic reality, to presupposition for this understanding is a plurality of senses of 'cause', one of
substance, the category to which all other categories imply a reference." them being the so-called efficient cause. Efficient causes are not to be confused
Aquinas comments that Aristotle accordingly points out, first, that he has al- with necessary and sufficient conditions as explanans of an explanandum in the
ready discussed the primary, most basic kind of reality (de ente primo) to which all modern sense.
the other categories are referred, namely, substance. All other entities - quantity, The scholastic notion of efficient cause corresponds in a broad way to what we
quality, and the like - involve and presuppose substance. One can speak about nowadays call "agent causation". The natural way of characterising this type of
them only by speaking about the individuals which have them (dicuntur secundum causation is to refer to our experience of making something or bringing it about
rationem substantiae). Predicating quantity, for example, is predicating the mea- that something be the case: I am the source of my own activity.
sure of substance, and predicating quality is predicating a certain disposition of Of course, the defence of agent causation by reference to this experience
substance. Qualities are real as some or other disposition of a substance (quaedam is controversial. Those defending agent causation contend, however, that the
dispositiones substantiae). The definition too of any property includes a proper commonsense view of ourselves as fundamental causal agents is theoretically
bearer or subject; in order to define, for example, "snub" it is necessary to refer understandable, internally consistent, and consistent with what we have come
to the nose which has a certain form.i7As we can see, this Aristotelian multi- to know about the nature and workings of the natural world. They understand
categorical substance ontology clearly differs from the modern mono-categorical agent causation as a species of the more primitive "causal production", underlying
ontologies. realist or non-Humean conceptions of causation.
The idea of causal production corresponds to the wider notion of efficient
causation in the Aristotelian tradition as is apparent from the Aristotelian defi-
nition: Aristotle defines efficient cause as "that from which the first beginning
15 Met. V, 12, 1019 a 32 ff. of change or of rest comes [...]; for example, an adviser is a cause, and a father is
16 Met. IX, 1, 1045 b 27.
"7 THOMAS AQUINAS, In Met. IX, lect. 1, n. 1768. IS Met. IX, 2, 1046 b 4-7.

190 • MODALITIES MODALITIES • 191


Edmund Runggaldier Edmund Runggaldier
POTENTIALITY IN SCHOLASTICISM POTENTIALITY IN SCHOLASTICISM

the cause of a child, and in general a maker is a cause of the thing made, and a but not in the same way. For it is impossible that there should be many proper
changer a cause of the thing changed."'9 causes of the same thing within the same genus and in the same order.23
Agent causation in the Aristotelian tradition is not limited to conscious inter'.
tional beings: it is predicable of inanimate things as well. Actio is synonymous 5. CONCLUSION
with doing, making, or producing, and is thus intimately linked to the notion of We have seen that scholastic philosophers distinguished between potentiae
power or potentia subjectiva. ubjectivae, as capacities or active dispositions of living beings and real things
s
In order to avoid misunderstandings it should be said that the relation of
on the one hand and potentiae objectivae in a logical sense, as mere possibilities
causing in the sense of efficient causation holds not between the agent and her on the other. They were correspondingly familiar with two different accounts of
action or her doing, but between the agent and the effect of the doing: The actio
modalities, one rooted in everyday life, i.e. in our experience of having certain
is not the efficient cause's effect; instead, it is the very nature of the causing:
capacities and acting accordingly, the other corresponding in a certain sense to
"... actionem autem non esse effectum causae efficientis, sed rationem causandi..."20 the modern possible-worlds approach. The more basic account is for them the
At the beginning of modernity the Aristotelian causes came under attack, and first one. It presupposes agent causation in a wide sense, however, understood
so scholastics like Suarez tried to clarify them. Suarez even concedes a certain as the causa efficiens. Scholastic philosophers defended the reality and the causal
obscurity of the notion of efficient causation but defends it by referring to its role role of powers by appeal to their bearers: The reality of dispositions depends on
in everyday life. We know by experience, by the experience of acting and bringing the reality of agents having them. This presupposes a multi-categorical ontology
it about that something is the case, that we are agents and thus efficient causes. with substances and properties. For explanatory purposes contemporary realists
Suarez refers to the first example of an advisor given by Aristotle: it is a personal assume that dispositions and powers have causal roles, but in the Aristotelian
cause, a human person acting on another person. "An advising cause of an effect scholastic ontology their causal role is derivative. What is causally efficacious are
E is, roughly, a rational agent who, by means of counsel, inducement, provocation, the living beings and the things having causal powers.
request, persuasion, threat, command, prohibition, etc., influences another agent
to contribute freely to E.""
To characterise agency and agent causality by the activity of acting or pro-
ducing seems circular. Suarez sees the danger of a certain circularity of the
Aristotelian account of agent causation. He is not bothered, however, since many
philosophical notions have circular explications. Nowadays we would say that
some philosophical notions are primitive or basic.
Efficient causality does not exclude event causality. The two corresponding
kinds of explanation can complement each other. Suarez himself declares that
in the realm of nature an efficient cause always acts via changes or events and
points out that according to Aristotle a natural cause always acts through motion
or change: "... si Aristotelis mentem inspiciamus, videtur quidem solum definivisse causam
efficientem naturalem, quae semper agit per motum vel mutationem." 22
Since the term "cause" is used in many senses, it is possible that one and the
same state of affairs or phenomenon has several causes. The maker of a statue is a
proper cause and not an accidental cause of the statue, and so also is the bronze,

19 Met. V, 2,1013 a 29-32.


20 F. SUAREZ, Disputationes Metaphysicae, d. 17, s. 1, n. 5.
21 A. F. FREDDOSO, Note 4 in F. Suarez, On Efficient Causality. Metaphysical Disputations, trans!.

by A. J. Freddoso (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1994), 8.


22 SUAREZ Disputationes Metaphysicae, d. 17, s. 1, n. 4. 23 THOMAS AQUINAS, In Met. V, left. 2, n. 773.

192 • MODALITIES MODALITIES • 193


-.r
POTENTIALITY IN SCHOLASTICISM
BIBLIOGRAPHY
AQUINAS, THOMAS. In Duodecim Libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelis. Cura et studio P. Fr. m...R,
Cathala et P. Fr. R. M. Spiazzi. Taurini: Marietti, 1964.
— De potentia. Vol. 2 of Quaestiones disputatae. Cura et studio R. P. Pauli M. Passion. Taurini: DISPOSITIONAL NECESSITY
Marietti, 1965. AND ONTOLOGICAL POSSIBILITY
ARISTOTLE, Aristotle's Metaphysic. A Revised Text with Introduction and Commentary David Peroutka
by W. D. Ross. 2 vols. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1924. Reprint, Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1997.
BIRD, ALEXANDER., Nature's Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.
CARTWRIGHT, NANCY. Nature's Capacities and their Measurement. Oxford: Oxford University ABSTRACT
Press, 1989. Potency (disposition, power) is a property leading necessarily to an effect, whenever
DONAT, JOSEPH. Ontologia. Oeniponte: Felicianus Rauch, 1953. its bearer is suitably tested. A power belongs to the essence of the corresponding quality, it
ELLIS, BRIAN. Scientific Essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001. belongs to it as its relation to some (possible) effect. if powers belong to the essence of qualities,
a qualified thing, qua qualified, necessarily has the corresponding power. As a power ascription
— The Philosophy of Nature. Chesham: Acumen, 2002. can be substituted with a conditional sentence, we may formulate the following proposition:
MOLNAR, GEORGE. Powers: A Study in Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003. Necessarily (in all possible worlds): a qualified thing is tested in relation to some power corresponding
MUMFORD, STEPHEN. Dispositions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998. to its quality —■ it manifests this power. Having defined the notion of causal potency I offer then
an account of ontological possibility, i.e. possibility founded not only on logical non-contra-
— Laws in Nature. London: Routledge, 2004). diction, but also on causal powers, dispositions or potencies. Causal accessibility of two dif-
SUAREZ, FRANCISCUS. Disputationes Metaphysicae. Vol. 25-26 of Opera Omnia. Parisiis: apud 1 ferent worlds means that the two worlds differ from one another by some causal process or
processes ("distinguishing" causal processes), and that the two worlds share each bearer of
Ludovicum Vives, 1861.
potency, which in one of them manifests its potency by initiating some distinguishing causal
— On Efficient Causality. Metaphysical Disputations. Translated by A. J. Freddoso. New Haven: process. The ontologically possible can then be defined as something that exists in some
Yale University Press, 1994. causally accessible world.

1. INTORDUCTION
The first aim of this paper is to show the necessity of causal connexions by
means of an ontological analysis of what is called "potency" in the Aristotelian
tradition and "power" or "disposition" in contemporary philosophy. I will argue
that the modality of necessity is needed for feasible conditional analysis or defi-
nition of potency.
The second aim is to give an account of possibility founded not only on logical
non-contradiction, but also on the notion of causal powers or potencies. In the
last section I will argue that something is ontologically possible if there are active
and passive causal capabilities enabling its production (which happens either
immediately or as a result of a causal chain).

2. CONDITIONAL ANALYSIS OF DISPOSITIONAL PREDICATES


In order to introduce the topic of dispositions, I first have to describe the
problem of the conditional analysis of dispositional predicates.

194 MODALITIES • 195


David Peroutka David Peroutka
DISPOSITIONAL NECESSITY AND ONTOLOGICAL POSSIBILITY DISPOSITIONAL NECESSITY AND ONTOLOGICAL POSSIBILITY

The conditional analysis of dispositions tells us that a disposition ascription Let us suppose that the conditional analysis does not hold, because it is pos-
such as "x has disposition to an effect (1)" can be adequately paraphrased by a cop. sible that the object having the disposition in question is suitably tested without
ditional sentence of the following type: "if x is/were suitably tested, x manifests/ showing its disposition, i.e. without producing the effect. Let us suppose that the
would manifest P". For example the disposition ascription "wood is combustible. following formula sometimes may be true:
can be analysed by the conditional sentence "if wood is/were left in fire, it burns/
would burn". -.((x has disposition to D) --• (if x is suitably tested, x manifests (b))
This analysis is correct, if the disposition ascription and the corresponding
conditional sentence are equivalent: Let us consider two objects both having dispositions and both being suitably
tested. Given our suppositions, it is possible that one of the two objects manifests
(x has disposition to 0) 4-• (if x is suitably tested, x manifests (I)) its disposition, while the other does not. Since we suppose that both objects do
have their dispositions and both tests are suitable, there is not a sufficient reason for
It cannot be denied that if the conditional sentence is true, then the disposition such a divergence. Therefore if anyone wants to refute the conditional analysis
ascription must also be true: and (consequently) allow this kind of divergence, he also has to drop the principle
of sufficient reason. If we are determined to retain the principle of sufficient
(if x is suitably tested, x manifests 0) —• (x has disposition to (I)) reason, we have to retain the conditional analysis as well.
In this way my assumption of the accuracy of the conditional analysis is re-
But various philosophers have denied the inverse direction: duced to another more basic assumption, that of the validity of the principle of
sufficient reason. By this principle I mean the claim that no state of affairs can
(x has disposition to (1)) —• (if x is suitably tested, x manifests 4b) obtain, and no statement can be true unless there is sufficient reason why it
should not be otherwise. Without trustworthy general validity of this principle,
Charles B. Martin offered the following counter-example. It could be the case the world would not be very intelligible. Whenever we look for an explanation, a
that a live wire is connected to an electro-fink, which is a device that detects truthmaker, a cause, a justification of some statement, we implicitly presuppose
when the wire is about to be touched, and instantaneously renders the wire and confirm the validity of the principle of sufficient reason. In this paper the
dead. But according to the conditional analysis "the wire is live" means "if the recourse to the principle shall be a "refrain" of my argumentation.
wire is touched by a conductor then electric current flows from the wire to the Even if my reader is not convinced of the necessary validity of the principle of
conductor". Therefore the conditional analysis fails...' sufficient reason, I hope he regards its violation (i.e. the absolute non-availability
I do not think that this objection is fatal. Each description of a test implicitly of a required explanation) as a strange situation. I hope he agrees that every good
includes suitable conditions for the test. By "suitable test" I mean a test (1) cor- theory refuses to suppose such situations as long as it is not necessary to allow
responding to the given disposition, (2) carried out under favourable conditions them. Violation of the principle of sufficient reason might be declared possible
and without hindrances. Saying that a match lights up when suitably struck, we only if there were a case in which it would be necessary to allow it. But why should
implicitly suppose the presence of oxygen and the absence of water at the moment it ever be necessary?
of the described test. Such an implicit assumption can always be made explicit. In Now let us begin our research of the necessity involved in the application of
the case of the live wire we may protect our conditional analysis against Martin's a disposition. Rudolf Carnap drew attention to the question of how to formalise
objection by extending the description of the test: exclude explicitly the influence the conditional analysis. Certainly we cannot do it by means of a material impli-
of an electro-fink for the moment of testing. cation (test —• manifestation). Since the falsity of such a material implication
Martin's objection would merit a more elaborate answer; however this is requires (in all cases) the truth of the antecedent describing the test, then the
not the main concern of this paper. I do not want to prove the accuracy of the whole sentence is true of every untested object, and therefore it would ascribe
conditional analysis; my goal is to prove the causal necessity. The conditional the disposition to every untested object.' Therefore we need to use a modally
analysis is only one of many prerequisites. Nevertheless, since this assumption
can be called into question more than other assumptions, I will add the following 2 RUDOLF CARNAP, "Testability and Meaning", in Readings in the Philosophy of Science,
argument in favour of it. ed. H. Feigl et M. Brodbeck (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1953), 52-53. Reprinted
from Philosophy of Science 3 (1936); 4 (1937). In this paper Carnap tries to resolve the problem
CHARLES B. MARTIN, "Dispositions and Conditionals", Philosophical Quaterly 44 (1994): 2. by means of a "reductive sentence", but his analysis is applicable only in the case of tested

196 • MODALITIES MODALITIES • 197


David Peroutka David Peroutka
DISPOSITIONAL NECESSITY AND ONTOLOGICAL POSSIBILITY DISPOSITIONAL NECESSITY AND ONTOLOGICAL POSSIBILITY

reinforced implication' ❑(test manifestation). In this paper I will try to show With Stephen Mumford we may argue for the numerical identity of a disposi-
that the ontological reasons for the application of necessitation consist in saying tion with its qualitative basis (with quality or qualities). We sufficiently explain
that power or disposition belongs essentially to the qualitative constitution on the behaviour of physical things by their qualities. The "causal role" is occupied
which it is based. If the needed necessity is found, the Carnap problem will be by q ualities. A disposition conceived as something additional, non-identical with
resolved, the Humean account of causality will be refuted, and the concept of the corresponding qualitative constitution would be quite superfluous; it would
natural law will be clarified. not serve an explanation. If there are (causally relevant) dispositions at all, they
are identical with their qualitative grounds.'
3. How DISPOSITION IS ESSENTIALLY IDENTIFIED WITH QUALITY Mumford says that the difference between a quality and the corresponding
Sidney Shoemaker argued that a disposition essentially belongs to its qualita- disposition is similar to the Fregean difference between the morning star and
tive basis. His argument goes as follows. We come to know (qualitative) properties the evening star in the case of Venus.6 This comparison is not exact since it is
only thanks to their causal potentialities, to dispositions or powers based in them not essential for the morning star to be the evening star. However, I agree with
(for example their dispositions to influence our senses). If dispositions didn't Mumford that the difference between quality and corresponding disposition is
belong to the corresponding (qualitative) properties essentially, "a thing might a conceptual one: we can conceive the same accident in two different manners -
undergo radical change with respect to its properties without undergoing any according to its two essential aspects: (1) according to its basic qualitative aspect
change in its causal powers..." Such a situation implies "that it is impossible for and (2) according to its dispositional aspect. For example we may describe the
us to know various things which we take ourselves to know", because on these same accidental property of a stone as "round shape" or as "disposition to roll".
suppositions "there would be no way in which a particular property could be
picked up so as to have a name attached to it..."4 4. THE QUESTION OF "PROPERTY MONISM"
To Shoemaker's argument I will add another one. If dispositions do not belong Against the thesis of identity (property monism) it may be objected that
to qualities essentially, the following situation would be possible: two objects differ in a micro-world there are dispositions without any basis describable in a non-
in dispositions without differing in qualities. Since each disposition ascription can dispositional manner. The nuclear physicist and philosopher Ian J. Thompson
be translated into a conditional sentence, it follows that the conditional if the object wrote: "For suppose that the exact shape and size of an object were known, the
were tested, it would manifest the effect would be false about one of our objects, but shapes and sizes of all its constituents, along with a list of these facts at every
true about the other. Where is the sufficient reason for such a divergence? There time. We would still know nothing about how or why the object would change
is no truthmaker, which could justify this divergence in the truth-value of the with time or on interactions."' S. Mumford cannot give a sufficient answer, since
sentence about qualitatively equal objects. If we want to avoid these consequences he conceives the "categorical basis" of disposition only as "shape and structure"
which violate the principle of sufficient reason, we have to accept the thesis that or "shape, macrostructure and microstructure".9 George Molnar challenged
a disposition is essential to the qualitative constitution in which it is grounded. Mumford's monism at this point: "In the case of essential properties of the fun-
damental subatomic particles we have, on the very best of experimental and
dispositions. We may object that we need to define the term "disposition" ascribable also to theoretical evidence, no reason for supposing that they have a non-dispositional
non-tested objects. Sometimes we do ascribe disposition to non-tested objects: "...a certain or qualitative nature (certainly not a nature exemplified by size and shape).".°
nuclear fuel may have a disposition to explode, which justifies the taking of special precautions in its
use, even if (thanks to those precautions) no fuel of that kind ever does explode." - J. L. MACKIE, Truth, In order to respond to such an objection we may ask: why does a certain object
Probability and Paradox (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1973), 127. on similar occasions manifest similar behaviour? Why do we expect similar
Willard V. 0. Quine intended to avoid the application of modality. According to Quine,
the dispositional ascription "x is soluble" should be paraphrased thus: "there is y such thatx 5 STEPHEN MUMFORD, Dispositions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003, first published
and y are alike in molecular structure and y dissolves" (the employed verbs are understood 1998), 114-117; 146-150.
as tenseless). WILLARD V. O. QUINE, Word and Object (Cambridge: Massachusetts Institute of 6 Ibid., 147.
Technology, 1960), 224. The insufficiency of Quine's resolution is obvious: it may happen that
IAN J. THOMPSON, "Real Dispositions in the Physical World", British Journal for the Philosophy
x and y are alike in molecular structure without sharing a disposition; for example in the
case when a given disposition of y is grounded in certain macrostructure that differs from of Science, 39 (1988): 67-79.
the macrostructure of x. 8 S. MUMFORD, Dispositions, 111-112.

SYDNEY SHOEMAKER, "Causality and Properties", in Metaphysics. An Anthology, ed. J. Kim 9 Ibid., 148.

et E. Sosa (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1999), 257-258. l° GEORGE MOLNAR, Powers, ed. S. Mum ford (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), 156-157.

198 • MODALITIES MODALITIES • 199


David Peroutka David Peroutka
DISPOSITIONAL NECESSITY AND ONTOLOGICAL POSSIBILITY DISPOSITIONAL NECESSITY AND ONTOLOGICAL POSSIBILITY

behaviour on future occasions of similar type? If the explanation does not re- . A certain determination of an object can be conceived insomuch as it determines
course to the qualitative constitution of the given object, the only reason for the object itself; then we have the concept of quality. (Aristotle says: "By 'quality'
expecting the usual behaviour would be the persistent numerical identity of the mean that in virtue of which things are said to be such and such".")
object. But is that enough? David M. Armstrong rightly asks: "What is the magic
• But the same determination can by conceived according to its relation to some
in numerical identity?"" possible effect, and thus we have the concept of power or disposition.
Furthermore, let us consider that if there were "ungrounded dispositions", the
following situation would then be possible: two objects differing in dispositions A disposition is a relation to some possible effect, "directedness" to an effect
without differing in qualities. Consequently the dispositional conditional if the (as Charles B. Martin called it)." But, as George Molnar observed, it is a relation in
object were tested, it would manifest the effect would be false for one of our objects, but a very special sense, because the existence of such a relation does not require the
true for the other. The problem is that there is no sufficient reason for such diver- existence of the correlative, namely of the corresponding effect (as the object can
gence in the truth-value of the same sentence when it is said about qualitatively have a disposition also at a time when the corresponding effect does not obtain)."
equal objects. Therefore there are no ungrounded dispositions. Scholastic philosophers knew of such a relation; they called it relatio trans-
Molnar's abovementioned objections play up the fact that sometimes a dis- cendentalis? Such a relation does not belong to the predicament of relation (to
position is not grounded in a shaped microstructure. But this fact does not give the category of relation)." Thomism supposed that potency, as "transcendental"
rise to any problem for property monism. With Max Kistler we may suppose relation (or relation secundum dici), is included in the essence of a related thing (in
"la base categorique" without always requiring micro-reductive basis describable the essence of a quality) without constituting a further accident or accidental
in terms of shapes and spatial structures.° We may recall the scholastic philo- essence.° In the case of potency, there is no connexion of two accidents, quality
sophy supposing that each quality is a form, but not necessarily a shape. Each plus relation; there is only the accident of quality, which is related "by itself', by
quality is a form, but not each quality is a geometrical (stereo-metrical) figure or its proper essence.
a configuration. According to Thomas Aquinas a form is (generally speaking) an Apart from potencies that are identical with accidents (namely with qualities),
inner determination or modification of a subject." But the form is not necessarily there are also ontologically more basic receptive potencies, which belong to the
a geometrically describable determination. Even if some dispositions are not based on category of substance. Substance can be conceived as a transcendental relation
"shaped" microstructures, they are based on qualitative forms and are essentially
identical with them. '4 ARISTOTLE, Categoriae, cap. 8, 8b 25.
15 CHARLES B. MARTIN, "Final replies to Place and Armstrong", in D. M. ARMSTRONG, C. B.
5. DISPOSITION AS A RELATION MARTIN and U. T. PLACE, Dispositions - A debate, ed. Tim Crane (London and New York: Routledge,
1996), 187-188.
So far we know that a disposition belongs essentially to the corresponding 16 G. MOLNAR, Powers, 62.
quality. This means that by a dispositional term we conceive an aspect of the "7 "Sed relatio transcendentalis, etiam non existente termino ad quem, intelligitur manere, quia
essence of the corresponding quality. The disposition is merely an essential aspect manet essentia subiecti, quod ad aliud elicit ordinem." - VINCENTIUS REMER, Summa praelectionum
of the quality, i.e. a special aspect of the essence of the quality. The disposition is philosophiae scholasticae, editio tertia (Prati: Universitas Gregoriana - Giachetti, filii et soc.,
namely the relational aspect of the essence of the quality. Let us now try to explain 1912), vol. 1: 332.
the pertinent "relationality". 18 "...differt relatio pertinens ad praedicamentum relationis ab aliis respectibus caeterorum generum,
qui a quibusdam transcendentes vocantur..." - THOMAS DE VIO CAJETANUS, Commentarium super
Opusculum De Ente et Essentia Thomae Aquinatis (Romae ex Pontificia officina typographica,
1907), cap. 7, q. 16, p. 218.
19 "Similiter scientia, sensus et similia dicuntur relativa secundum dici, quia significant res quas
consequuntur quaedam habitudines, sive reales, sive rationis; et ideo propter relationes adductas videntur
" DAVID M. ARMSTRONG, A Materialist Theory of the Mind (London and New York: Routledge, relativa et dicuntur talia. Apellantur vero relativa transcendentalia, quia propria eorum essentia, ad quam
1993-2002, first published 1968), 87. sequuntur tales relationes, licet sit quid absolutum, sumitur tamen in ordine ad aliquid extrinsecum, et
12 MAX KISTLER, "L'efficacite causale des proprietes dispositionnelles macroscopiques", in sic habent aliqualem modum relationis. siquidem habitus, potentiae et plures aliae qualitates sunt
Cause, pouvoirs, dispositions en philosophie - Le retour des vertus dormitives, ed. Bruno Gnassounou relationes transcendentales, ut patet." - COLLEGIUM COMPLUTENSE S. CYRILLI OCD, Artium cursus
and Max Kistler (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 2005), 144. osive D isaputationes in Aristotelis dialecticam et philosiphiam naturalem (Compluti: apud loannem de
rdun
'3 THOMAS AQUINAS, Summa theologiae q. 49, a. 2, co. 1624), disp. 13, q. 2, p. 560-561; disp. 15, q. 2, p. 628.

200 • MODALITIES MODALITIES • 201


David Peroutka David Peroutka
DISPOSITIONAL NECESSITY AND ONTOLOGICAL POSSIBILITY DISPOSITIONAL NECESSITY AND ONTOLOGICAL POSSIBILITY

to accidents. Substance is potency towards an accidental form, because sub. According to Aristotle, the same necessity holds also for rational potencies,22
stance can receive further accidental determination. Similarly, prime matter is but in this case the description of the test must also comprise a (free) decision
transcendental relation or potency towards substantial form. Nevertheless, the o f the agent. For rational potencies, the Aristotelian analysis could be expressed
receptive potentiality of a substance demonstrates itself in the physical world t hus: x has the disposition if and only if it is necessary that if x is suitably tested and (freely)
always through accidental potencies, namely through qualities. Certain qualities decides to manifest the effect, then x manifests it. (In the case of God's omnipotence the
allow the substance to receive other qualities or accidents. application of the Aristotelian analysis would be quite special, as the description
of the test includes only a free decision: God has the power to cause a certain effect iff
6. PROOF OF CAUSAL NECESSITY it is necessary that if He decides to cause the effect, He causes it.)
Now finally let us return to our research of the necessitation needed in the Somebody would perhaps object that there may exist a world, in which the
definition of potency. Shoemaker asserted that potencies are essential to qua- bearer of a given quality does not manifest the corresponding disposition, when
litative properties; he meant that potencies belong to the identity of a qualitative suitably tested, because that world differs from the actual world in laws of nature.
property.2° From this thesis he quickly and quite intuitively passed to the further I answer that there is no reason to suppose the existence of laws as powerful
assertion of "causal necessity". He said that "the introduction into certain circum- entities directing the behaviour of things and influencing upon causal processes.
stances of a thing having certain properties causally necessitates the occurrence With regard to ontological parsimony and Ockham's razor I claim that laws are
of certain effect" and that it is "logically necessary" that such an introduction rather mere abstractions which generally describe the necessary behaviour of
has such an effect.2' I agree with Shoemaker's opinion, nevertheless it has to be things. Laws are nothing but generalised descriptions of the behaviour of things,
proved. Let us continue our considerations in the following way. behaviour that is directed by causal necessity, which is based on dispositions of things.
If powers belong to the essence of qualities, a qualified thing, qua qualified, Laws depend on dispositions and not vice versa.23 There may possibly be a world
necessarily has the corresponding power. If powers belong to the essence of quali- with different laws of nature, but as Shoemaker said, "if the laws are different,
ties, there is no possible world in which the bearer of a quality (or qualities) then the properties will have to be different as well."24
lacks the corresponding disposition. (Essential affiliation is per definitionem an If my reasoning is right so far, it seems that the validity and necessity of natural
across-all-worlds connexion). laws consists in the here-described causal necessity based on the dispositional
character of qualities. And since the said necessity (the necessity contained in
• In every possible world it is true, that the bearer of a quality also has the disposition our analysis of dispositions) works in the cases of causal connexions," Hume's
belonging to the essence of the given quality. account of causal necessity as a psychological necessity" is wrong. In our analysis
As a disposition-ascription can be adequately expressed by a conditional sen- of dispositions the test is nothing but the application of causal potencies; and the
tence, we may simply reformulate the last sentence in this way: manifestation is the manifestation of the effect. We have found that the causal
• In every possible world it is true that if the bearer of a quality is properly (under suitable
conditions) tested, then the bearer of the quality manifests the effect (which is proper
to the disposition belonging to the essence of the given quality). 22 ARISTOTLE, Metaphysics IX, 5, 1048 a 10-14. Cf. URSULA WOLF, Moglichkeit und Notwendigkeit

If we assume that the range of the variable x is not the realm of bare substan- bei Aristoteles und heute (Munchen: Wilhelm Fink Verlag, 1979), 29.
23 STEPHEN MUMFORD, Laws in Nature (London and New York: Routledge, 2004), 17; 181;
ces, but of things considered insomuch as they are determined by their qualities,
199-200; ALEXANDER BIRD, "The Dispositionalist Conception of Laws", Foundations of Science
we may define disposition-ascription as follows:
10 (2005): 353-370.
24 S. SHOEMAKER, "Causality and Properties", 263.
D(x) 4— df ❑(T(x) M(x))
25 Cf. ULLIN T. PLACE, "Structural properties: Categorical, dispositional or both?", in D. M.
ARMSTRONG, C. B. MARTIN AND U. T. PLACE, Dispositions - A debate, ed. Tim Crane (London and
D means to have a disposition, T means to be (properly) tested, and M means to manifest New York: Routledge, 1996), 111.
it by the effect.
26 "Either we have no idea of necessity, or necessity is nothing but that determination of the thought

to pass from causes to effects and from effects to causes, according to their experienc'd union." - DAVID
2° S. SHOEMAKER, "Causality and Properties", 259. flumE, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. G. Mossner (London: Penguin Books, 1969, 1984), book I,
21 Ibid., 261. part IV, sect. 5, p. 216.

202 • MODALITIES MODALITIES • 203


David Peroutka
1 David Peroutka
DISPOSITIONAL NECESSITY AND ONTOLOGICAL POSSIBILITY DISPOSITIONAL NECESSITY AND ONTOLOGICAL POSSIBILITY

connexion between them is necessary, as Aristotle supposed." With Thomas a sentence or its negation, but not both. The possibility of a world-description
Aquinas we note, that causal necessity works whenever (universaliter) a cause is is identified with its logical consistency. But, as it seems to us, there are some
"sufficient and not prevented"," i.e. whenever a cause bears the pertinent causal logically consistent world-descriptions which include sentences describing some
potency and is tested without hindrances (suitably tested). in facto impossible things. For example, things not admitted by the laws of nature.
In addition to the non-contradiction of possible worlds some philosophers
7. DISPOSITIONAL FOUNDATION OF POSSIBILITY urge also the nomological accessibility of possible worlds. In this view something
Now, having defined the notion of causal potency or disposition, I may define is possible, if it is part of a consistently describable world that does not differ from
the possibility, which is grounded in potency: something is possible if and only if the actual world in the laws of nature. But (even if we leave aside many questions
there are active and passive causal capabilities enabling its production. Thomas about the laws of nature) the nomological accessibility does not seem satisfactory.
Aquinas knows the "absolute" possibility, given only by the non-contradictory For example a world in which God exists, a "theistic" world, seems not to be
character of the possible, and the possibility guaranteed by an existing causal accessible from any "atheistic" world, despite the supposed natural nomological
potentiality." The second case obtains when the possible exists "in the potency of parity of a "theistic" world with some "atheistic" world. It is because nothing
some cause" (in potentia alicuius causae)." In this sense Petr Dvofak rightly claimed: in the history of an atheistic world has the real causal power to introduce the
"The key is that the ontological status of the possible can, at least partly, be re- existence of God (as God cannot be conceived otherwise than as non-creatable).
duced to actual things possessing causal powers...."" In order to define ontological possibility, first let us introduce the notion of
I start the reasoning by marking the insufficiency of the concept of possibility causal accessibility of a possible world. If we speak about possible worlds, what are
based purely on non-contradiction. Let us consider a maximal class of sentences, the conditions for y being causally accessible from x?
i.e. class containing the negation of every sentence not contained in it. Such a • The first condition is that x andy differ from one another just (only) by some
class of sentences, according to Carnap, represents or describes a possible world.32 causal process or processes. Causal process is a chain - or ramified chain
This class of sentences must be above all non-contradictory: it contains either - of causes and effects (including at least one cause and one effect). To be a
distinguishing causal process means to exist in one of the two worlds, but not
21 ARISTOTLE, Metaphysics IX, 5. See also Physics VIII, 4, 255 a 34-35, where Aristotle says:
in both.
"it is always the case that when we have something capable of acting and something capable of being
correspondingly acted on, in the event of any such pair being in contact what is potential becomes at • The second condition of causal accessibility between x andy is that each entity
times actual..." U. WoLF interprets this sentence as a description of causal necessity (Meiglichkeit playing the role of the causal initiator of a distinguishing process exists in
and Notwendigkeit, 24). Indeed, Aristotle's expression "always" (aei) means "necessarily". In
De generatione et corruptione II, 11, 337 b 35 - 338 a 4 Aristotle says: "what is of necessity (ex anankes)
both worlds, though it plays this singular causal role only in one of them.
coincides with what is always (aei)". Cf. MICHAEL J. WHITE, "Aristotle and Temporally Relative Causal initiator is the bearer of causal potency that manifests its potency in
Modalities", Analysis 39, no. 2 (1979): 88; JEROEN VAN RIJEN, Aspects of Aristotle's Logic of Modalities that one of the two worlds, in which it initiates a distinguishing causal process
(Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1989), 5. or processes.
" Summa theologiae I'-II", q. 75, a. 1, arg. 2; ibid. ad 2: "Praeterea, causa est ad quam de necessi-
tate sequitur aliud. si illa definitio causae universaliter debeat verificari, oportet ut intelligatur de cause
These conditions define causal accessibility between two different possible
sufficienti et non impedita." Scriptum super Sententiis II, d. 36, q. 1, a. 1, ad 2: "... et quod dicitur, quad worlds. Let us also stipulate that each possible world is accessible from itself.
ad causam de necessitate sequitur effectus, intelligitur de causa completa non impedita." Finally I may define the ontologically possible and also the ontologically ne-
29 Summa theologiae I, q. 25, a. 3, ad 4: „Ad quartum dicendum quod possibile absolutum non dicitur cessary. If the range of the variable x includes individuals:
neque secundum causas superiores, neque secundum causas inferiores sed secundum seipsum. Possibile
vero quod dicitur secundum aliquam potentiam, nominatur possibile secundum proximam causam."
• x is possible in the world w iff there is some possible world causally accessible
De potentia, q. 3, a. 1, ad 2: "Dicitur enim V Metaph., aliquid aliquando dici possibile, non secundum from win which x exists;
aliquam potentiam, sed quia in terminis ipsius enuntiabilis non est aliqua repugnantia... Vel potest • x is necessary in w iff x exists in each possible world that is causally accessible
quod erat possibile propter potentiam activam agentis..."
from w.
3° Scriptum super Sententiis I, d. 38, q. 1, a. 4, co.
3 ' PETR DVOKAK, "The Ontological Foundation of Possibility: An Aristotelian Approach", In the end of my speculation the following question may arise. It may seem
Organon F 14, no. 1 (2007): 75. that the causal necessity, which works in the application of potencies, implies
" RUDOLF CARNAP, Meaning and Necessity (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1947), 9. that every ontological possibility must necessarily be effectuated. But it would be

204 • MODALITIES MODALITIES • 205


David Peroutka David Peroutka
DISPOSITIONAL NECESSITY AND ONTOLOGICAL POSSIBILITY DISPOSITIONAL NECESSITY AND ONTOLOGICAL Possiewrry

a mistake. In reality, the causal necessity is not absolute, but only hypothetical. BIBLIOGRAPHY
Such a necessity may be described by a hypothetical or conditional sentence AQUINAS, THOMAS. Corpus Thomisticum. Sancti Thomae de Aquino Opera Omnia. Recogno-
("necessarily: if..., then..."). And the antecedent of the conditional may sometimes vit ac instruxit Enrique Alarcon. Automato electronico Pampilonae ad Universita-
include a description of a free (not necessary) decision, as we have seen above. tis Studiorum Navarrensis aedes a MM A. D. (http://www.corpusthomisticum.org/

8. CONCLUSION ARISTOTLE. Complete Works of Aristotle. Ed. J. Barnes. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Let us now recapitulate the reasoning offered in this paper. I explained that s s, 198
Press,
a disposition belongs to the essence of that quality in which it is based. Since VID4DAM. A Materialist Theory of the Mind. London and New York: Routledge,
A R MSTRONG,
essential appurtenance is defined as an across-all-worlds connexion, we may 1993-2002, first published 1968.
assert that in every possible world the bearer of a quality bears also the dis- BIRD, ALEXANDER. "The Dispositionalist Conception of Laws". Foundations of Science 10
position belonging to the essence of the given quality. If we suppose the accuracy (2005): 353-370.
of the conditional analysis, then the last sentence can be reformulated thus: In CAJETANUS, THOMAS DE VIO, CA RDI NALIS. Commentarium super Opusculum De Ente et Essentia
every possible world it is true that if the qualified thing (insomuch as qualified) is properly Thomae Aquinatis. Romae: ex Pontificia officina typographica, 1907.
(under suitable conditions) tested, then the qualified thing manifests the effect. In this way CARNAP, RUDOLF. Meaning and Necessity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1947.
I have described potency as a property leading necessarily to an effect, when- —"Testability and Meaning". In Readings in the Philosophy of Science, edited by H. Feigl et
ever suitably tested. This means that the Aristotelian account of causality as M. Brodbeck, 47-92. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1953. Reprinted from Philo-
a necessary connexion is confirmed, and the concept of natural law is explained sophy of Science 3 (1936): 420-468; 4 (1937): 1-40.
by means of ontological analysis of dispositional properties. COLLEGIUM COMPLUTENSE S. CYRILLI OCD. Artium cursus sive Disputationes in Aristotelis
Having defined the notion of causal potency, I based on this notion the con- dialecticam et philosiphiam naturalem. Compluti: apud loannem de Orduria, 1624.
cept of ontological possibility. At first I introduced the notion of causal accessi-
DvokAic, PETR. "The Ontological Foundation of Possibility: An Aristotelian Approach".
bility. The reciprocal causal accessibility of two different worlds means that the Organon F 14, no. 1 (2007): 72-83.
two worlds differ from one another only by some causal process or processes
HOME, DAVID. A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by G. Mossner. London: Penguin Books,
(distinguishing causal processes), and that the two worlds share each bearer of 1969,1984.
potency, which in one of them manifests its potency by initiating some distin-
guishing causal process. This notion of causal accessibility permitted me to define KISTLER, MAX. "L'efficacite causale des proprietes dispositionnelles macroscopiques",
in Cause, pouvoirs, dispositions en philosophie - Le retour des vertus dormitives, ed. Bruno
the ontologically possible as something that exists in some causally accessible
Gnassounou and Max Kistler, 115-154. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 2005.
world: x is possible iff there are active and passive causal capabilities enabling
the production of x, so that the bearers of such potencies are either immediate MACKIE, J. L. Truth, Probability and Paradox. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1973.
causes of x, or causal initiators of a causal process leading to the production of x." MARTIN, CHARLES B. "Dispositions and Conditionals". Philosophical Quaterly 44 (1994): 1-8.
—"Final replies to Place and Armstrong". In D. M. ARMSTRONG, C. B. MARTIN and
U. T. PLACE, Dispositions - A debate, edited by Tim Crane, 163-192. London and New
York: Routledge, 1996.
MOLNAR, GEORGE. Powers. Edited by S. Mumford. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003.
MUMFORD, STEPHEN. Dispositions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003, first published
1998.
— Laws in Nature. London and New York: Routledge, 2004.
PLACE, ULLIN T. "Structural properties: Categorical, dispositional or both?" In D. M. ARM-
STRONG, C. B. MARTIN AND U. T. PLACE, Dispositions - A debate, edited by Tim Crane.
London and New York: Routledge, 1996.
QUINE, WILLARD VAN ORMAN. Word and Object. Cambridge: Massachusetts Institute of
" The research was supported by the Grant Agency of the Academy of Sciences of the Czech Technology, 1960.
Republic, project no. IAA 908280801.

206 • MODALITIES MODALITIES • 207


David Peroutka
DISPOSITIONAL NECESSITY AND ONTOLOGICAL POSSIBILITY
Tar
REMER, VINCENTIUS. Summa praelectionum philosophiae scholasticae. Editio tertia. p rati:
Universitas Gregoriana - Giachetti, filii et soc., 1912.
RIJEN, JEROEN VAN. Aspects of Aristotle's Logic of Modalities. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic
Publishers, 1989. THE OPTIMAL AND THE NECESSARY
SHOEMAKER, SYDNEY. "Causality and Properties". In Metaphysics. An Anthology, ed. j. Kim
et E. Sosa, 253-268. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1999. Originally published in: Time IN LEIBNIZ' MATHEMATICAL FRAMING
and Cause, edited by Peter van Inwagen, 109-135. Dordecht: Reidel, 1980. OF THE COMPOSSIBLE
THOMPSON, IAN J. "Real Dispositions in the Physical World". British Journal for the Philosophy Mark Faller
of Science, 39 (1988): 67-79.
WHITE, MICHAEL J. "Aristotle and Temporally Relative Modalities". Analysis 39, no. 2 (1979).
88-93.
WOLF, URSULA. MOglichkeit und Notwendigkeit bei Aristoteles und heute. Munchen: Wilhelm ABSTRACT
Fink Verlag, 1979. B SThis paper tries to show that Leibniz had a metaphysics of possibility and necessity that
R
attempted
TA to clarify and develop the usages of the two concepts. It further establishes that
this system bridged the reciprocal weaknesses of both relativism and scepticism in order to
nurture an organically realist model for the nature of truth and its corresponding reality.
working out the details of his full system is complicated by two factors. Leibniz never lays
out the full details of this system in any extended work. And he often overstates the conditions
of one or another of these categories in response to contentious debates he is involved with
at the time. My paper will show that we can develop a unified reading of his position by
comparing a number of his works on freedom, determinism and causality into a seamless and
consistent view on the nature of possibility and necessity.
More precisely, this paper will demonstrate how Leibniz' works on mathematical analysis
and mathematical optimality contribute to the framing of his radically novel concept of
"compossibility". It is this conceptual model that allows him to reconcile the dialectical poles
of telos and necessity in a rich and complex synthesis that anticipates many of the problems
that will haunt his heretical intellectual descendent, Kant.

1. INTRODUCTION
The meaning of the concepts "necessity" and "possibility" have become viti-
ated and equivocal as the dual ideologies of relativism and empirical scepticism
have undermined their metaphysical moorings.
Empirical scepticism from its foundations with Heraclitus and Gorgias up to
its heyday with Hume has cast a "duality" spell on our vision of the world. They
preach an "evening" knowledge that idealises the past and the dead as the model
for the living. Knowledge of the world is like, and therefore reducible to, the stable
and inert facts that have already passed. Anything that is not translatable to this
paradigm is dismissed as ethereal or merely of the mind.
Empirical sceptics are "twoness" thinkers where necessity can either be from
reason or from the world. Under this spell, necessity is either empty (from reason)
or a mythical narrative we tell ourselves, but not fully applicable to the world.

208 • MODALITIES MODALITIES • 209


Mark Faller Mark Faller
THE OPTIMAL AND THE NECESSARY IN LEIBNIZ THE OPTIMAL AND THE NECESSARY IN LEIBNIZ

The only type of necessity that is relevant to reality is one based on habit and Truths of Reason Truths of Fact
empirical probabilities (Hume). God's Reason God's Will - Compossible
Relativism on the other hand, attempts to transfix our vision toward the
"morning" knowledge of an ever unformed future, where all things are equally Original Derived Hypothetical Moral
possible. Berkeley's "threeness" perspective rejects any robust distinctiveness identities identities necessities necessities
between truth and fiction and instead holds that the justified beliefs of any corn. Human
Logic Math Science affairs
munity or individual are equally "true".
Within this Protagorean vision, necessity is in the eye of the beholder, with
rhetoric the only tool of negotiating whether one view is more useful than epistemic counterparts. In a realist line the conditions of knowability flow from
another. the conditions of being and the epistemic gradations are analogical to the ontic.
We need to return to a time before the great transfixing webs of Hume and A Divided Line can for Leibniz, as it did for Plato, mediate the passage be-
Berkeley to appreciate the possibility of a more balanced idea of truth. It is in the tween scepticism and relativism. As a continuum with objective "cuts", a Divided
subtle and complex metaphysical nuances of Leibniz that we may begin to purge Line represents a kind of "fourness" thinking that is able to reconcile the appa-
our souls of these dual contaminants of modernity. rently conflicting logics of relativism and scepticism, through a dimensional
I will make the case that Leibniz had a metaphysics of possibility and necessity embellishment of our ontological model.
that attempted to clarify and develop the usages of the two concepts. I will further There are some interesting differences and similarities we can immediately
show that this system attempted to bridge the reciprocal weaknesses of both mine from Leibniz' Line when compared with Plato's. For one, there are unwork-
relativism and scepticism in order to nurture an organically realist model for the able inconsistencies in Plato's model. The knowability of ontological kinds is laid
nature of truth and its corresponding reality. out on a continuum with the faculties of knowing. Yet Plato has clearly specified
Working out the details of his full system is complicated by two factors. He that within man, it is usually the lower faculties that predominate, and that we
never lays out the full details of this system in any extended work. And he often have little and tenuous direct access to the divine nous. The two sides of the line
overstates the conditions of one or another of these categories in response to should rightly be in inverse proportion, with knowledge itself some monstrous
contentious debates he is involved with at the time. I will try to show that we can hybrid ratio.
develop a unified reading of his position by comparing a number of his works on In the Leibniz Line there is no demand for such a tension. It is judgements
freedom, determinism and causality into a seamless and consistent view on the of truth, not faculties, which he lines up with the types of possible being. Since
nature of possibility and necessity. judgements just are the identity between knowledge and being no inconsistencies
More precisely, I will try to demonstrate how Leibniz' works on mathematical need arise. The grounds of knowing and those of being just are the same:
analysis and mathematical optimality contribute to the framing of his radically The nature of truth consists in the connection of the predicate with the subject, or
novel concept of "compossibility". It is this conceptual model that allows him the predicate is in the subject either in a way that is manifest, as in identities, or
to reconcile the dialectical poles of telos and necessity in a rich and complex hidden. In identities this connection and the inclusion of the predicate in the subject
synthesis that anticipates many of the problems that will haunt his heretical, are explicit; in all other prepositions they re implied and must be revealed through
the analysis of the notions, which constitutes a demonstration a priori.'
intellectual descendent, Kant.
But there are also strong similarities. The truths of logic and mathematics are
2. LEIBNIZ' DIVIDED LINE together as two distinct categories on one side of a major division, with those of the
One concrete way in which to envision Leibniz' full spectrum for the grounds phenomenal world on the other. The truths of logic and mathematics are truths
of necessity and possibility is to project his kinds of judgements onto a model of of reasoning. They are necessary truths and their opposites are contradictions.
a Divided Line (se the opposite page). Truths of the phenomenal realm are truths of fact; they are contingent, and their
A Divided Line can help us to recognise how two distinct kinds of relationships opposites are possible:
may be brought under a consistent relational rubric. On one side we have the
ontological relationships between the levels of being. There is a spectrum of
necessity and possibility that holds with respect to their position on this conti- ' A quote of G. W. LEIBNIZ, in MARTIN HEIDEGGER, The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic,
nuum. There is also the lateral relationships between the ontic levels and their transl. Michael Heim (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1984), 39.

210 • MODALITIES MODALITIES • 211


Mark Faller Mark Faller
THE OPTIMAL AND THE NECESSARY IN LEIBNIZ THE OPTIMAL AND THE NECESSARY IN LEIBNIZ

There are in turn two genera of derivative truths: for some can be reduced to primary 3. MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS IN LEIBNIZ
truths; others can be reduced in an infinite progression. The former are necessary, There are important implications for the development of modern philosophy
the latter are contingent.' in general, and Kant in particular, in how we frame Leibniz' understanding of this
We should be careful not to interpret this seemingly complete disjunction process of conceptual/mathematical analysis.
as any kind of absolute dualism in either ontology or judgement. Leibniz' Line, Wolff's interpretation of Leibniz, and that of most contemporary logical posi-
like Plato's, is in fact a line, a continuum. The truths of fact can be construed as tivists, is that mathematical truths just are reducible to logical truths with no
tautologies - implicit identities between the subject and predicate. The continuum residue. This simplistic reading of Leibniz would seem to ignore many of his most
of relationships between the subject and predicate cannot, however, be made penetrating works on the nature of mathematical thinking and knowledge. In
explicit in a finite number of steps. particular his work on in situ geometry and the attempt to frame a geometrical
The physical facts of which these truths refer can also be classified as "contin- semantics for his Universal Characteristic, indicate that Leibniz believed that
gent" only in a qualified sense. They have a hypothetical necessity for which they mathematical knowledge was far richer and more semantically determinate than
are grounded by a sufficient reason for their being as they are: the syntactical relationships accessible solely from the law of identity.
There are two ways to flesh out the nuances of Leibniz' analytic framework.
There is thus the tendency in his theory to assimilate as far as possible the veritates
The first is to demarcate the substantial differences between mathematical and
facti to truths of reasoning - though this is not stated with complete accuracy, since
truths of fact are supposed to retain their own quality and nonetheless have the logical truths. The other is to illustrate how they remain fully reconcilable.
character of Identities.' Logical propositions are inherently tautologies, in and of themselves com-
pletely empty of semantic content. In order for logic to have any utility beyond
Hypothetical necessity is conditioned by the double constraints of mechanical playing with definitional identities, semantic content must be imported from
determinism and economic compossibility. The compossible, Leibniz' novel con- the more determinate segments of our divided line. It is the precise nature of
tribution to causal thinking, framed to reconcile the traditional polemic between the limits and possibilities that this spectrum of ontological kinds introduces
mechanism and teleology, is the set of interactions between discretely determined which makes Leibniz' continuum of grounds so provocative. The Principle of
events that mediates their "compatibility": "My principle, namely is that whatever Contradiction holds throughout all the subsequent realms of necessity and possi-
can exist and is compatible with other things, does exist, because the reason bility, but it has an extremely thin realm of its own. Analysis is just the working
for existing in preference to other possible cannot be limited by any other con- out of the specific spatial or phenomenal conditions within which the Principle
siderations than that not all things are compatible."4 Leibniz' recognition that of Contradiction may gain footing.
the compossible could be tamed by his mathematics of the optimum, informs the For Leibniz analysis went beyond what Hume or Kant meant by the taking
implicit identity between the contingent and reason. apart of a concept. Leibniz explored a new kind of analysis, an analysis situs:
Equally as significant as the disjunction between the truths of reason and
fact, is that distinction drawn within the truths of reason. Truths of definition are The true analysis of situation is therefore still to be supplied. This can be shown
logically transparent and immediately identical. They are original truths. from the fact that all analysts, whether they use algebra in the new manner or deal
with the given and the unknown after the ancient pattern, have to assume many
Those of mathematics are preponderantly derived. They are implicit or virtual things from elementary geometry which are not derived from the consideration
identities that can be fully analysed into their explicit identities in a finite number of magnitude but from that of figure, and which have not yet been explained in
of steps, and are deducible from them. any determinate way. Euclid himself was forced to assume certain obscure axioms,
without proof, in order to proceed with the rest. And the demonstration of theorems
and the solution of problems in his Elements sometimes seem to be achieved through
hard labor rather than method and skill, even though he also seems sometimes to
2 G. W. LEIBNIZ, "On Freedom", in L. A. FOUCHER DE CALEIL, ed., Nouvelles lettres et opuscules conceal the ingenuity of his method.'
inedits de Leibniz (Paris, 1857) [henceforward F. DE C.], 179; English translation L. E. LoEmKER,
ed. and transl., G. W. Leibniz: Philosophical Papers and Letters, 2^d edition (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1969) Leibniz held that this science was known to the ancients and involved the
[henceforward LOEMKER], 264. specific interpretation of geometrical loci, or the continuum of qualitative relation-
3 HEIDEGGER, The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic, 43. ships. While algebraic analysis could only deal with quantity or magnitude, this
4 G. W. LEIBNIZ, "Two Notations for Discussion with Spinoza", in C. I. GERHARDT, Hrsg.,

Die philosophischen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, 7 vols. (Berlin: Weidmannsche Buch- G. W. LEIBNIZ, "On Analysis Situs", in C. I. GERHARDT, Hrsg., Leibnizens mathematische
handlung, 1875-1890) [henceforward G], vol. 7: 262 (LOEMKER, 169). Schriften, 7 vols., Berlin and Halle, 1849-1863 [henceforward GM], vol. 5: 178 (LOEMKER, 254).

212 • MODALITIES MODALITIES • 213


Mark Faller
I Mark Faller
THE OPTIMAL AND THE NECESSARY IN LEIBNIZ THE OPTIMAL AND THE NECESSARY IN LEIBNIZ

other analysis could capture the inherent nature of quality itself. Key to this he helped to develop and it is clear that we can have necessary knowledge of such
distinction was identifying the essential quality of the similarity of figures: "Thus °contained" infinite processes in his example of an asymptote:
a true geometric analysis ought not only consider equalities and proportions Ordinarily, for example, we find that two lines which approach each other continu-
which are truly reducible to equalities but also similarities and, arising from the ously finally meet, and many people would be quick to swear that this could never
combination of equality and similarity, congruences."' happen otherwise. Yet geometry does furnish exceptional lines, called asymptotes
Similarity for Leibniz was the measure of quality and its significance reached for this reason, that when extended to infinity they approach each other continuously
beyond geometry: and yet never meet.'°
Besides quantity, figure in general includes also quality or form. And as those figures Mathematics in general, and geometry in particular, has a unique capacity to
are equal whose magnitude is the same, so those are similar whose form is the same. represent the unlimited. And it is through the mining of the geometrical facility
The theory of similarities or of forms lies beyond mathematics and must be sought within the soul that we can begin to grasp the deeper mysteries of the world and
in metaphysics.' mind:
Where algebra and logic were forced to reduce all relationships to mere iden- new and unexpected light arose at last, however, from where I least expected it,
tity, geometry could work with the more complex and subtle nature of forms that namely, from mathematical considerations of the nature of the infinite. For there are
were both alike but different. Leibniz developed an invariant definition for the two labyrinths in which the human mind is caught. One concerns the composition
concept of similarity which he believed would finally free the property of quality of the continuum, the other concerns the nature of freedom. And both arise from
or form from its subservience to quantity: "In undertaking an explanation of the same source, the infinite."
quality or form, I have learned that the matter reduces to this: things are similar Once I have determined a mathematical truth, its statement and derivation
which cannot be distinguished when observed in isolation from each other."8 can be fully translated into a logical proof. It is less clear whether that truth could
He believed, like Lull and Bruno before him, that he was on the threshold of have been reasonably derived using only logical rules, in less than an infinite
discovering the Adamic language of the imagination, which could finally open number of steps. And if the truth were derivable with logic, the question remains
the soul to the free gaze of the intellect: "All other matters which the power of whether logic would have the capacity to finally identify that truth as a significant
imagination cannot penetrate will also follow from it. Therefore this calculus of mathematical truth. In this sense the comparison is similar to the problem of
situation which I propose will contain a supplement to sensory imagination and computer searches and their relationship to the Meno paradox: How can I find
perfect it, as it were."9 something if I do not already know what it is I am looking for. There is a rich
While defining the Truths of Reason as those that can be analysed in a finite mathematical content, with its own complex order of necessity and possibility
number of propositions achieves precise conceptual clarity, there remain signi- that is "lost" in a reduction to merely logical principles.
ficant problems. There are many mathematical relationships that represent In this sense, geometrical thinking is like the strategic logic (vs. the syntactic
potentially infinite processes. The relationships between incommensurables or rules of play) for winning an infinite game (or the Slave Boy Problem). No logic
those elaborated in the squaring of a circle can only be approximated within a finite can develop an algorithm for final victory. But once an "optimum" strategy is
set of calculations. Although there are mathematical operations that can fully discovered through geometrical insight, it can subsequently be translated into
comprehend infinite processes within a finite procedure, like differentiation and a logical proof.
integration, there remain kinds of operative definitions that defy such handling
- the calculation of pi. 4. A MISPLACED DISJUNCTION IN KANT
But Leibniz also realises that there is in mathematics the possibility of "captu-
If my interpretation is substantially correct, we can discover two relevant
ring" such potentially infinite processes. This is the very nature of the calculus
insights into its significance for Kant. First, following Leibniz, Plato and the Empi-
ricists, Kant realised that there were significant differences between the kinds of

6 Ibid. (GM 5: 179; LOEMKER, 255).

' Ibid. (GM 5: 178; LOEMKER, 259). I° G. W. LEIBNIZ, "On What is Independent of Sense and Matter" (Letter to Queen Sophia
" ibid. (GM 5: 179; LOEMKER, 255). of Prussia, 1702) (G 9: 509; LOEMKER, 551).
4 Ibid. (GM 5: 181; LOEMKER, 257). " F. DE C., 179; LOEMKER, 264.

214 • MODALITIES MODALITIES • 215


Mark Faller Mark Faller
THE OPTIMAL AND THE NECESSARY IN LEIBNIZ THE OPTIMAL AND THE NECESSARY IN LEIBNIZ

knowledge represented by experience and reason. The first was particular and knowledge seems to bridge this dichotomy in a way that defeats the sceptical
fleeting, the latter universal and invariant. claim. Mathematical thinking is both a priori in the universality and necessity
Second, with Plato and Leibniz, Kant recognised a differential hypotheticality of its results and synthetic in the expansively ampliative promise of its enquiry.
for mathematical judgement in his interpreting mathematical judging as a priori To understand why he got mathematical thinking so wrong we will have to
synthetic. Mathematical thinking is not strictly logical. it is a liminal middle kind understand how an inherent disposition interacted with this driving motivation.
of "figuring" that shares aspects of both pure reason and imaginative experience. Kant is not a dialectical thinker. His priority as a critical philosopher is
It is a priori in that it can be fully translatable to logical identities in a finite set of clarity over coherence, and he most often dismisses dialectical oppositions as
propositions. It is synthetic in the sense that it takes a synthetical construction to "antinomies" and "paralogisms". Even though he needs mathematics to hold as
bridge the intuitional gap and discover the explicit analytical steps. an absolute "middle" to bridge the Humean fork, he is little able to illustrate the
We must be very careful here in parsing our terms. It is exactly in the period essentially liminal nature of mathematical thinking.
between Leibniz and Kant that the meaning of the terms analysis and synthesis Kant creates an absolute duality between the mathematical and the philo-
get completely inverted by the empiricists. For Leibniz, analysis is that art of sophical uses of reason. One is "quantitative" while the other is "qualitative"; One
the ancient geometers that took apart problems before inverting them into is constitutive of its object, the other merely regulative; One is rational cognition
synthetic proofs. So when he refers to analysis in mathematics he is referring to from concepts while the other is rational cognition from the construction of
the same taking apart of figures and relationships that Kant would later refer to concepts: "Mathematical definitions can never err. For since the concept is first
as synthetic, due to its origins in the intuition. For both thinkers this was an "art" given through the definition, it contains exactly just what the definition wants
deeply buried in the soul. us to think through the concept.""
But Kant goes perhaps too far in establishing the uniqueness of mathematical This clean dichotomy between the mathematical and dynamical uses of
concept formation. He wants to absolutely disjoin this process from that which reason does allow Kant to set an autonomous ground for mathematics against the
frames concepts of the understanding. In this effort he comes up with the enchan- reductive thesis of the empiricists. It also allows him to build a critical bulwark
ting, but misleading maxim: "Philosophical cognition is rational cognition from against the claims of dogmatism that haunts the historical rationalists like Leibniz
concepts. Mathematical cognition is rational cognition from the construction of and Plato who apparently just assume that mathematical ideas apply to the world.
concepts."" This neat divide produces two one sided caricatures of conceptual But there is a serious cost to this clarity. Concepts that I construct can have
formation and leaves both frameworks open to sceptical attack: constitutive clarity, but how do I objectively compare and contrast them to the
Hence philosophical cognition contemplates the particular only in the universal. empirical concepts I have formed through abstraction? How do I know that the
Mathematical cognition, on the other hand, contemplates the universal in the parti- circle I have constructed in my intuition has at all the same sense as the circle I
cular, and indeed even in the individual, yet does so nonetheless a priori and by "see" in the plate?'5
means of reason."
" CPR 682 (B 759 I A 731).
First we must recognise how important it is for Kant to establish the principle 15 This issue has a very old pedigree. The ancient academy was divided over the issue
of mathematical cognition on an absolutely firm and autonomous grounding. of whether universals were abstracted or projected. The mathematical followers of Plato
Mathematical knowledge holds the key to defeating the Humean sceptical fork, leaned toward the projection thesis, while those of the linguistic-orientated Aristotle leaned
i.e. that synthetic a priori judgements were possible. The vicious dichotomy of towards an abstraction thesis. A similar debate would rage after Kant within the philosophy
nominalism maintains that there are two absolutely incommensurable types of mathematics. Dedekind and Cassirer followed Kant in holding that mathematics was a
projective process, typified by the ordinal generation of the number line. Russell and Cantor, on
of knowledge, the a priori analytic and a posteriori synthetic, each deriving from
the other hand, seeing mathematical concepts as the cardinal abstractions from set theory. But
two radically distinct sources, reason and experience. This divide makes the
if mathematical thinking can truly bridge the conceptual divide of concepts and experience it
product of reason, logic, empty and relegates knowledge of nature as merely must be inherently liminal. Numbers must somehow be both ordinal and cardinal - construc-
particular and therefore blind. Kant's insight was to recognise that mathematical ted and discovered. There is an implicit proof of the invariance of mathematical liminality
in the Theaetetus. The only way to uniquely understand the number six is to see it as a scaled
relationship between its cardinal and ordinal properties: six is the uniquely smallest perfect
12 IMMANUEL KANT, The Critique of Pure Reason, transl. W. Pluhar (Indianapolis: Hackett, number, where its multiplicative or formal factors add up to its material sum. This hybrid
1996) [CPR], 668 (B 741 I A 713). formulation of the nature of number would match well Leibniz' idea of an invariant, universal
13 CPR 669 (B 742 I A 714). characteristic.

216 • MODALITIES MODALITIES • 217


Mark Faller Mark Faller
THE OPTIMAL AND THE NECESSARY IN LEIBNIZ THE OPTIMAL AND THE NECESSARY IN LEIBNIZ

It is at this point, when we transition from the Truths of Reason to those of and a purposive perspective, and each is equally as "mathematical". It is precisely
Fact, where the consequences of Kant's first mathematical error get compounded. the mathematically dynamic aspects of the phenomenal world that contribute
The rigid distinction between the construction of concepts in math and the use of directionality to the causal interplay of the compossible.
concepts in the understanding, leads Kant to develop an equally rigid distinctive
ground for their determination of phenomena. The physics of Newton, based on 5. THE MATHEMATICAL GROUNDING OF LEIBNIZ' OPTIMISM
the constructive patterns of geometry just are constitutive of the phenomena of The full success or failure of Leibniz' project of reconciling teleology with
nature, while the dynamic purposiveness of biology can only be "regulative" of necessity lies in the possibility of bringing his conceptual model of compossibility
our understanding of nature: "It has just been shown that since this principle of onto a rigorous foundation of mathematical formulation, something ironically
purposiveness is only a subjective principle of the division and specification of akin to Newton's rehabilitation of his mysterious "gravity" through the equa-
nature, it does not determine anything with regard to the forms of the products tions of mass and distance. The vision and vehicle for this formulation is his
of nature." mathematically dynamic model of pulchritude and plenitude.
These two sets of disjunctions are merely aspects of the same error. This in- In the fall of 1697, Leibniz wrote "On the Radical Origination of Things", in
sight can be illustrated with a look at the inherent ambiguity within the emerging which he attempted to illustrate the complex orders of necessity that ruled the
controversies surrounding the biological definition of species. Taxonomists and compossible world of nature. His major focus in this essay was to "explain how
cladists argue for two radically distinct ways by which to group organisms. Func- temporal, contingent, or physical truths arise out of truths that are eternal and
tional or dynamical causal frameworks will determine a substantially different essential, or if you like, metaphysical... "
kind of biological classification than one presuming a morphological or genetic Leibniz proceeds by attempting to demonstrate how those forms which are
basis for the generation of species. The choice one makes is presumed by and most likely to emerge into reality are those which have some sort of priority
further determines ones causal narrative. of metaphysical perfection in possibility. So he states that in the undertaking
With Leibniz, the form of mathematical thinking cannot be so easily simplified. of the drawing of an unspecified triangle, that figure which will be most easily
In different writings Leibniz appears as both a logicist and a functionalist with constructed with a compass will be also the "best" one - the equilateral triangle,
regard to the formation of mathematical concepts. We have shown earlier that he "Hence it is very clearly understood that our of the infinite combinations and
develops the idea that there is a unique and implicit qualitative knowledge within series of possible things, one exists through which the greatest amount of essence
geometry that can never be merely captured by quantity or reduced to logic. And or possibility is brought into existence?"' He goes on to complete this formulation
mathematics has a double directionality. There is an "upward" and a "downward" with his statement that the actual world is the best of all possibilities in that
path in the differential and integral calculus. Some critics have judged this "a maximum effect should be achieved with a minimum outlay"
dualist-like approach within Leibniz as a type of weakness or equivocation, but This definition of optimality or elegance by the specification of the identity of
as we move towards an examination of the "lower" half of our Divided Line, that sides is completely consonant with contemporary information theory. The accep-
which deals with the compossible relationships between phenomena, we find that ted standard of measuring the complexity of a phenomenon is by the amount of
this pluralism is the source of much of the enduring richness in his metaphysics. information it takes to specify it. The recursiveness of the equilateral triangle
Leibniz in his work with the calculus would be aware that it is the dynamical and makes it the ultimately "simplest" triangle from this aspect of informational
functional aspects of geometrical representations that empower mathematical describeability.
models to completely capture and determine the hypothetical necessity of the Paul Schrecker has noted that this effort by Leibniz is in fact an explanation of
phenomenal world. The dynamical relationships of the regulative laws of nature how order arises out of chaos in Plato's Timaean receptacle.20 Plato implies that his
are every bit as determinate of the phenomenal world as the mathematical elemental triangles are the result of the interplay between likelihood (symmetry)
relationships of the mechanical causes. In fact for Leibniz they are sufficiently
more so.
For Leibniz this mutuality already infects his model of the grounding of phe-
nomenal truth. We can understand causes of the physical from both a mechanical '' G. W. LEIBNIZ, "On the Radical Origination of Things" (G 6: 303; LOEMKER, 487).
18
ibid.
16 IMMANUEL KANT, The Critique of the Power of judgment, trans!. P. Guyer and E. Matthews
19 ibid.

(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 22. 20 PAUL SCHRECKER, "Leibniz and the Timaeus", Review of Metaphysics 4 (1951): 495-505.

218 • MODALITIES MODALITIES • 219


Mark Faller Mark Faller
THE OPTIMAL AND THE NECESSARY IN LEIBNIZ THE OPTIMAL AND THE NECESSARY IN LEIBNIZ

and necessity (dynamic stability). There is a thermodynamic rationa l for why the light". The fact that light seemed to seek the path of shortest time, eliminated the
triangular, mechanical vectors rule the micro-dynamics of atomism. possibility of mechanical or efficient explanations. Only an end-driven or teleo-
This reading of the consonance between the Leibnizean and Platonic cosmos logical hypothesis could explain such activity, and that end was to an efficient
perhaps does not go far enough. According to Leibniz the order that rules the order. Leibniz' own development of the methods of differential calculus aided him
diverse levels of the phenomenal hierarchy is determined not by God's reason, in envisioning the economic elegance of such an optimisation principle.
or the laws of Newtonian mechanics (although it can be translated to them), but Even though Leibniz' work predates the theoretical work on thermodynamics
rather the goodness of God's will. It is not enough, however, to merely show that the by more than a generation, it is clear that his vision of nature is equally as "sto-
mechanical laws are an exemplification of the most probable. For both Leibniz and chastic". Compossibility is the unitary outcome of the totality of mechanical
Plato mechanics represents the bare necessary conditions of causal interaction, micro-states of a system. Compossibility is Leibniz' anticipation of thermodyna-
that set of constraints within which possibility can be framed. It cannot be Socra- mic theory. Both the principle of least action and his work in the Origination show a
tes' "ligaments and bones" that finally keeps him in his imprisonment. sophisticated dynamic view about how such systems are mathematically disposed
In the Timaeus it is reason, in the form of the harmonic movements of the toward self-organisation. I will therefore, try to make the case that his vision
heavens that finally persuades necessity to do its bidding. This formulation of about the way the phenomenal world is ordered to following God's will towards
persuasion is also central to Leibniz' concept of God's will determining towards what is the most perfect, is inherently a rigorous elaboration of what will be
what is best. Heidegger notes that Leibniz' framing of the Principle of Sufficient thermodynamic theory.
Reason, with the phrase "rather than" is a direct implication of ground as "pre- The Second Law is indisputably a teleological principle. The Second Law just
ference": We can only have the ground as preference where freedom and ground does determine the final state of any closed system, regardless of any unique
go mutually together as a "decision about value."" For both Plato and Leibniz initial configuration of the elements. This condition establishes that the Second
the value that is designed into the cosmos is the stochastic good of mathematical Law is "end driven" or "pulled" rather than "pushed".
order. In this sense there can be no conflict between God's will and His knowledge, The establishment of the Second Law as teleological would seem to be little
the Good is just the perfection of the whole and to know the good is to do it. consolation to the grand optimism and romance of our Metaphysical Mathe-
Since the time of Voltaire's Dr. Pangloss, defending Leibniz' dual doctrines maticians. Their vision was of a universe designed by God to be the best and most
of pulchritude and plenitude- that God has chosen the most perfect world, "the beautiful, not a chaotic soup of heat death. In this sense Maxwell's finalism seems
simplest in its hypotheses and the richest in phenomena"," - has become a double untranslatable to Aristotle's.
burden. First, one must show that such a belief can be based on scientific principle, What Aristotle implies by his "telos" is not disorder, but quite the opposite.
not simply optimism or dogmatic faith. And one must further demonstrate that Purpose is some ordering entelechy that, except for its autonomy from initial
such a principle is not in substantial conflict with established scientific practices. conditions, seems the very antithesis of the end predicted by the Second Law.
If such a task should seem daunting, hopeful challengers can take heart in the Here we must account for the fact that Aristotle affirmed that the final cause
quality of the company. Leibniz is joined by no less that Fermat, Maupertuis, and was most closely associated with the formal cause. It is this relationship, between
Euler in his belief that the universe was guided by some principle of beauty or the formal principles of how transitions must take place, and the teleological or
efficiency. And all four of these great minds thought they had found the fount of final conditions, of where the transitions are headed, that must be understood if
that elegance in some form of "least action" principle. While modernity has mostly we are to make sense of either order or disorder.
accommodated some form of such a principle, it has unilaterally rejected the
metaphysical implications drawn by these four great mathematical philosophers. 5.1 The thermodynamic origins of harmony
The enduring stature of these brilliant and sober intellects demands that we It has been widely recognised since the time of Helmholtz that the overtone
carefully re-examine such an easy dismissal. series and its relationship to musical harmonics, through the occurrence of beats,
Leibniz based his principle of an efficiently ordered universe, like Fermat is an objective phenomenon of the physical world and not merely a cultural or
before him, largely on evidence such as Snellius' Law for the propagation of subjective preference. The motion of a plucked string successively breaks downs
into harmonic patterns, the overtone series, expressing the progressively increas-
ing ratios of small integers:
21 HEIDEGGER, The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic, 116.
22 G. W. LEIBNIZ, Discourse on Metaphysics (G 4: 431; LOEMKER 306). 21 Ibid. (G 4: 449; LOEMKER 318).

220 • MODALITIES MODALITIES • 221


Mark Faller Mark Faller
THE OPTIMAL AND THE NECESSARY IN LEIBNIZ THE OPTIMAL AND THE NECESSARY IN LEIBNIZ

Ratio to Ratio to Relationship This overtone series is the basis of all the diverse, traditional systems of
Harmonic Note
Fundamental Preceding to Preceding scaling - diatonic, just and equal temperament - and therefore cannot in any
absolute way determine which "musical" system is "better". All the varieties of
1:1 Fundamental C scale "cutting" share certain absolute and objective characteristics. The octave
(2:1) and the higher harmonies, the fifth (3:2) and the fourth (4:3) appear to be
1:2 1:2 2nd Harmonic Octave C'
essential to both the "sweetness" and the ordering capacity of the overtone series.
1:3 2:3 3rd Harmonic Fifth G' The lesser harmonies and the sizes of the whole and half notes appear to have only
a "normative" or cultural hold on diverse tastes. Once we are given the overtone
1:4 3:4 4th Harmonic Fourth C" series, the arithmetic pattern itself determines all the relationships of harmony.
The mystery remains: Why do continuously dissipating systems conform to such
1:5 4:5 5th Harmonic Major Third E"
a pattern?
1:6 5:6 6th Harmonic Minor Third G" The Second Law of thermodynamics states that any closed system whose
initial state is out of equilibrium, will eventually work its way to a final state of
This harmonic pattern holds great physical significance for a variety of di- equilibrium. In a two chamber system with a set number of particles (eight) in one
half and a vacuum in the other, will eventually settle into the equilibral state of
verse, continuously dissipative sources that to some degree conform to these same maximum probability distribution when the chambers are opened to each other.
orderly patterns. From the indefatigable motion of the electron, to the massive The final and most probable state of the system is given by the equal distribution
symphonic stroll of the heavenly bodies, the mathematics of harmonic con- of particles in the two chambers. With all eight molecules in one chamber the
sonances order much of the world around us. Fourier found that heat dissipates maximum number of unique distributions is eight. However, with four molecules
from a solid object in such an harmonic pattern. What has been less clear is in each chamber the number of possible distribution states maximises at 70:
why this pattern of simple whole number ratios is a physical determiner of the
harmonic order. N=8
The overtone series of harmonics is the pattern of sinusoidal waves into which
a plucked string progressively declines as its energy dissipates. The pattern is • •
that of simple whole number ratios and corresponds closely to the traditional • •

harmonic consonances: 1:1, 2:1, 3:1, 4:1, 5:1 etc.: •
• •
• •
• • •
1:1 fundamental

) octave (1:2) 1 arrangement 8! / 4! 4! = 7o arrangements

When a constrained string is plucked, energy dissipates in a lawfully ordered


■IIIII■ ■IIIIII■ 1:2 1st overtone
> fifth (2:3)
progression. Since the disturbance is to a continuous medium, the string, the
number of possible intermediary states approaches the indefinite. Not all inter-
1:3 2nd overtone mediary states, however, are equally probable. Those states that attain an equal
> fourth (3:4) distribution of the system's parts will attract the motion of the string as being
1:4 3th overtone the states of maximum possible distribution. Since equality can only attain where
> major third (4:5) there are an integer number of divisions: 2, 3, 4, etc., the successive intermediary
1:5 4th overtone states of the string returning to its rest state will be through the series of integer
> minor third (5:6) divisions - the harmonic series.
ic:=:><=>oc-c•ci 1:6 5th overtone This theoretical hypothesis of how continuity directs the way in which gra-
dients within a system must "dissipate" has been empirically well verified within

222 • MODALITIES MODALITIES • 223


7
Mark Faller Mark Faller
THE OPTIMAL AND THE NECESSARY IN LEIBNIZ THE OPTIMAL AND THE NECESSARY IN LEIBNIZ

many different kinds of phenomena. It has been identified variously as a "spite" BIBLIOGRAPHY
principle by Joseph Kestin or a "moderation" principle by Prigogine.24 This prin. fouCHER DE CALEIL, L. A., ed. Nouvelles lettres et opuscules inedits de Leibniz. Paris, 1857.
ciple also stands as an explanatory ground that illuminates the multiple faces of
GERHARDT, C. I., Hrsg. Die philosophischen Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. 7 vols.
the enigmatic Least Action Principle. Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung, 1875-1890.
What can be understood from the thermodynamic origins of harmonics is the
Leibnizens mathematische Schriften. 7 vols. Berlin (vol. 1-2) and Halle (vol. 3-4), 1849-1863.
underlying ordering power of the law of disorder. The final state parameters of the
Second Law are that any system will continually move towards a minimisation HEIDEGGER, MARTIN. The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic. Translated by Michael Heim.
of gradient differentials. There are, however, continuity parameters that govern Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1984.
the way in which such systems transition to those final states. These transition KANT, IMMANUEL. The Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by Werner Pluhar. Indianapolis:
parameters, that continuously dissipative systems will be attracted to the most Hackett 1996.
probable intermediary states, determine that the retreat of stochastic dissipative —The Critique of the Power of Judgment. Translated by Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews.
systems from gradient extremes will necessarily be maximally ordered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.
LOEMKER, LEROY. E., ed. and transl. G. W. Leibniz: Philosophical Papers and Letters. 2nd edition.
6. CONCLUSION Dordrecht: Reidel, 1969.
It should perhaps not surprise us that our Divided Line turns out to be a SCHNEIDER, ERIC and SAGAN, DORION. Into the Cool: Energy Flow, Thermodynamics, and Life.
"cutting of a cannon", a harmonic division. Our avowed purpose in transposing Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005.
Leibniz' spectrum of norms onto a line was to make sense of the dimensions of SCHREcRER, PAUL. "Leibniz and the Timaeus". Review of Metaphysics 4 (1951): 495-505.
conditionality within his complex ontology. Harmonic theory offers us just such
a spectrum of necessities.
Science, since the enlightenment, has pushed for the absolute disjoining of
nature from value in explaining the world. Neuro-philosophers have attempted to
go even further in eliminating the place of the non-mechanical in human affairs.
An accurate study of the great Leibniz should serve as a healthy prophylactic to
these incursions.
For Leibniz there are two principles of necessity, one negative, the Principle
of Contradiction, and one positive, the Principle of Sufficient Reason. While the
negative principle is stronger, it can never be violated under any circumstances,
the Principle of Sufficient Reason is the determinant cause of all of nature and all
of reason. God's good will does not overrule his reason, so much as it frames the
continuing and progressive context within which it has authority to legislate. The
good is the final, absolute necessity within which reason manages the possibilities
of expression.
The good determines the providence and forces of historical development.
Physics marshals the movements of the particulate conditions. The interplay of
compossible, mathematical forces will determine the development of that world
which evolves towards perfection: It is the awakening of the sleeping god, in its
progressively conscious choice of its self-determination. Plato and Leibniz have
looked upon that face, and it is us.

24 ERIC SCHNEIDER and DORION SAGAN, Into the Cool: Energy Flow, Thermodynamics, and Life
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005), 76.

224 • MODALITIES MODALITIES • 225


SECTION VI

PREDICATION
THE INTERPRETATION(S) OF PREDICATION
Uwe Meixner

ABSTRACT
RtACTcourse
the of the history of Western philosophy, various philosophers have given
various answers to the question of the ontological basis of predication. This essay presents the
m ain, the crucial answers: the paradigms and theories of predication of the Sophists (and of all
later radical relativists), of Plato, of Aristotle, of the Aristotelian-minded non-nominalists, of
Leibniz, and of Frege. The essay follows (to some extent) the most influential - the Aristotelian
or quasi-mereological - paradigm of predication in its continuity and modification through the
many centuries of its reign. But this essay is not content to adopt the merely historical point
of view; it also poses the question of adequacy. Prior to Frege, a philosophically satisfactory
theory of predication was not even in the offing, and the essay points out the shortcomings
(besides aspects that can be viewed as advantages) of each pre-Fregean predication-theory
it considers. Frege, in the 19" century, brought the philosophy of predication on the right
track. But his own theory of predication has its own deficits (which it shares with still other
predication-theories). The essay ends with the presentation of a theory of predication that
the author himself considers adequate.

In the economy of science, and of knowledge in general, simple predicative


statements have a fundamental and indispensable role to play. Such statements,
simple as they are: containing no logical functors, have various forms in natural
language. Here is a far-from-complete list of such forms, each item in the list
combined with an illustrative example:

FORMS EXAMPLES
a Os [covering also: a is] Kate laughs
a is (1) Kate is beautiful
a is a (13, Kate is an actress
a Ws 13 [covering also: a is (3] Kate loves George
a is+pr [3 Kate is in Boston
a is (I:0+pr p Kate is married to George
a is a 4)+pr p William is a descendant of Albert
a is+pr 13 and y The tree is between the house and the street

[pr: some preposition]

229
Uwe Meixner Uwe Meixner
THE INTERPRETATION(S) OF PREDICATION THE INTERPRETATION(S) OF PREDICATION

Notwithstanding these many forms, the general form of simple predicative state- Put formally, that is: in the most general way, the described view is this:
ments, which is familiar from first-order predicate logic, is just this: Social conventionalism in predication-theory:
..., a r,) "(1)(a', ..., as)" is true - this amounts, "ontologically", to the following: (a', ...,
Here the sequence "a', ..., as" represents the occurrences of the singular terms is purely on the basis of social convention designated by the general term "0".
in a simple predicative statement, all of them without syntactical structure, in Hence, for the special case of non-relational predications:
the order in which they follow each other in the statement (noting that a singular
term may occur more than once in it); and the letter "0" represents the rest "0(a)" is true - this amounts, "ontologically", to the following: a is purely on
of the statement: the predicative basis, devoid of all logical functors, in which all the basis of social convention designated by the general term "0".
of the occurrences of singular terms in the statement are embedded; finally, If this were true, then the following instantiation of this general schema would
the unifying function of the predicative basis is indicated by the embracing have to be true, too:
brackets, "(" and ")". In order to make matters as simple as possible - that is: in
"Kate is a woman" is true - this amounts, "ontologically", to the following: Kate
order to focus on the basic problem of predication - I stipulate, in addition to the is purely on the basis of social convention designated by the general term "woman".
description of simple predicative statements just given, that the singular terms
in simple predicative statements are not to refer to linguistic items or abstract Now, this does not seem to be true; for, while it is true that Kate is a woman, it is
entities, and that the predicates in simple predicative statements are to be chosen hard to believe that Kate is purely on the basis of social convention designated by the
accordingly. general term "woman".
Some simple predicative statements are true. But from the earliest times of On the other hand, I can to some extent understand it - psychologically - if
philosophy to this day the nature of the truth of true simple predicative state- social conventionalism in predication-theory is adopted as a weapon against
ments has been controversial among the philosophers. Does the truth of such classifications that are, one feels, merely socio-conventionally based but masque-
statements have ontological import? And if it has ontological import, what exactly rade as hard and objective, ontologically based truths. One may be prompted by the
is that import? These questions are philosophical evergreens, and not accidentally - hardly rational - implicit belief that the charge "Mere convention!", if advanced
so: their importance can hardly be overestimated. For what is at stake in these against such classifications, can only be truly effective in one's mouth if one
questions is nothing less than the basic determination on what it truly amounts has managed to convince oneself of its being true for all classifications that are
to when we claim to have knowledge of the world and to speak the truth about the generally thought to be true.
world. In this essay, I shall look at some of the milestones of a discussion that spans A fundamental attitude of protest against established social power - mere power,
almost 25 centuries: among other predication-theories, at the theories of Plato, but manifesting itself, the protester believes, in disguise: in simple predicative
Aristotle, and the Aristotelian-minded non-nominalists, at the theories of Leibniz statements that rather persuasively pretend to express incontrovertible objective
and of Frege. At the end of the essay, I shall briefly present my own approach. facts - may be something that modern feminist philosophers' have in common
The positions on predication of the just-mentioned philosophers - different as with the ancient Sophists. The prime target of the Sophists, however, were not
they are - have at least one thing in common: all of them are opposed to the view simple predicative statements expressing what is generally regarded to be natural
that simple predicative statements have no ontological import at all. According facts, but simple predicative statements expressing what is generally regarded to
to the no-ontological-import view, if a simple predicative statement is true, then be axiological facts, statements like "This decision is just", or "That deed is cou-
its truth is a product merely of social convention, and hence a product merely of rageous", where everyone in the community, on being informed of the relevant
the allocation of power in the relevant group of speakers, since social convention circumstances, feels compelled to say, "Yes, that's true". Nevertheless, it is total,
follows social power. This view - the conviction that social convention, social unrestricted social conventionalism in predication-theory which, very plausibly,
power are the basic truthmakers, that basic truth itself is a social construction underlies the famous homo-mensura-dictum of the Sophist Protagoras, according
- was present at the beginning of philosophy in the teachings of the Sophists, it to which "man is the measure of all things, of the things that are, that they are,
unmistakably shines through the voluntarism of mediaeval nominalists, and it and of the things that are not, that they are not". Applying the homo-mensura-
reappears recognizably in the philosophy of the later Wittgenstein.' dictum to axiological statements, one can very well declare that "This decision is
just" and "This deed is courageous" are true (in the relevant circumstances) - "as
' Significantly, Wittgenstein says the following in the Philosophical Investigations (§ 381):
"How do I know that this colour is red? - It would be an answer to say: 7 have learnt English'." 2 For example (and paradigmatically), Judith Butler.

230 • PREDICATION PREDICATION • 231


Uwe Meixner Uwe Meixner
THE INTERPRETATION(S) OF PREDICATION THE INTERPRETATION(S) OF PREDICATION

everybody says they are"; but one will add that all that is implied by these truths Thus, the beautiful itself is beautiful, the just itself is just, the human being itself
is this: the mentioned decision is purely on the basis of social convention designated is a human being. Indeed, since the (1) itself is not only sufficiently similar to the
by the term "just", and the mentioned deed is purely on the basis of social convention itself but is the only object that is maximally similar to it, in other words: the
designated by the term "courageous"; for man - in another word: society, in other only object that is identical to it, the logic of Plato's predication-theory requires
words: the social group which is in power - is the measure of all things. that the (I) itself is the unique object that is maximally (I). Thus, the beautiful itself is
It was this utterly subversive attitude that Plato, following Socrates, was re- the unique object that is maximally beautiful, the just itself is the unique object
acting against. His philosophically most significant move in this was to offer that is maximally just - and all the other beautiful or just items are beautiful or
a predication-theory which is not conventionalistic. Showing full awareness just only by being more or less remote likenesses of those two eide. - And, note,
of the problem of predication, Plato came up with the first explicitly formulated according to Plato's predication-theory, the woman itself is the unique object that
predication-theory ever. Now, Plato, in the course of his career as a philosopher, is maximally a woman.
underwent substantial development in his thinking about predication, and in fact, Unfortunately, this last consequence, if nothing else, constitutes a reductio ad
in later phases, became critical of earlier positions of his. But this did not hinder absurdum of Plato's predication-theory. If there is such a thing as the woman itself,
that the predication-theory that is imposingly present in the dialogues from the it is certainly not maximally a woman, nor even a woman. Plato himself noted
middle of Plato's career - in the Symposium, the Phaedo, the Republic - had a massive (through the mouth of one of his dramatis personae: Parmenides) that it seems
effect on the history of ideas. Very soberly - quite without the poetic splendour ridiculous to postulate that there are such things as the hair itself or the dirt itself
of philosophical mythology - that predication-theory can be formulated in the (cf. Parm., 130 c 7-8). Even if the existence of such eide were not ridiculous, it would
following way (and Plato himself formulates it that way in Parm., 132 d 1-5): still be incontrovertibly absurd to suppose, as Plato's predication-theory forces
one to suppose, that no other dirt is dirt in the degree that the dirt itself is dirt.
Plato's (classical) predication-theory:
This is a much more serious problem for Plato's predication-theory than the
"(1)(a)" is true - this amounts, ontologically, to this: a is sufficiently similar to much canvassed so-called Third-Man-Argument, which, in essence, can already
the (1) itself be found in Plato's dialogue Parmenides and might also be called "the Third-Large-
Applying this theory, we get for example: object-Argument" (see Parm. 132 a 1- b 2). It can be put in the following way:
"This deed is just" is true - this amounts, ontologically, to the following: this The visible large objects are large in virtue of participating in a first largeness.
deed is sufficiently similar to the just itself But this first largeness is another large object. Hence the first-mentioned
"Kate is beautiful" is true - this amounts, ontologically, to the following: Kate large objects and this other large object are large in virtue of participating in
is sufficiently similar to the beautiful itself a second largeness. But, again, this second largeness is another large object.
Hence the first-mentioned large objects, the second-mentioned one and this
"Kate is a woman" is true - this amounts, ontologically, to the following: Kate now apparent third large object are large because they participate in a third
is sufficiently similar to the woman itself largeness. But, again, this third largeness is another large object - and so on
Even when divested of its poetic splendour (involving an eternal, unchangeable ad infinitum.
transcendent realm of being itself which one is likely to imagine awash with "the This argument tries to settle Plato's predication-theory - not only for the
white light of truth"), Plato's predication-theory has fascinating features. One of
term "large", which is merely an example, but for each and every general term
them is, of course, the introduction of an entirely new order of objects: the eide, that can be truthfully applied in the empirical world - with an infinite number of
as Plato called them, the separate forms, serving as paradeigmata: the just itself, the different eide without a real difference to them. But the argument fails. According
beautiful itself, the woman itself, and so on. And note, since the itself is certainly
to Plato's predication-theory, the visible large objects and the first largeness are
sufficiently similar to the (I) itself (no matter which general term 43. we are looking indeed large, but not in virtue of participating in a second largeness: the visible
at), Plato's predication-theory has the following logical consequence:
(or empirical) large objects are large because they are sufficiently similar to the
Platonic self-predication: first largeness, and the first largeness is large - for the same reason: it is sufficiently
4'(the (1) itself). similar to (since it is identical with) the first largeness: the large itself Thus, there
is no need whatsoever to postulate any other largeness than the first largeness.

232 • PREDICATION PREDICATION • 233


if
Uwe Meixner Uwe Meixner
THE INTERPRETATION(S) OF PREDICATION THE INTERPRETATION(S) OF PREDICATION

Plato's predication-theory has, however, a very limited scope of plausible ap- the main, the origin of this paradigm must be associated with Aristotle. Mainly on
plicability. There are some cases where the theory is not obviously inadequate: the basis of the wide-spread reception of Aristotle's writings since the beginning
statements like "Kate is beautiful" and "Kate is just". But the theory is certainly of the 13th century, the quasi-mereological paradigm of predication became rather
not adequate for the statement "Kate is a woman", or even the statement "Kate influential in Western philosophy. It stayed the standard approach for just about
is a human being" - or, for that matter, for the statements "Kate is hungry" and six centuries. Aristotle's predication-theory - which means: the predication-
"Kate is pregnant", although these latter two statements have adjectives standing theory which, given the data from Aristotle's writings, is the best summative
in predicative position just as the statements "Kate is beautiful" and "Kate is reconstruction of his opinions on predication - is a particular version of the
just" have. Moreover, Plato's predication-theory is meant for non-relational pre- quasi-mereological paradigm (which, indeed, has many versions); it can be put
dications only - and, in fact, I have formulated it only for non-relational predica- in the following way:
tions. If one tries to extend it to relational predications, inadequacy looms large: Aristotle's predication-theory /
Suppose the statement "George loves Kate" is true; but does this mean - in the The quasi-mereological predication-theory with particular forms:
spirit of Plato - that the ordered pair consisting of George in the first place, and of
"o(a)" is true - this amounts, ontologically, to the following: the a-particular
Kate in the second, is sufficiently similar to love itself? Presumably not. However,
the mystical implications of this Platonising ontological interpretation of the form of being (1) is in a.
statement "George loves Kate" will surely not fail to fascinate minds that are Thus we have for example:
receptive to such implications. The same can be said of the mystical implications
"Socrates is wise" is true - this amounts, ontologically, to the following: the
of the Platonic ontological readings of simple predicative statements that are
Socrates-particular form of being wise is in Socrates.
straightforwardly true and involve the term "good" as predicate, or merely the
word "is". Given acceptance of the classical Platonic predication-theory, it is "Kate is beautiful" is true - this amounts, ontologically, to the following: the
possible to elevate oneself - as it were - in one leap from rather earthly matters Kate-particular form of being beautiful is in Kate.
right up to the transcendent Godhead Itself (though only in ontological theory), "Kate is a woman" is true - this amounts, ontologically, to the following: the
Especially in Late Antiquity and the Early Middle Ages there were many minds Kate-particular form of being a woman is in Kate.
that very much appreciated this asset of the Platonic predication-theory. It should be noted that a special case of the situation that the a-particular form
Inadequate treatment of relational predications is a deficiency that is shared of being (1) is in a is this: the a-particular form of being (1)
is identical to a; this is the
by all predication-theories prior to Frege's. It is a deficiency not only Plato can be ( traditional Aristotelian ontological analysis of, so-called,
substantial predication (as
criticised for. Nor is the long persistence of it due to Plato's influence. As a matter in "George is a man"); whereas if the a-particular form of being I>
is in a, but is not
of fact, its persistence is due to the influence of Aristotle. identical to a, we have before us the traditional Aristotelian ontological analysis
In Plato's predication-theory, the partners of predication - the ontological of, so-called, non-substantial predication (as in "George is sitting").
subject and the ontological predicate - are external to each other, just as a like- There are two plausible equivalents for the phrase "the a-particular form
ness is external to what it is a likeness of. Moreover, in Plato's predication-theory, of being (I) is in a", each of which, if substituted for that phrase in Aristotle's
the ontological predicate is the dominant partner in predication. Aristotle, how- predication-theory, yields a predication-theory that is
plausibly equivalent to
ever, adheres to a paradigm of predication that is fundamentally different from Aristotle's predication-theory:
Plato's, a paradigm that is also rather more down to earth than Plato's. Accord-
ing to Aristotle's paradigm, the ontological subject is the dominant partner (1)Plausibly, "the a-particular form of being (1) exists" is true if, and only if, the
in predication, and the ontological predicate is, in predication, in some sense a-particular form of being (1) is in a.
encompassed by the ontological subject, comparable to the way in which a part (2) Plausibly, "the form of being (1) is in a" is true if, and only if, the a-particular
is encompassed by what it is a part of There are significant indications that Plato form of being 1:17. is in a.
himself was moving towards some form of the mereological or, better, quasi-mereo-
But in fact Aristotle denies that
logical paradigm of predication in the latter part of his philosophical career.' But, in
The quasi-mereological predication-theory with universal forms:
3 See FRANZ VON KUTSCHERA7PartS of Forms. An Essay concerning Plato's Parmenides".
"0(a)" is true - this amounts, ontologically, to the following: the form of being
Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy 1 (1998): 57-74. (I) is in a,

234 • PREDICATION PREDICATION • 235


Uwe Meixner Uwe Meixner
THE INTERPRETATIONS) OF PREDICATION THE INTERPRETATION(S) OF PREDICATION

is true. In the Categories (Cat. 1 a 20-23; see also Cat. 3 a 11-13), he declares that necessary and sufficient basis of its being in that subject (though in it only in a
Man - in other words: the form of being a human being - is, on the one hand, derivative, analogical sense) - Man and Animal being no exceptions to this rule.
(truthfully) said of a subject, namely, of a particular human being, but that it In any case, vacillations in Aristotle's writings are bound to have contributed,
is, on the other hand, not in any subject. This can only be taken to imply that in the centuries after Aristotle and especially in the Middle Ages, to the waning
according to Aristotle, the statement "George is a human being" is true, although of his distinction between universals that are not substances and are in some
the form of being a human being is not in George, and that therefore the quasi- subject, and universals that are substances and are not in any subject. This
mereological predication-theory with universal forms is not true (because it is distinction - a significant residue of Platonism in Aristotle - became less and
counter-instantiated). less important. The distinction finally dissolved - in favour of all universals being
Indeed, the quasi-mereological predication-theory with universal forms can just as much in some subject as all universals are said of some subject, and in
seem to be rather non-equivalent to the quasi-mereological predication-theory with favour of all universals being precisely in the subjects of which they are said.
particular forms, that is: to Aristotle's predication-theory. After all, the former A striking documentation of the endpoint of this development can be found in
theory involves universal forms, the latter only particular ones. But scepticism the commentary of Thomas Aquinas on the Posterior Analytics of Aristotle. There,
regarding universal forms - or briefly, universals - was certainly not Aristotle's Thomas simply connects a universal's being (truthfully) predicated of a subject,
problem with the former theory: he accepted universal forms at least as secondary being said of a subject, with its being in the subject of which it is predicated; no
entities, whereas he did not accept Plato's eide, that is, Plato's separate forms' His distinction is made in his characterisation of predication between substantial and
problem was that some universal forms are said of some subjects, but are not in non-substantial universals. Interpreting Aristotle, Thomas says (In Posteriorum
any subject because they can exist apart from any subject they may tentatively be Analyticorum I, lect. 11, n. 6):
supposed to be ins - because, as Aristotle believed at one point, they are substances: Primo, dicit [Philosophus: Aristotle] quod tunc est universale praedicatum, cum [cum
universal - or second - substances (in contrast to particular - or first - substances).6 iterativum] non solum in quolibet est de quo praedicatur, sed et primo demonstratur
However, in several places of the Metaphysics, we also find Aristotle denying inesse ei, de quo praedicatur.
that universals - any universals - are substances.' Now, if no universal were a Firstly, he [the Philosopher] says that a universal is a predicate [of something: a]
substance for Aristotle after all, then it would seem most plausible to assume whenever it is not only in everything of which it is predicated, but is first demon-
that, for Aristotle, any universal is said (truthfully) of a subject' after all on the strated to be in that [i.e., the something: a] of which it is predicated.
From this quotation, it is apparent that Thomas accepted - under the presumed
' For an explicit statement of Aristotle's acceptance of universals in contrast to Plato's authority of Aristotle - the quasi-mereological predication-theory with universal forms,
separate forms, see An. Post. 77 a 5-9; that passage also contains Aristotle's definition of because the quotation can, without much effort, be made to support the following
universal, which is this: one which can be truthfully said of many. reasoning that yields just that predication-theory:
s See Cat. 1 a 24-25, where Aristotle defines - or rather: gives a partial explication of - being
1. The (universal) form of being (I) is (demonstrated to be) in a.
in a subject: "In a subject I call that which exists in something, but not as a [literal] part, and cannot be
separate from that in which it is." [Translation U. M.] Note that the "cannot be separate from" is not 2. Hence according to Thomas ["tunc est universale praedicatum, cum ... demon-
meant by Aristotle to express a symmetrical relationship: "x cannot be separate from y" does stratur inesse ei, de quo praedicatur"]: the form of being (I) is (truthfully) pre-
not entail, for Aristotle, "y cannot be separate from x". For he understands "x cannot be separate dicated (said) of a.
from y" in the sense of "x cannot exist apart from y", and "y cannot be separate from x" in the
sense of "y cannot exist apart from x", and of course it can be - and sometimes is - the case 3. And hence: "(I)(a)" is true.
that x cannot exist apart from y, while y can very well exist apart from x.
6 That this is the correct diagnosis is strongly suggested by Cat. 3 a 7-15. Regarding Aris- 1'. "(I)(a)" is true.
totle's asserting separability - the ability to exist apart from any supposed subject - of sub-
stances, see Met. VII, 1029 a 27-28. But note that in the same short passage Aristotle also asserts 2'. Hence: the form of being (1) is (truthfully) predicated (said) of a.
particularity of substances. 3'. Hence according to Thomas ["universale... in quolibet est de quo praedicatur"]:
' See Met. III, 1003 a 8-10; Met. VII, 1038 b 8-12, 34-37, 1091 a 3; Met. X 1053 b 16-20; Met. XIII the form of being (I) is in a.
1087 a 2.
Note that for Aristotle any universal is said truthfully of some subject (because it is by Now, as long as one assumes what Aristotle himself at some time - for some
definition truthfully said of many subjects; cf. note 4). cases - did not assume, namely,

236 • PREDICATION PREDICATION • 237


Uwe Meixner Uwe Meixner
THE INTERPRETATION(S) OF PREDICATION THE INTERPRETATION(S) OF PREDICATION

that "the form of being (I) is in a" is true if, and only if, the a-particular form of being is in a", or by the equivalent phrase "a particularisation of the form of
being (1) is in a [cf. the plausible assumption (2) above], being 'b is in a" - these phrases being taken to express the original Aristotelian
ontological basis for predication.m After the Middle Ages, the quasi-mereological
the quasi-mereological predication-theory with universal forms will be found to
be equivalent to the quasi-mereological predication-theory with particular forms. predication theory with universal forms started a life of its own.
During the Renaissance, due to the influx of ancient Platonic texts to Italy
This equivalence and, in the first place, the assumption on which it is based seem
after the fall of Constantinople in 1453, there was a significant resurgence of
plausible without argument. One can also rather plausibly argue for them in the
Platonism, broadly conceived. This led to a very strong reaction against the
following way:
Aristotelianism of the Schools and - combining with forces that emphasised
Asserting of a universal form that it is in a subject is merely a non-literal, the importance of the individual human being, of the individual human mind
analogical way of speaking. Such an assertion cannot be literally true, because - brought about the philosophical (so-called) Enlightenment of the 17th century.
the universal form is not a particular, whereas the subject is one. Only a parti- in the field of ontology, a significant consequence of these revolutions was the
cular can be literally in a particular. What is literally true in those cases where following: universals turned into absolute concepts for those thinkers who, on
a universal form is truthfully but analogically said to be in a subject can only the one hand, did not deny universals, like the nominalists had always done,
be this: the particularisation relative to the subject of the universal form is - and who on the other hand, Platonically and humanistically inspired, did not
literally - in the subject. want to continue along the old mediaeval Aristotelian lines. For those thinkers,
Thomas and his Aristotelian-minded non-nominalist contemporaries and succes- universals took on an absoluteness that traditional Aristotelians had not conceded
sors - and, for that matter, Husserl, who much later in the history of ideas once to universals; it faded into the background that universals were supposed to be
again followed Aristotelian lines in formal ontology - would have found this argu- anthropogenic abstractions from particulars. At the same time, those thinkers
ment entirely convincing.9 However, the history of ideas after the Middle Ages emphasised the conceptualness of universals more strongly than it had ever been:
took a course that was not in keeping with the argument's Aristotelian spirit. After the affinity of universals to mind - which, given the absoluteness newly accorded
the Middle Ages one rather tended to forget the analogical equivalence - Aristotelian to universals, could of course only be their affinity to a transcendent supermind.
in spirit - of the quasi-mereological predication-theory with universal forms to Mind-affinity had to some extent already been a characteristic of Plato's eide. But
the quasi-mereological predication-theory with particular forms, an equivalence it was Plotinus who had, in late Antiquity, explicitly conceptualised the eide by
based on the assumption that the phrase "the form of being (1) is in a" is merely an See R. E. ALLEN, "Substance and Predication in Aristotle's Categories", in Exegesis and
analogical facon de parler (though no denial of universal forms is involved in that Argument. Studies in Greek Philosophy Presented to Gregory Vlastos, ed. E. N. Lee et al. (Assen,
assumption) and that the phrase's ultimate truth-relevant import - what it really Netherlands: van Gorcum, 1973), 367: "If Socrates is just, there is, according to the Categories,
says - just amounts to what is expressed by the phrase "the a-particular form of an instance of justice in him, an instance which is individual, numerically one, and inseparable from
Socrates in the sense that it cannot exist apart from him." In other words: If Socrates is just, there is
9 Regarding Husserl, the following passage from his lecture Phenomenological Psychology a particularisation of the form of being just ("an individual instance ofjustice") in him - and,
[Phanomenologische Psychologie] of 1925 rather strongly suggests his being ready to uphold the clearly, that particularisation is the Socrates-particular form of being just. In general we have:
two classical quasi-mereological predication-theories simultaneously, the universalistic one (a) If a particularisation of the form of being (1) is in a, then the a-particular form of being 4)
standing, as it were, on top of the particularistic one: "One must not believe that the identity of the is in a (because every particularisation of the form of being 4) that is in a is identical with
eidos [which for Husserl merely amounts to the universal] is just an exaggerating way of speaking. the a-particular form of being 4)). And we also have the converse: (b) If the a-particular form of
... [It is not merely the case that] every object has its in-being moment, for example, of redness, and being 4) is in a, then a particularisation of the form of being (1) is in a (because the a-particular
[that] each of the many objects, all of which are red, has its individually own moment, but in sameness. form of being 4) is, if in a, a particularisation of the form of being 4)). One can derive both
Rather, one must see that the sameness is only a correlate of the identity of something that is general (a) and (b) on the basis of the following definition: the a-particular form of being 4) =Def the
and in common [eines Allgemeinen], that can, in truth, be intuited as one and the same out of - and particularisation of the form of being (1) that is in a - presupposing, for all cases of a and 4), that
as a 'counterpart' of - what is individual. This identical something 'particularises' itself in many ways there is no more than one particularisation of the form of being 4) that is in a and that there
and can be thought, in an open infinity, arbitrarily particularised. All of these particularisations are, is a particularisation of the form of being 4) that is in a if the particularisation of the form of being
in virtue of their relationship to what is identical, related to each other, and are accordingly called 'each 4) that is in a is in a. One might object that there can easily be more than one particularisation
the same as the other. In an extended, non-literal way of speaking, the concrete objects themselves are, of the form of being red (for example) in a subject: if a table has a red area here and a red area
in virtue of having eidetic particularisations in them, each called the same as the other 'with respect to there. But one can stipulate that the phrase "[there is] a particularisation of the form of being
the red, and are themselves, in a non-literal sense, particularisations of the something that is general (1) [that] is in a" is understood to refer, if true, to the (relatively to a) entire particularisation of
and in common [des Allgemeinen]." - Phan. Psych., 80; translation and italics U. M. the form of being 4) in a.

238 • PREDICATION PREDICATION • 239


Uwe Meixner Uwe Meixner
THE INTERPRETATION(S) OF PREDICATION THE INTERPRETATION(S) OF PREDICATION

making them denizens of the nous, while maintaining their absoluteness, their of the homo-concept being essentially subsumed under the extension of the
ontological independence from particulars. It is not unlikely that the influence
animal-
concept). But it does not follow from this that the simple predicative statement
of Plotinus (via Marsilio Ficino and Pico della Mirandola) helped bring about the "Socrates est homo" is, analogously, true in virtue of the homo-concept being in
described post-mediaeval developments." the Socrates-concept - because "homo est animal" cannot serve as a paradigm for
Remarkably, these developments did not necessarily endanger the acceptance "Socrates est homo", since "homo est animal" is, contrary to appearances, not a
of the quasi-mereological paradigm, that is, of precisely that paradigm of predi- simple predicative statement, but a statement that is different in meaning from
cation that Aristotle, setting himself off from Plato, had inaugurated with his "Socrates est homo" even in the very category of meaning.
particular version of a quasi-mereological predication-theory. The predication- Thus, Leibniz's predication-theory would seem to rest on a simple confusion:
theory of Leibniz can serve as a striking example of a syncretistic result of the the confusion of the in-being of a universal in a particular with the in-being
post-mediaeval developments I just sketched. Leibniz was an Enlightened follower of one concept in another - if one weren't reluctant to settle the great man
of the quasi-mereological paradigm and, in fact, had more sympathies with tradi- with such a big blunder. And, indeed, there is a more favourable perspective on
tional Aristotelianism than most of the new intellectuals of his time. He did Leibniz's predication-theory than that: Given that the quasi-mereological predi-
subscribe to the Scholastic slogan of praedicatum inest subjecto, but he did so in a cation-theory with universal forms emancipated itself in post-mediaeval times
new manner, reflecting the revolution of ideas which had come about. In Section along the lines I have described (which emphasise both the absoluteness and the
8 of the Discours de Mitaphysique he very clearly formulates conceptualness of universals) from the quasi-mereological predication-theory with
particular forms, the problem of how a universal predicate could be in a particular
Leibniz's predication-theory: subject needed a new solution. In this situation, making use of the relation of in-
"(I)(a)" is true - this amounts, ontologically, to the following: the 0-concept is being between concepts must have seemed the only way to go. It was, therefore,
in the a-concept. not unreasonable - relatively speaking - of Leibniz to interpret "praedicatum
Obviously, the predication-making relation of in-being (inesse) in Leibniz's predi- inest subjecto" as "the predicate-concept is in the subject-concept". What else
cation-theory is neither of the two relations of in-being that are invoked in the two could it mean?
previously canvassed quasi-mereological predication-theories. In fact, it is not a Leibniz dauntlessly accepted the strange consequences of his predication-
relation of in-being between the predicate and the subject at all: it is a relation theory: that Alexander once defeats Darius (cf. Discours de Mitaphysique 8) - this
between the predicate-concept and the subject-concept. This latter relation of in- is so because the concept of once defeating Darius is in the concept of Alexander;
being, between concepts, was already at the time of Leibniz not a newly discovered that Caesar once crosses the Rubicon - this is so because the concept of once
one; it had already been familiar for a long time, and, as a matter of fact, it had crossing the Rubicon is in the concept of Caesar (cf. Discours de Mitaphysique 13). But
not been clearly distinguished from the other two relations of in-being I have if this is true, then these historical truths about Caesar and Alexander, which we
already considered." The common form of the statements "homo est animal" and regard as contingent, are not contingent at all, but necessary truths in the strictest
"Socrates est homo" suggests that they both are simple predicative statements, sense. We human beings learn only a posteriori and never completely - and hence
and that therefore the relation of in-being invoked under a quasi-mereological with an almost irresistible appearance of contingency - what is, for example, the
theory of predication for analysing "Socrates est homo" must be the same as the content of the concept of Caesar (a consistent concept maximally rich in content,
relation of in-being invoked for analysing "homo est animal". But in fact "homo a notio completa). But, according to Leibniz, that concept cannot be otherwise for
est animal" is not a simple predicative statement - it is a statement of essential Caesar than it is (would it be otherwise, then it wouldn't be the concept of Caesar),
subsumption. It is true that "homo est animal" is true in virtue of the animal- and God, according to Leibniz, knows it a priori and completely. Because Caesar
concept being in the homo-concept (or in other words: in virtue of the extension once crosses the Rubicon, the concept of once crossing the Rubicon is contained
in that concept of Caesar according to Leibniz's predication-theory - we just
" From the 17'h to the 19'h century, the idea of the mind-affinity, the conceptualness of saw -, hence contained in it with strict necessity, since the relation of in-being
universals remained present, but, progressively, it took on decidedly human proportions; for between concepts is a relation that holds with strict necessity whenever it holds
the initially co-present Platonic/Plotinic idea of the absoluteness of universals progressively at all." And hence it follows, again according to Leibniz's predication-theory, that
disappeared - until it triumphantly re-appeared in the work of Frege.
12 For the history of in-being between concepts and its relationship to predicative in-being,
see UWE MEIXNER, "Negative Theology, Coincidentia Oppositorum, and Boolean Algebra", Logical " For concluding that the concept of once crossing the Rubicon is necessarily contained
Analysis and History of Philosophy 1 (1998): 75-89. in the concept of Caesar, the reason given is, in fact, not in itself sufficient: "the concept

240 • PREDICATION PREDICATION • 241


-NI

Uwe Meixner Uwe Meixner


THE INTERPRETATION(S) OF PREDICATION THE INTERPRETATION(S) OF PREDICATION

it is necessary in the strictest sense that Caesar once crosses the Rubicon. Leibniz The intuitive oddness of this predication-theory decreases considerably if one
might have noticed that we can learn to know the concept of Caesar a posteriori takes into account that Frege conceived, in extension of the mathematical concept
(which is the only way for us) only by coming to believe in the truth of simple of a function, of concepts as functions whose functional values are the true or the
predicative statements about Caesar - and that for our coming to believe in the false, and of functions, employing a chemical metaphor, as entities that are in
truth of these statements the concept of Caesar is, in fact, entirely irrelevant. This themselves unsaturated, but that are saturated by their functional arguments, thus
might have given pause to Leibniz. producing their functional values (see Frege's 1891 paper "Funktion and Begriff").
Like all predication-theories prior to Frege's, Leibniz's predication-theory is Therefore, instead of saying that
not adequate for relational predications, although, because it deals in concepts, the functional value of the 0-concept for (a', ..., a,,,) is the true,
it is not as inadequate as other theories under the quasi-mereological paradigm.
Notice that relational predications are implicit in the very examples Leibniz one can, following Frege, just as well say:
chooses: Alexander once defeating Darius, Caesar once crossing the Rubicon. It is the saturation of the 0-concept by (a', ..., a,,,) is the true.
possible to assimilate relational predications to non-relational ones, along the lines
of "Caesar once crosses the Rubicon" being read as "Caesar is a Rubicon-crosser". This is still somewhat odd, the main reason for this impression being Frege's as-
And while it is surely absurd that an original-Aristotelian universal form of being sumption of a truth-object, the true, corresponding to which he has an even odder
a Rubicon-crosser is in Caesar - because it is absurd that an original-Aristotelian falsity-object, the false. But notice the flexibility and ease Frege's predication-
Caesar-particular form of being a Rubicon-crosser is in Caesar (Caesar carrying theory displays in the treatment of relational predications. What is the onto-
that thing around with him, and with it the Rubicon, it would seem) -, it is not logical basis for the fact that the statement "George loves Kate" is true whereas
absurd that the concept of being a Rubicon-crosser is in the concept of Caesar. But "Kate loves George" is not true? Why, the saturation of the concept of love by
we have seen that, still, there are reasons for not accepting this as the basis that the ordered pair that has George first and Kate second is the true, whereas the
is appropriate for predicating being a Rubicon-crosser of Caesar. saturation of that same concept by the inversely ordered pair is the false.
A time came - by and large with the 19th century - when the anti-relationalist, There is nothing wrong with this - except, of course, that it does not make
substantialist conception of the world began to loosen its grip on the human contact with what it actually is that we base our judgements on when we assert
mind, and concatenations of non-privileged, non-dominant beings (such concatenations that George loves Kate, and that Kate does not love George. Frege's predication-
may be called "states of affairs") instead of privileged, dominant gravitational centres theory is a mere logical rationalisation of predication, not an account of predication
of being (such centres may be called "substances") began to capture the ontological that tries to honour the actual ontological foundation of our actual human prac-
imagination. But it took a philosopher-mathematician who had less respect - and tice of making simple predicative statements intended to be true - something
probably less knowledge - of the philosophical tradition than Leibniz for progress which Aristotle's predication-theory, and, indeed, Plato's, did try to do, though
to be made with regard to relational predications. Frege finally abandoned the not with entire success. As far as a mere logical rationalisation of predication
quasi-mereological paradigm, and came up with something entirely new. There goes, Frege's theory is true and adequate, just as true and adequate as its nearest
is no precedent or analogue in the antecedent history of ideas for equivalent not employing the notion of function is, which became a standardly used
technical tool in 20th-century model-theoretic logical semantics:
Frege's predication-theory:
The set-theoretical theory of predication:
"0(at, ..., ar ,)" is true - this amounts, ontologically, to the following: the func-
tional value of the 0-concept for (a', ..., aN) is the true. "0(at, ..., a,,,)" is true - this amounts, ontologically, to the following: (at, ..., a,,,)
is an element of the 0-set.'"

of Caesar" and "the concept of once crossing the Rubicon" must also each refer to one and " Frege's concepts (Begriffe) are extensional concepts (that is: they are identical if, and only if,
the same (respective) concept in every possible world (compare the situation regarding the they have the same extension); they are, therefore, one-to-one correlates of sets. Extensionality
necessity or contingency of true identity statements). Leibniz certainly assumed the rigidity of is not the only feature of Fregean concepts that fits ill with the normal concept of a concept:
the mentioned designators; but in the case of "the concept of Caesar" rigidity is, as a matter another is lack of mind-affinity (which is in part a consequence of their extensionality). Thus:
of fact, doubtful (the reason being this: if the concept of Caesar is the sum of all concepts Frege's use of the word "concept" ("Begriff") - for the items that are really intended by him -
that apply to Caesar, then that sum seems to be different in different possible worlds, since, still bears witness to the (above-described) emphasis on the conceptualness of universals, after
apparently, in different possible worlds different concepts apply to Caesar). the Middle Ages, but it does so only on the linguistic surface.

242 • PREDICATION PREDICATION • 243


1
Uwe Meixner Uwe Meixner
THE INTERPRETATION(S) OF PREDICATION THE INTERPRETATION(S) OF PREDICATION

But one certainly does not - not explicitly, and not implicitly - apply the set-theo- relational predications; but it is, in contrast to Frege's predication-theory, helpful
retical theory of predication, or Frege's theory, when determining, for example, for belief-foundation and truth-explanation. It is the theory I myself favour,
the truth of the statement "George loves Kate", nor would it be a good idea to The fact-referring functional predication-theory:
apply these theories in the effort to explicate the ontological basis for the truth
"0(a', ..., as)" is true - this amounts, ontologically, to the following: the comple-
of "George loves Kate". The same can be said of an account that - restricted to
non-relational predications - was in use as a purely logical tool throughout the tion of the 0-universal by (a', ..., as) is a fact, that is: an obtaining state of affairs.
entire Aristotelian tradition, which I therefore call Universals that need at least in some cases two entities for completion are called
"relations", universals that always need only one entity for completion are called
The minimal Aristotelian theory of predication:
"properties". Thus, we have:
"0(a', ..., as)" is true - this amounts, "ontologically", to the following: the
(monadic or relational) 0-universal is said (truthfully) of (a', ..., as). "Kate is a woman" is true - this amounts, ontologically, to the following: the
completion of the woman-property (i.e., the property of being a woman) by
The three last-mentioned theories (beginning with Frege's), though true, have Kate is a fact, or in other words: Kate has the property of being a woman.
no belief-foundational and no truth-explanatory value. Though they do introduce
onto-theoretical entities in order to account for predication - concepts, the truth- "George loves Kate" is true - this amounts, ontologically, to the following: the
object, sets, universals - they, in essence, just reformulate the normal expression completion of the love-relation (i.e., the relation of love) by (George, Kate) is a
of predication in technical logico-ontological terms; though they have som e fact, or in other words: George stands in the relation of love to Kate.
ontological content, they, in essence, just logically rationalise predication." They Facts - the states of affairs that obtain, or are actualised - are sometimes, in their
do so in keeping with the truth (though those who do not believe in universals or factuality, a product purely of social conventions; but normally they are not.
concepts or sets would deny this). But truth is not enough - as can easily be seen In any case, facts that are merely made up of universals and particulars - in a
by a glance at what may be dubbed manner that I have here merely hinted at, using the metaphor of completion16 -
are the primary objects of human objective cognition, not particulars as such
The "redundancy theory" of predication:
and not universals as such. To particulars and universals we come in cognition
"0(ai, ..., as)" is true - this amounts, "ontologically", to this: 0(al, ..., a,.,). only via states of affairs that involve them, and foremost via facts that involve
Or by a glance at the so-called (historically not unimportant and, like the immedi- them. Because facts that are merely made up of universals and particulars are
ately preceding theory, nominalism-compatible) the primary objects of human objective cognition, the fact-referring functional
predication-theory is helpful for founding belief in the truth, and for ontologically
"Identity theory" of predication:
explaining the truth, of simple predicative statements. We apply this theory
"o(a)" is true - this amounts, "ontologically", to this: "(1)" refers (as general implicitly when we judge that a simple predicative statement is true, and we do
term) to the same object that "a" refers to (as singular term). well to apply this theory explicitly when we seek to explain, from the ontological
These theories are obviously true (true for simple predicative statements as point of view, why - that is, on what ontological basis - a simple predicative
specified at the beginning of this essay, the "identity theory" being additionally statement is true.
restricted in its range to the non-relational ones among those statements); but just
as obviously they are not helpful at all for belief-foundation or truth-explanation.
But here, finally, follows a theory of predication which, like Frege's, falls
under the functional paradigm of predication. It is recognizably a modification of
Frege's theory and preserves the great advantage of that theory: the capturing of

'5 If one leaves out Leibniz's assumption of the rigidity of the designator "the concept of
a" (for example, "the concept of Caesar"; see footnote 13), then Leibniz's predication-theory
turns out to be adequate also with respect to our normal modal expectations. But what it
then offers is merely a true logical rationalisation of non-relational predication; it has no '6 The full theory is presented non-metaphorically in UwE MEIXNER, The Theory of Ontic
belief-foundational or truth-explanatory value. Modalities (Heusenstamm bei Frankfurt a. M.: Ontos, 2006).

244 • PREDICATION PREDICATION • 245


Uwe Meixner
THE INTERPRETATION(S) OF PREDICATION

BIBLIOGRAPHY

ALLEN, R. E. "Substance and Predication in Aristotle's Categories". In Exegesis and Argument.


Studies in Greek Philosophy Presented to Gregory Vlastos, edited by. E. N. Lee et al., 362-373.
Assen, Netherlands: van Gorcum, 1973. TOWARDS A THOMISTIC THEORY OF PREDICATION
ARISTOTLE. Kategorien. Hermeneutik. Vol. 2 of Organon. Edited by H.-G. Zekl. Darmstadt: Stanislav Sousedik
Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1998.
— Erste Analytik. Zweite Analytik. Vol. 3-4 of Organon. Edited by H.-G. Zekl. Darmstadt:
Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1998).
— Aristoteles' Metaphysik. BUcher 1(A) - VI(E). Edited by H. Seidl. Hamburg: Meiner, 1989. ABSTRACT
— Aristoteles' Metaphysik. Biicher VII(Z) - XIV(N). Edited by H. Seidl. Hamburg: Meiner, 1991. Thomas Aquinas formulates a theory of predication, according to which a predicative
statement expresses identity of some sort of the subject and the predicate. Such a theory can
BUTLER, JUDITH. Gender Trouble. Feminism and the Subversion of Identity. New York: Routledge,
be dubbed an "identity theory of predication". The author of the present paper aims to to
1990.
work out a modernised version of this theory, on the basis of the interpretation of Aquinas's
FREGE, GoTrws. "Funktion and Begriff'. In Funktion, Begriff; Bedeutung, edited by G. Patzig, legacy provided by some important 17th century Thomists. In his paper he demonstrates his
17-39. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1975. approach on the case of singular essential statement. The paper is divided in two parts. In the
HUSSERL, EDMUND. Phanomenologische Psychologie. Edited by D. Lohmar. Hamburg: Meiner, first part the author examines, how we actually predicate essential properties to empirical
2003. individuals in natural language. In the other part he propounds a theory aiming to explain the
facts observed in the first part by means of the assumption of a peculiar intelligible structure
KUTSCHERA, FRANZ VON. "Parts of Forms. An Essay concerning Plato's Parmenides". Logical in empirical individuals.
Analysis and History of Philosophy 1 (1998): 57-74.
LEIBNIZ, GOTTFRIED WILHELM. "Discours de Metaphysique". In GOTTFRIED WILHELM
LEIBNIZ, Opuscules Mitaphysiques / Kleine Schriften zur Metaphysik, edited by H. H. Holz, 1. INTRODUCTION
49-165. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1985.
The principal idea of the Thomistic theory of predication was formulated by
MEI XNER, UwE. "Negative Theology, Coincidentia Oppositorum, and Boolean Algebra". Logical Thomas Aquinas in his Summa theologiae. There he claims that a positive predi-
Analysis and History of Philosophy 1 (1998): 75-89.
cative sentence is signum identitatis eorum, quae componuntur.' A simple predica-
— The Theory of Ontic Modalities. Heusenstamm bei Frankfurt a. M.: Ontos, 2006. tive sentence is compounded of a subject and a predicate. The composition of a
PLATO. Phaidros. Parmenides. Epistolai. Vol. 5 of Werke in 8 Blinden. Edited by G. Eigler. sentence is according to Aquinas the composition of the intellect. Composition
Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft: Darmstadt, 1990. of the intellect differs from the composition of things; for in the latter the things
THOMAS AQUINAS. In Aristotelis Libros Peri Hermeneias et Posteriorum Analyticorum Expositio. are diverse, whereas the composition of the intellect is a sign of the identity of
Cum textu ex recensione Leonina. Augusta Taurinorum: Marietti, 1964. the components. So it seems that Thomas intended to say that what we mean by
WITTGENSTEIN, LUDWIG. Philosophical Investigations. New York: Macmillan, 1953. the subject and the predicate of such a sentence refers to one and the same thing.
His theory can be thus called the identity theory of predication.
The identity theory proposed by Thomas certainly gives very incomplete
semantics of propositions, since Thomas and his followers were concerned mostly
with predicative (atomic) propositions only, leaving the problems of so called
molecular propositions aside. This fact may be one of the reasons why this identity
theory is nowadays not presented besides other contemporary predication theo-
ries. Yet the importance of the identity theory for the revival of metaphysics
seems to be principal.

' Summa theologiae I, q. 85, a. 5, ad 3.

246 • PREDICATION PREDICATION • 247


n

Stanislav Soused& Stanislav Soused&


TOWARDS A THOMISTIC THEORY OF PREDICATION TOWARDS A THOMISTIC THEORY OF PREDICATION

The aim of my paper is to clarify the meaning of the identity theory by means as human. So we have to distinguish: the empirical feature of Peter (the laughter,
of a quite simple but important example, viz. the case of a positive, singular, the DNA pattern etc.) and a trait of his substance hinted at by that feature (in our
predicative proposition with a proper name as the subject and a common term example: Peter's humanity)! It generally holds that if A is a necessary condition of
as its predicate. In that type of propositions it is possible to distinguish two ways B, then B can be considered as a sign of A. Consequently we can take a proposition
of how a predicate can be attributed to a subject: The first may be called essential as a whole for a compound sign for something that is a condition of its being true,
predication (e.g. Socrates is a man), the other one accidental predication (e.g. Peter i.e. for the „truthmaker". The truthmaker (= the "verificativum" of the scholastics)
is ill). For the sake of brevity I will consider here the essential predication only, viz. consists - in the case of essential predication - of what was mentioned in points
sentences of the type Socrates is a man.' (1) and (2), i.e. of an individual substance with a trait hinted at by a certain feature
In the first part of my paper I will give some observations on the meaning of of it.
such kind of propositions in natural language. These observations will raise some
questions that cannot be answered by observation of natural language itself. 2.2 Second observation
They can be only answered by means of a theory. In the second part I shall argue If a singular proposition is a compound sign, the question arises, how its parts
that the identity theory of predication proposed by some later pupils of Aquinas (viz. subject and predicate) contribute to what is signified by it as a whole.
- representatives of the so called Second Scholasticism such as Thomas de Vio The answer seems to be clear in the case of the subject term, Peter in our
(Cajetanus, t1534),3 loannes a Sancto Thoma (= Joao Poinsot, t1644),4 Ludovicus example. Such a term picks out a certain individual we want to speak about. I hold
Babenstuber (t1726)5 (and last but not least their late follower Josephus Gredt, that a proper name refers directly to the bearer of the name without a mediation
t1940)6 - provides an acceptable starting point for such a theory. My present of some "sense". I have two reasons for my opinion: Firstly, I find the causal theory
aim nevertheless is not to offer a historical reconstruction of the teaching of of S. Kripke convincing. The second reason is that a very similar theory was also
these authors, but rather to contribute to some future version of an acceptable held by many old Thomists (scholars such as Ioannes a S. Thomas). That follows
Thomistic theory of predication on the basis of their doctrines. from the fact that in the case of proper names they didn't admit any so called
"suppositio simplex". So I suppose together with them that we refer directly to an
2. OBSERVATIONS individual (person or thing) by a proper name.
Let us consider the predicate, is a man in our case, now. The task of the predi-
2.1 First observation cate is to "characterise" the individual referred to by the subject term in some
Let us begin by considering propositions of the type Socrates is a man! It seems way. To characterise an individual means in general to direct the attention of the
to be clear that if such singular predicative proposition concerning an empirical hearer to some trait which the thing characterised has.
individual is true, there must exist something in the world that is a necessary If this is true, an important question arises: What does it mean, when we say
condition for its being true. Thus, e.g., if it is true that Peter is a man, then (1) Peter that an individual has some trait?9 In other words: what is the relation between
must exist, and (2) there must be something observable in Peter's body (e.g. he an individual substance and its trait?
laughs, he has a certain DNA pattern etc.), that qualifies him (i.e. his substance)
2.3 Third observation
2 The problems connected with the Thomistic conception of accidental predication are It is well known, that we use proper names not only in affirmative, but also in
discussed more widely in my book: Identitni teorie predikace [= The Identity Theory of Predication] vocative sentences. We say not only e.g.
(Praha: OIKOYMENH, 2006).
3 CAJETANUS, Commentarius in opusculum S. Thomae Aquinatis De ente et essentia, cap. 4. (there
are many old and modern editions of this work). ' So by "feature" I mean what the scholastic tradition calls "proprium". According to Tho-
4 IOANNES A SANCTO THOMA, Cursus Philosophicus Thomisticus, vol. 1, Logica, pars 2, q. 1-5 mists, we do not have direct knowledge of substance, we are able to get only an indirect one,

(first edition Romae, 1636; modern critical edition by B. Reiser, Turin: Marietti, 1948 [this by means of "propria". Proprium is not a concrete accident, but the fourth "praedicabile", that
edition is cited here, henceforward Reiser]), 251-369. means a concept of a certain concrete accident.
5 LUDOVICUS BABENSTUBER, Philosophia Thomistica Salisburgensis (Augustae Vindelicorum, B Cursus Philosophicus Thomisticus, vol. 1, Logica, pars 1, q. 6, a. 3 (Reiser, 176).
1706), tomus 1: 139-185. 9 A different question would be: What does it mean, when we say that an individual has

6 JOSEPHUS GREDT, Elementa Philosophiae Aristotelico-Thomisticae, § 114-139, 13`h ed. (Barci- some feature? But this question does not pertain to the essenial, but to the accidental way of
nonae, Friburgi Brisgoviae, Romae, Neo-Eboraci, 1961), vol. 1: 108-133. predication, so I leave it aside here.

248 • PREDICATION PREDICATION • 249


Stanislav Soused& Stanislav Sousedik
TOWARDS A THOMISTIC THEORY OF PREDICATION TOWARDS A THOMISTIC THEORY OF PREDICATION

(1)Peter is a man, 2.5 Fifth observation


(a) We can predicate more than one common term of an individual, we say
but also
e.g. not only Peter is a man but also Peter is an animal, Peter is a living being, Peter is
(2)Peter, come here! a substance etc.
Now it seems clear, that a proper name used in an affirmative sentence refers (b) We can often predicate one and the same common term of more than one
to an individual who is identical with what is addressed by using the same proper individual.
names in vocative sentence.
2.6 Sixth observation
Let us notice now that instead of proper names, we can also use common terms
in addressing individuals. A teacher can say e.g.: Every empirical individual and every part or trait of it is particular. The
individual is "all through" particular.
(3)Peter, don't speak without permission!
but he can express the same thought by saying 2.7 Seventh observation
No real part of an individual, which is actually distinguished from the whole,
(4)Man, don't speak without permission! can be predicated of it. So every proposition like "Peter is his left foot" is logically
Now, if the proper name Peter used in (3) refers to a certain individual (viz. false.
Peter), the common term man used in (4) seems to refer (in the right situation)
to the same individual. So we can see that not only proper, but also common 2.8 The problem
names refer to individuals in natural language. So if common terms, used as The task is now to answer the question, what the "weak identity" means and
predicates, direct our attention to some traits of the individual referred to by by means of it to show, how the six observations mentioned above build a coherent
the subject term, it means consequently that these traits must be identical with whole. To solve this problem, it doesn't suffice what we have done so far, viz.
that individual in some sense.' to observe the way we understand and use natural language. It is necessary to
explain all that by a certain theory.
2.4 Fourth observation
The traits of an individual we refer to by the predicate cannot be identical 3. THE THEORY
with the individual in the usual way of speaking. It is clear that by Peter is a man 3.1 The distinctions
we provide some information, but no information is offered by Peter is Peter. So
the "is" in the first sentence must express some other type of identity than in the According to the fifth observation it is possible to assert more than one
other. Nevertheless, it seems that both cases of "is" have something in common." essential predicate about one and the same individual subject. If - according to
If this is correct we have to abandon (what is after Frege generally accepted) that the second observation - these predicates refer to some trait of the individual,
there is a principal difference between "is" as a sign of identity and "is" as a sign the question arises, what the difference between these traits in one and the same
of predication. In both cases "is" seems to express some identity relation: in one individual is. In the identity theory of predication it is presupposed that between
case (Peter is Peter) we shall speak about "strong" identity, in the other (Peter is man) these traits there is the so called "virtual distinction". What kind of relation is it?
about "weak" one. (Def. 1) Between x, y there is virtual distinction, iff (i) x, y are really identical;
(ii) x can become an object of some cognitive act (I), withouty being the object
of the same act (I) (the range of variability of x,y are entities, viz. individuals
'° An interesting fact follows from the third observation: The grammatical predicate e.g. and any kind of components these individuals may have).
"is a man" does not seem to be an unanalysable whole, but a composite sign consisting of
what is traditionally called "copula" and the predicate in the strict sense of the word, "man" Now what does the term "real identity" used in the above definition mean?
in our example.
" It is generally accepted that "Peter is Peter" expresses identity. But from 2.3 it follows (Def. 2) Between x,y there is real identity, iffx,y have all properties F in common
that "Peter is a man" expresses some kind of identity, too. So it seems there cannot be a prin- (the range of variability of F being every property with the exception of "to
cipal difference between the "is" occuring in the first and "is" in the second sentence. be an object of a cognitive act (I)").

250 • PREDICATION PREDICATION • 251


Stanislav Sousedik
TOWARDS A THOMISTIC THEORY OF PREDICATION
I Stanislav Soused&
TOWARDS A THOMISTIC THEORY OF PREDICATION

Let us now make a stipulation, that we shall use the word "metaphysical part" 3.3 Metaphysical parts in concrete and abstract states
(abbreviated: "MP") instead of the word "trait". By the word "part" we usually So far we have considered the metaphysical parts only in as much as they are in
mean a piece of a body, so e.g. we can call Peter's left leg a part of his body. So it the concrete state ("in an individual"). We have seen that according to the identity
may seem strange to call a trait of a substance its "metaphysical part". However, theory they are really identical, but virtually distinct in that state. Now, as proper
it is a traditional scholastic way of speaking,12 and - if we respect the stipulation MPs are virtually distinct, they may be grasped separately from one another by
above - an absolutely innocent one. our understanding. If so (i.e. separately or "abstractly") grasped they get into
By means of this new term one may say that between metaphysical parts there another state than they originally were in. Let us call their original state the
is virtual distinction. concrete state (abbreviated: "C"), that new state the abstract state (abbreviated: "A").
It seems clear that a metaphysical part in the abstract state is partly different
3.2 The essence from what it has been in the concrete state. What are the properties that differen-
Our consideration 2.5b seems to suggest that really distinct individuals can tiate a metaphysical part in one state from the same metaphysical part considered
have a numerically identical metaphysical part. But this is with respect to obser- in the other?
vation 2.6 unacceptable. To prevent what seems to follow from 2.5b, we must First difference: Each in C occurring metaphysical part of an individual is only
suppose that among the proper metaphysical parts of an individual, there must be potentially distinguished from every other MP contained in the same individual,
one improper part, which (in contrast to the proper parts) can be from any point of the same part considered in A is distinguished actually from every other.
view only in the individual, whose part it actually is. Let us call this special part Note: Between MPs in A there is an "intentional distinction" (traditionally:
"individuality"." Let us suppose that between the individuality of an individual distinctio rationis ratiocinatae): We can define it as follows:
x and every other MP of x there is virtual distinction. Since the individuality is (Def. 5) There is an intentional distinction between F, G, iff (i) F, G are actually
really identical with the other MPs, it makes them individual. Thus observation
distinguished, and (ii) there is an individual essence in which (the absolute
2.6 is satisfied.
subjects" of) F, G are really identical.
(Def. 3) The specific essence of an individual is the sum of all proper metaphysical
Second difference: The metaphysical parts in the state C exist really, the meta-
parts of that individual.
physical parts in the state A exist intentionally.
(Def. 4) The individual essence of an individual is the sum of all proper and Note: In the identity theory existence is considered to be a first level predicate.
improper metaphysical parts of that individual.'" Two kinds of first level existence are distinguished within this theory: real exis-
tence belongs to entities which exist independently of the fact whether they
(Consequently the individual essence is thus really identical with the sub- are object of our understanding or not. Intentional existence belongs to entities
stance of the individual). which exist only in dependence upon the fact that they are objects of our under-
standing.
The proper metaphysical parts in the C state are particular in consequence of
their real identity with individuality, the same metaphysical parts in the A state
are universal in consequence of their intentional distinction from individuality.
12 See e.g. IOANNES A S. THOMA, Cursus philosophicus Thomisticus, vol. 1, Logica, pars prima,
Summulae, lib. 2, cap. 3 (Reiser 20 b 11). 3.4 Weak identity
13 Individuality differs from Scotistic haecceitas by having its source (= principium) in a cer-
We have stated in our fourth observation that the meaning of a predicate is
tain physical part of the (empirical) substance, viz. in prime matter. We are able to refer to the
"somehow" identical with the individual of which it is predicated. Our task will
individualities of different individuals by the common term "individuality" in consequence
of the fact, that the relations of singular individualities to "their" substances are similar. So now be to explain, what that "somehow" exactly means.
the concept "individuality" is an analogous one. A proper metaphysical part in A state is called by the late scholastic tradition
" Thomas Aquinas does not speak about "individual", but about "particular" essence: „Sed "conceptus obiectivus". Within the identity theory of predication these objective
quia individuationis principium est materia, ex hoc forte videtur sequi, quod essentia, quae materiam
complectitur in se simul et formam, sit tantum particularis et non universalis..." - THOMAS AQUINAS,
De ente et essentia, cap. 2. 15 The meaning of the term "absolute subject" will be explained later in 3.4.

252 • PREDICATION PREDICATION • 253


iw

Stanislav Sousedik Stanislav Sousedik


TOWARDS A THOMISTIC THEORY OF PREDICATION TOWARDS A THOMISTIC THEORY OF PREDICATION

concepts are held for the meaning of a certain kind of predicates, let us call them According to the adequacy theory, truth is a kind of relation ("adaequatio")
elementary predicates. The most conspicuous feature of elementary predicates is between the meaning of a proposition with the piece of the world we speak
that they are built up without any formal signs (as conjunctions, quantifiers etc.), about." At the end of my paper I would like to say something about the terms of
Now, one could be tempted to say that a metaphysical part F in the abstract that relation, i.e. about (a) the meaning of a proposition, and then (b) about its
state is weakly identical with an individual, if this individual has F among its MPs. denotatum.
However, this cannot be correct, because a MP in A is universal, has an intentional
existence etc. and as such it cannot be one of the MP in C(oncrete state) of an 4.2 The meaning of a proposition
individual. It is necessary to define weak identity with more caution: Let us remind the reader once more that by a true singular predicative pro-
position we characterise an individual x by means of a universal concept F. In a
(Def. 6) The metaphysical part F in A is weakly identical with an individual x, if positive proposition the universal concept F is - as we have seen - a MP in A of the
the individual x has among its metaphysical parts in C such a metaphysical individual x. So it seems to be clear that a positive proposition about an empirical
part (I) that (I) and F have a common constituent. individual expresses weak identity of F (= a MP in A) with x (an individual). As the
converse of weak identity is what we have called participation," we can express
Stipulation: Let us call this common constituent "absolute subject".
the same idea by saying that a true singular predicative proposition expresses
By the term "absolute subject" I mean what remains, if we abstract from both that an individual participates on a MP in A (= on a universal concept). On the
the properties that are possessed by F only in A, and the properties possessed by other hand, a negative true singular proposition (e.g. Peter is not a horse) expresses
(I) only in C. The tradition (following Avicenna) speaks about "natura secundum se". the lack of participation of an individual on a MP in A."
But I prefer to call it "the absolute subject" here. Consequently, it seems that the meaning of a singular proposition (irrespec-
We shall call the converse relation of weak identity the relation of partici- tive of its truth-value) is a compound entity, in which a really existing individual
pation. is placed into a relation with an intentionally existing object, i.e. with an objective
The notion of universality is linked with weak identity. Universality is a pro- concept. The most important (but also the most scandalous for many people)
perty of a MP in A consisting in the fact that it may be weakly identical with more feature of the identity theory is the thesis that two profoundly different objects
than one individual. are connected within the meaning of a singular proposition, namely a real exis-
Between "weak" and "strong" identity there is obviously a great difference. ting individual on the one hand and an intentionally existing concept on the
Strong identity is reflexive, symmetric and transitive, weak identity has none of other. However, this is a sign of the Aristotelian origin of the theory.
these formal properties. Despite that there is an interesting connexion between
both these identities. Weak identity may have degrees (e.g. the weak identity be- 4.3 Denotation
tween the notion "body" and Socrates is weaker, than the weak identity between True singular propositions not only have a meaning, but they also denote
"man" and Socrates). It seems clear that one can conceive strong identity as a some piece of the world by means of that meaning. It seems possible to conceive
final state, a certain "maximum", of weak identity. Within the identity theory the relevant piece of the world that a true positive proposition denotes as its
the principal difference between "is" as a copula and "is" as a sign of identity (as denotatum. In the case of a true positive proposition of the type Peter is a man the
stated by Frege) is not admitted. denotatum is an individual considered as having the same M(etaphysical)P(art) in
the concrete state which in the abstract state is the meaning of the predicate. By
4. TRUTH "the same" I mean "having a common absolute subject" here. In the case of a true
negative proposition (Peter is not a horse) the denotatum is an individual considered
4.1 Truth conditions as lacking the relevant MP. A false proposition like Peter is a horse applies to Peter,
The notion of weak identity offers a tool for formulating the main idea of the but lacks a denotatum: There is no such a thing as Peter having the MP horse.
Thomistic adequacy theory of truth a little clearer (with respect to the tradition).
The truth conditions of a singular predicative proposition are as follows:
76 It is not necessary to stress, I presume, that the relation of adequacy is quite different
(Def. 7) A singular positive predicative proposition is true, if (i) the individual from the relation of correspondence.
denoted by the subject term exists in the time indicated by the verb, and (ii) '7 See above, section 3.4.
the meaning of the predicate is weakly identical with that individual. Hence negative facts are admitted in the identity theory.

254 • PREDICATION PREDICATION • 255


1
Stanislav Soused&
TOWARDS A THOMISTIC THEORY OF PREDICATION

BIBLIOGRAPHY
AQUINAS, THOMAS. Summa theologiae. Vol. 4-12 of Opera omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita.
Romae, 1888-1906.
— De ente et essentia. Vol. 43 of Opera omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita. Romae, 1976.
AUTHORS
BABENSTUBER, LUDOVICUS. Philosophia Thomistica Salisburgensis. Augustae Vindelicorum,
1706. MARK FALLER is Professor of Philosophy and former Chair-
CAJETANUS, THOMAS DE VIO, CARDINALIS. In De ente et essentia divi Thomae Aquinatis commen- person at the Liberal Studies Department of the Alaska Pa-
tarius. Edited by M.-H. Laurent. Turin: Marietti, 1934. cific University. As an undergraduate Physics and Philosophy
GREDT JOSEPHUS. Elementa Philosophiae Aristotelico-Thomisticae, 13th ed. Barcinonae, Friburgi major at Harvard University he worked under Hilary Putnam
Brisgoviae, Romae, Neo-Eboraci, 1961. and David Layzer on an Honors Thesis challenging the Pre-
IOANNES A SANCTO THOMA. Cursus Philosophicus Thomisticus. Edited by B. Reiser. Augusta
Chaos Theory assumptions of an easy reconciliation between
Taurinorum: Marietti, 1948. Evolutionary Theory and the Second Law. As a Doctoral
student under Edward Halper at the University of Georgia,
SOUSEDIK, STANISLAV. Iclentitni teorie predikace. Praha: OIKOYMENH, 2006.
Dr. Faller worked on interpreting the mathematical puzzles
in Plato's dialogues as a heuristic system for determining how
geometrical analysis can guide logical argument. His writing
continues to follow both vectors. Along the way he has taught
rock climbing, coached college and Olympic wrestlers, and
sailed around the world in the merchant marine. He is an
addict of used book stores and chocolate, and now teaches
philosophy because he is convinced that ideas are the living
tools by which we transform the world.
E-MAIL: mfaller@alaskapacific.edu

EDWARD FESER is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Pasa-


dena City College in Pasadena, California. He holds a Ph.D. in
philosophy from the University of California at Santa Barbara,
an M.A. in religion from the Claremont Graduate School, and
a B.A. in philosophy and religious studies from the California
State University at Fullerton. He is the author of On Nozick,
Philosophy of Mind, Locke, The Last Superstition: A Refutation of
the New Atheism, and Aquinas, and editor of The Cambridge Com-
panion to Hayek, and of many academic articles. His primary
academic research interests are in the philosophy of mind,
moral and political philosophy, and the philosophy of religion.
Feser also writes on politics and culture, from a conservative
point of view; and on religion, from a traditional Roman Ca-
tholic perspective. He lives in Los Angeles with his wife and
six children.
E-MAIL: edwardfeser@hotmail.com

256 • PREDICATION 257


AUTHORS AUTHORS

Ross INMAN is a Ph.D. candidate in philosophy at Trinity MICHAEL J. Loux is Emeritus Professor of Philosophy, past
College, Dublin. His general interests include metaphysics, George Shuster Professor of Philosophy, and past dean of the
mediaeval philosophy, value epistemology, and philosophy of College of Arts and Letters at the University of Notre Dame.
religion. He has a particular interest in bringing ancient and His interests include Greek philosophy (especially Aristotle)
mediaeval metaphysics to bear on current debates in material and metaphysics. He has authored numerous influential works
objects. His current research focuses on the intersection of in metaphysics and Greek philosophy, including Substance and
metaphysical grounding and mereology. Attribute (1978), Primary Ousia: An Essay on Aristotle's Metaphysics
E-MAIL: rossinman@gmail.com
Z and H (1991), Metaphysics: a Contemporary Introduction, 3rd ed.
(2006), and "Aristotle's Constituent Ontology" (2006). He has
edited Universals and Particulars (1970), The Possible and the Actual
(1990), and The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics (with Dean Zim-
merman, 2003).
E-MAIL: MichaelJ.Loux.i@nd.edu
PETER VAN INWAGEN is the John Cardinal O'Hara Professor
of Philosophy at the University of Notre Dame, Indiana. His
work in the fields of ontology (nature of material objects), E. J. LOWE is Professor of Philosophy at the Durham Univer-
philosophical theology (problem of evil, bodily resurrection) sity, UK. He has published over 150 articles on metaphysics,
and philosophy of action (he introduced the "compatibilism the philosophy of mind and action, the philosophy of logic,
vs. incompatibilism" distiction into the free will debate) make the philosophy of language, and early modern philosophy.
him one of the leading figures in contemporary analytical Some of his books include: Kinds of Being (1989), Locke on Hu-
metaphysics broadly construed. man Understanding (1995), Subjects of Experience (1996), The Pos-
E-MAIL: peter.vaninwagen.1@nd.edu sibility of Metaphysics (1998), An Introduction to the Philosophy of
Mind (2000), A Survey of Metaphysics (2002), Locke (2005), The
Four-Category Ontology (2006), and Personal Agency (2008). He
is a General Editor of the Cambridge Studies in Philosophy
monograph series.
V: •141 1
i4
GYULA KLIMA is Professor of Philosophy at the Fordham Uni-
versity, New York. His scholarly interests comprise mediaeval E MAIL: e.j.lowe@durham.ac.uk
il, philosophy, semantics, metaphysics, philosophy of mind and
' ff language, and, significantly, comparative studies of mediae-
val and modern theories. He has published almost a hundred UWE MEIXNER teaches philosophy at the University of Augs-
articles and several books on these topics. In his research he burg, Germany. His main philosophical interests are meta-
pays special attention to Aquinas and Buridan. physics (general and special, including the philosophy of mind
E-MAIL: gyula.klima@gmail.com and the philosophy of causation), the history of philosophy,
and logic. He is currently working on a comparative study of
the philosophies of psychology of Husserl and Wittgenstein.
His main publications in English are: Axiomatic Formal Ontology
(1997), The Two Sides of Being. A Reassessment of Psycho-Physical
Dualism (2004), The Theory of Ontic Modalities (2006), Modelling
Metaphysics. The Metaphysics of a Model (2010).
E-MAIL: uwe.meixner@phil.uni-augsburg.de

258 259
111

AUTHORS AUTHORS

DANIEL D. NOVOTNi is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at ANNE SIEBELS PETERSON is a philosophy Ph.D. candidate at the
the Faculty of Theology, University of South Bohemia in Ceske University of Notre Dame. She focuses on metaphysical issues
Budejovice, Czech Republic. His interests include history of in Aristotle, in particular on topics surrounding Aristotle's
philosophy, metaphysics, philosophical anthropology, com- hylomorphism. She is writing her dissertation on the issue
parative philosophy, and teaching philosophy. His current of numerical diversification in Aristotle's Metaphysics, with
research focuses on the history of the controversies about an eye toward exploring the implications which Aristotle's
entia rationis in post-mediaeval scholasticism. He is the Edi- metaontology has for this issue. She is also especially inter-
tor-in-Chief of Studia Neoaristotelica, A Journal of Analytical ested in Aristotle's account of change, including his reply to
Scholasticism. the Parmenidean argument for the impossibility of genera-
E-MAIL: danieldnovotny@gmail.com tion and destruction, as well as the understanding of matter
presupposed by this reply. Having also studied contemporary
metaphysical issues, she concentrates on ontology and meta-
ontology in the contemporary scene, and on exploring ways
Lux.Ag NovAK is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at the Fac- in which Aristotle's views might provide a promising perspec-
ulty of Arts and Philosophy, Charles University, Prague, and tive different from those currently on offer in contemporary
Faculty of Theology, University of South Bohemia in Ceske metaphysics. She is also interested in the philosophy of biol-
Budejovice, Czech Republic. Historically, he is interested in ogy, wherein she has focused on the problem of articulating
the philosophical legacy of Duns Scotus and its later develop- the metaphysical basis for the homology of biological traits.
ment especially in the 17th century. In his systematic work he E-MAIL: asiebels@nd.edu
attempts to combine traditional scholastic and contemporary
analytic approach in areas such as metaphysics, philosophy
of logic and epistemology. He has been editor of the journal EDMUND RUNGGALDIER SJ was born in 1946, studied theology
Studia Neoaristotelica since its foundation in 2004. (Mag. Theol.) and philosophy - he received his Ph.D. from
E-MAIL: lukas.novak@skaut.org Oxford University in 1977, his thesis having been supervised
by A. J. Ayer. He has been Professor for Philosophy at the Theo-
logical Faculty of Innsbruck University since 1990 and from
DAVID PEROUTKA OCD studied theology and philosophy at 2003 to 2007 he was "Professore titolare" for analytic ontology
the Charles University, Prague. He teaches philosophy at the at the University Cattolica di Milano. From 2007 to 2009 he
Faculty of Philosophy, Jan Evangelista Purkyne University, held the Romano Guardini Chair at the Protestant Theological
Usti nad Labem, Czech republic. Up to now his research has Faculty, Humboldt University, Berlin. From 2000 to 2006 he
focused mainly on the dialogue between Aristotelian and was President of the Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society.
analytic philosophy. His interests comprise ontology, classical metaphysics and
E-MAIL: david.peroutka.ocd@seznam.cz scholasticism. Currently he is working on a research project
"Powers and the Identity of Agents" funded by the Austrian
Science Fund (FWF Austria).
E-MAIL: Edmund.Runggaldier@uibk.ac.at

260 261
ra

AUTHORS

PROKOP SOUSEDlK works at the Department of Logic, Institute


of Philosophy of the Academy of Sciences of the Czech Repub-
lic. He teaches logic, epistemology and analytic philosophy at
the Catholic Theological Faculty of the Charles University and GENERAL INDEX
at the Faculty of Arts of the Jan Evangelista Purkyne Univer-
sity. He is interested in philosophy of mathematics.
E-MAIL: Prokop.Sousedik@seznam.cz The index does not comprise the abstracts and the descriptions of individual articles in the
preface. References to occurences in footnotes are in parentheses, bold numbers imply substantial
discussion in the text. In crossreferences, semicolons separate distinct entries, commas parts of the
same entry.

a priori vs. a posteriori - in relation to substance 29, 81-86,


STANISLAV SOUSEDIK, born 1931, is Professor Emeritus of the 177, 180-181, 211, 216-217,241-242 119-120, 123; cf inherence
History of Philosophy at the Faculty of Arts and Philosophy abstract - mental 30
and the Catholic Theological Faculty, Charles University, - answer 12-13 - separated 73, 78, 81, 83, 87
Prague. Among the main areas of his scholarly interest belong - concept 137 - vs. essence 104
history of early modern scholasticism, and analytical philoso- - idea 13 accidental
phy. His aim is to find inspiration there for the renewal and - nouns 98, (174) - being: see being accidental
development of Catholic-orientated philosophy (in the spirit - number 134-137 - form 86, 88, 119, 202
of the encyclical Fides et ratio) in the Czech republic. - object, thing, entity - property: see property' essential
12, 18, 22-23, 37, 48-50,134-139,153,230 vs. non-essential or accidental
E MAIL: sousedik.s@volny.cz - quality 59 act' (vs. potency) 85, 145-146, 160;
- state: see state concrete vs. abstract cf. actuality
- structure 138-139 - first vs. second 188
- units 129 - of existence: see existence act of
- vs. concrete 17-18, 22-23, 48-50, 138; - pure 145-150,163,165
DAVID SvosoDA is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at the
cf state concrete vs. abstract
Department of Philosophy, Catholic Theological Faculty, act': see action
Charles University, Prague. His scholarly interests include abstraction 17, 23, 103, 120, 137, 139, 152, - abstractive: see abstraction
history of mediaeval and early modern academical philo- 161, 176, 203, 217, 239 - mental 35, 176, 251
- mere 103, 120, 152, 161, 203, 239
sophy, metaphysics, and philosophy of mathematics; he is action: cf. operation
- of numbers 126-128,137
specially interested in the thought of Thomas Aquinas and - and causality 191-192
- of prime matter 65, 70
his followers. His current research focuses on the problem of - and reaction 186-187
the ontological status of number and the ontology of relations accessibility - as second act 188
- of possible worlds 187 - belongs to the substance 190
in post-mediaeval scholasticism.
- - causal 205-206 - for an end 155-156, 221
E-MAIL: davidsvoboda@sovice.net accident - indicative of active potency 187-188, 193
- a modified meaning of 139 active vs. passive potency, power,
- and predication (50), 67, 73 capability 163-165,188-190,193, 195,
- and truthmaking 86-89 204, 206; cf. power; capability causal;
- concrete (249) disposition
- conditioned 202
actual
- contingent, vs. property 94-95
- actualiser 146-149
- dispositional 199;
- dependence:
cf. disposition; power; potency
see dependence actual vs. aptitudinal

262 263
GENERAL INDEX GENERAL INDEX

- distinction 251, 253 anti-essentialism: see essentialism being (15), 22-24, 27, 32-36, 123, 153-154, - necessity: see necessity causal
- existence 30, 52, 64, 83, 85, 105, 109-110, vs. anti-essentialism 157, 210-211; cf. existence; object; entity - power, potency, disposition
156, 170-173, 178-181 Antiquity 234, 239 - accidental 28, 88, 123 147, (156), 158, 193, 195, 198, 204;
- foundation of predication 243 appellatio 174-178 - actual: see actual object, thing, entity cf capability, capacity causal
- generation of effect 155 - contingent: see contingency of things, - of God 203
Aristotelian beings, objects
- object, thing, entity - process 205-206
- account of dispositions: - extrinsic 27-28, 31, 36
27, 29, 52, 105, 109-110, 172, 204 - - and laws of nature 203
- reality 29-31 see analysis of dispositions Aristotelian - genuine 62-63
- account of events 188 - - unintelligent 156
- thinking 33 - impossible 29-31 - production 191
- account of number 127 - intentional:
- union of substance and accident; - regularity 155
inherence: see inherence actual - account of predication: see intentional object, being, entity - role and efficacy 187, 190-193, 199
see analysis of predication Aristotelian - necessary: see necessary being
vs. potential - series, chain 195, 205;
- analysis of the elements 69 - negative vs. positive 27, 30, 35
- world : see world actual, this, real cf. causal connexion
- categories: see category Aristotelian - of reason 25-37;
actualism 60, 64-66, 70-71, 150, 204 - - per se vs. per accidens ordered
- causes: see cause Aristotelian cf non-being; non-existence;
actuality: cf act'; actual - constituent ontology 67-71; 81, 146-147, 149, 152, 158
- amounts to keeping one's essence 171 intentional being, object, entity - tendency 155
et ontology constituent vs. relational - possible: see possible being, entity
- condition of being at all 64 - definition of efficient cause 191-192 - theory of reference 108-109, (133), 249
- given by accidents 85 - rationate, intentional, mental: causality 187, 191, 195, 198
- definition of ontology 23 see intentional being, object, entity
- of prime matter 64-65, 70, 151 - essentialism: - divine 162, 203
- pure: see act' pure - real 30, 36 - efficient 148, 155, 157, 191-192, 155,
see essentialism Aristotelian
- vs. potentiality 32, 82, 85, 145-146, 150, - form: see form Aristotelian boson 16-17, 21 191-192; cf. cause efficient
189-190 - hylomorphism: calculus - event vs. agent causation 187, 191-193
aggregate 28, (36), 126-137, 160-161 see hylomorphism Aristotelian - differential and integral - final, finality 145, 154-158, 163, 218-219;
- metaphysics: 214-215, 218, 221 cf cause final, teleology
analysis
see metaphysics Aristotelian - of situation 214 - formal 85, 153
- algebraic 213
- ontology: see ontology Aristotelian capability, capacity causal 82, 187-191, - - of quantity 124
- Aristotelian of the elements 69
- teleology: see teleology Aristotelian 195, 204, 206, 215; cf. causal power, - in Leibniz 210, 212, 220
- conceptual 137, 211, 213
- mathematical 210, 213-216 - tradition: see Aristotelianism potency, disposition; disposition; power; cause
- of dispositions - universals 66, 242; cf. universal potency; active vs. passive potency, - and the principle of sufficient reason 197
cf. disposition; power; potency Aristotelianism power, capability - Aristotelian (162), 191-192
- - Aristotelian 186, 190, 195, 203, 206 78, 84, 150, 186-193, 195, 244 categorical basis 198-200 - determinant 224
- - conditional 185, 195-197, 206 - vs. Platonism 46, 136, 239-240 - efficient 82, 148-149, 153-154, 191-192
category 25, 28-29, 32-33, 128;
- of free action 203 Aristotelian-scholastic (doctrines) cf. super-category - final 154-158, (162), 221; cf. end
- of language (logical) 5, 114, 129-131 6, 187, 193 - Aristotelian 97-98, 128, 133, 189-190, 201 - formal 161-(162), 221; cf. form
- of natural substances 164 - non-material 128, 133 - has many meanings 191-192
Aristotelian-Thomistic (doctrines) - immediate 206
- of predication Aristotelian 148, 158, 163-164, 165 - of quantity: see quantity
235, 239, 244, 255; cf: predication - ontological - intrinsic vs. extrinsic (162)
arithmetic 131, 136, 139, 223 - material 161-(162)
- situs, geometric 213-214, 216 13, (15), 18-24, 98-100, 103, 120, 135
astrology 16-17 - mechanical 218
analytic vs. synthetic 49, 116, 216-217 category mistake 48-51
atheism 49, 163, 205 - natural 155, 157, 192
analytical metaphysics 5-6, 26, 32, 37, 73 causal - not power but bearer thereof 191
analytical philosophy 5-8, 11, 26, 28, 32, ausser-being 34 - accessibility 205-206 - of beings of reasons 36
113-114 axiology 231 - capability: see capability causal - of oneself 149
Analytical Thomism 6 Baroque scholasticism - connexion, interaction 109, 195, 203-205 - of return of metaphysics 5
6, 25, 28, 30-33, 37 - dependence: see dependence causal - of the matter-form conjunction 152
angel (26), 151-152

264 265
GENERAL INDEX GENERAL INDEX

- of truth: see truthmaking - extensional (243) continuum 211-215 - of matter and form 151-152
- personal 192 - objective 255 contradiction 31, 34-35, 115-116, 173-175, - of number 124, 139
- proper vs. accidental 192-193 - of an accident (249) 211; cf. incoherence - of truth 84, 100
- sufficient 204 - primitive: see primitive notion contraries 34, 131-132, 191 - on mind: see mind-dependence
- sustaining 159-(160) - quidditative (80), 82, 176-178 - elemental 59, 65-71 - on substance or subject
- uncaused 147, 148-149, 153 - scientific 176-177 81-84, 86, 123, 138
- sortal vs. non-sortal 133-134 convention 13, 17-18, 186
class 26, 31, 97-98, 124, 135-136 - social 230-232, 245 - ontological 65-67, (77), 86, 102-103
- complementary 15-16 - superior 128 - rigid vs. non-rigid 75-76, 87
- empty 15-16, 21 - universal 255 conventionalism social 231 - the order of 79, 81; cf order essential
- large 17-18, (22) - vague, confused 176 copula 134, (250), 254 - upon predication 65-66, 71
- natural 13-23, 31 - vs. object 115, 120, 132-133, 217 correspondence 210, (255) description 130, 132-134
- high 18 concept formation 178, 216 corruption: description of a world 205
- highest 19, 21 concrete see generation and corruption disposition 185-190, 193, 195-206;
- of sentences maximal 204 - accident (249) creation 143-144, 151 cf. potency; power; capability; active
- universal 15-18, 22-23 - individual 137-138 creature 18, 79, 169-172, 181 vs. passive potency, power, capability
- virtual 21 - number, unit, aggregate 126-131, 137
de re vs. de dicto 113-116, 120-121 - causal:
coincidence (local) 94, 107 - object, thing, entity 17-18, 22-23, see causal power, potency, disposition
48-50, 95-98, 110, 134, 137-139, (238) definition
combination: cf. composition - to inhere 82
- state: see state abstract vs. concrete - as original truth 212-213
- of matter and form 93-99, 103 - ungrounded 200
- substance 95, 127-130 - biological 218
- of substance and accident 88 dissipation 222-224
- system 138 - mathematical 217
commitment ontological, metaphysical - of number 126-128, 133-134, 136 distinction
- vs. abstract: see abstract vs. concrete
(32), 37, 54, 100 - of ontological category 19-21 - essential vs. accidental 119
composition: cf. combination; relation of condition necessary 248-249
- of ontology, first philosophy 23; - grammatical 98
composition conditional analysis of dispositions: see Aristotelian definition of ontology - intentional 253
- metaphysical 160, 162-163, 165; see analysis of dispositions conditional - of potency 202 - numerical 63, 88, 107
cf: part metaphysical connexion causal: see causal connexion - of small number 18 - real 119, 172, 252
- of essence and existence consistency 182, 192, 205, 241 - real, quidditative vs. verbal, nominal - between essence and existence 148-149,
145, 147, 151-152, 162, 170 constituent: 4 part 104-106, 108, 110, (171) 152-154, 158, 169-175, 177, 181
- of matter and form - scientific, quidditative - virtual 251-253
constituent ontology, strategy: see
145, 147, 150-152, 161-162 (171)-172, 176, 178-181 divided line 210-213, 218, 224
ontology constituent vs. relational
- of (ordinary) objects 44-45, 51-55, 102 denomination, denominativeness
contingency divine conservation 143-145
- of potency and act 145, 160, 162 36, 85-86
- of the intellect 247 - of constitutional role 52 division
- of dependence 66-67, 83-84 denotatum of a proposition 255 - material 125-128, 133
compossibility 210, 212, 218-221, 224
- of exemplification 47, 101-102 dependence - real among things 13-17
conceivability, thinkability 31, 150 - of existence 178 - actual vs. aptitudinal 83-85 dormitive power 163
concept 109, 132-139, 176 - of history 20 - causal 81, 147 dualism 48, 212, 218
- absolute - of non-existence 34, 36 - contingent 66-67, 83-84
- abstract 137 dynamical vs. mathematical (model,
- of properties, features 54, 95, 114 - essential 73-79, 84, 87;
- and number 132-139 - of substantiality 119 cf order essential relationship, explanation...) 217-221
- and opaque context 174, 176 - of the world 150, 164 - existential 78-87, 147, 151-153, 160; eide 232-233, 236, 239; cf. idea
- and predication 240-243, 255 - of things, beings, objects cf d. rigid vs. non-rigid electron 12, 16, 96-97, 101, 178, 222
- common 31 20, 52-53, 102, 144, 152, 158-163, 178 - identity (77), 101-103, 106 element'
- complete 241-242 - of truths 102, 211-212, 219, 241 - logical 178; cf logical independence - Aristotelian 59-71
- determinate, clear, distinct 174, 176 - radical vs. superficial 158-160 - metaphysical 75-77, 87 - chemical 161, 179, 186
- empirical 217 - of dispositions 187, 193, 203

266 267
GENERAL INDEX GENERAL INDEX

element' (member) - knowledge thereof: - individual 171-173 feature


131, 133, 135, 137, 221, 243 see knowledge of essence - intentional 253-255; - extrinsic vs. intrinsic 31
elemental transformation 59-71 - lack thereof 63-64 et e. objective - necessary 101; cf: trait; property'
- low-level 60 - knowledge thereof: - of prime matter 68-69
ellipse 105-108 see knowledge of existence
- modal construal of 75, 104, 113-114, 150 - real of the world 146, 148
eminence 79 - of a quality 200-202, 206 - objective (in the intellect) 30; - vs. trait 249
empirical - part thereof: see part of essence et e. intentional; intentional object, fermion 16-17, 21
- concept 217 - real (vs. nominal) 171-173 being, entity
fiction 30, 36-37, 210
- feature 249 - robust construal of 73, 104-110, 114, 150 - of God 144, 163, 165, 170-171, 177, 205
- object, individual - vs. existence 145-165, 169-182, 219 - of natural classes 13-16 figure (geometrical)
135-139, 233, 247-249, 255 - - real distinction thereof: see distinc- - of prime matter 65 105-106, 108, 200, 213-214
- world 123, 233 tion real of essence and existence - of universals 46-47 finality: see causality final
empiricism 13, 209-210, 185, 216-217 essential - real 95, 100, 119, (171), 188, 253, 255 form
end' (goal) 145, 155-158, (162), 221; - dependence: see dependence essential - specific vs. individual 170-171 - abstracted 137
cf. cause final - order: see order essential existential inertia 143-145, 159-165 - accidental: see accidental form
end' (extremity) 125 essentialism existential quantifier: - in the mind 156
- analytic 114 see quantification, quantifier - inherent, Aristotelian
Enlightenment 224, 239, 240 43-44, 55, 67, 79, 85-86, 93-98, 242, 200
- Aristotelian experience
ens in se vs. ens in alio 123-124, 136-139 - logical: see logical form
60, 62-64, 67, 71, 105, 108, 113-114 146, 148, 150, 152, 154, 157, 160, 216
ens rationis 25, 29-30 see being of reason - constituent 52-54 - material 152, 172
- our as agents, deliberators
entelechy 221,189-190 - mereological 52 - particular
186, 188, 190-193
entity - real or serious 73 99, 172, 235-236, 238-239, 241-242
explanation - Platonic 153-154, 232, 236; cf. eicle
- abstract: - strong vs. weak 114 - and the principle of sufficient reason 197 - qualitative 200, 214
see abstract object, thing, entity - vs. anti-essentialism 113-116, 120 - end-driven 221
- and essence 108-110 - separate 236, 232, 236
Eucharist 73, 78, 81-84, 87 - of events, behaviour 187, 192, 199-200
- broadest meaning of 26 - substantial 98, 147, 149, 154, 161, 172, 202
event 49, (128), 146-147, 150, 185, 187-189, - of change and variety 117 - universal 55, 98-99, 235-239, 241-242
- complete vs. incomplete 93-94 192, 212 - of persistence 162-164
- concrete: - vs. feature 94
- quantum level 163 - of truth 244-245 - vs. matter 88, 93-95, 98, 103, 145,
see concrete object, thing, entity event causality: see causality event - ontological, of character 44, 47, 53
- hypostatic 79 150-152, 158-160, 162-165, 172, 202;
vs. agent - ultimate 153, 165 cf hylomorphism
- characterising vs. characterisable; extension 22, 130, 136, 153, 240-241, 243
instantiated vs. instantiating 97-98 exemplification 47, 98-103, 117-119; formal content 178
- predicative 65 cf: instantiation extrinsic freedom 210, 215, 220, 203, 206
- saturated vs. unsaturated 243 existence: et being - being: see being extrinsic
- property, feature, relation 31, 37, 101, function biological 155
epistemology 11, 108, 110, 127 - act of 147-149, (151), 157-158, 160,
106, 119; cf. extrinsic denomination function' (mathematical etc.) 77, 242-245
172-175; cf essence vs. existence
error 36 - teleology 154, (156) function' (role, office) 137-138
- actual: see actual existence
essence 60-64, 73-88, 94, 104-110, 252 - and dependence: - thinkability 31 future 33, 36, 178, 190, 210
- and essential order 79; see dependence existential fact 28, (35), 50, 245; cf. state of affair generating principle 105-106
cf order essential - and its presuppositions 145-149 - axiological vs. natural 231
- and universals 120 generation
- and truthmaking 74-77 - brute 163 - and corruption 151-152, 159;
- divine 177; cf. act pure - as a predicate (32), (74), 253 - negative 33-36, (255)
- includes transcendental relations 201
cf existence gained or lost
- continued, persistent 81-82, 143-144, - objective 231 - of universals 118
- individual vs. specific 150, 159, 161-163, 165 - physical 212
172-173, 180, 252-253 - of elements 60-64
- gained or lost 54, 96, 148-151, 159, 161; - prephilosophical 47
- its built-in finality 155, 157 generic (properties etc.) 62, 120, 180
cf change; generation and corruption

268 1 269
GENERAL INDEX GENERAL INDEX

genus 13, 97, 62, 180, 193 - theory of predication intellectus essentiae 169-171 - private 5
- of particular numbers 125-126 244, 247-248, 251, 253-255 intention' (purpose, directedness) law
God 18, (29), 143-157, 163-164, 170-171, - through change 54, 61, 107-108, 117, 200; 155-156; cf intentionality' - natural, of nature
203, 205, 220-221, 224. cf persistence intention' (notion) 176 101, 164-165, 198, 203, 205-206, 218, 220
good 32, 153-15 4, 220, 220, 224, 234 - vs. similarity 214 - second 27, 35 - of (Newtonian) mechanics 145, 164, 220
- weak vs. strong 250-251, 253-255 intentional - of excluded middle 35
harmony 220-224
identity dependence: - act 35 - of identity 213
Humanism 239 see dependence identity - distinction: see distinction intentional - of inertia 145, 164
hylomorphism 53, 73, 87-89, 93-97, 99, implication material 197 - existence 253-255 - of thermodynamics 221, 223-224
103, 160-161; cf. form; matter; - linguistic context 173-174, 176 - Snellius' 220
combination of matter and form import
- modal 74, (82) - object, being, entity 29-30, 33-35; linguistic
- Aristotelian 93, 147, 160 cf being of reason - expression 176
- ontological 32, 230
hyper-essentialism 116 intentionality' (mind-dependence) - level etc. mere 130, 133
impossibility
hypostatisation 95, 103 29-31, 33, 36, 116, 188-189, 205 30, 33-37, 253 - product, item 118, 230
change 53-54, 116-119, 145, 148, 159, intentionality' (mental directedness) - relation 97
in-being, being in 97, (236)-237, 240-241;
188-192, 198-199; cf existence gained or cf inherence 187, 192; cf intention' location in space (and time) 48-50, 118
lost; generation and corruption ipsum esse subsistens, pure existence logic 11, 36, 113, 121, 129-130, 211-218
incapability
- accidental 95, 116-119 148, 153 see act pure; God - (first-order) predicate 173, 230
- elemental 59, 61, 68-69 Incarnation 78
item (22), 26-27, 31-33, 37 - formal 121
- of matter 94-95 incoherence 48, 53, 60, 69, 100, 109, 163, - Fregean 115, 120-121
- substantial (60) 165; cf: self-contradiction kat' allo vs. kath' hauto 43-44
- modal 5
character of familiar particulars individual kind 43, 95, 98-99, 101-109, 211, 213 - Transparent Intensional:
43-48, 51, 55 - bare (115); et particualr bare - natural 101, 119-120 see Transparent Intensional Logic
characterisation - essence: - substantial 65-67, 98, 120-121;
et substance secondary logical
32, 67-69, 71, 77, 97-103, 106, 129, 249, 255 see essence individual vs. specific - analysis: see analysis of language
Characterisation Principle 35 - existence: see existence individual knowledge: cf cognition - commensurability 182
- office, role 115 - a priori vs. a posteriori: - form 100, 121, 230, 240
Cheshire Cat's grin 101 - propertied 55 see a priori vs. a posteriori - functor 229-230
chimera 35; cf being impossible - substance: see substance primary, - by acquaintance 110 - grammar 96
Christ 78, 81 individual, particular - clear and distinct 176-177, 180 - independence 176, 178
idea' (Platonic, exemplar) 135, 156-157; - thing, object, entity 22, 26, 43, 55, 98-99, - divine 220 - modality: see modality logical
cf form Platonic, eide 114-118, 137-138, 248-255; cf. particular - empirical vs. rational 215-216 - necessity: see necessity logical
idea' (in mind) 128, 156-157 - vs. universal: - evening vs. morning 209-210 - omniscience 180
see universal vs. individual, particular - in general 211, 229 - positivism 5, 213
idealism 136 - mathematical 213-218
individuality 252-253 - possibility: see possibility logical
identity - of essence, quidditative
- i.e. whatness inertia 145, 164-165; cf existential inertia - rationalisation 243-244
108, 110, 172-181, 211
77, 88, 95, 101-103, 106, 116, 186, 202 inherence 50, 81-85, (124), 137; - of existence 172-175, 177-181 manifestation of a tendency or
- is unity 131 et in-being; characterisation - of metaphysical modality 108, 110 disposition 150, 155, 185, 188, 191,
- numerical 62-64, 199-200 - actual vs. aptitudinal 81-86 - of potencies or dispositions 188, 198-199 196-200, 202-203, 205-206.
- of essence and existence 170-171, 173 instantiation 46-47, 66, 96-103, - of the world, of nature 209, 216, 230 material' (stuff) 55, 186
- of indiscernibles: see principle of the (115), (118)-119, 129-130, 138, 191; - scientific 163, 173-181, 211 material'
identity of indiscernibles cf. exemplification language - cause: see cause material
- of knowledge and being 211
- real 251, 253
- statement 134-135, 250
- Principle of:
see principle of instantiation I - formal 114
- natural 5, 114-115, 130, 134, 229, 248-251
- division 125-128, 133, 135
- form 152

270 I 271
GENERAL INDEX GENERAL INDEX

- implication 197 - of substance 84 nominalism (14), 21, 115, 216, 230, 239, 244 optimality 210, 219, 221
- object, thing 43, 50-51, 89, 107, 133, modus dicendi (per se) 114; - austere (22), 47 order
150-151, 165; cf. substance material cf predication essential non-being 23, 27-31, 33-37; - essential 78-84, 87
- part, constituent 46, 50-51, 98, 159-161 multitude 125-127, 131-134 cf being of reason; non-existence - of dependence vs. of eminence 79;
- substance: see substance material non-contradiction 204-205 cf dependence essential
natural kind: see kind natural
- vs. non-material (29), 124, 133 - of parts in the whole 125
nature' (essence) 45, 51, 79, 101, 106, 109, non-existence 22-23, 33, (35), 28-37, 76,
- whole 124; cf. division material
150, 159, 163, 172-173, 176; cf. essence 150; cf non-being overtone 221-223
materialism 46, 48 para-being 27-28
- common 34, 45, 254 number 17-18, 26, 76-77, 123-139, 222-223
mathematics 139, 211-222, 243 - human in Christ 78, 81, 83 - absolute vs. concrete 126-130; part: cf constituent; component
matter 96-99 nature' (non-artificial reality) ef. multitude - commonsense 44, 50-52
- prime 186, 192, 216-219, 221, 224; - particular 125-127 - integral 124, 187
59-71, 93, 147, 149, 152, 161, 202, (252) cf law natural, of nature - small 18 - material: see material' part, constituent
- vs. form: necessary object - metaphysical 44, 50-51, 252-255
see form vs. matter, hylomorphism - being 76-77, 145, 150-151, 153 - abstract: see abstract object - of essence 77, 80, 82, 88, 101-108, (165),
mediaeval period, doctrines: - condition: see condition necessary - actual: see actual object 175-177, 252; cf. part metaphysical
see Middle Ages - property: see property' - geometrical 106 - proper vs. improper' 50, 88, 94
mechanics; mechanism 212, 218-221 - feature 101; cf trait; property' - intentional: - proper vs. improper' 252
mental representation 178 necessity et existence objective in the intellect - substantial 51
- kooky 89 - temporal 12, 48-51
mereological - absolute 145, 150-153
- causal 195-196, 202-206 - material: see material' object, particular - vs. whole: see whole vs. part, constituent
- sum 95-96
- de re vs. de dicta: see de re vs. de dicta - mental : see object intentional participation 45, 47, 153-154, 233,
- theory of predication 234-242
- dispositional 195, 197-198, 203; - of thought: see object intentional 254-255
mereology 21, 44-45, 51-52 - ordinary : see particular familiar
meta-ontology 24 cf. necessity causal particular 13, (22), 94, 97-98, 115-120, 126,
- from reason vs. from the world 209-210 - set theoretical 129-131, 172, 216, 238-241, 245, 251, 253;
metaphysics - Humean account 203, 209-210 - vs. concept: see concept vs. object et individual
5-6, 11, 21, 36, 47, 89, 104, 115, 214, 218 - hypothetical 206 , 211, 212, 218 objective' (vs. object) 27-28 - bare or thin 54, 56, 114-116, 120
- analytical 5-6, 26, 32, 37, 73 - Leibniz's account objective' (vs. subjective) 30; - concrete (22), 48
- Aristotelian 25, 73, 104, 172 210-220, 224, 241-(242) cf intentional object, being, entity; - familiar 43-49, 52-55
- descriptive 130 - logical 75, (82), 115-116, 150, 202 concept objective - form: see form particular
- scholastic 25, 37, 73, 104, 161 - mathematical 217 - material 50, 151
Ockham's Razor 158, 164, 203
- Thomistic 163-166 - metaphysical 75, (82), 101-107, 110, 150; - number: see number particular
ontological
Middle Ages see de re vs. de dicto - sensible 44, 47
- commitment (32), 37, 54, 100
5, (25), 113, 230, 234, 237-239, (243) - moral 211 - substance: see substance primary,
- strategy:
mind 215, 239-240, 242 - of itself vs. from another thing see ontology constituent vs. relational individual, particular
mind-affinity 239-240, 243 151-152, 159 - vs. universal:
- physical 75 Ontological Square 97-99 see universal vs. individual, particular
mind-dependence: see intentionality' ontology 11-24; cf. metaphysics
- psychological 203 passive vs. active potency, power,
modality 5, 21, 54, 75-76, 78, 86-88, 102- - vs. possibility or contingency 103-104, - Aristotelian 23, 64, 81, 93, 97-98, 103, capability: see active vs. passive
104, 116, 119 ; cf truth' modal; necessity, 120, 123, 187-193, 238-239
110, 150, 209-210, 213, 215; cf modality potency, power, capability
contingency, possibility, potentiality - constituent vs. relational
- de re vs. de dicto: see de re vs. de dicta negation' (non-entity) 36, 115 past 33, 47, 178, 209
11, 43-54, 67, 70-71, 99-103, 120
- logical 189 negation' (logical constant) - four-category 97-103 per se vs. per accidens
- metaphysical 108, 110 173, 175, 204-205 - Meinongian 22-24, 34-35 - causal series 81, 146-147, 149, 152, 158
mode 77, 88, 99-102 negation of material division 125 - Quinean 11-13, 19 - unity 28
- of being 160 - scholastic (30), 33, 37, 123, 187, 193 perception 28, 36, 103, 110, 127, 137

272 273
GENERAL INDEX GENERAL INDEX

persistence - passive 82, 85-86, 188; cf: active vs. pas- principle
53-54, 94, 150-151, 159-162, 165 sive potency, power, capability - "spite"/"moderation" 224 - positive singular 248-249, 254-255
- conditions 107-108 - pure 60-61, 65, 147, 151-152, 161; - of conservation of mass-energy 164 - predicative 247-249, 254-255
- of prime matter 59-66, 70-71, 151 cf. matter prime - of constituent identity 53, 55 proton 96-97
person 49, 79, 186-187, 192 - rational vs. natural or physical 191, 203 - of contradiction 213, 224 pure act: see act pure; God
- receptive 201-202 - of identity of indiscernibles 55 quality 59, 94, 189-190, 198-203, 206, 214
petitio principii 179
- subjective 187, 191 - of independence of so-being from being 35
phenomenalism 53 - vs. act: see actuality vs. potentiality - of instantiation 46-47, 66, (118) quantification, quantifier
phenomenon 164, 172, 192; - of least action 221 12, (13)-(14), (32), 170-171
potency, potentiality 33, 60-61,
cf. world phenomenal 64-65, 145-147, 149, 185-193, 195, 198, - of sufficient reason quantity 50, 124-128, 131-132, 136,
phoenix 170-171 201-205; cf potency; possibility; power; 197-198, 200, 212, 220, 224 189-190, 213-214, 218
physics (modern) 97, 218 disposition; capability private language 5 - continuous 125
- vs. act, actuality: - discrete 125, 128, 131
place: see location in space (and time) privation 27, 30, 36, (118), 189
see actuality vs. potentiality al 34, (35)
Platonism 46, 124, 135-137, 147, 153-156, probability 154-156, 210, 220, 223-224
220, 232, 234, 237, 239-240 power' (potency) 36, 163, 186-193, 195, real
proper name 130, 133, 173, 248-250 - being, thing, object
198-205; cf. disposition; potency;
Porphyrian Tree 126, 180 property monism 199-200 30-36, 100, 118, (171), 187, 255
capability causal
positivism 5, 146, 213 - active 163-(165); cf. active vs. passive property' (wide sense) 43, 46-55, 86, - capability, disposition, possibility, power
possibility 27, 29, 36, 54, 187-193, 195, potency, power, capability; capability 115-116, 119-120, 131-139, 187-190, 193, 187-188, 119, 190-193, 205
204-206, 209-215, 219-220; cf-. potency; causal; disposition 203, 245, 251, 253-254; cf. feature - definition: see definition real, quiddita-
potentiality; power; disposition; - causal: see causal power - causal (155) see disposition; power; tive vs. verbal, nominal
contingency; modality - dormitive 163 capability causal; active vs. passive - difference, change 98, 117-119, 233
- logical 150, 193, 195, 188, 195 - mental 36 potency, power, capability - distinction: see distinction real
- mere 29-30, 33, 146, 149, 178, 187-190, 193 power2 social 230-232 - contingent vs. necessary 47, 54, 62, - division among things 13-17
- metaphysical 83, 87, 104, 107, 110, 150 113-115; see property2 - essence: see essence real (vs. nominal)
predicate - essential vs. non-essential, accidental 54, - existence: see existence real
- of non-existence 150
- elementary 254
- ontological 195, 205 62, 64, 68, (70), 104, 106, 108, 114-115, 199 - identity: see identity real
- essential 251 - extrinsic: see extrinsic property, - property: see property' real, irreducible
- real: see real capability, disposition,
possibility, power - existential (32), (74), 253 feature, relation - world: see world actual, this, real
- grammatical (250) - generic: see generic (properties etc.)
- synchronous 119 realism (15), 185-187, 191, 193, 210-211
- higher-order 35 - material vs. non-material 128
- vs. impossibility 29, 33-34, 188-189 reason' (ground)
- low-level 12
- vs. necessity: - qualitative 198-199, 202, 214 - ontological 198
see necessity vs. possibility, contingency - ontological 234 - real, irreducible 185-188
- universal 237; cf. universal - sufficient 197-200, 212, 220, 224
possible - relational: see relational properties,
- vs. subject: see subject vs. predicate attributes, modes reason2 (faculty), reasoning
- being, entity 209, 211-218, 224
27, 29-30, 33-(37), 188, 211, 219 predication 251 - repeatable vs. nonrepeatable 53, 55
- accidental 77, 86-88, 248-(249) - trivial vs. non-trivial 32, 114-116 reductionism 115, (155), 185, 215
- world 7, 20-21, 74, 76, 101-104, 108, 150,
187, 189-190, 193, 202-206, (242)
- and prime matter 65-71 property2 (flowing from essence) reference
- essential 114, 248-249 94-95, 106, 114-115; cf. trait - identifying 26
potency - identity theory thereof:
proposition 110, 249, 255; - oblique vs. explicit 174
- active 188 see identity theory of predication et statement; sentence; truthbearer - same 160
- causal: see causal power, potency, - relational vs. non-relational 231, 234,
disposition; potency active, passive - atomic vs. molecular 247 - theory thereof 108-109
242-245 - to accidents or modes vs. to their bearer
- identical with accident 201-202 - false 255
- various analyses thereof 229-245, 68, 88, 190
- knowledge thereof 188, 198-199 247-255
- logical 213, 216
- logical 188 - negative 255 - to aggregates 130-133
primitive notion (76), 192 - particular 171 - to classes (13)-(15)
- objective 188

274 275
GENERAL INDEX GENERAL INDEX

regress (infinite) - properties, attributes, modes scholasticism 6, 73, 78, 81, 84, 104, 161, - of predication 65-71, 97
- causal etc. 146, 149, 152, 165 99-100, 137, 200 186-188, 191, 193, 200-201, 253 - of properties, accidents 53, 65-67, 81,
- in explanations of characterisation or - system 137, 139 - second (Renaissance or Baroque) 84-88, 97, 113-116, 119-120
exemplification 44-45, 99-100, 119 - theory of space 15 6, 25-37, 248 - ontological 119, 234
- of essences 108 - truth 100 signum - vs. predicate 66-67, 71, 126-135,
relation, relationship relativism 209-211, 229 - identitatis 247 211-212, 240-241, 247-254; cf. relation
22, 26, 43-45, 49, 137, 200-201, 214, 245 Renaissance 6, 25, (28), 239 - quantitatis, particulare 171 of subject and predicate; predication
- across the categories 99-103; representation mental: singleton 77, 104 subjectivism 5
cf. r. transcendental see mental representation social conventionalism 231 subjectivity 12-13, 19-20
- dynamical 218; Russell's paradox 136 something 31 substance
cf dynamical vs. mathematical - its constitution 50, 93-96, 103, 252
- harmonic 222-223 scepticism sophists 230-231
67-(70), 109, 209-211, 216-217, 236 Sosein 22-23 - its generation and corruption (64), 81, 96
- industrial 137-139 - material 124-125, 151-152, 159-162, 164;
- internal vs. external 100-102 Scotism 6, (252) soul (33), 86, 151-152, (161), 214-216 cf. material' object
- linguistic, syntactical 97, 213 second intention: see intention' second species - natural 146-149
- mathematical 214, 218 Sein: cf being; existence - biological 16, 178, 218 - of a thing 50, 172, 248, 252
- of accessibility: self-contradiction - of metaphysical dependence or necessity - primary, individual, particular
see accessibility of possible worlds 31, 35; cf-. contradiction; incoherence 76-77, 87 22, 83, 93-95, 97-99, 103, 120, 129-130,
- of composition 51-53; cf. composition - of quantity 124-126
self-evidence 177 152, 159, 189-190, 236, 249
- of dependency: see dependence - vs. genus 13, 62, 97, 126, 131-132, (176) - secondary, universal 97-98, 236-237;
- of exemplification: see exemplification self-identity (32), 114
state concrete vs. abstract 138, 253-255 et kind substantial
- of identity: see identity self-predication 232
state of affairs - separated 46
- of more and fewer 138-139 semantics 36-37, 115, 213, 243, 247 - spiritual 124
27-(28), 50, 87, 192, 197, 242, 245; cf. fact
- of parts in a whole 125 - Fregean 115, 120 - vs. accident 29, 78, 81-88, 94-95,
- of reason 27, 30, 36 statement: cf. proposition; sentence
sense' (meaning) 28, 109, 128, 133, 249 - axiological 231 119-120, 123-124, 139, 190, 202
- of subject and predicate 66, 212, 240; - vs. aggregate of substances 127-130
et predication; subject vs. predicate sense2 (cognitive faculty) - conditional 185; cf sentence conditional
36, 110, 137, 150, 187, 198 - existential 21 - vs. attribute 18, 21, 97
- of substance and accident 81, 83, 85-86; - vs. event or state of affairs 146-147, 242
cf. inherence; in-being sentence 28, 204-205 - justification thereof 197
- conditional 196-202, 206 - modal 104 - vs. feature and trait 248-249
- of truthmaking: see truthmaking - vs. mode 97
- ordering 79, 81; cf. order essential - positive predicative 247, 250 - number 126-135
- vocative vs. affirmative 249-250 - senseless 130, 133 - vs. potency 191, 201-202
- secundum dici 201
- vs. property 94-95, 193
- social 37 series causal: see causal series - simple predicative
229-231, 234, 240-245 - vs. relation 22
- spatial, geometrical 100, 213 set 12-14,21,37,51-52,77,95,104,108,
- subclass 16, (19) - singular 129-132 substance-kind: see kind substantial
127-129,136,243-244
- to act or effect 188, 192, 201; - of possible worlds 21 - subject-predicate 132, 134 substratum 54, 59-71
et causality; act vs. potency; power; - of properties 104, 108 strategy ontological (constitutive or substratum theory 54-55
capability, capacity causal; disposition set theory 136, (217) relational): see ontology constitutive subsumption 240-241
- transcendental 201-202 vs. relational super-category 26-28, 31, 37
set-theoretical
relational - composition 52 subclass 15-16, 18-19
super-transcendentals 31-32
- ontology, strategy: see ontology - object 135-136 subject
constituent vs. relational supposition 178
- theory of predication 243-244 - absolute (253)-255
- predication: see predication relational - of change, transformation synthesis 216
shape 106, 199-200
vs. non relational 67-68,116-119 tautology 164, 212-213

276 277
GENERAL INDEX GENERAL INDEX
teleology 212, 219, 221; cf. causality final truth' (trueness) universal 22, 31, 34, 37, 46-47, 66-67, Word (divine person) 78, 81
- Aristotelian 154-157 - adequacy theory thereof 254-255 77, 97-99, 101, 117-120, 129-131, 216, world
temporality 36, 48, 119, 219 - its grounding 74-78, 84, 87-88, 100, 210, 236-245, 253-255 - actual, this, real 21, (29), 101, 126, 150,
tendency 155, (162), 186;
230-231; cf. truthmaking - class: see class universal 187-188, 190, 203, 205, 219
cf finality; teleology; disposition - its nature 210-211, 230-243, 254-255 - form: see form universal - empirical 123, 233
- to cease or continue to exist 150-151, - transcendental 153 - substance: see substance secondary, - its continuance 143-146, 148, 155-156,
159, 161-163; cf: existential inertia - vs. fiction 210 universal 164-165
truth' (something true) 74-75 - term 127, 129 - its furniture 185
test of a disposition
- contingent vs. necessary - vs. individual, particular - knowledge thereof 209, 215, 217
196-198, 200, 202-20 4, 206
100-102, 106-107, 113, 212, 219, 241 34, 94, 97, 117-120, 130, 216, 253 - material 160-161
theism 48, 163, 205 - essential 102, 106-107, 110, 219 Universal Characteristic 213, (217) - microscopic vs. macroscopic 186, 199
theory of predication - historical 241 universality 254 - most perfect 220
(84), 229-245, 247-255 - Leibniz's classification thereof 211 - natural 156-157, 163-164, 191
- Aristotle's 235-236, 240, 243 ununoctium 179-180
- logical vs. mathematical 211-216 - of particulars 116-119
- fact-referring 245 - modal 110 way of givenness 132
- of things 28-29, 169, 178
- Frege's 242-243, 245 - negative 33 whole - phenomenal 211, 218-221
- identity 244, 247-248, 251, 253-255 - of coincidence 107-108 - arbitrary 28 - physical 202, 221
- Leibniz's 240-242, (244) - of exemplification 102 - composite vs. its part, constituent - possible: see possible world
- minimal Aristotelian 244 - of fact vs. of reason 211-212, 214, 218 32, 44-45, 50-54, 67, 71, 125, 129-130, 147 - theistic vs. atheistic 205
- Plato's 232-234 - original vs. derived 212 - essence 106-107
- pre-Fregean 234, 241 - phenomenal 218 - material vs. spiritual 124
- quasi-mereological 235-238, 240-241 - physical, temporal vs. eternal, - quantitative 125
- redundancy 244 metaphysical 219
- set-theoretical 243-244 - relational 100
- socially-conventionalist 231 truth conditions 254
- Thomistic 247-248
- truthmaking (84) truth-explanation 244-245
thermodynamics 220-224 truth-value 36, 198, 200, 255
thinkability, conceivability 31, 150 truthbearer 28
truthmaker, truthmaking 28, 73-78, 81,
Third Realm 135, 156
83, 84-88, 100, 102, 197-198, 230, 249
Third-Man-Argument 233
truthmaker necessiatrianism 74
Thomism 6, (30), 201, 145-148, 150, 158,
163-166, (171), 175, 247-249, 254 units
- analytical 6 - class 15
- charge 101
thought 33, 36, 103, 109
unit' (of a multitude or number)
time (13), 54, 95, 107, 110, 117, 118-119, 123, 125-129, 132-135
135; cf temporality; past; future - synonymous to individual etc. 26
trait 249, 251-252; cf property' unity
transcendentals 32, 153-154 - divine 153
Transparent Intensional Logic (TIL) - hypostatic 78
114-116 - internal of things 15-17, 28
trope 46-47, 49, 53-55, 87, 99, 119-120; - per se vs. per accidens 28
cf accident - transcendental 153-154
- vs. number 128-133

278 279
INDEX OF PERSONS

The index does not comprise the abstracts and the descriptions of individual articles in the
Preface. Persons not discussed but merely cited in footnotes and bibliography are usually omitted,
as well as the authors of the articles themselves (unless significantly mentioned by someone else)
and persons mentioned merely in titles of written works. References to occurences in footnotes are in
parentheses, bold numbers imply substantial discussion in the text. "GI:" refers to the General Index.

Adams, Marilyn McCord (81), 86 - on being 15


Adler, Mortimer 143, 158-164 - on causality 191-192, 207
Aquinas, Thomas - on change 116, 192
- his "Five Ways" 143-158 - on essence 105, 108
- his legacy 6, 248; see also GI: Thomism - on essential order 79
- criticised by Buridan - on kat' allo vs. kath' hauto 43-44
173-176, 178, 181-182 - on kinds of composition 50-51
- on absolute nature 34 - on knowledge 174-175
- on beings of reason 32 - on matter and form 43, 53, 93, 97, 172
- on change 145-147, 159 - on number 123-124, 126-127, 133
- on divine conservation 143-166 - on ontology and metaphysics
- on essence 150, 169, 171, 175-182 23, 25, 60, 97-98, 104
- on existence - - relational vs. constituent 43-47
148,159-162, 169-173, 177-179, 182 - on predication
- on inherence 85-86 67-68, 97, 230, 234-237, 240, 243
- on matter and form - on prime matter 59-71
73, 87-88, 97, 151, 159-160, 172, 200 - on quality 201
- on mental representation 178 - on rational potencies 191, 203
- on metaphysical composition - on substance and accident
160-162, 165 (50), 97, 116, 123, 190
- on modalities 150-153, 159, 188-189, 204 - on teleology 155-156, 221
- on number 123-129, 133-134 - on truthmaking 84
- on participation 153-154 - on universals 46, 67, 97, 236-237
- on potency and act 146-147 Armstrong, David M. 45-46, 200
- on predication 128, 237-238, 247 Augustine 143
- on substance and accident Babenstuber, Ludwig 248
85-86, 146, 190
Beaudoin, ohn 143-144, 162-165
- on teleology 155-156
- on transcendentals 153 Benacerraf, Paul Joseph Salomon 136
- on truthmaking 84-88 Bergmann, Gustav 11, 45-46, (115)
Aristotle Berkeley, George 45, 53, 210
- on abstraction (217) Bird, Alexander 185
- on act and potency 189-191, 207 Bradley, Francis Herbert 99

281
i
INDEX OF PERSONS INDEX OF PERSONS
Braine, David 164-165 Kant, Immanuel 210, 213, 215-218 - on mathematics and numbers Scotus, ohn Duns 78-88
Bruno, Giordano 214 Kenny, Anthony 169-173 123-124, 215-217 Shields, Christopher 144
Buridan, John (36), 169, 173-182 Kestin, Joseph 224 - on participation 154
Shoemaker, Sidney 198, 202-203
- on predication 230, 232-234, 240, 243
Butler, Judith (231) Kistler, Max 200 Snellius, Willebrord 220
- paradigm of relational ontology 43, 46
Cajetanus, Thomas de Vio (171), 248 Kripke, Saul 5, (133), 249 Socrates 232
Plotinus 239-240
Cantor, Georg (217) Kvanvig, Jonathan (144), (163)-165 - in examples
Poinsot, Joao
Carnap, Rudolf 197-198, 204 Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm 18, 76-77, 82, 85-88, 104, 115-116,
(Ioannes a Sancto Thoma) 248
Cartwright, Nancy 186 209-224, 230, 240-24 2, (244) 137-138, 171, 220, 235, 239-241, 248, 254
Porphyry see GI: Porphyrian Tree
Cassirer, Ernst (217) Lewis, David Kellogg 51 Speusippus 46
Prigogine, Ilya 224
Castaileda, Hector 45, (55) Lewis, Frank (62) Spinoza, Baruch 105-106
Prior, Arthur Norman 28
Chisholm, Roderick 45 Locke, John 13-14, 45, 98, 103, 105 Strawson, Peter Frederick 26, 45, 49-50
Protagoras 210, 231
Cmorej, Pavel (116) Loux, Michael 60, 68, 120 Suarez, Francisco 28, 30-31, 192
Pythagoras 116-117, 123
Cohen, Sheldon (70) Lowe, E. J. (48), 73, 75-77, 80, 87, (117), (127) Thompson, Ian J. 199
Quine, Willard Van Orman
Cross, Richard (83), 85, Lullus, Raymundus 214 Tich3i, Pavel 114
5, 11-13, 32, 34, 47, 113, (198)
Dedekind, Julius Wilhelm Richard (217) Mally, Ernst 35 Voltaire 220
Robinson, H. M. 61
Dvaik, Petr 204 Martin, Charles B. 196, 201 Williams, C. J. F. 59
Rundle, Bede 162
Einstein, Albert 12 Matthews, Gareth 89 Wittgenstein, Ludwig 28, 158, 164-165, 230
Russell, Bertrand
Ellis, Brian 185 Maupertuis, Pierre-Louis Moreau de 220 26, 34, 43, 45, 135-136, 217 Wolff, Christian 213
Euler, Leonhard 220 Maxwell, James Clerk 221 Scaltsas, Theodore (62) Wolterstorff, Nicholas 44-45, 47, (99), 120
Fermat, Pierre de 220 McCann, Hugh (144), (163)-165 Schrecker, Paul 219 Zermelo, Ernst 136
Ficino, Marsilio 240 Mclnerny, D. Q. 160, (161)
Findlay, John N. 34 Meinong, Alexius
Fine, Kit 75, 104 (15), 22-24, (27)-(28), (33)-35
Fox, John 84 Mirandola, Pico della 240
Frege, Gottlob Molnar, George 185, 199-201
32, 115, 120-121, 124, 126, 128, 131-136 Monty Python 161
Gilson, Etienne 159 Mumford, Stephen 185, 199
Gorgias 109 Neumann, John von 136
Gorman Michael 80 Newton, Isaac 145, 164, 218-220
Gredt, Josephus 248 Ockham, William see GI: Ockham's Razor
Grice, Paul 49-50 Paley, William 154, 156-157
Heidegger, Martin 220 Parmenides 33, 233
Helmholtz, Hermann von 221 Pasnau, Robert 144
Heraclitus 209 Paul, Laurie 45
Hobbes, Thomas 13 Plantinga, Alvin 45, (62)
Hume, David 135, 187, 191, 198, 203, Plato see also GI: Platonism
209-210, 213, 216-217 - compared to Leibniz 211-220, 224
Husserl, Edmund 238 - his Divided Line 211-212
- on ideas 135,153-154,236,239
Inwagen, Peter van 49

282 283

Anda mungkin juga menyukai