Anda di halaman 1dari 16

Public Choice Theory and Natural Resources: Methodological Explication and Critique

Author(s): Mark Sproule-Jones


Source: The American Political Science Review, Vol. 76, No. 4 (Dec., 1982), pp. 790-804
Published by: American Political Science Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1962971
Accessed: 03/12/2010 09:46

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=apsa.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

American Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
The American Political Science Review.

http://www.jstor.org
Public Choice Theory and Natural Resources:
Methodological Explication and Critique
MARKSPROULE-JONES
McMaster University

The article is a methodological examination of public choice analysis, with particular reference to
the currently topical policy field of natural resources. It is also a methodological critique of public
choice analysis on logical, epistemological, and normative grounds. Its purpose is to make scholars of
natural resources management aware of the substantive and methodological features of the public
choice approach to the field, and to make public choice scholars and philosophers of science aware of
the methodological grounds of the approach.
The so-called hard core of concepts of public choice are first described in relation to the natural
resource policy field, and the selection of these hard core concepts, as well as their distinguishing
features from political science, economics, and public administration, are justified. The argument is
advanced that the hard core is interrelated by the methodological criterion of logical consistency-one
interpretation of the notion of rationality-and the criterion accounts for the impetus behind the
growth of the paradigm. It is also argued that the paradigm is buttressed and protected from rival ap-
proaches at an epistemological level, and it is shown that a variety of epistemologies have been linked
to the approach. Finally, I argue that the congruence of public choice with this variety of epistemolo-
gies makes many of the criticisms about the normative implications of the approach inaccurate and
misleading.

The management of natural resources is a counterpart, a specialized academic journal


major item on the agenda of most governments, (Public Choice), and an increasing number of
and the scarcity of particular natural resources, textbooks attempting to codify its findings and
such as energy-producing resources, is a matter of pointing the way to new endeavors.' But this
concern to citizens in many communities. It is a growth and maturation of an academic paradigm
policy arena, however, where knowledge is often has taken place with little or no self-conscious
conflicting and complex. methodological framework of self analysis. Fun-
There is a stream of theory and scholarship that damental criticisms of the methodological prem-
embraces the more traditional fields of eco- ises of social sciences provided by philosophers of
nomics, political science, and public administra- science have been largely ignored by public choice
tion, and that offers the prospect of coherent and analysts and practitioners.2 Particularly important
systematic knowledge about natural resource is the criticism that the empirical-analytical dis-
management. This is public choice analysis, which tinction characterizing modern social science leads
is now a major interest of social scientists in North to a narrow concern with "technical rationality"
America and Europe. One objective of this article and a narrow set of misguided normative postures
is to explicate the major features of a public (e.g., Bernstein 1975; Giddens 1976; and the so-
choice analysis of natural resource management. called Frankfurt School). This article attempts to
A second objective is to examine critically answer such criticism in the context of public
public choice analysis itself. The paradigm has choice and also attempts to fill the obvious gap in
grown in its number of practitioners, its theo- methodological awareness about the public choice
retical sophistication, and its policy applications. paradigm. It is a methodological explication of
It is institutionalized in the manner of mature public choice analysis from within public choice,
paradigms: there is a Public Choice Society, a and a methodological critique of the analysis from
European Society to match its original American outside the paradigm.

I wish to acknowledge the helpful comments of 'These include Bish (1971), Bish and Ostrom (1973),
Richard L. Bish, James C. McDavid, Patricia L. Riker and Ordeshook (1973), Sproule-Jones (1975),
Richards,WilliamC. Mitchell,DonaldS. Schwerinand Plott (1976), Schmid (1978), Frolich and Oppenheimer
(1978), Mueller (1979), Abrams (1980).
DouglasE. Williamson an earlierdraft. The comments
of the anonymousrefereesof thisjournalwereusefulin 2Two exceptions are McDavid (1976) and Buchanan
revision. (1959).

790
1982 PublicChoiceTheoryand NaturalResources 791
The organization corresponds to these two ob- heuristic, is composed of the guidelines, sugges-
jectives. Findings and implications of public tions, and supplementary hypotheses that develop
choice analysis for natural resource management the empirical and analytical range of the research
are used throughout to illustrate the explication. program. The positive heuristic is subject to em-
In this regard, this article differs considerably pirical verification, unlike the negative heuristic.
from the major texts and overviews of public Proponents of the research program are not pre-
choice, which tend to offer only passing allusions pared to use core concepts and hypotheses to ex-
to the rich policy field of natural resources. The plain away evidence disconfirming the positive
concern with this policy area also means that cer- heuristic (Lakatos 1974).
tain features of public choice analysis which are Lakatos developed the notions of a negative
often given only limited attention are highlighted and a positive heuristic in research programs in
in more detail. For example, I emphasize the use the context of a still ongoing debate on the growth
of property rights as a form of institutional ar- of scientific knowledge and its problems of verifi-
rangement for natural resource management and cation and confirmation. These matters are ad-
mismanagement. dressed in subsequent sections. In this section, I
More important, the article is organized around develop a hard core of concepts and assumptions
the central methodological features of a inherent in a public choice analysis of natural
paradigm. Section 1 uses the notion of a hard core resources management; in Section 2, I attempt to
of concepts developed by Lakatos (1974) to de- justify the concepts selected for the- hard core of
scribe the crux of public choice analysis. Section 2 public choice analysis.
presents a justification of the selection of the hard
core concepts, as well as the features that dis- Hard Core Concept 1:
tinguish these concepts from those of political The Nature of the Good
science, economics, and public administration.
In Section 3 the analysis changes from an inter- Any analysis of natural resources policy, or in-
nal explication to an explication and critique from deed of any public policy, must come to terms
outside the paradigm. Attention is given to the with the technical nature of the policy in question.
principle that underlies and animates public Natural resources, the non-human endowments
choice theorizing and its applications. It is argued of the world, are found in abundance or scarcity
that logical consistency is the criterion that inter- in any one place and at any one time. Any single
relates the hard-core concepts of public choice, natural resource, be it a physical resource like ox-
and that this criterion is the impetus behind the ygen or a biological resource like a benthic in-
expansion of the paradigm. vertebrate, is therefore a constraint or an oppor-
Section 4 contains the explicit examination of tunity for human and social activities.
the epistemological foundations of public choice Natural resource goods may be valued in dif-
analysis. I argue that a variety of epistemologies ferent degrees and ways. Human and social ac-
has been offered as grounds for the interpretation tivities may exhaust a particular resource in one
of, and as evidence for, public choice proposi- part of the world, like removing the seams of a
tions. This variety enables the paradigm to main- coal mine, or they may replenish or regenerate a
tain itself against rival theories. Further, the resource, like re-aerating a lake displaying
variety of epistemologies used by public choice eutrophication. We may use a resource, like a
carries a variety of normative implications, and marine park, for enjoyment in its natural state.
hence charges about a particular normative cast to Further we may attempt to accommodate all of
public choice are false and misleading. these uses of resources-for production of inter-
mediate and end products as well as for direct
consumption and enjoyment-over time and over
Hard Core geographic space. The art of managing natural
resources is such an accommodation.
The basic concepts of a public choice analysis An analysis in depth of natural resource
of natural resource management may be con- management takes into account four central
sidered the hard core of the paradigm or research characteristics of resources:
program. The notion of a hard core is derived Type of Resource. Any portion of land, water,
from Imre Lakatos, the historian of science, who or air contains a large number of physical,
argues that scientific paradigms or research pro- chemical, and biological properties which deter-
grams consist of two parts: the first, the negative mine its type. The slowly accumulating nodules to
heuristic, comprises the basic assumptions and be found on parts of the ocean floor contain, for
auxiliary hypotheses which are accepted as a per- example, manganese, which poses different
manent hard core not subject to falsification by management problems in extraction, processing,
empirical testing. The second part, the positive and disposal of residuals than does a fugitive
792 The American Political Science Review Vol. 76
resource like salmon, which similarly has to be ex- (1965), and much of their subsequent refinement
tracted, processed, and have its organic residuals has been made by scholars associated with the
disposed of before it is consumed. public choice field.
Abundance of Resource. The physical endow- Many natural resources are goods that are
ments of the natural world are distributed uneven- public in nature, namely their use remains avail-
ly over space and time in terms of the uses to able to others after one person has used the
which they may be put. Clean water available for resource, and potential users cannot be excluded
direct human consumption is an obvious example. from using the resource. This so-called availabil-
The relative scarcity of many minerals, such as ity of a resource is determined partly by its abun-
petroleum, and the increasing scarcity of many dance and partly by technologies for exploitation.
non-renewable minerals, is a theme that domi- The exclusive character of a resource is also af-
nates current scientific and social science thinking fected by technological considerations. For exam-
(for example, The Limits to Growth debates). ple, the forests of the Pacific Northwest and of
Knowledge about the physical endowments of the British Columbia could be conceptualized in the
world is uncertain, however, and often a function early nineteenth century as public goods. They
of the commercial value of the particular resource seemed sufficiently abundant to avoid congestion
that is being exploited. There is a wide variation in for all potential users, and the use of horse and
the estimates and even methods of estimation of steam power equipment, in the absence of well-
the chemical composition of the earth's crust defined and enforced property arrangements,
(Smith and Krutilla 1979). There is comparable made entry relatively cheap. The same forests in
dispute about the levels of biological diversity, the latter half of the twentieth century are farmed,
productivity, and irreversibility that may con- with some uncertainties, within the limits of sus-
strain social activities. Uncertainty about the scar- tainable physical yield, with technologies applied
city of a resource is therefore a dimension of to increasing the biological productivity of forests
natural resource management. and to improving access to mountaintop stands.
Technologies for Exploiting and Managing a Exclusion is now feasible through the develop-
Resource. The feasibility of using any natural ment of a variety of private property and land
resource for production or direct consumption or tenure legal systems. The use of forests for saw-
both is partly a function of available technology. logs and pulp chips is no longer a public good.
The feasibility of recycling residuals or returning Owing to their technical nature, natural resources
residuals to the natural environment in a benign can be public goods if particular kinds of property
state also depends on available technology. Not arrangements are absent.
only the type of resource that may be used, but Interdependencies between natural resources
also the abundance of a resource, is determined are conceptualized as potential externalities. In
partly by available technology. For example, the previous example, the use of forests for wood
electric-sonor technology has made possible the products can affect other uses. These conse-
exploitation of fugitive marine fishing stocks, but quences can sometimes be beneficial, or yield
the technologies for managing the productivity of potentially positive externalities, as in increasing
such stocks are inadequate (Larkin 1979, Sproule- deer stocks for hunting or developing logging
Jones 1981). roads for certain forms of outdoor recreation.
Interdependencies among Resources. The use Consequences can also be potentially negative, on
of any one resource may create positive, negative, bear stocks, for example, or on soil erosion
or unknown consequences on other resources. (without appropriate silvaculture practices).
The transportation and storage of sawlogs on a These interdependencies or potential externalities
river produces leachates as well as oxygen- can become actual externalities if they are not
consuming debris, for example, and escaped saw- taken into account by the users of a resource.
logs may have consequences for navigation, In sum, public choice concepts of the public-
recreation, and other uses of the water resource. ness of goods and of externalities can be sys-
The magnitude of such physical interdependencies tematically used to analyze natural resources. The
will vary from site to site, and over time, with four critical dimensions of any resource will affect
often uncertain effects. the precise applicability of these concepts.
These are the four critical, technical dimensions
of natural resources. Public choice conceptualizes Hard Core Concept 2:
these four critical dimensions of goods in terms of Institutional Arrangements
their "publicness" and their externalities. These
concepts are borrowed from economics, although Institutional arrangements are the laws, regula-
their formalization occurred almost concurrently tions, and rules for making laws and regulations
with the publication of some of the classics in that grant opportunities and constraints for in-
public choice, such as Downs (1957) and Olson dividuals and corporate bodies in both the private
1982 PublicChoiceTheoryand NaturalResources 793
and public sectors. Public choice analysis, using tional arrangements can be devised to prevent
concepts developed initially in institutional congestion.
economics, refers to such institutional arrange- In addition, the interdependencies among
ments as property rights, duties, liabilities, and resources may create positive or negative exter-
exposures. Grand concepts in political theory, like nalities. Rivers may be used for the disposal of
"the state" or "federalism," can be systematic- some wastes (residuals of resources) that may act
ally re-analyzed as particular structures of institu- as nutrients for the enhanced biological produc-
tional arrangements. tivity of invertebrates and lower forms of biologi-
There are two fundamental attributes of pro- cal life. They may also be used for disposal of
perty rights for public choice analysis. First, such other kinds of resource residuals, like heavy
rights are solely instrumental means for improving metals and chemicals that are toxic to humans,
human welfare, and as such, they have no intrin- plants, or fish. In the former case, positive exter-
sic value. For example, there is no intrinsic value nalities may be yielded ultimately to the fisher-
in either the private market or public sector ac- man; in the latter case, a fisherman may bear only
tivities. The institutional arrangements in society negative externalities. In general, positive exter-
can be compared in order to determine which is nalities are underproduced and negative exter-
most conducive to individual welfare. Second, nalities over produced because no single class of
any structure of rights creates burdens as well as resource user has an incentive to consider the
benefits. There are no such things as costless in- benefits (or costs) of his uses on other classes of
stitutional arrangements; alternative property resource users. Institutional arrangements ranging
rights structures can be posed, devised, and im- from the extension of the legal liabilities of one
plemented. The task is to compare alternative in- user to the collective regulation of users can inter-
stitutional arrangements for managing goods nalize such externalities.
(Hard Core Concept 1) in the light of individual Public choice analysis of natural resources
preferences (Hard Core Concept 3, to be dis- evaluates alternative institutional arrangements
cussed below). This nature of institutional ar- for solving public goods, common pool, and ex-
rangements will be illustrated with regard to ternality problems in the light of the potential net
natural resource goods. benefits that can accrue over time to users of
Many natural resources have a public good resources. Three major conclusions are identified
character. A free running river may be enjoyed, in the literature. First, if a resource is sufficiently
for example, by a recreational boater who still abundant or technologies are available for en-
leaves the resource available for others to enjoy hancing and discovering more of a resource, it
and who cannot exclude other potential users may be more costly to define and enforce a new
from also enjoying the resource. Unfortunately, a property right structure (whether in private or
recreational boater in such a situation may "ride public ownership) than to ignore a public good,
free" on others who wish to remove snags and common pool, or externality problem. For exam-
submerged logs. There is consequently an incen- ple, it might be more costly to make urban land-
tive for such hazards to remain, unless means are owners liable for the runoff of waste materials in-
found to ensure that all boaters contribute to safe to an adjacent river, and to enforce such legal
navigation. Institutional arrangements can be liability, than it is to allow the negative exter-
devised to remove the free-rider incentive. License nalities to remain unsolved.
fees collected by a government or authorized Second, where a property right exists, bargain-
group of users is one example of such an arrange- ing between users of a resource that has public
ment. A bounty on logs imposed by collective good, common pool, or externality characteristics
authority is another. A publicly operated dredging will yield the greatest benefits to all users in the
industry is a third. absence of the costs (called transaction costs) of
Many natural resources are of a common pool precisely identifying and enforcing rights, duties,
character. The lack of exclusion of users from en- liabilities, and exposures, and making decisions
joying a resource creates an incentive for over use about bargaining exchanges.4 A fisherman, for
and rapid depletion of the resource that may be example, could bargain with a riparian landowner
greater than the physical or biological renewal of on a stream bank to ensure that minimum daily
the resource. The so-called tragedy of the com- flows of water remain in stream for adequate
mons, in which individual farmers overgrazed temperatures and a sustained yield of fish.
common lands because the benefits to each of
them from grazing an extra animal outweighed 4This conclusion of property rights analyses of
the costs borne by all farmers of sustained yields natural resources occurred after the publication of
of grass, is the classic example.3 Again, institu- Coase's seminal article in 1960. The study still domi-
nates subsequent property rights analyses of resource in-
3The best known explication is Hardin (1968). terdependencies.
794 The AmericanPoliticalScience Review Vol. 76
Unfortunately, the transaction costs of identi- ture the benefits of the resource before he can.
fying and enforcing property rights and of making Studies of North American Indian bands indicate,
decisions with large numbers of users of a for example, that these bands abandoned a sus-
resource are typically great. Substantial uncertain- tained yield management of beaver resources
ty always is present in estimating the abundance when they were no longer capable of excluding the
of and interdependencies between resources, and white trapper in the nineteenth century (Stroup
substantial difficulties may occur in securing and Baden 1980). Their preferences for hunting
agreement between users (itself subject to the free and trapping in a changing property right struc-
rider problem) and in limiting use of a common ture changed their behavior. Institutional arrange-
pool. As a result, collective action through ments altered the incentive structure in which they
government may yield greater net benefits. made decisions.
The third major conclusion is that collective ac- A second example of how institutional arrange-
tion itself is subject to particular kinds of costs. ments create incentives and disincentives for the
On the demand side for collective action are costs behavior of individuals in resource decision mak-
associated with signalling the extent and intensity ing is government enforcement of effluent stan-
of user preferences as well as with aggregating and dards on point sources of environmental pollu-
representing these preferences (see below, Hard tions. Effluent standards are used even when
Core Concept No. 3). On the supply side of col- knowledge of the consequences of such an exter-
lective action are the administrative costs of im- nality are predictable-organic wastes, for exam-
plementation and coordination as well as wasted ple, in a turbulent river-and alternative institu-
resources associated with possible monopolies. tional arrangements, like pollution taxes or auc-
In short, public choice analysis anticipates that tions of disposal rights, would be more efficient.
alternative institutional arrangements for manag- The reason is that the benefits and costs of an effi-
ing natural resources will all be costly, and that cient property rights change are unevenly dis-
the fundamental task of analysts is to compare tributed between the polluter and the individual
alternatives among property right structures to citizen. Active participation and influence on the
find the least disadvantageous means to accom- part of most individuals carries transaction costs
modate the variety of resource users. greater than the benefits for any one individual of
efficiently internalizing an externality. For most
point source polluters, the benefits are greater
Hard Core Concept 3: Individualism than the costs. Changes in institutional arrange-
ments, like a statutory right to class-action suits,
Public choice analysis assumes that decisions are designed to reduce transaction costs for some
made in both public and private arenas are made citizen-consumers and thus to alter the distribu-
by individual citizens, individual public officials, tion of benefits and costs and hence citizen
or individual representatives of collective and cor- behavior (Sproule-Jones and Hart 1973, Lucas
porate bodies. Decisions made in society can 1976, Buchanan and Tullock 1975, Mumy 1980).
always be disaggregated into decisions made by In public choice analysis, resource decision
individuals alone or interacting with others. Two making is evaluated in terms of its impact on in-
attributes of this methodological individualism dividual citizens rather than on groups, corporate
distinguish it from mere psychologism. First, the bodies, or governments. The value citizens place
decisions made by individuals are not simply on water quality, for example, is a subjective
determined by their preferences. Individuals make evaluation that is not reflected in the structure of
choices in the light of their own perceptions and market prices for all users of a basin (Sproule-
incentives structured by institutional arrange- Jones 1978a, b). Subjective value may not exhibit
ments. Second, the outcomes of decisions made a one-to-one relationship with either particular
within institutional arrangements are evaluated in physical or biological parameters of water quality
terms of their impacts on individual citizens, not (such as levels of dissolved oxygen), or with physi-
in terms of their effects on aggregate concepts cal proxies of output used by management agen-
(like a society, nation, or group), nor in terms of cies (such as proportion of point source discharges
their effects for public officials and representa- under effluent standard permits), or with absolute
tives of corporate and collective bodies. Both of or relative input variables (like expenditure levels
these attributes are illustrated for natural of government, businesses, or households on pol-
resources. lution control). For example, citizen-consumers
In a common-pool situation marked by an of the water quality environment in the Fraser
absence of a property right structure limiting ex- River Basin in British Columbia associate the pat-
ploitation of a resource, any individual has an in- tern of land uses, such as the location of houses,
centive to ignore the social costs of resource high-rises, industrial sites, roads, and transporta-
depletion for fear that other individuals will cap- tion corridors, with continuing deleterious condi-
1982 Public Choice Theory and Natural Resources 795
tions of water quality and do not feel that govern- Withoutthe Natureof the Good:
ment agencies have appropriate management MainstreamPoliticalScience
practices toward non-point source pollution. In
contrast, only small proportions of citizen- A river basin typically has multiple uses. In-
consumers are concerned with the effects of point streamuses may includeshippingand navigation,
source pollution, despite the priority placed on recreationalboating and swimming,commercial
such concerns by government agencies (Sproule- and recreationfisheries, and waste disposal, for
Jones 1981). example.On-the-landuses mayincludewatersup-
In sum, individuals have preferences, usually ply for irrigation,industrialcooling, anddomestic
diverse and varying in intensity, for different uses consumption.Other possible uses include shore-
of a resource, but such preferences are structured line sites for docking, marinas,recreation,wild-
by institutional arrangements into different forms fowl, fishery feeding, and houses and cottages.
of behavior, and the successful accommodation Positive and negative externalitiesmay exist be-
of the uses of a resource over space and time are tween one or more of these uses, and some uses
evaluated by individual citizens in their private may display the characteristicsof public goods
capacities. The next section of the paper justifies and common pools. The water quality of the
the selection of the hard core concepts, describes river, for example,may be deterioratedby some
their coming together in public choice theory, and uses such as the disposalof toxic wastes, but un-
shows how they apply to natural resource disturbedby others,suchas pristineformsof out-
management. door recreation.Some riversare of sufficientsize
and turbiditythat the waterqualitymaynot suffer
from the congestionand type of use likelyto turn
a riverfrom a publicgood into a common pool.
A critical difference between a public choice
analysis and a political science analysis of the
multipleuses of a riverbasinis in the scaleor unit
Theory of analysischosen for scrutiny.The basic unit of
analysis for public choice, called a provision
The hard core concepts come together with system, consists of all of the individual, cor-
auxilary concepts to form a network of proposi- porate, and governmentalusers as well as the
tions about natural resource management, or in- regulatorsof users of the resource(Gregg 1974;
deed other policy areas. The key to understanding Sproule-Jones1978b, 1981).The boundariesof a
the theory is understanding the relationship provisionsystemmay or may not correspondwith
among the hard core concepts. One must consider the territoriallegal boundariesof a singlegovern-
the nature of the good before one can draw con- ment. Indeed, a provisionsystemis most unlikely
clusions about the associations between institu- to coincidewith a singlejurisdiction(Kneeseand
tional arrangements and individualism. Further, Bower 1968;Klevonickand Kramer1973),owing
one must consider institutional arrangements to to the natureof the good and the numberof and
understand the relationship between individuals interdependenciesamong its uses. One expectsto
and goods, and one cannot understand this rela- find a large number of individualsand a large
tionship without considering citizen preferences. numberof locally, regionally,nationally,and in-
The interlocking nature of the hard core is ternationally owned corporations and groups
something not fully appreciated by philosophers jointly involvedin the productionand consump-
of science, which has led to misplaced criticism by tion of one or moreuses of the basin. One also ex-
social scientists working outside the paradigm. In pects to find agenciesof government(organizedat
this section, the interlocking nature of the hard local, regional, national, and internationalscale)
core concepts is demonstrated by describing the jointly involved in one or more uses, either as
kinds of conclusions about natural resources directusersor as regulatorsof other users. In the
which would be reached if the hard core were "water quality provision system" of the Fraser
missing each of the hard core concepts in turn. River, for example, are over 100 policy actors
Were the hard core to delete the nature of the from some 54 agencies and organizations, in-
good, the conclusions would fit mainstream cluding local, provincial, federal, and interna-
political science. Were individual preferences to tional agenciesof governmentplus local, provin-
be deleted, mainstream public administration cial, federal, and internationalcorporationsand
would ensue. And were institutional arrangements groups(Sproule-Jones1981).In addition,one ex-
to be deleted, mainstream economics would be the pects this organizationalnetworkto be changing
result. This interdependence of the three concepts in complexityover time, as new marketableand
justifies their selection as the hard core of public nonmarketableuses of the basin are enhancedor
choice analysis. diminished.
796 The AmericanPoliticalScience Review Vol. 76
An analysis based on the territorial legal boun- authority fragmented among its governmental
daries of governments reaches differing conclu- agencies, is a case in point. A number of public
sions about water resource decision making and agencies, each responsible for a particular
the role of institutional variables, as well as on resource use, like waste disposal, navigation, or
more generic policy topics (e.g., Ackerman et al. fishing, may ignore the positive and negative ex-
1974; Golembiewski 1977; Dye 1978). Citizen ternalities among resource uses without necessari-
preference for one or more uses of a river basin ly ensuring that functional specializations are ef-
may be articulated (or remain latent in the case of fectively coordinated. The public too is often left
public goods and common pools) through confused because it does not know which level of
private market and group action, but it may be government or which agencies at which level of
voiced through electoral behavior and traditional government are responsible for managing dif-
forms of representation. Elected and appointed ferent resource uses, and government levels and
officials of a level of government may have a agencies can abjure responsibility for overall
severely constrained impact on resource decision management.
making; variables designed to indicate the policy The solution often posed is to move to a set of
outputs of a level of government are likely to ex- hierarchical institutional arrangements. A single
clude some river basin uses, like private market- river basin authority should have the powers dele-
able uses, and include some water uses from more gated to it to eliminate the overlap and fragmenta-
than one basin. tion among agencies, and to coordinate effectively
Analyzing a resource like wheat production and resource use in the light of public values. The
processing, public choice would predict a dif- model found on the Ruhr should be imitated else-
ferent kind of provision system varying in com- where (Kneese and Bower 1968).
plexity and in the nature of policy decisions. A public choice analysis of river basin manage-
Water resources and wheat production have dif- ment suggests that comparisons be made between
ferent kinds of abundancies, technologies for ex- alternative institutional arrangements. A frag-
ploitation, and interdependencies with other agri- mented provision system is costly, but single
cultural and land use resources. Generalizations hierarchies tend to be more costly in a number of
about citizen and governmental behavior would ways. First, they place a river-basin authority in a
be correspondingly different. It would be unlikely monopoly position, and public monopolies can be
that generalizations about citizen and governmen- successfully captured by one or a subset of
tal behavior within a particular system of govern- resource users, because of the distribution of
ment could be transferred from the one resource benefits and costs associated with demand ar-
area to the other. Only a careful public choice ticulation. Second, a monopoly of expertise con-
analysis that takes into account the nature of the tained within a single authority implies that
good can unravel the extent and significance of elected officials cannot estimate the real value of
political behavior. governmental activities, with the consequence of
inflated budgets and overregulation, the so-called
Niskanen hypothesis (Niskanen 1971). Third, the
number and complexity of resource interdepen-
Without Individual Preferences: dencies may ensure that any river-basin authority
Mainstream Public Administration is of such size that control from the top of the
hierarchy is dissipated, and that managerial dis-
The multiple uses of a river basin, or of any economies of scale will issue in a lack of coordina-
other "bundle" of resources found in a well- tion and agency "free enterprise" (Tullock 1965).
defined geographic space, provide an apt example The fragmented authority found in typical pro-
of the differences between a public choice analysis vision systems does not, by definition, contain
of resource management and what might be called such disadvantages of monopoly, and empirical
mainstream public administration. evidence on the Fraser River indicates that (a)
Mainstream public administration recognizes there is substantial coordination within the provi-
the problems associated with public goods, com- sion system, (b) this coordination is not sporadic
mon pools, and externalities. Mainstream public and unplanned, and (c) it takes place both across
administration, however, is concerned that the ex- and within government and the privately owned
pertise necessary to solve such problems is in- sectors (Sproule-Jones 1980). Citizen preferences
effectively applied, that organizational conflicts for different resource uses may be better articu-
may amplify resource interdependencies, and that lated and traded through a multiplicity of political
governmental agencies with the power to make access points combined with market prices rather
and implement resource decisions are not ac- than through concentrated political authority.
countable to the general public. A provision The Fraser model is more appropriate than the
system, with its multiple organizations and Ruhr (Sproule-Jones 1978b).
1982 Public Choice Theory and Natural Resources 797
WithoutInstitutionalArrangements: clusive preserve of the riparian landowner or ten-
MainstreamEconomics ant. Also, such a change in property rights would
indicate that commercial fishermen and their
Mainstream economics recognizes market allies were more successful than riparian land-
failurewhen pricesfail to signal, or signalinade- owners and tenants in exploiting the institutional
quately, the value that citizen consumers may arrangements under which statutory changes are
place on certainresourceuses, and the value that enacted.
producersof commodities (involving resources) The above arguments show that the three hard
may place on their form of productionand pro- core concepts of a public choice analysis are all
cessing rather than on another form. Market necessary components of the paradigm. Although
failures and weaknesses include private sector public choice analysis draws on work in political
monopolies,publicgoods, common pools, exter- science, public administration, and economics, it
nalities, and so-calledequity or income distribu- represents a form of analysis distinct from con-
tion concerns.The role of the state is to correct ventional or mainstream thinking in those disci-
for such marketfailuresand weaknesses.In this plines. One cannot draw any conclusions about
regard,mainstreameconomicsdoes not appearto natural resources management without consider-
differ greatlyfrom public choice. ing all three concepts: the nature of the resource
The case of the multipleuse of resources,how- under scrutiny, the institutional arrangements for
ever, illustratesthe differencesbetween the two management, and the differing citizen-consumer
kinds of analyses.Mainstreameconomicanalysis preferences for differing uses of the resource.
of multipleuse is based on the premisethat the
costs to any single class of resourceusers should
be balancedagainst the benefits to those users.
For short-runpricingdecisions, it means that a Animating Principle of Public Choice
varietyof market-likemechanismsshould be in-
troduced by the private or public sector pro- Concepts like the hard core concepts of public
prietorsof a land, air, or watersite. The mecha- choice can normally characterize the properties of
nisms includeuser fees, transferablelicensesand particular empirical elements. Concepts have a
permits,and bonus bids. Any user will then have descriptive function: the concept of a public good
an incentiveto use a resourceonly to the degree characterizes, for example, certain properties in
that his satisfactionis equalto or greaterthan the the nature of resources. Concepts also have theo-
satisfactionhis use forcesothersto forego (Walter retical significance, however; they are used in one
1978). For long-runinvestmentdecisions, public or more propositions to explain the relationships
or private sector facilities should be introduced among sets of empirical elements. My examples in
only if the aggregatebenefitsto all resourceusers the previous section illustrate how concepts about
exceed the aggregatecosts over a specified time the nature of the resource, institutional arrange-
horizon.The criterionof evaluationis utilitarian; ments, and the choice behavior of individuals are
net benefitsshould be maximizedover all uses. related together to form an understanding of
The implication of such an analysis for the resource use and exploitation.
nature of institutionalarrangementsis that the In this section I explore and illustrate the theo-
publicsectoris both an "ethicalobserver"in that retical significance of public choice concepts with
it can estimateand aggregatenon-marketvalues reference to natural resources and argue that the
with marketableones, and also a monopolistthat network of public choice propositions is dis-
can implementthe appropriatepricingand invest- tinguished by logically consistent interrelations.
ment decisions(Sproule-Jones1972). Further, I propose that this logical consistency is
In contrast,a publicchoice analysisarguesthat the impetus behind the public choice paradigm
the propertyright structurein any society will which expands the range of analysis into different
create benefits and costs for different resource policy arenas and different social science dis-
uses (marketableand non-marketable)with dif- ciplines.
fering consequencesdependingon the nature of
the good. Moreover,the propertyright structure Logical Consistency
for resourceusersis also a dependentvariableof
those other institutionalarrangementsgoverning Logical consistency refers to the way in which
the operationof the "state." One would antici- the propositions of public choice analysis are in-
pate, for example, a different distribution of terrelated. They are interrelated such that no con-
benefitsand costs and a differentmix of resource clusion drawn from one set of propositions in the
uses if commercialfishermenwere given a statu- analysis contradicts another conclusion drawn
tory property right for the protection of fish from a different set. The propositions conform to
habitat rather than if such rights were the ex- the rules of logic, where logic refers to purely for-
798 The AmericanPoliticalScience Review Vol. 76
mal relations and does not connote anything cur Olson's 1965 classic, The Logic of Collective
existential. Action, is a good example. The two structural
The contradiction between the standard of characteristics of a public good were extended to
Pareto optimality and the welfare loss associated the nature of group action, yielding conclusions
with the collective provision of a public good is an about the free-rider incentive which can operate
example of logical inconsistency. Pareto optimal- within groups as it can operate within a market
ity, which states that any policy change is an im- economy. The propositions yielded predictions
provement if it makes at least one person better about a new class of events previously not thought
off and no one worse off, is a standard used in about in such terms.
conventional welfare economics to evaluate Two possible objections may be raised against
market decisions. It is not applicable to, and is the thesis that logical consistency is the necessary
contradicted by, the concept of a welfare loss component of public choice analysis. First, it
associated with collective provision of a public might be objected that the analysis consists of
good, because except under extreme assumptions, establishing connections between facts that are
such as identical consumer preferences or a substantively interesting. For example, it might be
perfectly discriminating monopolist, the tax costs suggested that natural resource management is
will exceed the benefits of a public good for at subject to public choice analysis because of an in-
least one consumer. Public choice analysis has terest in seeing what difference institutional ar-
responded to such contradictions by developing rangements make in resource use and exploita-
alternative standards, such as institutional fair- tion. However, natural resource management has
ness or a mutually agreed social contract to ap- been made the subject of intense scrutiny by
praise both market and nonmarket outcomes. scholars in economics, political science, and
The criterion of logical consistency among its public administration, among other fields, and
propositions has two major implications for the the hard core concepts have been developed at
public choice analysis of natural resource manage- least in part by scholars in these different fields.
ment. First, the analysis rationalizes the existing Were public choice not characterized by logical
state of resource use, exploitation, and manage- consistency as a necessary part of its methodol-
ment. Second, the analysis leads to the logical ogy, it would have nothing to add to disciplinary
deduction of conclusions in areas previously not work. It is the attempt to combine such hard core
subject to public choice analysis.' concepts in a network of logically consistent
A deductive-nomological explanation consists propositions, and to eliminate the contradictions
of an explanandum, or the set of events to be ex- found in work in these separate disciplines, that
plained, and an explanans, or the determining gives public choice analysis its rationale.
conditions and covering laws that account for the A second possible objection might be that
explanandum. An explanans that includes the logical consistency is a result of broader theo-
covering law "if exclusion of fishermen is very retical and epistemological assumptions inherent
costly, then fishing stocks will be depleted" will in public choice analysis. This objection holds
explain or account for diminished fishing stocks that since logical consistency is a necessary ele-
in a particular natural environment, other things ment of all theory, it is the epistemological nature
being equal. Or to put the matter the other way of public choice that makes it a distinct form of
around, the existence of diminished fishing stocks analysis. Such a claim will be refuted in the next
can be rationalized with the covering law in ques- section, where it is argued that public choice
tion. There may, of course, be other covering laws analysis is open to a number of rival epistemolo-
that could adequately explain the diminished fish- gies; no single epistemology is "stamped" as that
ing stocks, such as a loss of habitat, fish disease, of public choice, and no single epistemology, such
or more productive technologies for catching fish, as logical empiricism, is accepted that would pre-
but the criterion of logical consistency offers in scribe the criterion of logical consistency.
and of itself no solution which one would apply to As the necessary component of public choice,
the case in hand. Any single proposition used as a logical consistency may be the source of its im-
covering law in an explanans is a rationalization petus.
of existing events.
Logical consistency is also a mean whereby one
or more covering laws can be applied to areas The Impetus of Public Choice
previously not part of the scope of analysis. Man-
The search for logical consistency among
propositions about natural resources or other em-
5Theepistemologicaland normativeimplicationsof pirical conditions is the impetus behind public
logical consistencyand the hard core concepts are ex- choice analysis. Moreover, the search is never
ploredin the fourth section. completed, because new theoretical concepts are
1982 PublicChoiceTheory and NaturalResources 799
developed and new applications are found for the ments. In other words, higher level propositions
analysis. containing the concept of constitutional arrange-
In the first place, any covering law used as a ra- ments offer a rational (in the sense of logically
tionalization of existing empirical conditions may consistent) justification for lower level covering
be challenged by alternative propositions that can laws containing the hard core concept of institu-
predict equally well similar conclusions about the tional arrangements.
empirical world. The argument that pollution This methodological process can continue ad
regulatory agencies are captured by those whom infinitum. More and more logically consistent
they are designed to regulate may be deduced as propositions can be posed as higher level ra-
easily from public choice propositions about the tionalizations for lower level propositions. For
relative benefits and costs of active participation example, the concept of constitutional arrange-
on the part of the polluters and the general public, ments has stimulated extended theoretical reason-
as it may be from, for example, neo-Marxian ing about the nature of constitutions by re-
propositions about an identity of interests be- examining social contracts, anarchy and the emer-
tween polluters and their elected or appointed gence of constitutions, obligation and consent
"class factions." with constitutional regimes, and liberty and politi-
Public choice analysis does not respond to such cal order. The works of Rawls (1971), Nozick
a theoretical challenge to its rationalizations by (1974), and Hayek (1973, 1976, 1979) are some of
crucial hypothesis testing (Popper 1968), nor does the more frequently analyzed philosophic tracts.
public choice resort to an "instrumental fic- Logical consistency contains its own impetus.
tionalist" view of theory building in which its Similar consequences are found, in the second
covering laws containing theoretical concepts are place, when the covering laws of public choice are
never independently verified (Friedman 1953; applied to different empirical arenas. The concept
Davis 1969). Instead, public choice searches for of a service provision system, for example, was
new theoretical concepts that can form higher initially developed from a study of the California
level propositions which can, in turn, rationalize water industry (Ostrom and Ostrom 1965) and
its covering law or laws. Such higher level propo- used as one organizing concept in studies of polic-
sitions can explain away the apparent inconsis- ing carried out by the Workshop in Political
tency between a lower level rationalization and an Theory and Policy Analysis (Ostrom, Parks and
alternative covering law (Lakatos 1974). In other Whitaker 1978). It was then applied to estuarine
words, the criterion of logical consistency is used water quality management (Sproule-Jones 1978a,
to generate a more extensive theoretical frame- b, 1981), where the nature of the good neces-
work of propositions. An example is again in sitated a number of modifications and elabora-
order. tions of the concept. For example, estuarine water
The concept of constitutional arrangements is quality is important to certain fish and wildfowl
frequently invoked to explain away inconsisten- species that migrate over thousands of miles.
cies between public choice rationalizations and Recreationists, ecologists, and the commercial
alternative propositions posed by competing ex- fishing interests are therefore drawn from large
planations. The concept received its first extended and differing territorial scales which differ in turn
application in the seminal The Calculus of Con- from other resource users like shippers and boat
sent (Buchanan and Tullock 1962). It was used owners. In and of itself, public choice analysis
there to account for how individuals would freely contains no auxiliary measurement theory to
impose collective choice upon themselves, or have predict what territorial boundaries, and hence
it imposed because of Arrow Paradox circum- classes of users and potential users, should validly
stances. Necessary solutions to free-rider prob- be included within the boundaries of a provision
lems are acceptable, provided long-run constitu- system. The methodological solution posed in the
tional decisions are based on the willing consent Fraser River study was to use a snowball sample
of every individual in the collectivity. The concept of resource users for one point in time, and
has since been used to account for weaknesses and assume the boundaries of the provision system
failures in institutional arrangements, such as were open because of the nonexclusionary
those allowing the capture of regulatory agencies character of water quality as a public good. This
by those whom the agency is supposed to regulate. example illustrates how the theoretical proposi-
In the case of natural resource management, tions of public choice may be logically and con-
resource degradation or the misallocation of sistently applied to "new" empirical problems.
resource uses among current and potential Logically consistent applications are a necessary
resource users can theoretically be attributed to but not a necessary and sufficient specification of
weaknesses and failures in institutional ar- any empirical verification. The result is that the
rangements which, in turn, can be attributed to scope of potential applications is large, and that
weaknesses and failures in constitutional arrange- the standard of logical consistency contains its
800 The AmericanPoliticalScienceReview Vol. 76
own impetus for including more and more ap- But the impetus of public choice is not ex-
plications under the deductive power of its pro- clusively grounded in the logical consistency that
positions. These applications can include subject makes possible the deduction of new propositions
matter traditionally examined in a variety of and the construction of new higher level proposi-
disciplines. Public choice thus offers, through its tions to explain away apparent contradictions.
adoption of a standard of logical consistency, the Public choice is compatible with, and open to, a
prospect of continual multidisciplinary studies. variety of epistemologies; or to put the point
In sum, the hard core of public choice concepts another way, public choice analysis does not pre-
is defined by the criterion of logical consistency, clude the application of a variety of epistemolo-
and this criterion can account for the impetus of gies to its reasoning and proofs. I defend this
the approach. Other important methodological thesis by showing how public choice has been
implications of the approach are addressed in the welded with alternative epistemologies, and how
next section. any peculiar normative status of public choice and
its basic concepts is dependent on the type of
epistemology selected or assumed to lie at its
roots.
Epistemological Foundations

The appeal of public choice analysis would be


relatively slight were it to be based solely on the Alternative Epistemologies
logical consistency with which its hard core and
auxiliary concepts are combined and applied. Knowledge claims are grounded in one of three
Public choice analysis would be considered, on mutually exclusive sources: experience, reason,
the one hand, as a more "realistic" form of and perception. All three sources are used in
economics, political science, or public administra- public choice analysis, and all three sources have
tion in that it took account of an extra class of been explicitly invoked by theorists.
variables in its explanation. For example, it would In the first place, the appeal to experience and
have the equivalent position of social psychology the use of empirical factual evidence as confirma-
to the disciplines of sociology and psychology. tion, proof, falsification, or verification is most
On the other hand, it would be subject to the frequently invoked as the source of knowledge
variety of charges against the standard of logical about citizens, institutional arrangements, and the
consistency as rationality levied by philosophers nature of the good. Thus Plott and Smith (1979,
of science, particularly since World War II. These p. 169) were recently able to write in defense of
charges, made from a variety of premises, argue laboratory methods in public choice that:
that logical consistency is a standard imposed by
Therewill alwaysbe some aspectof realitythata
theorists on the kinds of causal connections or designermightsuspectis important,and whichis
supporting evidence or both, acceptable within missing from an experiment,that might cause
the paradigm or within the scholarly community him or herto remainless thanconvincedthat the
at large. In natural resource management, for results are externally valid.... The bottom line
example, resource scarcity, institutional arrange- is that the robustnessof empirical results on
ments facilitating the entry of resource users and behavioracrossdifferentenvironmentscan only
the behavior of the users themselves might be be determinedempirically.Wheneverreplicable
causally connected in public choice analysis by laboratory behavior has been demonstrated,
propositions about common pool behavior, but then it is entirelyfittingto seek field tests of the
hypothesisthat the behavioris manifestin more
the resource users might not share this causal con- complexenvironments.
nection, preferring, for example, one about the
inculcation of an "environmental ethic." Similar- This resort to empiricism is taken only within the
ly, the kinds of logically valid supporting evidence boundaries laid down by the theoretical concepts
for these alternative causal connections might well of public choice analysis. The problems deemed
differ, and the kinds of logically valid evidence ac- worthy of investigation and the interpretation of
ceptable to the adherents of the rival approaches empirical evidence are theoretically specified.
might not conform to the standards of "critical Davis (1969, p. 36) has written:
rationalism" of an ideal scholarly community If the first role of empiricismis the testing of
(Popper 1968). In sum, were any of these kinds of theory, the second is the attempt to bridge the
charges accurate, public choice analysis would be gap between refined theoreticalstructuresand
merely another analytical approach in the social the real world via the methodof havingempiri-
sciences, albeit a peculiarly Western and liberal cists insist upon asking how concepts may be
one. measuredand theoriestested.
1982 Public Choice Theory and Natural Resources 801
Moreover, as I have indicated previously, the evi- knowledge. Some use reason as the basis of
dence interpreted in this form of analysis is judged knowledge. Buchanan and Tullock (1962), who
by the logical consistency of its propositions. This offered a new understanding of the strategic im-
is an apparent paradox of public choice analysis. portance of constitutional arrangements to the
The problems deemed worthy of scrutiny and the operation of institutional arrangements, devel-
evidence deemed appropriate are theory impreg- oped their arguments by asking, in effect, "What
nated; the requirement of logical consistency form would such arrangements take if they were
among its theoretical propositions allows the to be specified by 'any person' over a risky
theoretician to interpret empirical evidence as future?" A comparable kind of question was
confirmatory or to explain away apparent discon- posed by Rawls (1971) for individuals making
firmatory evidence by developing higher level pro- decisions in a "veil of ignorance." The problem,
positions. Grounding public choice analysis in if it is a problem, with such forms of knowledge
such logical empiricism therefore offers security about goods, institutional arrangements, and
to the paradigm and renders it impregnable to citizens is that the conclusions reached by pure
assaults of rival theories. reason are sensitive only to the assumptions
Of course, public choice theory frequently uses adopted by the theorist. Public choice theory,
empirical evidence to disconfirm or corroborate with its standard of logical consistency, is not
propositions in the body of the theory. Any unwittingly prepared to accept contradictory
potentially contradictory evidence, however, can axioms. As was the case with logical empiricism,
be reinterpreted by developing higher level pro- the use of reason as a source of knowledge acts to
positions (axioms) to explain away such evidence. maintain the impetus of the approach in the face
In other words, logical consistency is the mecha- of rival political theories.
nism that enables this strategy to succeed. For ex- The third source of knowledge, that of percep-
ample, the exhaustion of fugitive resources like tions, has also been invoked in public choice
whales, buffalo, and salmon is typically inter- analysis. The most sophisticated version of such
preted as a function of mis-specified property an epistemology in public choice has been offered
rights that do not limit entry, the tragedy of the by Ostrom and Hennessey (1975), and Ostrom
commons. When property rights that limit entry (1979, 1980), who have taken certain notions
are established, and the resultant economic rents associated with the reasoning of Winch (1958) and
are captured by one group of users, this evidence turned them into an epistemology of individual
is interpreted as a consequence of rent-seeking choice for goods within institutional arrange-
behavior on the part of the group. If, on the other ments. For Ostrom, individual choice and con-
hand, the rent does not appear to be captured by a straints on that choice are determined by the
group of users, it is then argued that the rents are human artifactual system of language. Choice and
dissipated by the agency or agencies that regulate constraints on choice are a function of this funda-
the resource. That is, one can use either the mental set of decision rules. A subset of these ar-
Krueger-Tullock arguments about rent seeking to tifactual decision rules consists of the institutional
explain the consequences of limited entry or the and constitutional arrangements in any society
Niskanen (and others) hypothesis about agency which order the relationships between man and
behavior to account for these consequences the state, and between and among state officials.
(Krueger 1974, Tullock 1967, 1971; Niskanen In turn, however, the artifactual institutional and
1971, Anderson and Hill 1980; Buchanan et al. constitutional arrangements, as decision rules, in-
1980). It was Lakatos who first pointed out these fluence the perceptions of individuals about the
kinds of principles associated with paradigm range of admissible choice. Artifactual decision
development. However, most theorists have rules are a consequence of both individual choice
argued that the reasons lie in the psychological at- and behavior. The nature of the good is merely a
tachment that theorists have to their paradigms. constraint on this interactive dynamic of society.
The reasons actually lie in the standard of logical Such an epistemology is, like the epistemologies
consistency which can be used as a mechanical of logical empiricism and reason, impermeable to
device to explain away disconfirmatory evidence. challenge from alternative perspectives. It cannot
Most paradigms are similar to public choice in this be refuted or subjected to disconfirmatory evi-
respect. For example, Marxism frequently relies dence by someone from outside this perspective,
on concepts of "false consciousness" and "bour- for the evidence and interpretation of evidence by
geois ideology" to account for disconfirmatory such a person can be reasoned away as a product
evidence. Freudian psychology similarly uses of the artifactual decision rules determining his or
propositions including nonobservational con- her choice of evidence and interpretation of that
cepts. evidence. The impetus of public choice within
Some public choice theorists do not rely ex- such an epistemological framework can be main-
clusively on logical empiricism as a source of tained.
802 TheAmericanPoliticalScience Review Vol. 76
AlternativeEpistemologiesand could argue that the assumption is normative only
NormativeImplications if it fails to make factual evidence possible (e.g.,
Buchanan 1959). A rationalist could claim,
All three kinds of epistemologies,those based equivalently, that the assumption merely facili-
on experience,reason, and perception,have been tates reasoned knowledge about individuals. And
used as groundsfor interpretationand evidencein a perspectivist could argue that there are different
publicchoice analysis.Each exampleabove plays normative implications about the assumption; it
a double role. Each epistemology provides a represents one element in a broader normative
groundingfor the theoreticalconceptsand propo- position about knowledge, perception, choice and
sitions and offers a form of interpretationand their relation to artifactual decision rules.
verification,but each also insulatesthis form of It could be argued that the existence of alterna-
analysisfrom potentialrivalsand acts to maintain tive epistemologies and alternative normative im-
the impetusof the approach.It is the criterionof plications of each epistemology may not deny that
logicalconsistency,ratherthan any shallowtricks there is a coherent and single normative strain in
on the part of the theorist, that renders the this type of analysis, because the selection of the
paradigmsecureand impregnable. three concepts as the hard core of the analysis
This dual role of the rivalepistemologiesprac- eliminates the selection of any other candidates
ticedin publicchoice casts a differentlight on the for the hard core, and this is by default a nor-
normativeclaimsand implicationsof this type of mative posture. For example, public choice
analysis. For if diversity can exist at an epis- analysis neatly sidesteps questions about the per-
temological level about the theoreticalconcepts sonality causes of individual preferences, prefer-
and propositionsof the core of the analysis,then ring to examine demonstrated preferences and
claimsthat public choice prescribesone and only choices within the constraints and incentives of in-
one normativeinterpretationabout collectiveac- stitutional arrangements; this implies, it might be
tion are rendereddubious. further argued, a normative posture about the
For example, it might be assertedthat the in- value of understanding individual behavior in
strumentalassumptionthat institutionalarrange- psychological terms. The counterclaim to such an
ments are merely means for effecting citizen- argument is, of course, related to the nature of
consumer preferencesis a decidedly normative theory. Theories deliberately select a subset of all
claimaboutthe state. The statehas no rationalein of the possible elements of the world that could be
and of itself, and man is not perfectablethrough used as potential explanatory concepts. If theories
political activities. However, an empiricistepis- did not make such selections, no knowledge
temologymightarguethat the normativeimplica- claims could be made until all knowledge claims
tions of such an interpretationwill depend on were somehow revealed. Every concept would be
whether the assumptioncan generate verifiable an explanatory concept until it were shown to be
conclusions about the relationshipsbetween in- otherwise. But we have no means to tell whether a
stitutionalarrangements,goods, and individuals. concept is explanatory or not if we do not develop
A rationalistepistemologymayclaimthat such an theories. The claim is a tautology.
assumption, along with others, will merely It might also be argued that logical consistency
generateinsightsinto the natureof the state, and as the fundamental methodology of public choice
a perspectivistepistemologycould interpretthe is in itself a normative criterion. By placing logic,
claim that institutionalarrangementsare instru- as a mere technique, at the center of the public
mentaldevicesas part of a much broadernorma- choice approach as the method by which the hard
tive claim about the relationshipsbetween arti- core propositions are linked together, public
factual decision rules and individualchoices and choice theorists are substituting mere technical ra-
knowledge. tionality for a wider notion of rationality toward
As a second example,it might be assertedthat the interests of persons in society.6 But we have
the assumptionof methodologicalindividualism seen that logical consistency does not foreclose
represents a normative posture, perhaps of a and is compatible with alternative epistemologies
peculiarly liberal sort. The proposition that and hence with what could be conceived as the
elected and appointed officials make choices in wider external rationality (Kekes 1976) of
the light of their own preferencesand the incen- theories. Indeed, the perspectivist epistemology
tive of institutional arrangementsdenies, for previously illustrated would imply no empirical or
example,the claim that thereis a widerpublicin- analytical basis for the argument against technical
terestthat cannot be disaggregatedinto decisions rationality.
made by individuals alone or interacting with
others. Again, the alternativepublic choice epis-
temologiescan drawdifferentnormativeimplica- 6This is an application of the reasoning of The Frank-
tions about such propositions. An empiricist furt School to public choice analysis.
1982 Public Choice Theory and Natural Resources 803
In sum, public choice analysis is compatible Anderson, T. L., and Hill, P. J. 1980. Property rights
with alternative epistemologies, each of which can as a common pool resource. Paper at Public Choice
act to protect the hard core against rival Society meetings, San Francisco, March.
arguments. The epistemologies also act to main- Bernstein, R. 1975. The restructuring of political and
tain the impetus of the approach. Moreover, social theory. New York: Harcourt, Brace,
alternative epistemologies imply alternative nor- Jovanovich.
Bish, R. L. 1971. The public economy of metropolitan
mative postures about relationships among in- areas. Waco, Tex.: Markham Press.
stitutional arrangements, individuals, and goods. Bish, R. L., and Ostrom, V. 1973. Understanding
Although it might appear that more public choice urban government. Washington: American Enter-
practitioners are logical empiricists in method and prise Institute.
assumption (see Mueller 1979, for example), the Buchanan, J. M. 1959. Positive economics, welfare
analysis is open to and compatible with different economics, and political economy. Journal of Law
normative postures. and Economics 2:124-38.
It is conceivable that the diversity of epistemol- 1962. The calculus of consent. Ann Arbor:
ogies within the paradigm could lead to fractious University of Michigan Press.
dispute and dissipation of effort, but until an Tollison, R. D., and Tullock, G. ed. 1980.
Toward a theory of the rent-seeking society. College
unambiguous interpretation of concepts, proposi- Station: Texas A&M University Press.
tions, and the meaning of terms is developed, no , and Tullock, G. 1975. Polluter's profits and
priority can be assigned to one or another alterna- political response. American Economic Review 65:
tive epistemology. 139-47.
Coase, R. H. 1960. The problems of social cost. Jour-
nal of Law and Economics 3:1-44.
Conclusion Davis, 0. A. 1969. Notes on strategy and methodology
for a scientific political science. In Mathematical ap-
Public choice analysis contains a hard core of plications in political science IV, ed. J. L. Bernd, pp.
concepts, about the nature of the good, about in- 22-38. Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia.
Downs, A. 1957. An economic theory of democracy.
stitutional arrangements, and about individuals. New York: Harper & Row.
This set of hard core concepts distinguishes the Dye, T. R., ed. 1979. Symposium on determinants of
paradigm from rival approaches in political public policy: cities, states, and nations. Policy
science, public administration, and economics. Studies Journal 7:652-803.
The hard core concepts are interrelated by the Friedman, M. 1953. The methodology of positive eco-
methodological criterion of logical consistency nomics. In essays in positive economics. Chicago:
one interpretation of the notion of rationality- University of Chicago Press. Reprinted in Readings
and the criterion accounts for the impetus behind in the philosophy of the social sciences. ed. May
the growth of the paradigm. The paradigm is but- Brodbeck, pp. 508-528. New York: Macmillan.
Frohlich, N., and Oppenheimer, J. A. 1978. Modern
tressed and protected from rival approaches at an political economy. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice
epistemological level, and a variety of epistemolo- Hall.
gies (empirical, perceptual and "rational") have Giddens, A. 1976. New rules of sociological method.
been linked to the approach. The congruence of New York: Basic Books.
public choice with this variety of epistemologies Golembiewski, R. T. 1977. A critique of "democratic
makes many of the criticisms about the normative administration" and its supporting ideation. Ameri-
implications of the approach inaccurate and mis- can Political Science Review 71:1488-1507.
leading. Gregg, P. M. 1974. Units and levels of analysis: a prob-
The type of goods known as natural resources lem of policy analysis in federal systems. Publius
4:59-86.
illustrates the argument. Natural resources are
Hardin, G. 1968. The tragedy of the commons. Science
commanding increasing public attention and 162:1243-48.
scholarly analysis, but other kinds of goods could Hayek, F. A. 1973, 1976, 1979. Law, legislation and
have been used. A public choice analysis of liberties, 3 vol. Chicago: University of Chicago
natural resources is not only a sound scholarly Press.
enterprise but also one that rests on sound Kekes, J. 1976. A justification of rationality. Albany:
methodological foundations. State University of New York Press.
Klevoick, A. K., and Kramer, G. H. 1973. Social choice
on pollution management: the genossenschaften.
Journal of Public Economics 2:101-46.
References Kneese, A. V., and Bower, B. T. 1968. Managing water
quality. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Abrams, R. 1980. Foundations of political analysis. Lakatos, I. 1974. Falsification and the methodology of
New York: Columbia University Press. scientific research programs. In Criticism and the
Ackerman, A.; Ackerman, S. R.; Sawyer, J. W.; and growth of knowledge, eds. Imre Lakatos and Allan
Henderson, D. W. 1974. The uncertain search for Musgrave, pp. 91-196. New York: Cambridge Uni-
environmental quality. New York: Free Press. versity Press.
804 TheAmericanPoliticalScienceReview Vol. 76
Larkin, P. A. 1979. Fisheries management: the coming Russell, pp. 167-72. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Uni-
crisis. In Coastal resources in the future of B.C., ed. versity Press.
A. H. J. Dorcey, pp. 1-12. Westwater Research Cen- Popper, K. R. 1968. The logic of scientific discovery.
tre, University of British Columbia. Bridgeport, Conn.: Hutchinson.
Lucas, A. R. 1976. Legal foundations for public par- Rawls, J. A. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge,
ticipation in environmental decision making. Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Natural Resources Journal 16:73-102. Riker W. H., and Ordeshook, P. C. 1973. An introduc-
McDavid, J. C. 1976. "Crucial testing" for the study tion to positive political theory. Englewood Cliffs,
of complex institutions. In Problems of theory in N.J.: Prentice Hall.
policy analysis, ed. P. M. Gregg, pp. 137-148. Lex- Schmid, A. A. 1978. Property, power and public
ington, Mass.: D.C. Heath. choice. New York: Praeger.
Mueller, D. C. 1979. Public choice. New York: Cam- Smith, V. K., and Krutilla, J. V. 1979. The economics
bridge University Press. of natural resource scarcity: an interpretive in-
Mumy, G. E. 1980. Long run efficiency and property troduction. In Scarcity and growth reconsidered, ed.
rights sharing for pollution control. Public Choice V. K. Smith, pp. 1-35. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
35:59-74. University Press.
Niskanen, W. A., Jr. 1971. Bureaucracy and represen- Sproule-Jones, Mark. 1972. Strategic tensions in the
tative government. Hawthorne, N.Y.: Aldine- scale of political analysis. British Journal of
Atherton. Political Science 2:173-91.
Nozick, R. 1974. Anarchy, state and utopia. New York: 1975. Public choice and federalism in Australia
Basic Books. and Canada. Canberra: Australian National Univer-
Olson, M. 1965. The logic of collective action. Cam- sity.
bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. 1978a. The social appropriateness of water
Ostrom, E.; Parks, R. B.; and Whitaker, G. D. 1978. quality management for the Lower Fraser River.
Patterns of metropolitan policing. Cambridge, Canadian Public Administration 21:1976-94.
Mass.: Ballinger. 1978b. Coordination and the management of
Ostrom, V. 1979. Constitutional level of analysis: estuarine water quality. Public Choice 33:41-54.
problems and prospects. Paper read at Western 1979. A fresh look at an old problem: coor-
Political Science Association meeting, 22-24 March. dinating Canada's shore management agencies.
1980. Artisanship and artifact. Public Admin- Western Political Quarterly 32:278-85.
istration Review 40:309-317. 1981. The real world of pollution control. Van-
Ostrom, V., and Hennessey, T. 1975. Institutional couver: Westwater Research Centre, University of
analysis and design. Workshop in Political Theory British Columbia.
and Policy Analysis, Indiana University. Sproule-Jones, M., and Hart, K. D. 1973. A public
Ostrom, V., and Ostrom, E. 1965. A behavioral ap- choice model of political participation. Canadian
proach to the study of intergovernmental relations. Journal of Political Science 6:175-94.
Annals of the American Academy of Political and Stroup, R., and Baden, J. 1980. Property rights and
Social Sciences 359:137-46. natural resource management. Cato Institute.
Ostrom, V.; Tiebout, C. M.; and Warren, R. 0. 1961. Tullock, G. 1965. The politics of bureaucracy. Wash-
The organization of government in metropolitan ington, D.C.: Public Affairs Press.
areas: a theoretical inquiry. American Political Sci- Tullock, G. 1967. The welfare costs of tariffs, mono-
ence Review 55:831-42. politics, and theft. Western Economic Journal. 5:
Plott, C. R. 1976. Axiomatic social choice theory: an 224-32.
overview and interpretation. American Journal of Tullock, G. 1971. The cost of transfers. Kyklos 24:
Political Science 20:511-96. 629-43.
Plott, C. R., and Smith, V. L. Further comments: the Walter, G. R. 1978. Market methods of multiple use
application of laboratory experimental methods to reconciliation. Journal of Environmental Manage-
public choice. In Collective decision-making: Ap- ment 7:291-96.
plications from public choice theory, ed. C. S. Winch, P. 1958. The idea of a social science. Boston:
Routledge & Kegan Paul.

Anda mungkin juga menyukai