Anda di halaman 1dari 35

Where is the market going?

Uncertain facts and novel theories

John H. Cochrane

Over the last century, the these issues. I start with the statistical analysis
stock market in the United of past stock returns. The long-term average
States has yielded impressive return is in fact rather poorly measured. The
returns to its investors. For standard statistical confidence interval extends
example, in the postwar period, from 3 percent to 13 percent. Furthermore,
stock returns have averaged 8 percentage points average returns have been low following times
above Treasury bills. Will stocks continue to of high stock prices, such as the present. There-
give such impressive returns in the future? Are fore, the statistical evidence suggests a period
long-term average stock returns a fundamental of quite low average returns, followed by slow
feature of advanced industrial economies? Or are reversion to a poorly measured long-term average,
they the opposite of the old joke on Soviet agri- and it cautions us that statistical analysis alone
culture—100 years of good luck? If not pure leaves lots of uncertainty.
good luck, perhaps they result from features of Then, I survey economic theory to see if
the economy that will disappear as financial standard models that summarize a vast amount
markets evolve. of other information shed light on stock returns.
How does the recent rise in the stock mar- Standard models do not predict anything like
ket affect our view of future returns? Do high the historical equity premium. After a decade
prices now mean lower returns in the future? of effort, a range of drastic modifications to the
Or have stocks finally achieved Irving Fisher’s standard models can account for the historical
brilliantly mistimed 1929 prediction of a “per- equity premium. But it remains to be seen
manently high plateau?” If stocks have reached whether the drastic modifications and a high
a plateau, is it a rising plateau, or is the market equity premium, or the standard models and a
likely to bounce around its current level for many low equity premium will triumph in the end. In
years, not crashing but not yielding returns much sum, economic theory gives one further reason
greater than those of bonds? to fear that long-term average excess returns
These questions are on all of our minds as will not return to 8 percent, and it details the kind
we allocate our pension plan monies. They are of beliefs one must have about the economy to
also important to many public policy questions. reverse that pessimistic view.
For example, many proposals to reform social
security emphasize the benefits of moving to John H. Cochrane is the Sigmund E. Edelstone
a funded system based on stock market invest- Professor of Finance in the Graduate School of
Business at the University of Chicago and a con-
ments. But this is a good idea only if the stock sultant to the Federal Reserve Bank of Chicago.
market continues to provide the kind of returns His research is supported by a grant from the
in the future that it has in the past. National Science Foundation, administered by the
National Bureau of Economic Research, and by
In this article, I summarize the academic, the University of Chicago. The author would like
and if I dare say so, scientific, evidence on to thank George Constantinides, Andrea Eisfeldt,
and David Marshall for many helpful comments.

FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF CHICAGO 3


However, I conclude with a warning that productivity of capital) or impatience by con-
low average returns do not imply one should sumers. Such high productivity or impatience
change one’s portfolio. Someone has to hold would lead to high returns on bonds as well.
every stock on the market. An investor should To understand average stock returns, and to
only hold less stocks than average if that investor assess whether they will continue at these levels,
is different from the average investor in some it is not necessary to understand why the econ-
identifiable way, such as risk exposure, attitude, omy gives such high returns to saving—it
or information. doesn’t—but why it gives such high compensa-
tion for bearing risk. The risk is substantial.
Average returns and risk
A 17 percent standard deviation means the
The most obvious place to start thinking market is quite likely to decline 9 – 17 = 8%
about future stock returns is a statistical analysis or rise 9 + 17 = 26% in a year. (More precisely,
of past stock returns. there is about a 30 percent probability of a
Average real returns decline bigger than –8 percent or a rise bigger
Table 1 presents several measures of average than 26 percent.)
real returns on stocks and bonds in the postwar
Risk at short and long horizons
period. The value weighted NYSE portfolio
It is a common fallacy to dismiss this risk
shows an impressive annual return of 9 percent
as “short-run price fluctuation” and to argue that
after inflation. The S&P 500 is similar. The
stock market risk declines in the long run.
equally weighted NYSE portfolio weights
The most common way to fall into this trap
small stocks more than the value weighted
is to confuse the annualized or average return
portfolio. Small stock returns have been even
with the actual return. For example, the two-year
better than the market on average, so the equally
log or continuously compounded return is the
weighted portfolio has earned more than 11
sum of the one-year returns, r0→2 = r0→1+ r1→2 .
percent. Bonds by contrast seem a disaster.
Then, if returns were independent over time, like
Long-term government bonds earned only 1.8
coin flips, the mean and variance would scale the
percent after inflation, despite a standard devi-
same way with horizon: E(r0→2 ) = 2E(r0→1 )
ation (11 percent) more than half that of stocks
and σ2(r 0→2) = 2 σ2(r0→1 ). Investors who cared
(about 17 percent). Corporate bonds earned a
about mean and variance would invest the same
slight premium over government bonds, but at
fraction of their wealth in stocks for any return
2.1 percent are still unappealing compared to
horizon. The variance of annualized returns
stocks. Treasury bills earned only 0.8 percent
does stabilize; σ(1/2 r0→2) = 1/2 σ2 (r0→1). But
on average after inflation.
the investor cares about the total, not annual-
A reward for risk ized return. An example may clarify the dis-
Table 1 highlights a crucially important tinction. Suppose you are betting $1 on a coin
fact. High average returns are only earned as a flip. This is a risky bet, you will either gain or
compensation for risk. High stock returns can- lose $1. If you flip the coin 1,000 times, the aver-
not be understood merely as high “productivity age number of heads (annualized returns) will
of the American economy” (or high marginal almost certainly come out quite near 50 percent.

TABLE 1
Annual real returns 1947–96
VW S&P500 EW GB CB TB
(- - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - percent - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - -)

Average return E(R) 9.1 9.5 11.0 1.8 2.1 0.8


Standard deviation σ(R) 16.7 16.8 22.2 11.1 10.7 2.6
Standard error σ(R) / T 2.4 2.4 3.0 1.6 1.5 0.4
Notes: VW = value weighted NYSE, EW = equally weighted NYSE, GB = ten-year government bond,
CB = corporate bond, TB = three-month Treasury bills. All less CPI inflation.
Source: All data for this and subsequent figures and tables in this article are from the Center for Research
on Security Prices (CRSP) at the University of Chicago.

4 ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES
However, the risk of the bet (total return) is TABLE 2
much larger: It only takes an average number
How risk and return vary with
of heads equal to 0.499 (that is, 499/1,000) to investment horizon
lose a dollar; if the average number of heads is
0.490, still very close to 0.5, you lose $10. Just E (R e ) σ(R e ) 1 E (R e )
Horizon h
as we care about dollars, not the fraction of (years) h h h σ (R e )
heads, we care about total returns, not annual-
ized rates. 1 8.6 17.1 0.50
To address the short-run price fluctuation 2 9.1 17.9 0.51
fallacy directly, table 2 shows that mean returns 3 9.2 16.8 0.55
and standard deviations scale with horizon just 5 10.5 21.9 0.48
about as this independence argument suggests, e
Notes: R = value weighted return less T-bill rate.
out to five years. Column one shows average excess return divided
by horizon. Column two shows standard deviation
(In fact, returns are not exactly indepen- of excess return divided by square root of horizon.
Column three shows Sharpe ratio divided by square
dent over time. Estimates in Fama and French root of horizon. All statistics in percent.
[1988a] and Poterba and Summers [1988]
suggest that the variance grows a bit less slowly
than the horizon for the first five to ten years,
on substantial risk. What happens to a funded
and then grows with horizon as before, so
social security system if the market goes down?
stocks are in fact a bit safer for long horizons
than the independence assumption suggests. Means versus standard
However, this qualification does not rescue the deviations—Sharpe ratio
annualized return fallacy. Also bear in mind Figure 1 presents mean returns versus their
that long-horizon statistics are measured even standard deviations. In addition to the portfoli-
less well than annual statistics; there are only os listed in table 1, I include ten portfolios of
five nonoverlapping ten-year samples in the NYSE stocks sorted by size. This picture
postwar period.) shows that average returns alone are not a
The stock market is like a coin flip, but it particularly useful measure. By taking on more
is a biased coin flip. Thus, even though mean risk, one can achieve very high average re-
and variance may grow at the same rate with turns. In the picture, the small stock portfolio
horizon, the probability that one
loses money in the stock market
does decline over time. (For exam- FIGURE 1
ple, for the normal distribution, tail Mean vs. standard deviation of real returns, 1947–96
probabilities are governed by E(r)/ average return, percent
σ(r), which grows at the square 16
root of horizon.) However, portfolio
advice is not based on pure proba-
bilities of making or losing money; 12
but on measures such as the mean Equally weighted
and variance of return. Based on S&P500
Value weighted
such measures, there is not much 8
presumption that stocks are dramati-
cally safer for long-run investments.
I cannot stress enough that the 4
high average returns come only as Corporate bonds
compensation for risk. Our task Treasury bill Government bonds
below is to understand this risk and 0
people’s aversion to it. Many dis- 0 4 8 12 16 20 24 28 32
standard deviation of return, percent
cussions, including those surrounding
Notes: Triangles are equally weighted and value weighted NYSE; S&P 500;
the move to a funded social security three-month Treasury bill; ten-year government bond; and corporate bond
returns. Unmarked squares are NYSE size portfolios.
system, implicitly assume that one
gets the high returns without taking

FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF CHICAGO 5


earns over 15 percent per year average real standard errors for a variety of horizons.
return, though at the cost of a huge standard The confidence interval, mean +/–2 standard
deviation. Furthermore, one can form portfolios deviations, represents the 95 percent probability
with even higher average returns by leveraging— range. As the table shows, even very long-term
borrowing money to buy stocks—or investing averages leave a lot of uncertainty about mean
in securities such as options that are very sensi- returns. For example, with 50 years of data, an
tive to stock returns. Since standard deviation 8 percent average excess return is measured
(and beta or other risk measures) grow exactly with a 2.4 percentage point standard error. Thus,
as fast as mean return, the extra mean return the confidence interval says that the true aver-
gained in this way exactly corresponds to the age excess return is between 8 – 2 × 2.4 = 3%
extra risk of such portfolios. When considering and 8 + 2 × 2.4 = 13% with 95 percent proba-
economic models, it is easy to get them to bility.1 This is a wide band of uncertainty about
produce higher mean returns (along with higher the true market return, given 50 years of data.
standard deviations) by considering claims to One can also see that five- or ten-year averages
leveraged capital. are nearly useless; it takes a long time to sta-
In sum, excess returns of stocks over Trea- tistically discern that the average return has
sury bills are more interesting than the level of increased or decreased. As a cold winter need
returns. This is the part of return that is a com- not presage an ice age, so even a decade of bad
pensation for risk, and it accounts for nearly all returns need not change one’s view of the true
of the amazingly high average stock returns. underlying average return.
Furthermore, the Sharpe ratio of mean excess The standard errors are also the standard
return to standard deviation, or the slope of a deviations of average returns over the next T
line connecting stock returns to a risk-free years, and table 3 shows that there is quite a lot
interest rate in figure 1, is a better measure of of uncertainty about those returns. For example,
the fundamental characteristic of stocks than if the true mean excess return is and will con-
the mean excess return itself, since it is invari- tinue to be 8 percent, the five-year standard error
ant to leveraging. The stock portfolios listed in of 7.6 percent is almost as large as the mean. This
table 1 all have Sharpe ratios near 0.5. means that there is still a good chance that the
next five-year return will average less than the
Standard errors
Treasury bill rate.
The average returns and Sharpe ratios look
On the other hand, though the average
impressive. But are these true or just chance?
return on stocks is not precisely known, the 2.4
One meaning of chance is this: Suppose that the
percent standard error means that we can confi-
average excess return really is low, say 3 percent.
dently reject the view that the true mean excess
How likely is it that a 50-year sample has an
return was zero or even 2–3 percent. The argu-
average excess return of 8 percent? Similarly, if
ment that all the past equity premium was luck
the next 50 years are “just like” the last 50, in the
doesn’t hold up well against this simple statis-
sense that the structure of the economy is the same
tical argument.
but the random shocks may be different, what is
the chance that the average return in the next 50
years will be as good as it was in the last 50?
Since we only see one sample, these ques- TABLE 3
tions are really unanswerable at a deep level. Standard error of average return
Statistics provides an educated guess in the at various horizons
standard error. Assuming that each year’s Horizon T Standard error σ / T
return is statistically independent, our best (years) (percentage points)
guess of the standard deviation of the average
return is σ / T , where σ is the standard devia- 5 7.6
tion of annual returns and T is the data size. 10 5.4
This formula tells us something important: 25 3.8
Stock returns are so volatile that it is very hard 50 2.4
to statistically measure average returns. Table 1 Note: Returns assumed to be statistically
independent with standard deviation
includes standard errors of stock returns mea- σ = 17 percent.
sured in the last 50 years, and table 3 shows

6 ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES
Selection and crashes banking panics, no depressions, no civil wars,
Two important assumptions behind the no constitutional crises, the cold war was not
standard error calculation, however, suggest ways lost, and no missiles were fired over Berlin,
in which the postwar average stock return might Cuba, Korea, or Vietnam. If any of these things
still have been largely due to luck. Argentina had happened, there undoubtedly would have
and the U.S. looked very similar at the middle been a calamitous decline in stock values. The
of the last century. Both economies were un- statistical problem is nonnormality. Taking the
derdeveloped relative to Britain and Germany standard deviation from a sample that did not
and had about the same per capita income. If include rare calamities, and calculating average
Argentina had experienced the U.S.’s growth return probabilities from a normal distribution
and stock returns, and vice versa, this article may understate the true uncertainty. But inves-
would be written in Spanish from the Buenos tors, aware of that uncertainty, discount prices
Aires Federal Reserve Bank, with high Argentine and hence leave high returns on the table.
stock returns as the subject. We can cast the issue in terms of funda-
The statistical danger this story points to is mental beliefs about the economy. Was it clear
selection or survival bias. If you flip one coin to people in 1945 (or 1871, or whenever the
ten times, the chance of seeing eight heads is sample starts) and throughout the period that
low. But if you flip ten coins ten times, the the average return on stocks would be 8 percent
chance that the coin with the greatest number greater than that of bonds? If so, one would
of heads exceeds eight heads is much larger. expect them to have bought more stocks, even
Does this story more closely capture the 50-year considering the risk described by the 17 per-
return on U.S. stocks? Brown, Goetzmann, and cent year-to-year variation. But perhaps it was
Ross (1995) present a strong case that the uncer- not in fact obvious in 1945, that rather than
tainty about true average stock returns is much slipping back into depression, the U.S. would
larger than σ / T suggests. As they put it, experience a half century of growth never be-
“Looking back over the history of the London fore seen in human history. If so, much of the
or the New York stock markets can be extraor- equity premium was unexpected; good luck.
dinarily comforting to an investor—equities
appear to have provided a substantial premium Time varying expected returns
over bonds, and markets appear to have recov- Regressions of returns on price/dividend ratios
ered nicely after huge crashes. . . . Less com- We are not only concerned with the aver-
forting is the past history of other major mar- age return on stocks but whether returns are
kets: Russia, China, Germany, and Japan. Each expected to be unusually low at a time of high
of these markets has had one or more major prices, such as the present. The first and most
interruptions that prevent their inclusion in natural thing one might do to answer this ques-
long term studies” [my emphasis]. tion is to look at a regression forecast. To this
In addition, think of the things that didn’t end, table 4 presents regressions of returns on
happen in the last 50 years. There were no the price/dividend (P/D) ratio.

TABLE 4
OLS regressions of excess returns and dividend growth on VW P/D ratio
Rt→t+k = a + b(Pt /Dt) Dt+k/Dt = a + b(Pt/Dt)
Horizon k
(years) b σ( b ) R 2
b σ( b ) R2

1 –1.04 (0.33) 0.17 –0.39 (0.18) 0.07


2 –2.04 (0.66) 0.26 –0.52 (0.40) 0.07
3 –2.84 (0.88) 0.38 –0.53 (0.43) 0.07
5 –6.22 (1.24) 0.59 –0.99 (0.47) 0.15
Notes: Rt→t +k indicates the k year return on the value weighted NYSE portfolio less the k year
return from continuously reinvesting in Treasury bills; b = regression slope coefficient
(defined by the regression equation above); σ(b) = standard error of regression coefficient.
Standard errors in parentheses use GMM to correct for heteroscedasticity and serial correlation.

FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF CHICAGO 7


The regression at a one-year horizon analysis simple. In a similar fashion, cross-
shows that excess returns are in fact predictable sectional variation in expected returns can be
from P/D ratios, though the 0.17 R2 is not par- very well described by the P/D ratio or (better)
ticularly remarkable. However, at longer and the ratio of market value to book value, which
longer horizons, the slope coefficients increase contains the price in its numerator. Portfolios
and larger and larger fractions of return varia- of “undervalued” or “value” stocks with low
tion can be forecasted. At a five-year horizon, price ratios outperform portfolios of “overvalued”
60 percent of the variation in stock returns can or “growth” stocks with high price ratios. (See
be forecasted ahead of time from the P/D ratio. Fama and French, 1993).
(Fama and French, 1988b, is a famous early
Slow moving P/D and P/E
source for this kind of regression.)
Figure 2 presents P/D and price/earnings
One can object to dividends as the divisor
(P/E) ratios over time. This graph emphasizes
for prices. However, price divided by just
that price ratios are very slow moving variables.
about anything sensible works about as well,
This is why they forecast long-horizon move-
including earnings, book value, and moving
ments in stock returns.
averages of past prices. There seems to be an
The rise in forecast power with horizon is
additional business-cycle component of expected
not a separate phenomenon. It results from the
return variation that is tracked by the term spread
ability to forecast one period returns and the
or other business cycle forecasting variables,
slow movement in the P/D ratio.2 As an analogy,
including the default spread and investment–
if it is ten degrees below zero in Chicago (low
capital ratio, the T-bill rate, the ratio of the T-
P/D ratio), one’s best guess is that it will warm
bill rate to its moving average, and the dividend/
up a degree or so per day. Spring does come,
earnings ratio. (See Fama and French, 1989,
albeit slowly. However, the weather varies a lot;
for term and default spreads, Campbell, 1987,
it can easily go up or down 20 degrees in a day,
for term spread, Cochrane, 1991c, for investment–
so this forecast is not very accurate (low R2).
capital ratios, Lamont, 1997, for dividend/earn-
But the fact that it is ten degrees below zero
ings, and Ferson and Constantinides, 1991, for
signals that the temperature will rise a bit on
an even more exhaustive list with references).
average per day for many days. By the time we
However, price ratios such as P/D are the most
look at a six-month horizon, we forecast a 90
important forecasting variables, especially at long
degree rise in temperature. The daily variation
horizons, so I focus on the P/D ratio to keep the
of 20 degrees is still there, but the change in
temperature (90 degrees) that can
be forecasted is much larger
FIGURE 2
relative to the daily variation,
P/D and P/E ratios implying a high R2.
60 The slow movement in the
P/D ratio also means that the
2 x S&P500 ability to forecast returns is not
price/earnings ratio the fabled alchemists’ stone that
40 turns lead into gold. A high P/D
ratio means that prices will
grow more slowly than divi-
dends for a long time until the
P/D ratio is reestablished, and
20 VW price/dividend
ratio
vice versa. Trading on these
signals—buying more stocks in
times of low prices, and less in
times of high prices—can raise
0
1948 ’56 ’64 ’72 ’80 ’88 ’96 (unconditional) average returns
Notes: VW is value weighted NYSE portfolio. Two times the S&P 500 P/E
a bit, but not much more than
ratio is plotted so that the lines can be more easily compared. 1 percent for the same standard

8 ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES
deviation. If there were a 50 percent R2 at a the out-of-sample forecasts, I paired the regres-
daily horizon, one could make a lot of money; sions from table 4 with an autoregression of P/Dt,
but not so at a five-year horizon.
The slow movement of the P/D ratio also P Dt +1 = µ + ρ P D t + δ t +1 .
means that on a purely statistical basis, one can
cast doubt on whether the P/D ratio really Then, for example, since my data run
forecasts returns. What we really know, look- through the end of 1996, the forecast returns
ing at figure 2 (figure 4 also makes this point), for 1997 and 1998 are
is that low prices relative to dividends and
earnings in the 1950s preceded the boom mar-
E( R1997 ) = a + b( P D1996 )
ket of the early 1960s; that the high P/D ratios
of the mid-1960s preceded the poor returns of E( R1998 ) = a + b(µ + ρ P D1996 ),
the 1970s; and that the low price ratios of the
mid-1970s preceded the current boom. We also and so on.3
know that price ratios are very high now. In any The one-year return forecast is extraordi-
real sense, there really are three data points. I narily pessimistic. It starts at a –8 percent excess
do not want to survey the extensive statistical return for 1997, and only very slowly returns to
literature that formalizes this point, but it is the estimated unconditional mean excess return
there. Most importantly, it shows that the t-statis- of 8 percent. In ten years, the forecast is still –5
tics one might infer from regressions such as percent, in 25 years it is –1.75 percent, and it is
table 4 are inflated; with more sophisticated still only 2.35 percent in 50 years. The five-year
tests, return predictability actually has about a return forecasts are similarly pessimistic.
10 percent probability value before one starts Of course, this forecast is subject to lots
to worry about fishing and selection biases. of uncertainty. There is uncertainty about what
actual returns will be, given the forecasts. This
What about repurchases? P/E
and other forecasts will always be true: If one could precisely
Is the P/D ratio still a valid signal? Per- forecast the direction of stock prices, stocks
haps increasing dividend repurchases mean would cease to be risky and would cease to
that the P/D ratio will not return to its histori- pay a risk premium. There is also a great deal
cal low values; perhaps it has shifted to a new of uncertainty about the forecasts themselves.
mean so today’s high ratio is not
bad for returns. To address this
issue, figure 2 plots the S&P 500 P/E FIGURE 3
ratio along with the P/D ratio. The
Actual and forecast one-year excess returns
two measures line up well. The P/E
percent, one-year excess return
ratio forecasts returns almost as 50
well as the P/D ratio. The P/E ratio,
price/book value, and other ratios
are also at historic highs, forecasting
25
low returns for years to come. Yet
they are of course immune to the
criticism that the dividend–earnings
0
relationship might be fundamentally
different from the past.
Return forecasts -25
In-sample forecast
What do the regressions of table
Actual returns
4 say, quantitatively, about future Out-of-sample forecast
returns? Figure 3 presents one-year -50
returns and the P/D ratio forecast. 1950 ’60 ’70 ’80 ’90 2000 ’10 ’20
Figure 4 presents five-year returns Notes: One-year excess returns on the value weighted NYSE and
forecast from a regression on the P/D ratio. Returns are plotted on the
and the P/D ratio forecast. I include day of the forecast. For example, 1995 plots a + b × P/D 1995 and the
1996 return. The out-of-sample forecast is made by joining R t+1 = a + bP/Dt
in-sample and out-of-sample fore- with P/D t+1 = µ + ρP/D t.

casts in figures 3 and 4. To form

FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF CHICAGO 9


FIGURE 4 likely to vary a lot given the
forecast. Five-year returns track
Actual and forecast five-year excess returns
the forecast more closely, but
percent, five-year excess return
here the chance of over-fitting
180
In-sample forecast
is greater.
150 Actual returns To get a handle on how
Out-of-sample forecast reliable or robust the pessimistic
120
forecast is, figure 5 gives a
90 scatter plot of one-year returns
and their forecasts based on
60
P/D, together with the fitted
30 regression line. The scatterplot
indicates that the regression
0 results are not spurious, or the
-30
result of a few outlying years.
The point marked “97?” is
-60 the P/D ratio at the end of 1996
1950 ’60 ’70 ’80 ’90 2000 ’10 ’20
together with the forecast return
Notes: Five-year excess returns on value weighted NYSE (five-year returns
minus five-year T-bill returns) and forecast from a regression of five-year for 1997. We see immediately
returns on the P/D ratio. Returns are plotted on the last day; for example,
1996 plots the forecast a + b × P/D
1991
and the return from 1991 to 1996. one source of trouble with the
The out-of-sample forecast is formed for 1997–2001 from the observed
P/D ratios, 1992–96, and for 2002 onward from P/D = µ + 0.98 P/D .
point forecast: the P/D ratio has
t t–1

never in the postwar period been


as high as it is now. Extending
historical experience to never-
The forecasts attempt to measure expected before seen values is always dangerous. One is
returns, the quantity that investors must trade particularly uncomfortable with a prediction
off against unavoidable risk in deciding how that the market should earn less than the T-bill
attractive an investment is, and they undoubt- rate, given the strong theoretical presumption
edly measure expected returns with error. for a positive expected excess return.4 One
The plots of actual returns on top of the could easily draw a downward sloping line
in-sample, one-year-ahead forecasts in figures 3 through the points, flattening out on the right,
and 4 give one measure of the forecast uncertainty. predicting a zero excess return for P/D ratios
One can see that year-to-year returns are quite above 30 to 35, and never predicting a negative
excess return. A nonlinear re-
gression that incorporates this
FIGURE 5 idea will fit about as well as the
One-year excess returns vs. one-year ahead linear regression I have run.
forecast from P/D However, the scatterplot does
not demand such a nonlinear
excess return, percent
60 relation either, so this is largely
a matter of choice. In sum,
while the scatterplot does sug-
40
gest that the current forecast
95 should be low, it does not give
20
96
robust evidence that the forecast
excess return should be negative.
0
What about the last few years of
94 97? high returns?
-20 The P/D ratios also pointed
to low returns in 1995 and
1996. Anyone who took that
-40
10 15 20 25 30 35 40 45 advice missed out on a dramatic
price/dividend ratio surge in the market, and some
fund managers who took that

10 ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES
advice are now unemployed. Doesn’t this decline, or the P/D ratio must never return to its
mean that the P/D signal should no longer historical average. Which of the three options
be trusted? holds for our stock market?
To answer this criticism, look at the figures Historically, virtually all variation in P/D
again. They make clear that the returns for 1995 ratios has reflected varying expected returns.
and 1996 and even another 20 percent or so At a simple level, table 4 makes this point with
return for 1997 are not so far out of line, despite regressions of long-horizon dividend growth
a pessimistic P/D forecast, that we should throw on P/D ratios to match the regressions of returns
away the regression based on the previous 47 on P/D ratios. The dividend-growth coefficients
years of experience. To return to the analogy, are much smaller, typically one standard error
if it is ten degrees below zero in Chicago, that from zero, and the R2 values are tiny. Worse,
means spring is coming. But we can easily have the signs are wrong. To the extent that a high
a few weeks of 20 degree below weather before P/D ratio forecasts any change in dividends, it
spring finally arrives. The graphs make vivid seems to forecast a small decline in dividends.
how large a 17 percent standard deviation To be a little more precise, the identity
really is, and to what extent the forecasts based
on the P/D ratio mark long-term tendencies Pt +1 + Dt +1
+1 Rt +1 = Rt +1
1 = Rt–1 –1
that are still subject to lots of short-term swings Pt
rather than accurate forecasts of year-to-year
booms or crashes. yields, with a little algebra, the approximate
Another source of uncertainty about the identity
forecast is how persistent the P/D ratio really ∞
is. If, for example, the P/D ratio had no persis-
tence, then the low return forecast would only
1) p t − d t = const. + ∑ ρ j(∆ d t + j − r t + j) +
j =1
last a year. After that, it would return to the
unconditional mean of 9 percent (8 percent lim ρ j ( pt + j − d t + j ),
over Treasury bills). Now, given a true value j→∞
ρ = 0.98 in P/Dt = µ + ρP/D t-1 + δt, the median
ordinary least squares (OLS) estimate is 0.90, where ρ = P/D/(1 + P/D) is a constant of approxi-
as I found in sample. That is why figure 3 uses mation, slightly less than one and lowercase
the value ρ = 0.98. However, given this true letters denote logarithms (Campbell and Shiller,
value, the OLS estimate lies between 0.83 and 1988). Equation 1 gives a precise meaning to
0.94 only 50 percent of the time and between my earlier statement that a high P/D ratio must
0.66 and 1.00 for 95 percent of the time. Thus, be followed by high dividend growth ∆ d, low
there is a huge range of uncertainty over the true returns r, or a bubble.
value of ρ. The best thing that could happen to Bubbles do not appear to be the reason for
the forecast is if the P/D ratio were really less historical P/D ratio variation. Unless the P/D
persistent than it seems. In this case, the near- ratio grows faster than 1/ρ j, there is no bubble.
term return forecast would be unchanged, but It is hard to believe that P/D ratios can grow
the long-term return forecast would return to 9 forever. Empirically, P/D ratios do not seem
percent much more quickly. to have a trend or unit root over time. 5
This still leaves two possibilities: are high
Variance decomposition prices signals of high dividend growth or low
When prices are high relative to dividends returns? To address this issue, equation 1 implies6
(or earnings, cash flow, book value, or some
other divisor), one of three things must be ∞
true: 1) Investors expect dividends to rise in the 2) var ( pt − d t ) = cov( pt − d t , ∑ ρ j∆ d t + j ) −
future. 2) Investors expect returns to be low in the j =1

future. Future cash flows are discounted at a ∞

lower than usual rate, leading to higher prices. cov( pt − d t , ∑ ρ j rt + j ).


j =1
3) Investors expect prices to keep rising forever,
in a “bubble.” This is not a theory, it is an
P/D ratios can only vary if they forecast
accounting identity like 1=1: If the P/D ratio is
changing dividend growth or if they forecast
high, either dividends must rise, prices must

FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF CHICAGO 11


changing returns. Equation 2 has powerful growth: the P/D ratio is about double its long-
implications. At first glance, it would seem a term average, so the level of dividends has to
reasonable approximation that returns cannot be double, above and beyond its usual growth.
forecasted (the “random walk” hypothesis) and However, if this time is at all like the past, high
neither can dividend growth. But if this were prices reflect low future returns.
the case, the P/D ratio would have to be a con-
The bottom line
stant. Thus, the fact that the P/D ratio varies at
Statistical analysis suggests that the long-
all means that either dividend growth or returns
term average return on broad stock market
can be forecasted.
indexes is 8 percent greater than the T-bill rate,
This observation solidifies one’s belief in
with a standard error of about 3 percent. High
P/D ratio forecasts of returns. Yes, the statistical
prices are related to low subsequent excess
evidence that P/D ratios forecast returns is weak.
returns. Based on these patterns, the expected
But P/D ratios have varied. The choice is, P/D
excess return (stock return less T-bill rate) is
ratios forecast returns or they forecast dividend
near zero for the next five years or so, and then
growth. They have to forecast something. Given
slowly rising to the historical average. The large
this choice and table 3, it seems a much firmer
standard deviation of excess returns, about 17
conclusion that they forecast returns.
percent, means that actual returns will certainly
Table 5 presents some estimates of the
deviate substantially from the expected return.
price-dividend variance decomposition (equa-
Finally, one always gets more expected return
tion 2), taken from Cochrane (1991b). As one
by taking on more risk.
might suspect from table 4, table 5 shows that
in the past almost all variation in P/D ratios Economics: Understanding the
has been due to changing return forecasts. equity premium
(The rows of table 5 do not add up to exactly Statistical analysis of past returns leaves
100 percent because equation 2 is an approxi- a lot of uncertainty about future returns. Further-
mation. The elements do not have to be be- more, it is hard to believe that average excess
tween 0 and 100 percent. For example, –34, returns are 8 percent without knowing why
138 occurs because high prices seem to fore- this is so. Perhaps most important, no statistical
cast lower dividend growth. Therefore they analysis can predict if the future will be like
must and do forecast really low returns. The the past. Even if the true expected excess return
real and nominal rows differ because P/D fore- was 8 percent, did that result from fundamen-
casts inflation in the sample.) tal or temporary features of the economy?
So much for history. What does it mean? Thus, we need an economic understanding
Again, we live at a moment of historically of stock returns.
unprecedented P/D, P/E, and other multiples. Economic theory and modeling is often
Perhaps this time high prices reflect high long-run portrayed as an ivory tower exercise, out of
dividend growth. If so, the prices have to reflect touch with the real world. Nothing could be
an unprecedented expectation of future dividend further from the truth, especially in this case.
Many superficially plausible stories have been
put forth to explain the historically high return
TABLE 5 on stocks and the time-variation of returns.
Variance decomposition Economic models or theories make these stories
of VW P/D ratio explicit, check whether they are internally
consistent, see if they can quantitatively explain
Dividends Returns
stock returns, and check that they do not make
Real –34 138 wildly counterfactual predictions in other dimen-
Standard error (10) (32) sions, for example, requiring wild variation in
Nominal 30 85 risk-free rates or strong persistent movements
Standard error (41) (19) in consumption growth. Few stories survive
this scrutiny.
Notes: VW = value weighted NYSE. Table entries
are the percent of the variance of the price/dividend We have a vast experience with economic
ratio attributable to dividend and return forecasts, theory; a range of model economies have
100 × cov(pt–dt, Σ15 ρj ∆dt+j)/ var(pt–dt) and similarly
for returns.
j=1
formed the backbone of our understanding of

12 ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES
economic growth and dynamic micro, macro, relative constancy of real risk-free rates over
and international economics for close to 25 time and across countries, and the relatively
years. Does a large equity premium make sense low correlation of stock returns with consump-
in terms of such standard economics? Did people tion growth. This is a tough assignment, which
in 1947, and throughout the period, know that is only now starting to be accomplished.
stocks were going to yield 8 percent over bonds Then I survey alternative views that do
on average, yet were rationally unwilling to promise to account for the equity premium,
hold more stocks because they were afraid without (so far) wildly counterfactual predic-
of the 17 percent standard deviation or some tions on other dimensions. Each modification
other measure of stocks’ risk? If so, we have is the culmination of a decade-long effort by a
“explained” the equity premium. If so, statis- large number of researchers. (For literature
tics from the past may well describe the future, reviews, see Kocherlakota, 1996, and Cochrane
since neither people’s preferences nor the riski- and Hansen, 1992). The first model maintains
ness of technological opportunities seems to the complete and frictionless market simplifi-
have changed dramatically. But what if it makes cation, but changes the specification of how
no sense that people should be so scared of people feel about consumption over time, by
stocks? In this case, it is much more likely that adding habit persistence in a very special way
the true premium is small, and the historical that produces a strong precautionary saving
returns were in fact just good luck. motive. The second model abandons the perfect
The answer is simple: Standard economic markets simplification. Here, uninsurable indi-
models utterly fail to produce anything like the vidual-level risks are the key to the equity pre-
historical average stock return or the variation mium. I will also discuss a part of an emerging
in expected returns over time. After ten years view that the equity premium and time-variation
of intense effort, there is a range of drastic of expected returns result from the fact that few
modifications to standard models that can people hold stocks. This view is not flushed
explain the equity premium and return predict- out yet to a satisfactory model, but does give
ability and (harder still) are not inconsistent some insight.
with a few obvious related facts about con- Both modifications answer the basic ques-
sumption and interest rates. However, these tion, “why are consumers so afraid of stocks?”
models are truly drastic modifications; they in a similar way, and give a fundamentally
fundamentally change the description of the different answer from the standard model’s
source of risk that commands a premium in view that expected returns are driven by risks
asset markets. Furthermore, they have not yet to wealth or consumption. The modifications
been tested against the broad range of experi- both say that consumers are really afraid of
ence of the standard models. These facts must stocks because stocks pay off poorly in reces-
mean one of two things. Either the standard sions. In one case a recession means a time
models are wrong and will change drastically, when consumption has recently fallen, no matter
or the phenomenon is wrong and will disappear. what its level. In the second case a recession is
I first show how the standard model utterly a time of unusually high cross-sectional (though
fails to account for the historical equity premium not aggregate) uncertainty. In both cases the
(Sharpe ratio). The natural response is to see raw risk to wealth is not a particularly impor-
if perhaps we can modify the standard model. tant part of the story.
I consider what happens if we simply allow a
The standard model
very high level of risk aversion. The answer
To say anything about dynamic economics,
here, as in many early attempts to modify the
we have to say something about how people
standard model, is unsatisfactory. While one
are willing to trade consumption in one moment
can explain the equity premium, easy explana-
and set of circumstances (state of nature) for
tions make strongly counterfactual predictions
consumption in another moment and set of
regarding other facts. The goal is to explain the
circumstances. For example, if people were
equity premium in a manner consistent with the
always willing to give up a dollar of consump-
level and volatility of consumption growth (both
tion today for $1.10 in a year, then the economy
about 1 percent per year), the predictability of
would feature a steady 10 percent interest rate.
stock returns described above, the relative lack
It also might have quite volatile consumption,
of predictability in consumption growth, the

FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF CHICAGO 13


as people accept many such opportunities. If adds detail, including at least labor, leisure,
people did not care what the circumstances and shocks. To study monetary issues, one
were in which they would get $1.10, then all adds some friction that induces people to use
expected returns would be equal to the interest money, and so on.
rate (risk neutrality). Of course, this is an ex- Despite the outward appearance of tension,
treme example. There certainly comes a point this is a great unifying moment for macroeco-
at which such willingness to substitute con- nomics. Practically all issues relating to busi-
sumption becomes strained. If someone were ness cycles, growth, aggregate policy analysis,
going to consume $1,000 this year but $10,000 monetary economics, and international economics
next year, it might take a bit more than a 10 are studied in the context of variants of this
percent interest rate to get him or her to con- simple model. The remaining differences con-
sume even less this year. cern details of implementation.
To capture these ideas about people’s Since this basic economic framework
willingness to substitute consumption, we use explains such a wide range of phenomena, what
a utility function that gives a numerical “happi- does it predict for the equity risk premium? Give
ness” value for every possible stream of future the opportunity to buy assets such as stocks
consumption, and bonds to a consumer whose preferences
are described by equation 3, and figure out

3) U = E zt =0
e −ρt u(Ct )dt. what the optimal consumption and portfolio
decision is. (The appendix includes derivations
of all equations.) The following conditions
E denotes expectation; Ct denotes consumption describe the optimal choice:
at date t; ρ is the subjective discount factor;
and e–ρt captures the fact that consumers prefer
earlier consumption to later. The function u(⋅) 4) r f = ρ + γE( ∆c )
is increasing and concave, to reflect the idea
that people always like more consumption, but 5) E ( r ) − r f = γ cov ( ∆c, r ) =
at a diminishing rate. The function u(C) = C1–γ
γ σ ( ∆c )σ ( r ) corr( ∆c, r ),
is a common specification, with γ between 0
and 5. γ = 0 or u(C) = C corresponds to risk
neutrality, a constant interest rate ρ, and a where ∆c denotes the proportional change in
perfect willingness to substitute across time. consumption, r denotes a risky asset return, r f
γ = 1 corresponds to u(C) = ln(C), which is a denotes the risk-free rate, cov denotes covari-
very attractive choice since it implies that each ance, corr denotes correlation, and
doubling of consumption adds the same amount
Cu ′′(C )
of happiness. For most asset pricing problems, γ≡−
writing the utility function over an infinite u ′( C )
lifespan is a convenient simplification that is a measure of curvature or risk aversion.
makes little difference to the results. Economic Higher γ means that more consumption gives
models are often written in discrete time, in less pleasure very quickly; it implies that people
which case the utility function is are less willing to substitute less consumption

now for more consumption later and to take risks.
U = E ∑ e −ρt u(Ct ). Equation 5 expresses the most fundamental
t=0 idea in finance. It says that the average excess
return on any security must be proportional to
Dynamic economics takes this representa- the covariance of that return with marginal
tion of people’s preferences and mixes it with utility and, hence, consumption growth. This
a representation of technological opportunities is because people value financial assets that
for production and investment. For example, can be used to smooth consumption over time
the simplest model might specify that output is and in response to risks. For example, a “risky”
made from capital, Y = f(K), output is invested stock, one that has a high standard deviation
or consumed, Y = C+I, and capital depreciates σ(r), may nonetheless command no greater
but is increased by investment, Kt+1 = (1-δ)Kt + It average return E(r) than the risk-free rate if its
in discrete time. To study business cycles, one

14 ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES
return is uncorrelated with consumption growth (1985), as reinterpreted by Hansen and Jagan-
corr(∆c,r) = 0. If it yields any more, the consumer nathan (1991). The failure is quantitative not
can buy just a little bit of the security, and come qualitative, as Kocherlakota (1996) points out.
out ahead because the risk is perfectly diversifi- Qualitatively, the right-hand side of equation 6
able. Readers familiar with the capital asset does predict a positive equity premium. The
pricing model (CAPM) will recognize the intu- problem is in the numbers. This is a strong
ition; replacing wealth or the market portfolio advertisement for quantitative rather than just
with consumption gives the most modern and qualitative economics.
general version of that theory.
Can we change the numbers?
The equity premium puzzle The correlation of consumption growth
To evaluate the equity premium, I transform with returns is the most suspicious ingredient
equation 5 to in this calculation. While the correlation is
undeniably low in the short run, a decade-long
rise in the stock market should certainly lead to
E( r ) − r f
6) = γ σ ( ∆c ) corr ( ∆c, r ). more consumption. In fact, the low correlation
σ( r ) is somewhat of a puzzle in itself: Standard (one-
shock) models typically predict correlations of
The left-hand side is the Sharpe ratio. As I 0.99 or more. Marshall and Daniel (1997) find
showed above, the (unconditional) Sharpe ratio correlations in the data up to 0.4 at a two-year
is about 0.5 for the stock market, and it is robust horizon, and by allowing lags. But even plugging
to leveraging or choice of assets. The right-hand in a correlation of corr(∆c,r) = 1, σ(∆c) = 0.01
side of equation 6 says something very impor- and γ < 10 implies a Sharpe ratio less than 0.1, or
tant. A high Sharpe ratio or risk premium must one-fifth the sample value.
be the result of 1) high aversion to risk, γ, or 2) A large literature has tried to explain the
lots of risk, σ(∆c). Furthermore, it can only occur equity premium puzzle by introducing frictions
for assets whose returns are correlated with the that make T-bills “money-like,” which artifi-
risks. This basic message will pervade the follow- cially drive down the interest rate (for example,
ing discussion of much-generalized economic Aiyagari and Gertler, 1991). The highest Sharpe
models. If the right-hand side of equation 6 is ratio occurs in fact when one considers short-
low, then the consumer should invest more in term risk-free debt and money, since the latter
the asset with return r. Doing so will make the pays no interest. Perhaps the same mechanism
consumption stream more risky and more corre- can be invoked for the spread between stocks
lated with the asset return. Thus, as the consumer and bonds. However, a glance at figure 1 shows
invests more, the right-hand side of equation 6 that this will not work. High Sharpe ratios are
will approach the left-hand side. pervasive in financial markets. One can recover
The right-hand side of equation 6 is a pre- a high Sharpe ratio from stocks alone, or from
diction of what the Sharpe ratio should be. It stocks less long-term bonds.
does not come close to predicting the historical
equity premium. The standard deviation of Time-varying expected returns
aggregate consumption growth is about 1 percent The consumption-based view with
or 0.01. The correlation of consumption growth u′(C) = C-γ also has trouble explaining the fact
with stock returns is a bit harder to measure that P/D ratios forecast stock returns. Consider
since it depends on horizon and timing issues. the conditional version of equation 6
Still, for horizons of a year or so, 0.2 is a pretty
generous number. γ •1 or 2 is standard; γ = 10 Et ( r ) − rt f
is a very generous value. Putting this all together, 7) = γ σt ( ∆c) corr t ( ∆c, r),
σ t (r )
10 × 0.01 × 0.2 = 0.02 rather than 0.5. At a
20 percent standard deviation, a 0.02 Sharpe
ratio implies an average excess return for where Et, σt , corrt represent conditional moments.
stocks of 0.02 × 20 = 0.4% (40 basis points) I showed above that the P/D ratio gives a strong
rather than 8 percent. signal about mean returns, Et(r). It does not
This devastating calculation is the celebrated however give much information about the
“equity premium puzzle” of Mehra and Prescott standard deviation of returns. Figure 5 does
suggest a slight increase in return standard

FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF CHICAGO 15


deviation along with the higher mean return Highly curved power utility
when P/D ratios decline—the leverage effect Since we have examined all the other
of Black (1976). However, the increase in numbers on the right-hand side of equation 6,
standard deviation is much less than the increase perhaps we should raise curvature γ. This is a
in mean return. Hence, the Sharpe ratio of mean central modification. All of macroeconomics
to standard deviation varies over time and and growth theory considers values of γ no
increases when prices are low. larger than 2–3. To generate a Sharpe ratio of
How can we explain variation in the Sharpe 0.5, γ = 250 is needed in equation 6. Even if
ratio? Looking at equation 7, it could happen if corr = 1, γ must still equal 50. What’s wrong
there were times of high and low consumption with γ = 50 to 250? Although a high curvature
volatility, variation in σt(∆c). But that does not γ explains the equity premium, it runs quickly
seem to be the case; there is little evidence that into trouble with other facts.
aggregate consumption growth is much more
Consumption and interest rates
volatile at times of low prices than high prices.
The most basic piece of evidence for low γ
The conditional correlation of consumption
is the relationship between consumption growth
growth and returns could vary a great deal
and interest rates. Real interest rates are quite
over time, but this seems unlikely, or more
stable over time (see the standard deviation in
precisely like an unfathomable assumption
table 1) and roughly the same the world over,
on which to build the central understanding
despite wide variation in consumption growth
of time-varying returns.
over time and across countries. A value of γ = 50
What about the CAPM? to 250 implies that consumers are essentially
Finance researchers and practitioners often unwilling to substitute consumption over time;
express disbelief (and boredom) with consump- equivalently that variation in consumption
tion-based models such as the above. Even the growth must be accompanied by huge variations
CAPM performs better: Expected returns of in interest rates that we do not observe.
different portfolios such as those in figure 1 line Look again at the first basic relationship
up much better against their covariances with between consumption growth and interest
the market return than against their covariances rates, equation 4, reproduced here:
with consumption growth. Why not use the
CAPM or other, better-performing finance models rt f = ρ + γEt (∆c).
to understand the equity premium?
The answer is that the CAPM and related High values of γ are troublesome even in
finance models are useless for understanding the understanding the level of interest rates. Aver-
market premium. The CAPM states that the ex- age consumption growth and real interest rates
pected return of a given asset is proportional to its are both about 1 percent. Thus, γ = 50 to 250
“beta” times the expected return of the market, requires ρ = –0.5 to –2.5, or a –50 percent to
–250 percent subjective discount rate. That’s
E( Ri ) = R f + β i , m E( R m ) − R f . the wrong sign: People should prefer current
to future consumption, not the other way
This is fine if you want to think about an around (Weil, 1989).7
individual stock’s return given the market The absence of much interest rate variation
return. But the average market return—the across time and countries is an even bigger
thing we are trying to explain, understand, and problem. People save more and defer consump-
predict—is a given to the CAPM. Similarly, tion in times of high interest rates, so consump-
multifactor models explain average returns on tion growth rises when interest rates are higher.
individual assets, given average returns on However, γ = 50 means that a country with
“factor mimicking portfolios,” including the consumption growth 1 percentage point higher
market. Option pricing models explain option than normal must have real interest rates 50
prices, given the stock price. To understand the percentage points higher than normal, and
market premium, there is no substitute for eco- consumption 1 percentage point lower than
nomic models such as the consumption-based normal must have real interest rates 50 percent-
model outlined above and its variants. age points lower than normal, implying huge
negative interest rates—consumers pay financial

16 ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES
intermediaries 48 percent to keep their money. bet to avoid taking it. For example, in the low-
This just does not happen. er right-hand corner, the family with γ = 250
This observation can also be phrased as would rather pay $9,889 for sure than take a
a conceptual experiment, suitable for thinking 50 percent chance of a $10,000 loss. This predic-
about one’s own preferences or for survey tion is surely unreasonable, and has led most
evidence on others’ preferences. For example, authors to rule out risk aversion coefficients
what does it take to convince someone to skip over ten. Survey evidence for this kind of bet
a vacation? Take a family with $50,000 per year also finds low risk aversion, certainly below γ = 5
income, consumption equal to income, which (Barsky, Kimball, Juster, and Shapiro, 1997), and
spends $2,500 (5 percent) on an annual vaca- even negative risk aversion if the survey is taken
tion. If interest rates are good enough, though, in Las Vegas.
the family can be persuaded to skip this year’s Yet the results for small bets are not so unrea-
vacation and go on two vacations next year. sonable. The family might reasonably pay 5 cents
What interest rate does it take to persuade the to 25 cents to avoid a $10 bet. We are all risk
family to do this? The answer is ($52,500/ neutral for small enough bets. For small bets,
$47,500)γ – 1. For γ = 250 that is an interest
rate of 3 × 1011. For γ = 50, we still need an amount willing to pay to avoid bet size of bet
interest rate of 14,800 percent. I think most of ≈γ .
size of bet consumption
us would defer the vacation for somewhat
lower interest rates.
The standard use of low values for γ in Thus, for any γ, the amount one is willing
macroeconomics is also important for delivering to pay is an arbitrarily small fraction of the bet
realistic quantity dynamics in macroeconomic for small enough bets. For this reason, it is
models, including relative variances of invest- easy to cook numbers of conceptual experi-
ment and output, and for delivering reasonable ments like table 6 by varying the size of the bet
speeds of adjustment to shocks. and the presumed wealth of the family. Signifi-
cantly, I only used local curvature above; γ
Risk aversion represented the derivative γ = –Cu″(C)/u′(C).
Economists have also shied away from high In asking how much the family would pay to
curvature γ on the basis that people do not avoid a $10,000 bet, we are asking for the
seem that risk averse. After examining the response to a very, very non-local event.
argument, I conclude that there are fewer solid The main lesson of conceptual experiments
reasons to object to high risk aversion than to and laboratory and survey evidence of simple
object to high aversion to intertemporal substi- bets is that people’s answers to such questions
tution via the consumption-interest rate relation- routinely violate expected utility. This observa-
ships I examined above. tion lowers the value of this source of evidence
as a measurement of risk aversion. As a similar
Surveys and thought experiments cautionary note, Barsky et al. report that whether
Since Sharpe ratios are high for many an individual partakes in a wide variety of
assets, much analysis of risk aversion comes risky activities correlates poorly with the level
from simple thought experiments
rather than data. For example, how
much would a family pay per year TABLE 6
to avoid a bet that led with equal Amount family would pay to avoid an even bet
probability to a $y increase or de-
Risk aversion γ
crease in annual consumption for
the rest of their lives? Table 6 Bet 2 10 50 100 250
presents some calculations of how
$10 $0.00 $0.01 $0.05 $0.10 $0.25
much our family with $50,000 per
100 0.20 1.00 4.99 9.94 24
year of income and consumption
1,000 20 99 435 665 863
would pay to avoid various bets of
10,000 2,000 6,921 9,430 9,718 9,889
this form.8 For bets that are reason-
ably large relative to wealth, high γ Notes: I assume the family has a constant $50,000 per year
consumption and an even chance of winning or losing the
means that families are willing to indicated net, per year.
pay almost the entire amount of the

FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF CHICAGO 17


of risk aversion inferred from a survey. In the The Achilles heel of this calculation is the
end, surveys about hypothetical bets that are hidden simplifying assumption that returns are
far from the range of everyday experience are independent over time, so no variables other
hard to interpret. than wealth show up in VW. If this were the case,
consumption would move one-for-one with
Microeconomic evidence wealth, and σ(∆c) = σ(∆w). If wealth doubles
Microeconomic observations might be a and nothing else has changed, the consumer
more useful measure of risk aversion, that is, would double consumption. The calculation,
evidence from people’s actual behavior in their therefore, hides a model with the drastically
daily activities. For example, the numbers in counterfactual implication that consumption
table 6 could be matched with insurance data. growth has a 17 percent standard deviation!
People are willing to pay substantially more The fact that consumption has a standard
than actuarially fair values to insure against car deviation so much lower than that of stock
theft or house fires. What is the implied risk returns suggests that returns are not indepen-
aversion? But even if there are other markets dent over time (as is already known from the
whose prices reflect less risk aversion than return on P/D regressions) and/or that other
stocks, this leaves open the question: If people state variables must be important in driving
are risk-neutral in other markets, why do they stock returns. If some other state variable, z,
become risk averse in the stockbroker’s office? is allowed—representing subsequent expected
Perhaps the risk aversion people display in the returns, labor income, or some other measure
stock broker’s office should be the fact and the of a consumer’s overall opportunities—the
(possibly) low risk aversion displayed in other substitution VW(W,z) = uc(C) in equation 6 adds
offices should be the puzzle. another term to equation 8,
Portfolio calculations
A common calibration of risk aversion E (r ) − r f − WVWW
comes from simple portfolio calculations = σ( ∆w) corr ( ∆w, r )
σ( r ) VW
(see Friend and Blume, 1975). Following the
principle that the last dollar spent should give zWWz
+ σ(z ) corr (z, r ).
the same increase in happiness in any alterna- VW
tive use, the marginal value of wealth should
equal the marginal utility of consumption,9 The Sharpe ratio may be driven not by consum-
VW(W,.) = uc(C). Therefore, if we assume returns ers’ risk aversion and the wealth-riskiness of
are independent over time and no other vari- stocks, but by stocks’ exposure to other risks.
ables are important for the marginal value of In the current context, this observation just
wealth, VW(W), equation 6 can also be written as tells us that portfolio-based calibrations of risk
aversion do not work, because they implicitly
E ( r ) − r f − WVWW assume independent returns and, hence, con-
8) = σ( ∆w ) corr( ∆w, r ). sumption growth as volatile as returns. Below,
σ(r ) VW
I introduce plausible candidates for the variable z
that can help us to understand high Sharpe
The quantity –WWWW/VW is in fact a better ratios. The fact that consumption is so much
measure of risk aversion than –Cucc/uc, since it less volatile than shock returns indicates that
represents aversion to bets over wealth rather the other state variables must account for the
than bets over consumption; most bets observed bulk of the equity premium.
are paid off in dollars. For a consumer who Overall, the evidence against high risk
invests entirely in stocks, σ(∆w) is the standard aversion is not that strong, and it is at least a
deviation of the stock return and corr(∆w,r) = possibility to consider. This argument does not
1. To generate a Sharpe ratio of 0.5, it seems rescue the power utility model with γ = 50 to
that we only need risk aversion equal to 3, 250—that ship sank on the consumption-interest
rate shoals. However, other models with high
− WVWW 0.5 risk aversion can be contemplated.
= ≅ 3.
VW 0.17

18 ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES
New utility functions and state variables bad a representation of risk aversion. Maybe
If changing the parameter γ in u′(C) = C-γ a modification of preferences can disentangle
does not work, perhaps we need to change the the two attitudes.
functional form. Changing the form of u(C)
is not a promising avenue. As I have stressed State separability and leisure
by using a continuous time derivation, only the With the latter end in mind, Epstein and Zin
derivatives of u(C) really matter; hence quite (1989) started an avalanche of academic research
similar results are achieved with other functional on utility functions that relax state-separability.
forms. A more promising avenue is to consider The expectation E in the utility function of equa-
other arguments of the utility function, or tion 3 sums over states of nature, for example
nonseparabilities.
Perhaps how people feel about eating more U = prob(rain) × u(C if it rains) + prob(shine) ×
today is affected not just by how much they are u(C if it shines).
already eating, but by other things, such as how
much they ate yesterday or how much they “Separability” means that one adds utility
worked today. Then, the covariance of stock across states, so the marginal utility of con-
returns with these other variables will also sumption in one state is unaffected by what
determine the equity premium. Fundamentally, happens in another state. But perhaps the mar-
consumers use assets to smooth marginal utility. ginal utility of a little more consumption in the
Perhaps today’s marginal utility is related to sunny state of the world is affected by the level
more than just today’s consumption. of consumption in the rainy state of the world.
Such a modification is a fundamental change Epstein and Zin and Hansen, Sargent, and
in how we view stock market risk. For example, Tallarini (1997) propose recursive utility func-
perhaps more leisure raises the marginal utility tions of the form
of consumption. Stocks are then feared because
they pay off badly in recessions when employ-
ment is lower and leisure is higher, not because Ut = Ct1− γ + e − ρ f Et f −1 (Ut +1 ) .
consumers are particularly averse to the risk
that stocks decline per se. Formally, our funda- If f(x) = x, this expression reduces to power
mental equation 6 is derived from utility. These utility functions are not state-
separable, and do conveniently distinguish risk
Et (r ) − rt f = covt ( ∆uc , r ), aversion from intertemporal substitution among
other modifications. However, this research is
and substituting uc = ∂u(c)/∂c. If I substitute uc only starting to pay off in terms of plausible
= ∂u(c,x)/∂c instead, then uc will depend on models that explain the facts (Campbell, 1996,
other variables x as well as c, and is an example) so I will not review it here.
Perhaps leisure is the most natural extra
ucx variable to add to a utility function. It is not
E(r ) − r f = γ cov( ∆c, r ) + cov( x , r ). clear a priori whether more leisure enhances
uc
the marginal utility of consumption (why bother
buying a boat if you are at the office all day
Since the first covariance does not account for and cannot use it?) or vice versa (if you have to
much premium, we will have to rely heavily on work all day, it is more important to come
the latter term to explain the premium. home to a really nice big TV), but we can let
There is a practical aim to generalizing the the data speak on this matter. However, explicit
utility function as well. As illustrated in the versions of this approach have not been very
last section, one parameter γ did two things successful to date. (Eichenbaum, Hansen, and
with power utility: It controlled how much Singleton, 1988, for example). On the other
people are willing to substitute consumption hand, recent research has found that adding
over time (consumption and interest rates) and labor income growth as an extra ad-hoc factor
it controlled their attitudes toward risk. The can be useful in explaining the cross section of
choice γ = 50 to 250 was clearly a crazy repre- average stock returns (Jagannathan and Wang,
sentation of how people feel about consump- 1996; Reyfman, 1997). Though not motivated
tion variation over time, but perhaps not so

FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF CHICAGO 19


by an explicit utility function, the facts in Recall our fundamental equation 6 for the
this research may in the future be interpretable Sharpe ratio,
as an effect of leisure on the marginal utility
of consumption.
Et ( r ) − rt f
= γ t σ t ( ∆c ) corrt ( ∆c, r ).
Force of habit σ t (r )
Nonseparabilities over time have been more
useful in empirical work. Anyone who has had a High curvature γt means that the model can
large pizza dinner knows that yesterday’s con- explain the equity premium, and curvature that
sumption can have an impact on today’s appetite. varies over time, as consumption rises
Might a similar mechanism apply over a longer in booms and falls toward habit in recessions,
time horizon? Perhaps people get accustomed means that the model can explain a time-varying
to a standard of living, so a fall in consumption and countercyclical (high in recessions, low in
hurts after a few years of good times, even though booms) Sharpe ratio, despite constant con-
the same level of consumption might have seemed sumption volatility, σt(∆c), and correlation,
very pleasant if it arrived after years of bad times. corrt(∆c,r).
This view at least explains the perception that So far so good, but doesn’t raising curva-
recessions are awful events, even though a ture imply high and time-varying interest rates?
recession year may be just the second or third In the Campbell-Cochrane model, the answer
best year in human history rather than the abso- is no. The reason is precautionary saving. Sup-
lute best. Law, custom, and social insurance pose times are bad and consumption is low
insure against falls in consumption as much as relative to habit. People want to borrow against
low levels of consumption. future, higher consumption and this should
Following this idea, Campbell and Cochrane drive up interest rates. However, people are
(1997) specify that people slowly develop habits also much more risk averse in bad times; they
for higher or lower consumption. Technically, want to save more in case tomorrow might be
they replace the utility function u(C) with even worse. These two effects balance.
The precautionary saving motive also
9) u( C − X ) = ( C − X )1− η , makes the model more plausibly consistent
with variation in consumption growth across
where X represents the level of habits. In turn, time and countries. The interest rate in the
habit X adjusts slowly to the level of consump- model adds a precautionary savings motive
tion.10 (I use the symbol η for the power, because term to equation 4,
curvature and risk aversion no longer equal η.)
This specification builds on a long tradition in
1 η
2
the microeconomic literature (Duesenberry, 1949, r f = ρ + ηE( ∆c ) − F I σ 2 ( ∆c),
and Deaton, 1992) and recent asset-pricing litera- 2 SH K
ture (Constantinides, 1990; Ferson and Constan- –
tinides, 1991; Heaton, 1995; and Abel, 1990). where S denotes the steady state value of
When a consumer has such a habit, local (C–X)/C, about 0.05. The power coefficient,
curvature depends on how far consumption is η = 2, controls the relationship between con-
above the habit, as well as the power η, sumption growth and interest rates, while the
curvature coefficient, γ = η C/(C–X), controls
the risk premium. Thus, this habit model allows
− Ct ucc Ct
γt ≡ =η . high risk aversion with low aversion to inter-
uc Ct − Xt temporal substitution and is consistent with
the consumption and interest rate data and a
As consumption falls toward habit, people sensible value of ρ.
become much less willing to tolerate further Campbell and Cochrane create a simple
falls in consumption; they become very risk artificial economy with these preferences.
averse. Thus, a low power coefficient η Consumption growth is independent over time
(Campbell and Cochrane use η = 2) can still and real interest rates are constant. They calcu-
mean a high and time-varying curvature. late time series of stock prices and interest rates

20 ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES
in the artificial economy and subject them to Habit models with low risk aversion
the standard statistical analysis reviewed above. The individuals in the Campbell-Cochrane
The artificial data replicate the equity premium model are highly risk averse. They would respond
(0.5 Sharpe ratio). The ability to forecast returns to surveys about bets on wealth much as the
from the P/D ratio and the P/D variance decom- γ = 50 column of table 6. The model does not
position are both quite like the actual data. The give rise to a high equity premium with low
standard deviation of returns rises a bit when risk aversion; it merely disentangles risk aver-
prices decline, but less than the rise in mean sion and intertemporal substitution so that a
returns, so a low P/D ratio forecasts a higher high risk aversion economy can be consistent
Sharpe ratio. Artificial data from the model with low and constant interest rates, and it
also replicate much of the low observed correla- generates the predictability of stock returns.
tion between consumption growth and returns, Constantinides (1990) and Boldrin,
and the CAPM and ad-hoc multifactor models Christiano, and Fisher (1995) explore habit
perform better than the power utility consump- persistence models that can generate a large
tion-based model in the artificial data. equity premium without large risk aversion.
The model also provides a good account That is, they create artificial economies in
of P/D fluctuations over the last century, based which consumers simultaneously shy away
entirely on the history of consumption. Howev- from stocks with a very attractive Sharpe ratio
er, it does not account for the currently high of 0.5, yet would happily take bets with much
P/D ratio. This is because the model generates lower rewards.
a high P/D ratio when consumption is very Suppose a consumer wins a bet or enjoys
high relative to habit and, therefore, risk aver- a high stock return. Normally, the consumer
sion is low. Measured consumption has been would instantly raise consumption to match
increasing unusually slowly in the 1990s. the new higher wealth level. But consumption
Like other models that explain the equity is addictive in these models: Too much current
premium and return predictability, this one consumption will raise the future habit level
does so by fundamentally changing the story and blunt the enjoyment of future consumption.
of why consumers are afraid of holding stocks. Therefore, the consumer increases consumption
From equation 9, the marginal utility of con- slowly and predictably after the increase in
sumption is proportional to wealth. Similarly, the consumer would borrow
to slowly decrease consumption after a decline
−η in wealth, avoiding the pain of a sudden loss at
uc = Ct− η
FG C − X IJ
t t
. the cost of lower long-term consumption.
H C K t The fact that the consumer will choose to
spread out the consumption response to wealth
shocks means that the consumer is not averse
Thus, consumers dislike low consumption
to wealth bets. If consumption responds little
as before, but they are also afraid of recessions,
to a wealth shock, then marginal utility of
times when consumption, whatever its level, is
consumption, uc(C), also responds little, as does
low relative to the recent past as described by
the marginal value of wealth, VW (W,⋅) = uc. Risk
habits. Consumers are afraid of holding stocks
aversion to wealth bets is measured by the
not because they fear the wealth or consumption
change of marginal utility when wealth changes
volatility per se, but because bad stock returns
(∂ln VW /∂lnW = –WVWW /VW).
tend to happen in recessions, times of a recent
The argument is correct, but shows the
belt-tightening.
problem with these models. The change in
This model fulfills a decade-long search
consumption in response to wealth is not elimi-
kicked off by Mehra and Prescott (1985). It is
nated, it is simply deferred. Thus, these models
a complete-markets, frictionless economy that
have trouble with long-run behavior of con-
replicates not only the equity premium but also
sumption and asset returns.
the predictability of returns, the nearly constant
If consumption growth is considered inde-
interest rate, and the near-random walk behavior
pendent over time (formally, an endowment
of consumption.
economy), which is a good approximation to
the data, the model must feature strong interest

FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF CHICAGO 21


rate variation to keep consumers from trying to candidates for extra state variables are vari-
adapt consumption smoothly to wealth shocks. ables that describe changes in expected returns.
For example, consumers all want to save if If stock prices rise, the consumer learns some-
wealth goes up, thereby slowly increasing thing important that is not learned from winning
consumption. For consumption growth to remain a bet: The consumer learns that future stock
unpredictable, we must have a strong decline returns are going to be lower. The trouble is
in the interest rate at the same time as the wealth the sign of this relationship. Lower returns in
increase. Of course, interest rates are in fact the future are bad news.11 Stocks act as a hedge
quite stable and, if anything, slightly positively for this bad news; they go up just at the time
correlated with stock returns. one gets bad news about future returns. This
Alternatively, interest rates may be fixed consideration makes stocks more desirable than
to be constant over time as in Constantinides pure bets. Thus, considering time variation in
(1990) (formally, linear technologies). But expected returns requires even more risk aver-
then there is no force to stop consumers from sion to explain the equity premium.
slowly and predictably raising consumption
after a wealth shock. Thus, such models predict Consistency with individual
consumption behavior
counterfactually that consumption growth is
The low risk aversion models face one
positively auto-correlated over time, and that
more important hurdle: microeconomic data.
long-run consumption growth shares the high
Suppose an individual receives a wealth shock
volatility of long- and short-run wealth.
(wins the lottery), not shared by everyone else.
The Campbell-Cochrane habit model
For aggregate wealth shocks, we could appeal
avoids these long-run problems with precau-
to interest rate variation to avoid the prediction
tionary savings. In response to a wealth shock,
that consumption would grow slowly and pre-
consumers with the Campbell-Cochrane version
dictably. However, interest rates can’t change
of habit persistence would also like to save
in response to an individual wealth shock.
more for intertemporal substitution reasons,
Thus, we are stuck with the prediction that the
but they also feel less risk averse and so want
individual’s consumption will increase slowly
to save less for precautionary savings reasons.
and predictably. The huge literature on individ-
The balance means that consumption can be a
ual consumption (see Deaton, 1992, for survey
random walk with constant interest rates, con-
and references) almost unanimously finds the
sistent with the data. However, it means that
opposite. People who receive windfalls consume
consumption does move right away, so uc and
too much, too soon, and have typically spent it
VW are affected by the wealth shock, and the
all in a few years. The literature abounds with
consumers are highly risk averse. In this model,
“liquidity constraints” to explain the “excess
wealth (stock prices) comes back toward con-
sensitivity” of consumption. The Campbell-
sumption after a shock, so that long-run wealth
Cochrane model avoids the prediction of slowly
shares the low volatility of long- and short-run
increasing consumption by specifying an external
consumption, and high stock prices forecast
habit; each person’s habit responds to everyone
low subsequent returns.
else’s consumption, related to the need to
A finance perspective “keep up with the Joneses,” as advocated by
To get a high equity premium with low Abel (1990). Though the external specification
risk aversion, we need to find some crucial has little impact on aggregate consumption and
characteristic that separates stock returns from prices, it means that individual consumption
wealth bets. This is a difficult task. After all, responds fully and immediately to individual
what are stocks if not a bet? The answer must wealth shocks, because there is no need for
be some additional state variable. Having a individuals to worry about habit formation.
stock pay off badly must tell you additional The downside is, again, high risk aversion.
bad news that losing a bet does not; therefore, In the end, there is currently no representa-
people shy away from stocks even though they tive agent model with low risk aversion that is
would happily take a bet with the same mean consistent with the equity premium, the stability
and variance. of real interest rates, nearly unpredictable con-
In the context of perfect-markets models sumption growth, and return predictability of
without leisure or other goods, the only real the correct sign.

22 ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES
Heterogeneous agents and the much more variable purchases of durable
idiosyncratic risks goods, such as cars and houses.
In the above discussion, I did not recog- More fundamentally, the addition of idio-
nize any difference between people. Everyone syncratic risk lowers the correlation between
is different, so why bother looking at represen- consumption growth and returns, which lowers
tative agent or complete market models? While the predicted Sharpe ratio. Idiosyncratic risk is,
making an assumption such as “all people are by its nature, idiosyncratic. If it happened to
identical” seems obviously foolish, it is not everyone, it would be aggregate risk. Idiosyn-
foolish to hope that we can use aggregate cratic risk cannot therefore be correlated with
behavior to make sense of aggregate data, the stock market, since the stock market return
without explicitly taking account of the differ- is the same for everyone.
ences between people. While differences are For a quantitative example, suppose that
there, one hopes they are not relevant to the individual consumption of family i, ∆c i, is deter-
basic story. However, seeing the difficulties mined by aggregate consumption, ∆c a, and idio-
that representative agent models face, perhaps syncratic shocks (such as losing your job), ε i,
it is time to see if the (aggregate) equity premium
does in fact surface from differences between
∆c i = ∆c a + ε i .
people rather than common behavior.
The empirical hurdle For the risk ε i to average to zero across people,
Idiosyncratic risk explanations face a big we must have E(ε i ) = 0 and E(ε i∆ca) = E(εir)
empirical challenge. Look again at the basic = 0. Then, the standard deviation of individual
Sharpe ratio equation 6, consumption growth does increase with the
size of idiosyncratic risk,
E( r ) − r f
= γ σ(∆c) corr ( ∆c, r ).
σ( r ) σ 2 (∆c i ) = σ 2 ( ∆c a ) + σ 2 (ε i ).

This relationship should hold for every (any) But the correlation between individual con-
consumer or household. At first sight, thinking sumption growth and aggregate returns de-
about individuals seems promising. After all, clines in exact proportion as the standard devi-
individual consumption is certainly more vari- ation σ(∆ci) rises,
able than aggregate consumption at 1 percent
per year, so we can raise σ(∆c). However, this E (r ) − r f cov ( ∆c a + ε i , r ) cov( ∆c a , r )
argument fails quantitatively. First, it is incon- =γ =γ .
σ( r ) σ( r ) σ( r )
ceivable that we can raise σ(∆c) enough to
account for the equity premium. For example,
even if individual consumption has a standard Therefore, the equity premium is completely
deviation of 10 percent per year, and maintain- unaffected by idiosyncratic risk.
ing a generous limit γ < 10, we still predict a The theoretical hurdles
Sharpe ratio no more than 10 × 0.1 × 0.2 = 0.2. The theoretical challenge to idiosyncratic
To explain the 0.5 Sharpe ratio with risk aver- risk explanations is even more severe. We can
sion γ = 10, we have to believe that individual easily construct models in which consumers
consumption growth has a 25 percent per year are given lots of idiosyncratic income risk.
standard deviation; for a more traditional γ = 2.5, But it is very hard to keep consumers from
we need 100 percent per year standard devia- insuring themselves against those risks, pro-
tion. Even 10 percent per year is a huge standard ducing a very steady consumption stream and
deviation of consumption growth. Remember, a low equity premium.
we are considering the risky or uncertain part of Start by handing out income to consum-
consumption growth. Predictable increases or ers; call it “labor income” and make it risky
decreases in consumption due to age and life- by adding a chance of being fired. Left to
cycle effects, expected raises, and so on do not their own devices, consumers would come
count. We are also thinking of the flow of up with unemployment insurance to share
consumption (nondurable goods, services) not this risk, so we have to close down or limit
markets for labor income insurance. Then,

FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF CHICAGO 23


consumers who lose their jobs will borrow be traded away. In addition, if marginal utility
against future income to smooth consumption were linear, an increase in variance would have
over the bad times, achieving almost the same no effect on the average level of marginal utili-
consumption smoothness. We must shut down ty. The interaction of cross-sector variance
these markets too. correlated with the market and nonlinear mar-
However, nothing stops our borrowing- ginal utility produces an equity premium.
constrained consumers from saving. They build The Constantinides-Duffie model and the
up a stock of durable goods, government Campbell-Cochrane model are quite similar in
bonds, or other liquid assets that they can draw spirit, though the Constantinides-Duffie model
down in bad times and again achieve a very is built on incomplete markets and idiosyncratic
smooth consumption stream (Telmer, 1993, risks, while the Campbell-Cochrane model is
and Lucas, 1994). To shut down this avenue in the representative-agent frictionless and
for consumption-smoothing, we can introduce complete market tradition.
large transactions costs and ban from the model First, both models make a similar, funda-
the simple accumulation of durable goods. mental change in the description of stock market
Alternatively, we can make idiosyncratic risk. Consumers do not fear the loss of wealth
shocks permanent, because borrowing and saving of a bad market return so much as they fear a
can only insure against transitory income. If bad return in a recession, in one model a time
losing your job means losing it forever, there of heightened labor market risk and in the other
is no point in borrowing and planning to pay it a fall of consumption relative to the recent past.
back when you get a new job. This recession state variable or risk factor drives
Heaton and Lucas (1996a) put all these most expected returns.
ingredients together, calibrating the persistence Second, both models require high risk aver-
of labor income shocks from microeconomic sion. While Constantinides and Duffie’s proof
data. They also allow the cross-sectional variance shows that one can dream up a labor income
of shocks to increase in a downturn, a very process to rationalize the equity premium for any
helpful ingredient suggested by Mankiw (1986) risk aversion coefficient, I argue below that even
that I discuss in detail in the next section. Despite vaguely plausible characterizations of actual
all of these ingredients, their model explains at labor income uncertainty will require high risk
best one-half of the observed excess average aversion to explain the historical equity premium.
stock return (and this much only with no net Third, both models provide long-sought
debt). It also predicts counterfactually that demonstrations that it is possible to rationalize
interest rates are as volatile as stock returns, the equity premium in their respective class
and that individuals have huge (10 percent to 30 of models. This is particularly impressive
percent, depending on specification) consump- in Constantinides and Duffie’s case. Many
tion growth uncertainty. researchers (myself included) had come to the
conclusion that the effort to generate an equity
A model that works
premium from idiosyncratic risk was hopeless.
Constantinides and Duffie (1996) con-
The open question in both cases is empirical.
struct a model in which idiosyncratic risk can
The stories are consistent; are they right? For
be tailored to generate any pattern of aggregate
Constantinides and Duffie, does actual individ-
consumption and asset prices; it can generate
ual labor income behave as their model requires
the equity premium, predictability, relatively
in order to generate the equity premium? The
constant interest rates, smooth and unpredict-
empirical work remains to be done, but here
able aggregate consumption growth, and so
are some of the issues.
forth. Furthermore, it requires no transactions
costs, borrowing constraints, or other frictions, A simple version of the model
and the individual consumers can have any Each consumer i has power utility,
nonzero value of risk aversion.
As mentioned earlier, if consumers are
given idiosyncratic income that is correlated U = E ∑ e −ρt Cit1− γ .
t
with the market return, they will trade away
that risk. Constantinides and Duffie therefore Individual consumption growth, Cit, is deter-
specify that the variance of idiosyncratic risk mined by an independent, idiosyncratic normal
rises when the market declines. Variance cannot (0,1) shock, η it,

24 ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES
where m t is a strictly positive discount factor13
F C I=η y −1y
10) ln G it 2 that prices all assets under consideration. That
H C JK
i ,t −12
it t t ,
is, mt satisfies

where yt is the cross-sectional standard devia- 14) 1 = Et −1 mt Rt for all Rt .


tion of consumption growth at any moment in
time. yt is specified so that a low market return, Then, they let
Rt, gives a high cross-sectional variance of
consumption growth,
Cit = δ it Cit

L F C I R OP LM
δit = δ it −1 exp ηit yt −
1 2
yt . OP
11) y = σ Mln G it N 2 Q
t
MN H C JK PQ
it −1
t

Following exactly the same argument in the


2 1
= ln + ρ . text, we can now show that
γ (γ +1) Rt
LM F C I −γ OP
1 = Et −1 e −ρ
MN GH C JK
it
Since ηit determines consumption growth, Rt +1
the idiosyncratic shocks are permanent, which
it −1 PQ
I argued above was important to keep consumers
from smoothing them away. for all the assets priced by m.
Given this structure, the individual is
exactly happy to consume Cit and hold the Microeconomic evaluation and risk aversion
stock (we can call Cit income Iit and prove the Like the Campbell-Cochrane model, this
optimal decision rule is to set Cit = Iit.). The model could be either a new view of stock
first-order condition for an optimal consump- market (and macroeconomic) risk or just a
tion-portfolio decision theoretically interesting existence proof. The
first question is whether the microeconomic
picture painted by this model is correct, or even
LM F C I −γ OP plausible. Is idiosyncratic risk large enough?
1 = Et −1 e −ρ
MN GH C JK
it
Rt +1 Does idiosyncratic risk really rise when the
it −1 PQ market falls, and enough to account for the
equity premium? Do people really shy away
holds, exactly.12 from stocks because stock returns are low at
times of high labor market risk?
The general model This model does not change the empirical
The actual Constantinides-Duffie model puzzle discussed earlier. To get power utility
is much more general than the above example. consumers to shun stocks, they still must have
They show that the idiosyncratic risk can be tremendously volatile consumption growth or
constructed to price exactly a large collection high risk aversion. The point of this model is to
of assets, not just one return as in the example, show how consumers can get stuck with high
and they allow uncertainty in aggregate con- consumption volatility in equilibrium, already
sumption. Therefore, they can tailor the idio- a difficult task.
syncratic risk to exactly match the Sharpe More seriously than volatility itself, con-
ratio, return forecastability, and consumption- sumption growth variance also represents the
interest rate facts as outlined above. amount by which the distribution of individual
In the general model, Constantinides and consumption and income spreads out over time,
Duffie define since the shocks must be permanent and inde-
pendent across people. The 10 percent to 50
2 C percent volatility (σ(∆c)) that is required to
12) yt = ln mt + ρ + γ ln t , reconcile the Sharpe ratio with low risk aver-
γ ( γ + 1) Ct −1
sion means that the distribution of consump-
tion (and income) must also spread out by 10
percent to 50 percent per year.

FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF CHICAGO 25


Constantinides and Duffie show how to return and risk aversion in my simple version
avoid the implication that the overall distribu- of Constantinides and Duffie’s model. If we
tion of income spreads out, by limiting inherit- insist on low (γ = 1 to 2) risk aversion, the
ance and repopulating the economy each year cross-sectional standard deviation of consump-
with new generations that are born equal. But tion growth must be extremely sensitive to the
the distribution of consumption must still spread level of the market return. Looking at the γ = 2
out within each generation to achieve the equity line for example, is it plausible that a year with
premium with low risk aversion. Is this plausi- 5 percent market return would show a 10 percent
ble? Deaton and Paxson (1994) report that the cross-sectional variation in consumption
cross-sectional variance of log consumption growth, while a mild 5 percent decline in the
within an age cohort rises from about 0.2 at market is associated with a 25 percent cross-
age 20 to 0.6 at age 60. This means that the sectional variation?
cross-sectional standard deviation of consump- The Heaton and Lucas (1996a) model can
tion rises from 0.2 = 0.45 or 45 percent at age be regarded as an empirical assessment of these
20 to 0.6 = 0.77 or 77 percent at age 60 (77 issues. Rather than constructing a labor income
percent means that an individual one standard process that generates an equity premium, they
deviation better off than the mean consumes calibrated the labor income process from
77 percent more than the mean consumer). microeconomic data. They found less persis-
This works out to about 1 percent per year, tence and less increase in cross-sectional varia-
not 10 percent or so. tion with a low market return than specified by
Finally, the cross-sectional uncertainty Constantinides and Duffie, which is why their
about individual income must not only be model predicts a low equity premium with low
large, it must be higher when the market is risk aversion. Of course, this view is at best
lower. This risk factor is after all the central preliminary evidence. They did not test the
element of Constantinides and Duffie’s expla- exact Constantinides-Duffie specification as a
nation for the market premium. Figure 6 shows special case, nor did they test whether one can
how the cross-sectional standard deviation of reject the Constantinides-Duffie specification.
consumption growth varies with the market All of these empirical problems are avoided
if we allow high risk aversion
rather than a large risk to drive
FIGURE 6 the equity premium. The γ = 25
line in figure 6 looks possible; a
Cross-sectional standard deviation of
consumption growth γ = 50 line would look even
better. With high risk aversion,
standard deviation, percent
60
we do not need to specify highly
γ=1 volatile individual consumption
growth, spreading out of the
45
income distribution, or dramatic
sensitivity of the cross-sectional
variance to the market return. As
γ=2
30
in any model, a high equity
premium must come from a
large risk, or from large risk
γ=5 aversion. Labor market risk
15
γ = 10 correlated with the stock market
γ = 25 does not seem large enough to
0 account for the equity premium
-25 -20 -15 -10 -5 0 5 10 15 20 25
without high risk aversion.
market return, percent

Notes: Cross-sectional standard deviation of individual consumption growth Segmented markets


as a function of the market return in the Constantinides-Duffie model.
All these models try to
2 1 Ct
The plot is the variable y t = ln + ρ + γ ln . Parameter answer the basic question, if
γ (γ + 1) Rt Ct −1
values are ρ = 0.05, ln C t /C t–1 = 0.01, and γ and ln Rt+1 as graphed. stocks are so attractive, why
have people not bought more of

26 ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES
them? So far, I have tried to find representations If these segmented market views of the
of people’s preferences or circumstances, or a past equity premium are correct, they suggest
description of macroeconomic risk, in which that the future equity premium will be much
stocks aren’t that attractive after all. Then the lower. Transaction costs are declining through
high Sharpe ratio is a compensation for risk. financial deregulation and innovation. The
Instead, we could argue that stocks really explosion in tax-deferred pension plans and
are attractive, but a variety of market frictions no-load mutual funds means more and more
keep people from buying them. This approach people own stocks, spreading risks more evenly,
yields some important insights. First of all, driving up prices, and driving down prospective
stock ownership has been quite concentrated. returns. Equation 6 will hold much better for the
The vast majority of American households have average consumer in the future. One would expect
not directly owned any stock or mutual funds. to see a lower equity premium. One would also
One might ask whether the consumption of expect consumption that is more volatile and
people who do own stock lines up with stock more closely correlated with the stock market,
returns. Mankiw and Zeldes (1991) find that which will result in a fundamental change in the
stockholders do have consumption that is more nature and politics of business cycles.
volatile and more correlated with stock returns
Technology and investment
than non-stockholders. But it is still not volatile
and correlated enough to satisfy the right-hand So far, I have tried to rationalize stock
side of equation 6 with low risk aversion. returns from the consumer’s point of view:
Heaton and Lucas (1996b) look at individual Does it make sense that consumers should not
asset and income data. They find that the richest have tried to buy more stocks, driving stock
households, who own most of the stocks, also returns down toward bond returns? I can ask
get most of their income from proprietary the same questions for the firm: Do firms’
business income. This income is likely to be investment decisions line up with stock prices
more correlated with the stock market than is as they should?
individual labor income. Furthermore, they The relative prices of apples and oranges
find that among rich households, those with are basically set by technology, the relative
more proprietary income hold fewer stocks number of apples versus oranges that can be
in their portfolios. This paints an interesting grown on the same acre of land. We do not
picture of the equity premium: In the past need a deep understanding of consumers’ de-
most stocks were held by rich people, and sires to figure out what the price should be. If
most rich people were proprietors whose other technology is (close to) linear, it will determine
income (and consumption) was quite volatile relative prices, while preferences will deter-
and covaried strongly with the market. This is mine quantities. Does this argument work for
a hard crowd to sell stocks to, so they have stocks?
required a high risk premium. The Campbell- Again, there is a standard model that has
Cochrane and Constantinides-Duffie models served well to describe quantities in growth,
specify that stock market risk is spread as macroeconomics, and international economics.
evenly as possible through the population, The standard model consists of a production
whereas if the risk is shared among a small function by which output, Y, is made from
group of people, higher rewards will have to capital, K, and labor, L, perhaps with some
be offered to offset that risk. uncertainty, θ, together with an accumulation
These views are still not sorted out quanti- equation by which investment I turns into new
tatively. We don’t know why rich stockholders capital in the future. In equations, together
don’t buy even more stocks, given low risk with the most common functional forms,
aversion and the tyrannical logic of equation 6.
We don’t know why only rich people held 15) Yt = f ( Kt , Lt , θt ) = θt Ktα L1t −α
stocks in the first place: The literature shows Kt +1 = (1 − δ) Kt + It
that even quite high transactions costs and
borrowing constraints should not be enough Yt = Ct + It .
to deter people with low risk aversion from
holding stocks.

FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF CHICAGO 27


It was well known already in the 1970s Now, there is a difference between installed
that this standard, “neoclassical” model would and uninstalled capital, and the price of installed
be a disaster at describing asset pricing facts. capital can vary. Adding an extra unit of capital
It predicts that stock prices and returns should tomorrow via extra investment costs 1–∂c(⋅)∂ I
be extremely stable. To see this, invest an extra units of output today, while an extra unit of capi-
dollar, reap the extra output that the additional tal would give (1–δ) units of capital tomorrow.
capital will produce, and then invest a bit less Hence the price of capital in terms of output is
next year. This action gives a physical or invest-
ment return. For the technology described in
1− δ ∂c
equation 15, the investment return is 18) Pt = ≈1+ −δ
1− ∂ c / ∂i ∂I
I
16) RtI+1 = 1 + fk ( Kt +1 , Lt +1 , θt +1 ) − δ = 1+ a t − δ,
Kt
Yt +1
=1+α − δ.
Kt +1
where the last equality uses the quadratic func-
tional form. (This is the q theory of investment.
With the share of capital α ≈ 1/3, an output- With an asymmetric c function, this is the basis
capital ratio Y/K ≈ 1/3, and depreciation δ ≈ 10%, of the theory of irreversible investment. Abel
we have RI ≈ 6%, so average equity returns are and Eberly [1996] give a recent synthesis with
easily within the range of plausible parameters. references.)
The trouble lies with the variance. Capital is Equation 18 shows that stock prices are
quite smooth, so even if output varies 3 percent expected to be high when investment is high,
in a year, the investment return only varies by or firms are expected to issue stock and invest
1 percent, far below the 17 percent standard when stock prices are high. The investment
deviation of stock returns. The basic problem return is now
is the absence of price variation. The capital
accumulation equation shows that installed
capital, Kt, and uninstalled capital, It, are per- 1 + fk (t + 1) − ck (t + 1) + ci (t + 1)
fect substitutes in making new capital, Kt+1 19) RtI+1 = (1 − δ)
1 + ci (t )
Therefore, they must have the same price—the
price of stocks relative to consumption goods Yt +1 a It2+1 It +1
1+α − 2 +a
must be exactly 1.0. Kt +1 2 Kt +1 Kt +1
The obvious modification is that there = (1 − δ )
it
1+ a
must be some difference between installed Kt
and uninstalled capital. The most natural extra
ingredient is an adjustment cost or irrevers- ≈1+α
Yt +1 I FG I
− δ + a t +1 − t .
IJ
ibility: It is hard to get any work done on the K t +1 H
K t +1 Kt K
day the furniture is delivered, and it is hard to
take paint back off the walls and sell it. To
recognize these sensible features of investment, Comparing equation 19 with equation 16,
we can reduce output during periods of high the investment return contains a new term pro-
investment or make negative investment costly portional to the change in investment. Since
by modifying equation 15 to investment is quite volatile, this model can be
consistent with the volatility of the market return.
17) Yt = f ( Kt Lt , θ t ) − c( It ,⋅). In equation 18, the last term adds price changes
to the model of the investment return.
How does all this work? Figure 7 presents
The dot reminds us that other variables may
the investment-output ratio along with the value
influence the adjustment or irreversibility cost
weighted P/D ratio. (The results are almost
term. A common specification is
identical using an investment-capital ratio with
capital formed from depreciated past investment.)
a I t2 Equation 18 suggests that these two series should
Yt = θ t Ktα L1t −α − .
2 Kt move together. The cyclical movements in
investment and stock prices do line up pretty

28 ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES
well. The longer-term variation in P/D is not that surrounds the size of the risk aversion
mirrored in investment: This simple model coefficient, γ. From equation 19 and the fact
does not explain why investment stayed robust that investment growth has standard deviation
in the late 1970s despite dismal stock prices. of about 10 percent, a ≈ 2 is needed to ratio-
However, the recent surge in the market is nalize the roughly 20 percent standard devia-
matched by a surge in investment. tion of stock returns. With I/Y ≈ 15% and
This kind of model has been subject to an Y/K ≈ 33%, and hence I/K ≈ 1/20, a value a ≈ 2
enormous formal empirical effort, which pretty means that adjustment costs relative to output are
much confirms the figure. First, the model is a I I 2 1
= F I
consistent with a good deal of the cyclical varia- 2 K Y 2 20 H K x 15% = 0.75%, which does
tion in investment and stock returns, both fore- not seem unreasonable. However, estimates of
casts and ex-post. (See, for example, Cochrane, a based on regressions, Euler equations, or
1991c.) It does not do well with longer-term other techniques often result in much higher
trends in the P/D ratio. Second, early tests values, implying that implausibly large frac-
relating investment to interest rates that imposed tions of output are lost to adjustment costs.
a constant risk premium did not work (Abel, This model does not yet satisfy the goal of
1983). The model only works at all if one rec- determining the equity premium by technological
ognizes that most variation in the cost of capi- considerations alone. Current specifications of
tal comes from time-varying expected stock technology allow firms to transform resources
returns with relatively constant interest rates. over time but not across states of nature. If the
Third, the model in equation 18 taken literally firm’s own stock is undervalued, it can issue
allows no residual. If prices deviate one iota more and invest. However, if the interest rate is
from the right-hand side of equation 18, then low, there is not much one can say about what
the model is statistically rejected—we can say the firm should do without thinking about the
with perfect certainty that it is not a literal descrip- price of residual risk, and hence a preference
tion of the data-generating mechanism. There is approach to the equity premium. Technically,
a residual in actual data of course, and the resid- the marginal rate of transformation across
ual can be correlated with other variables such states of nature is undefined.
as cash flow that suggest the presence of finan-
cial frictions (Fazzari, Hubbard, and Peterson, Implications of the recent surge in investment
and stock prices
1988). Finally, the size of the adjustment cost, a,
The association between stock returns and
is the subject of the same kind of controversy
investment in figure 7 verifies that at least one
connection between stock re-
turns and the real economy
FIGURE 7 works in some respects as it
Value weighted portfolio P/D and investment should. This argues against the
view that stock market swings
are due entirely to waves of
Investment-output irrational optimism and pessi-
ratio mism. It also verifies that the
flow of money into the stock
market does at least partially
correspond to new real assets
and not just price increases on
existing assets.
In particular, the surge in
stock prices since 1990 has been
Price/dividend accompanied by a surge in invest-
ratio ment. If expected stock returns
and the cost of capital are low,
’62 ’69 ’76 ’83 ’90 ’97 then investment should be high.
Notes: Investment-output ratio and P/D of value weighted NYSE. Statistically, high investment-
Investment = gross fixed investment, output = gross domestic output.
Series are stretched to fit on the same graph. output or investment-capital

FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF CHICAGO 29


ratios also forecast low stock returns (Cochrane, Alternatively, the Campbell-Cochrane model
1991c). Thus, high investment provides additional above already produces the equity premium
statistical and economic evidence for the view that with constant interest rates, which can be inter-
expected stock returns are quite low. preted as a linear production function. Models
with this kind of precautionary savings motive
General equilibrium
may not be as severely affected by the addition
To really understand the equity premium, of an explicit production technology.
we need to combine the utility function and Hansen, Sargent, and Tallarini (1997) use
production function modifications to construct non-state-separable preferences similar to those
complete, explicit economic models that repli- of Epstein and Zin in a general equilibrium
cate the asset pricing facts. This effort should model. They show that a model with standard
also preserve, if not enhance, our understanding preferences and a model with non-state-separable
of the broad range of dynamic microeconomic, preferences can predict the same path of quan-
macroeconomic, international, and growth tity variables (such as output, investment, and
facts underpinning the standard models. The consumption) but differ dramatically on asset
task is challenging. Anything that affects the prices. This example offers some explanation
relationship between consumption and asset of how the real business cycle and growth
prices will affect the relationship between con- literature could spend 25 years examining
sumption and investment. Asset prices mediate quantity data in detail and miss all the modifi-
the consumption-investment decision and that cations to preferences that we seem to need to
decision lies at the heart of any dynamic macro- explain asset pricing data. It also means that
economic model. We have learned a bit about asset price information is crucial to identifying
how to go about this task, but have developed preferences and calculating welfare costs of
no completely satisfactory model as yet. policy experiments. Finally, it offers hope that
Jermann (1997) tried putting habit persis- adding the deep modifications necessary to
tence consumers in a model with a neoclassical explain asset pricing phenomena will not demolish
technology like equation 15, which is almost the success of standard models at describing
completely standard in business-cycle models. the movements of quantities.
The easy opportunities for intertemporal trans-
formation provided by that technology meant Implications
that the consumers used it to dramatically smooth The standard economic models, which
consumption, destroying the prediction of a have been used with great success to describe
high equity premium. To generate the equity growth, macroeconomics, international economics,
premium, Jermann added an adjustment cost and even dynamic microeconomics, do not
technology like equation 17, as the production- predict the historical equity premium, let alone
side literature had proposed. This modification the predictability of returns. After ten years of
resulted in a high equity premium, but also effort, a range of deep modifications to the
large variation in risk-free rates. standard models show promise in explaining
Boldrin, Christiano, and Fisher (1995) also the equity premium as a combination of high
add habit-persistence preferences to real business risk aversion and new risk factors. Those modi-
cycle models with frictions in the allocation of fications are now also consistent with the broad
resources to two sectors. They generate about facts about consumption, interest rates, and
one-half of the historical Sharpe ratio. They predictable returns. However, the modifications
find some quantity dynamics are improved have so far only been aimed at explaining asset
over the standard model. However, their model pricing data. We have not yet established
still predicts highly volatile interest rates and whether the deep modifications necessary to
persistent consumption growth. explain asset market data retain the models’
To avoid the implications of highly volatile previous successes at describing quantity data.
interest rates, I suspect we will need represen- The modified models are drastic revisions
tations of technology that allow easy transfor- to the macroeconomic tradition. In the Campbell-
mation across time but not across states of nature, Cochrane model, for example, strong time-
analogous to the need for easy intertemporal varying precautionary savings motives balance
substitution but high risk aversion in preferences. strong time-varying intertemporal substitution
motives. Uncertainty is of first-order importance

30 ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES
in this model; linearizations near the steady In the economic models that generate the
state and dynamics with the shocks turned off equity premium, every investor is exactly happy
give dramatically wrong predictions about the to hold his or her share of the market portfolio,
model’s behavior. The costs of business cycles no more and no less. The point of the models is
are orders of magnitude larger than in standard that the superficial attractiveness of stocks is
models. In the Constantinides-Duffie model, balanced by a well-described source of risk, so
one has to explicitly keep track of micro- that people are just willing to hold them. Simi-
economic heterogeneity in order to say anything larly, the time variation in the equity premium
about aggregates. does not necessarily mean one should attempt
The new models are also a drastic revision to time the market, buying more stocks at times
to finance. We are used to thinking of aversion of high expected returns and vice versa. Every
to wealth risk, as in the CAPM, as a good start- investor in the Campbell-Cochrane model, for
ing place or first-order approximation. But this example, holds exactly the same portfolio all
view cannot hold. To justify the equity premium, the time, while buy and sell signals come and
people must be primarily averse to holding go. In the peak of a boom they are not feeling
stocks because of their exposure to some other very risk averse, and put their money in the
state variable or risk factor, such as recessions market despite its low expected returns. In the
or changes in the investment opportunity set. bottom of a bust, they feel very risk averse, but
To believe in the equity premium, one has to the high expected returns are just enough to
believe that these stories are sensible. keep their money in the market.
Finally, every quantitatively successful To rationalize active portfolio strategies,
current story for the equity premium still requires such as pulling out of the market at times of
astonishingly high risk aversion. The alternative, high price ratios, you have to ask, who is there
of course, is that the long-run equity premium who is going to be more in the market than
is much smaller than the average postwar 8 per- average now? And, what else are you going to
cent excess return. The standard model was do with the money?
right after all, and historically high U.S. stock More formally, it is easy to crank out
returns were largely due to luck or some other portfolio advice, solutions to optimal portfolio
transient phenomenon. problems given objectives like the utility func-
Faced with the great difficulty economic tion in equation 3. Assuming low risk aversion,
theory still has in digesting the equity premium, and no labor income or other reason for time-
I think the wise observer shades down the varying risk exposure or risk aversion, solutions
estimate of the future equity premium even typically suggest large portfolio shares in equi-
more than suggested by the statistical uncer- ties and a strong market timing approach, some-
tainty documented above. times highly leveraged and sometimes (now)
even short. (See Barberis, 1997; Brandt, 1997.)
Portfolio implications
If everyone followed this advice, however, the
In sum, the long-term average stock return
equity premium and the predictable variation in
may well be lower than the postwar 8 percent
expected returns would disappear. Everyone
average over bonds, and currently high prices
trying to buy stocks would simply drive up the
are a likely signal of unusually low expected
prices; everyone trying to time the market
returns. It is tempting to take a sell recommen-
would stabilize prices. Thus, the majority of
dation from this conclusion. There is one very
investors must be solving a different problem,
important caution to such a recommendation.
deciding on their portfolios with different
On average, everyone has to hold the market
considerations in mind, so that they are always
portfolio. The average person does not change
just willing to hold the outstanding stocks and
his or her portfolio at all. For every individual
bonds at current prices. Before going against
who keeps money out of stocks, someone else
this crowd, it is wise to understand why the
must have a very long position in stocks. Prices
crowd seems headed in a different direction.
adjust until this is the case. Thus, one should
Here, a good macroeconomic model of
only hold less stocks than the average person if
stock market risk could be extremely useful.
one is different from everyone else in some
The models describe why average consumers
crucial way. It is not enough to be bearish, one
are so afraid of stocks and why that fear changes
must be more bearish than everyone else.
over time. Then, individuals in circumstances

FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF CHICAGO 31


that make them different from everyone else is a dangerous stance to take. Someone must be
can understand why they should behave differ- wrong in the view that he or she is smarter than
ently from the crowd. If you have no habits or everyone else. Furthermore, this view also
are immune to labor income shocks, in other suggests that the opportunities are not likely to
words if you are unaffected by the state vari- last. People do learn. The opinions in this article
ables or risk factors that drive the stock market are hardly a secret. We could interpret the recent
premium, by all means go your own way. run-up in the market as the result of people
However, the current state of the art is not finally figuring out how good an investment
advanced enough to provide concrete advice stocks have been for the last century, and build-
along these lines. ing institutions that allow wide participation in
The last possibility is that one thinks one the stock market. If so, future returns are likely
is smarter than everyone else, and that the to be much lower, but there is not much one can
equity premium and predictability are just do about it but sigh and join the parade.
patterns that are ignored by other people. This

APPENDIX: DERIVATIONS

Variance decomposition Consumption-portfolio equations


Massaging an identity, I develop the consumption-portfolio prob-
lem in continuous time. This leads to a number
of simplifications that can also be derived as
1 = Rt−+11 Rt +1 approximations or specializations to the normal
Pt +1 + Dt +1 distribution in discrete time. A security has
1 = Rt−+11 price P, dividend Ddt and thus instantaneous
Pt
rate of return dP/P + D/Pdt. The utility func-
Pt P + Dt +1
= Rt−+11 t +1 tion is
Dt Dt
Pt P FG D
= Rt−+11 t +1 + 1 t +1
IJ z
Et e −ρs u( Ct + s ) ds .
Dt H
Dt +1 Dt K The first-order condition for an optimal
∞ j
P Dt +k consumption-portfolio choice is
20) t =
Dt
∑ ∏ Rt−+1k Dt + k −1
+
j =1 k =1
− ρs

lim
j →∞
F∏ R I P
GH
j
JK D −1
t+k
t+ j
. z
u ′(Ct ) Pt = Et e u ′( Ct + s ) Dt + s ds +
k =1 t+ j Et e − ρk u ′(Ct + k ) Pt + k .

This equation shows how price-dividend


Letting the time interval shrink to zero,
ratios are exactly linked to subsequent returns,
we have
dividend growth, or a potential bubble. It is
convenient to approximate this relation. We
can follow Cochrane (1991b) and take a Taylor 0 = Et d ( ΛP) + Dt dt
expansion now, or follow Campbell and Shiller
(1986) and Taylor and expand the first equa- where
tion in 20 to
Λ t ≡ e −ρt u ′(Ct ) .
pt − dt = ∆dt +1 − rt +1 + ρ( pt +1 − dt +1 )
Expanding the second moment, and divid-
and then iterate to ing by ΛP


pt − dt = ∑ ρ j (∆dt + j − rt + j ) +
0 = Et F dP I + D dt + E F dΛ I + E LM dΛ dP OP. t
j =1 H PK P H ΛK NΛ P Q t t
t
lim ρ ( pt + j − dt + j ) .
j
j →∞

32 ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES
1
Applying this basic condition to a risk-
free asset,
∑ δ j u(C − x ) = 2 ∑ δ j u(C + y) +
j j

1
f L dΛ O
r dt = − E M P = ρdt − E M
L du′(C) OP = ∑
2 j
δ j u(C − y) .
t
N QΛ
t
N u′(C) Q t

Cu ′′(C) L dC O Using the power functional form,


ρdt − EM P
u ′(C) NCQ t
1 1
L dC O (C − x )1− γ = (C + y)1− γ + (C − y )1− γ ,
r dt = ρdt + γE M P .
f
2 2
t
NCQ t

and solving for x,


This establishes equation 4. For any other asset,
1

x = C − LM (C + y ) OP
1 1− γ 1 1− γ
+ (C − y )1− γ
0 = Et F dP I + D dt − r dt = − E LM dΛ dP OP.
f t N2 2 Q .
H PK P t
NΛ P Q t
t

This equation is easier to solve in ratio


Using Ito’s lemma on Λ, we have form; the fraction of consumption that the
family would pay is related to the fractional

Et
LM dΛ dP OP = Cu′′(C) E F dC dP I .
t
wealth risk by

N Λ P Q u ′( C ) H C P K
t
t
1
x
= 1−
1 LM F
1+
y I 1− γ
1
+ 1−
yF I OP
1− γ 1− γ
.
Finally, using the symbols C 2 MN H
C K 2 CH K PQ
dP D
r= + dt, r f = r f dt, This equation is the basis for the calcula-
P P tions in table 5.
−Cu′′(C) dC For small risks, we can approximate
γ= , ∆c =
u ′(C) C
1
we have equation 5, u(C − x ) = u(C + y) + u(C − y)
2
1
Et (r ) − r f = − γ covt ∆c, r = − u ′ (C ) x ≈ u′′(C) y 2
2
a f
− γ σ t ∆c σ t (r )ρt ( ∆c, r ) . x

−Cu ′′(C ) y F I 2
=γ F yI 2

C u ′( C ) C H K H CK
I drop the t subscript in the text where it 2
is not important to keep track of the difference
x
≈ γ
y F I
between conditional and unconditional moments. C C H K
γF I .
x y
Risk aversion calculations ≈
What is the amount x that a consumer is
y H CK
willing to pay every period to avoid a bet that
either increases consumption by y every period
or decreases it by the same amount? The an-
swer is found from the condition

FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF CHICAGO 33


NOTES
1 8
More formally, we can only reject hypotheses that the I specify bets on annual consumption to sidestep the
true return is less than 3 percent or greater than 13 percent objection that most bets are bets on wealth rather than bets
with 95 percent probability. on consumption. As a first-order approximation, consum-
ers will respond to lost wealth by lowering consumption
2
A bit more formally, if you start with a regression of log at every date by the same amount. More sophisticated
returns on the P/D ratio, rt+1 = a + b p/dt + εt+1 , and a calculations yield the same qualitative results.
similar autoregression of the P/D ratio, p/dt = µ + ρ p/dt-1
+ δ t, then you can calculate the implied long-horizon 9
The value function is formally defined as the achieved
regression statistics. The fact that ρ is a very high number level of expected utility. It is a function of wealth because
implies that long-horizon return regression coefficients the richer you are, the happier you can get, if you spend
and R2 rise with the horizon, as in the table. See Hodrick your wealth wisely. The value can also be a function of
(1992) and Cochrane (1991a) for calculations. other variables such as labor income or expected returns
that describe the environment. Thus,
3
The OLS regression estimate of ρ, is 0.90. However, this
estimate is severely downward biased. In a Monte Carlo ∞
replication of the regression, a true coefficient ρ = 0.90
resulted in an estimate ρ$ , with a mean of 0.82, a median
V ( Wt ,⋅) = max Et
mct +s r z s=0
e − ρs u(ct + s ) ds s. t.(constraints).

of 0.83, and a standard deviation of 0.09. Assuming a true


The dot reminds us that there can be other arguments to
coefficient of 0.98 produces an OLS estimator ρ$ OLS , with
the value function. VW = u c is the “envelope” condition,
median 0.90. I therefore adjust for the downward bias of
and follows from this definition.
the OLS estimate by using ρ$ = 0.98.
10
4 Precisely, define the “surplus consumption ratio,”
To generate a negative expected excess return, we have
S = (C – X)/C, and denote s = ln S. Then s adapts to con-
to believe that the market return is negatively conditional-
sumption following a discrete-time “square root process”
ly correlated with the state variables that drive excess
returns, for example consumption growth. This is theoreti-
cally possible, but seems awfully unlikely. st +1 − st = −(1 − φ)(st − s ) +
LM 1 OP
1 − 2(s − s ) − 1 (ct +1 − ct − g).
5
NS Q
Craine (1993) does a formal test of price/dividend sta-
tionarity and connects the test to bubbles. My statements Taking a Taylor approximation, this specification is
are a superficial dismissal of a large literature. A lot of locally the same as allowing log habit x to adjust to
careful attention has been paid to the bubble possibility, consumption,
but the current consensus seems to be that bubbles, as I
have defined them here, do not explain price variation. xt +1 ≈ const . + φxt + (1 − φ)ct +1.
6
Eliminate the last term, multiply both sides by (pt – dt) –
Campbell and Cochrane specify that habits are “external”:
E(pt – dt) and take expectations.
Your neighbor’s consumption raises your habit. This is a
7
simplification, since it means that each consumption
Several ways around this argument do exist. Kocherlakota
decision does not take into account its habit-forming
(1990) defends a preference for later consumption. Kan-
effect. They argue that this assumption does not greatly
del and Stambaugh (1991) note that the argument hinges
affect aggregate consumption and asset price implications,
critically on the definition of ∆c. If we define ∆c as the
though it is necessary to reconcile the unpredictability of
proportional change in consumption ∆c = (Ct + ∆ t – Ct)/Ct
individual consumption growth.
as I have (or, more properly, ∆c = dC/C in continuous
time; see the appendix), then we obtain equation 4. How- 11
Technically, this assertion depends on the form of the
ever, if we define ∆c as the change in log consumption,
utility function. For example, with log utility, consumers
∆c = ln (C t + ∆ t /Ct ) or more properly ∆c = d(ln C), we
don’t care about future returns. In this statement I am assum-
obtain an additional term, r f = ρ +γE(∆c) – 1/2γ2σ2(∆c).
ing risk aversion greater than 1. See Campbell (1996).
For γ < 100 or so, the choice does not matter. The last
term is small, since E(∆c) ≈ σ(∆c) ≈ 0.01. However, since 12
To prove this assertion, just substitute for Cit and take
γ is squared, the second term can be large with γ = 250,
the expectation:
and can take the place of a negative ρ in generating a
1 percent interest rate with 1 percent consumption growth.
What’s going on? The model u′(C) = C–250 is extraordinar- LM
1 = Et −1 exp −ρ − γ ηit yt +
1 2
γ yt + ln Rt +1 .
OP
ily sensitive to the probability of consumption declines. N 2 Q
The second model gives slightly higher weight to those
probabilities. Rather than rescue the model with γ = 250, Since η is independent of everything else, we can use
in my evaluation, this example shows how special it is: E[f(ηy)] = E[f(ηy)y)]. Now, with η normal, E (exp
It says that interest rates as well as all asset prices depend [–γηit yt]yt ) = exp [1–2γ 2yt2]. Therefore, we have
only on the probabilities assigned to extremely rare events.

34 ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES
LM 1 γ y + 1 γ y + ln R OP
1 = Et −1 exp −ρ + 2 2 2
t +1
We can sometimes construct such discount factors by
N 2 t
2
t
Q picking parameters a, b in mt = max [a + bRt, e−ρ (Ct /Ct–1)−γ ]
L 1 OP to satisfy equation 14. However, neither this construction
1 = Et −1
F 2 IJ F ln 1 + ρI + ln R
exp M −ρ + γ ( γ + 1)G
MN 2 H γ (γ + 1) K GH R JK
t
t +1
PQ
nor a discount factor satisfying equation 13 is guaranteed
to exist for a given set of assets. The restriction in equation
1 = Et −11. 13 is a tighter form of the familiar restriction that mt ≥ 0 is
equivalent to the absence of arbitrage in the assets under
consideration. Presumably, this restriction is what rules
13
There is a possibility that the square root term in equa- out markets for individual labor income risks in the
tions 11 and 12 might be negative. Constantinides and model. The example m = 1/R that I use is a positive dis-
Duffie rule out this possibility by assuming that the count factor that prices a single asset return 1 = E(R–1R),
discount factor m satisfies but does not necessarily satisfy the restriction in equation
13. For high R, we can have very negative ln1/R. This
Ct is why the lines in figure 6 run into the horizontal axis
13) ln mt ≥ −ρ − γ ln
Ct −1 at high R.

in every state of nature, so that the square root term is


positive.

REFERENCES

Abel, Andrew B., “Optimal investment under Black, Fischer, “Studies of stock price volatility
uncertainty,” American Economic Review, Vol. changes,” Proceedings of the 1976 Meetings of the
73, No. 1, March 1983, pp. 228–233. Business and Economic Statistics Section, Ameri-
can Statistical Association, 1976, pp. 177–181.
, “Asset prices under habit formation
and catching up with the Joneses,” American Boldrin, Michele, Lawrence J. Christiano, and
Economic Review Papers and Proceedings, Vol. Jonas D.M. Fisher, “Asset pricing lessons for
80, No. 2, May 1990, pp. 38–42. modeling business cycles,” NBER, working
paper, No. 5262, 1995.
Abel, Andrew B., and Janice C. Eberly, “Opti-
mal investment with costly reversibility,” Review Brandt, Michael, “Estimating portfolio and
of Economic Studies, Vol. 63, 1996, pp. 581–594. consumption choice: A conditional Euler equa-
tions approach,” University of Chicago, Ph.D.
Aiyagari, S. Rao, and Mark Gertler, “Asset dissertation, 1997.
returns with transactions costs and undiversifi-
able individual risk,” Journal of Monetary Eco- Brown, Stephen J., William N. Goetzmann,
nomics, Vol. 27, No. 3, June 1991, pp. 311–331. and Stephen A. Ross, “Survival,” Journal of
Finance, Vol. 50, No. 3, 1995, pp. 853–873
Barberis, Nicholas, “Investing for the long run
when returns are predictable,” University of Campbell, John Y., “Stock returns and the term
Chicago, Center for Research on Security Prices, structure,” Journal of Financial Economics, Vol.
working paper, No. 439, 1997. 18, 1987, pp. 373–399.

Barsky, Robert B., Miles S. Kimball, F. Thomas , “Understanding risk and return,”
Juster, and Matthew D. Shapiro, “Preference Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 104, April
parameters and behavioral heterogeneity: An 1996, pp. 298–345.
experimental approach in the health and retire-
ment survey,” National Bureau of Economic Campbell, John Y., and John H. Cochrane, “By
Research, working paper, No. 5213, 1997. force of habit: A consumption-based explanation
of aggregate stock market behavior,” University of
Bernardo, Antonio, and Olivier Ledoit, “Gain, Chicago, working paper, 1997. [Revision of Na-
loss and asset pricing,” University of California tional Bureau of Economic Research, working
at Los Angeles, Anderson Graduate School of paper, No. 4995, dated January 1, 1995.]
Management, working paper, No. 16-96, 1996.

FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF CHICAGO 35


Campbell, John Y., and Robert J. Shiller, “The Eichenbaum, Martin, Lars Peter Hansen, and
dividend–price ratio and expectations of future Kenneth J. Singleton, “A time series analysis of
dividends and discount factors,” Review of Fi- representative agent models of consumption and
nancial Studies, Vol. 1, 1988, pp. 195–227. leisure choice under uncertainty,” Journal of
Business and Economic Statistics, Vol. 103,
Cochrane, John H., “Volatility tests and efficient February 1988, pp. 51–78.
markets: A review essay,” Journal of Monetary
Economics, Vol. 27, June 1991a, pp. 463–485. Epstein, Larry G., and Stanley E. Zin, “Substi-
tution, risk aversion and the temporal behavior
, “Explaining the variance of price– of asset returns,” Journal of Political Economy,
dividend ratios,” Review of Financial Studies, Vol. 99, 1989, pp. 263–286.
Vol. 15, 1991b, pp. 243–280.
Fama, Eugene F., and Kenneth R. French,
, “Production-based asset pricing “Permanent and temporary components of stock
and the link between stock returns and economic prices,” Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 96,
fluctuations” Journal of Finance, Vol. 41, March April 1988a, pp. 246–273.
1991c, pp. 207–234.
, “Dividend yields and expected
Cochrane, John H., and Lars Peter Hansen, stock returns,” Journal of Financial Economics,
“Asset pricing lessons for macroeconomics,” in Vol. 22, October 1988b, pp. 3–27.
1992 NBER Macroeconomics Annual, Olivier
Blanchard and Stanley Fischer (eds.), 1992, pp. , “Business conditions and expected
1115–1165. returns on stocks and bonds,” Journal of Finan-
cial Economics, Vol. 25, 1989, pp. 23–49.
Constantinides, George M., “Theory of valua-
tion: Overview,” in Theory of Valuation: Fron- , “Common risk factors in the re-
tiers of Modern Financial Theory, Volume I, turns on stocks and bonds,” Journal of Financial
Sudipto Bhattahcharya and George M. Constan- Economics, Vol. 33, February 1993, pp. 3–56.
tinides (eds.), Totowa NJ: Rowman and Little-
field, 1989, pp. 1–23. Fazzari, Steven M., Robert Glenn Hubbard,
Robert Glenn, and Bruce C. Petersen, “Financ-
, “Habit formation: A resolution of ing constraints and corporate investment,”
the equity premium puzzle,” Journal of Political Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, Vol. 0,
Economy, Vol. 98, June 1990, pp. 519–543. 1988, pp. 141–195.

Constantinides, George M., and Darrell Duffie, Ferson, Wayne E., and George Constantinides,
“Asset pricing with heterogeneous consumers,” “Habit persistence and durability in aggregate
Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 104, April consumption: Empirical tests,” Journal of Financial
1996, pp. 219–240. Economics, Vol. 29, October 1991, pp. 199–240.

Craine, Roger, “Rational bubbles: A test,” Jour- Friend, I., and M. Blume, “The demand for
nal of Economic Dynamics and Control, Vol. 17, risky assets,” American Economic Review, Vol.
1993, pp. 829–846. 55, 1975, pp. 900–922.

Deaton, Angus S., Understanding Consumption, Hansen, Lars Peter, and Ravi Jagannathan,
New York: Oxford University Press, 1992. “Restrictions on intertemporal marginal rates of
substitution implied by asset returns,” Journal of
Deaton, Angus, and Christina Paxson, Political Economy, Vol. 99, 1991, pp. 225–262.
“Intertemporal choice and inequality,” Journal
of Political Economy, Vol. 102, June 1994, Hansen, Lars Peter, Thomas J. Sargent, and
pp. 437–467. Thomas D. Tallarini, “Robust permanent in-
come and pricing” University of Chicago, manu-
Duesenberry, James S., Income, Saving, and the script, 1997.
Theory of Consumer Behavior, Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1949.

36 ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES
Heaton, John C., “An empirical investigation of Deepening the equity premium puzzle,” Journal
asset pricing with temporally dependent prefer- of Monetary Economics, Vol. 34, December
ence specifications,” Econometrica, Vol. 63, 1994, pp. 325–341.
May 1995, pp. 681–717.
Mankiw, N. Gregory, “The equity premium and
Heaton, John, and Deborah J. Lucas, “Evaluat- the concentration of aggregate shocks,” Journal
ing the effects of incomplete markets on risk of Financial Economics, Vol. 17, September
sharing and asset pricing,” Journal of Political 1986, pp. 211–219.
Economy, Vol. 104, June 1996a, pp. 443–487.
Mankiw, N. Gregory, and Stephen P. Zeldes,
, “Saving behavior and portfolio “The consumption of stockholders and non-
choice: Which risks matter?,” Northwestern stockholders,” Journal of Financial Economics,
University, working paper, 1996b. Vol. 29, March 1991, pp. 97–112.

Hodrick, Robert, “Dividend yields and expected Marshall, David, and Kent Daniel, “The equity
stock returns: Alternative procedures for infer- premium puzzle and the risk-free rate puzzle at
ence and measurement,” Review of Financial long horizons,” Macroeconomic Dynamics, Vol.
Studies, Vol. 5, No. 3, 1992, pp. 357–386. 1, No. 1, 1997 forthcoming, pp. 452–484.

Jagannathan, Ravi, and Z. Wang, “The condi- Mehra, Rajnish, and Edward Prescott, “The
tional CAPM and the cross-section of expected equity premium puzzle,” Journal of Monetary
returns,” Journal of Finance, Vol. 51, March Economics, Vol. 15, March 1985, pp. 145–161.
1996, pp. 3–53. [Updated in Staff Report, No. 208,
Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis, 1997.] Merton, Robert C., “An intertemporal capital
asset pricing model,” Econometrica, Vol. 41,
Jermann, Urban, “Asset pricing in production September 1973, pp. 867–887.
economies,” Journal of Monetary Economics,
1997 forthcoming. Poterba, James, and Lawrence J. Summers,
“Mean reversion in stock prices,” Journal of Finan-
Kandel, Shmuel, and Robert F. Stambaugh, cial Economics, Vol. 22, October 1988, pp. 27–59.
“Expectations and volatility of consumption and
asset returns,” Review of Financial Studies, Vol. Reyfman, Alexander, “Labor market risk and
3, No. 2, 1990, pp. 207–232. expected asset returns,” University of Chicago,
Ph.D. dissertation, 1997, Ch. 3.
, “Asset returns and intertemporal
preferences,” Journal of Monetary Economics, Rietz, Thomas A., “The equity risk premium: A
Vol. 27, February 1991, pp. 39–71. solution,” Journal of Monetary Economics, Vol.
22, July 1988, pp. 117–131.
Kocherlakota, Narayanna R., “On the ‘discount’
factor in growth economies,” Journal of Monetary Shiller, Robert J., “Consumption, asset markets,
Economics, Vol. 25, January 1990, pp. 43–47. and macroeconomic fluctuations,” Carnegie
Rochester Conference Series on Public Policy,
, “The equity premium: It’s still a Vol. 17, Autumn 1982, pp. 203–238.
puzzle,” Journal of Economic Literature, Vol.
34, March 1996, pp. 42–71. Telmer, Chris I., “Asset pricing puzzles and
incomplete markets,” Journal of Finance, Vol.
Lamont, Owen, “Earnings and Expected Re- 48, December 1993, pp. 1803–1832.
turns,” National Bureau of Economic Research,
working paper, No. 5671, 1996. Weil, Philippe, “The equity premium puzzle and
the risk-free rate puzzle,” Journal of Monetary
Lucas, Deborah J., “Asset pricing with undiver- Economics, Vol. 24, November 1989, pp. 401–421.
sifiable income risk and short sales constraints:

FEDERAL RESERVE BANK OF CHICAGO 37

Anda mungkin juga menyukai